메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 82, Issue 1, 2011, Pages 121-133

Is Desert in the Details?

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 78650683695     PISSN: 00318205     EISSN: 19331592     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1933-1592.2010.00387.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (28)

References (54)
  • 1
    • 78650693854 scopus 로고
    • says that "none of the most prominent contemporary versions of philosophical liberalism assigns a significant role to desert at the level of fundamental principle." Samuel Scheffler, "Responsibility, Reactive Attitudes, and Liberalism in Philosophy and Politics."Philosophy and Public Affairs
    • Samuel Scheffler says that "none of the most prominent contemporary versions of philosophical liberalism assigns a significant role to desert at the level of fundamental principle." Samuel Scheffler, "Responsibility, Reactive Attitudes, and Liberalism in Philosophy and Politics."Philosophy and Public Affairs 21, no. 4 (1992): 299-323
    • (1992) , vol.21 , Issue.4
    • Scheffler, S.1
  • 2
    • 78650707433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example, A Theory of Justice. Revised ed. Cambridge: Belknap Press
    • John RawlsSee, for example, A Theory of Justice. Revised ed. Cambridge: Belknap Press, 1999, 89
    • (1999) , pp. 89
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 3
    • 78650717531 scopus 로고
    • "The Basic Structure as Subject."American Philosophical Quarterly, 162
    • "The Basic Structure as Subject."American Philosophical Quarterly, 162 14, (1977): 159-165
    • (1977) , vol.14 , pp. 159-165
  • 4
    • 78650700149 scopus 로고
    • "Why Bakke Has No Case."New York Review of Books, November 10
    • Ronald Dworkin, "Why Bakke Has No Case."New York Review of Books, November 10, 1977
    • (1977)
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 5
    • 78650695213 scopus 로고
    • Mortal Questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Thomas Nagel, Mortal Questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979
    • (1979)
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 6
    • 78650716610 scopus 로고
    • Political Argument. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1965; Robert Goodin, "Negating Positive Desert Claims."Political Theory
    • Brian Barry, Political Argument. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1965; Robert Goodin, "Negating Positive Desert Claims."Political Theory 13, no. 4 (1985): 575-598.
    • (1985) , vol.13 , Issue.4 , pp. 575-598
    • Barry, B.1
  • 7
    • 78650687607 scopus 로고
    • A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971, 104.
    • (1971) , pp. 104
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 8
    • 78650699942 scopus 로고
    • Equal Justice. Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Eric Rakowski, Equal Justice. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991, 112.
    • (1991) , pp. 112
    • Rakowski, E.1
  • 9
    • 78650693855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberty, Desert, and the Market. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Serena Olsaretti, Liberty, Desert, and the Market. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004, 28.
    • (2004) , pp. 28
    • Olsaretti, S.1
  • 10
    • 78650683240 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Brute Luck Equality and Desert." In Desert and Justice, edited by Serena Olsaretti, 169-185. Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Peter Vallentyne, "Brute Luck Equality and Desert." In Desert and Justice, edited by Serena Olsaretti, 169-185. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003, 175.
    • (2003) , pp. 175
    • Vallentyne, P.1
  • 11
    • 78650693473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Principles of Social Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2003, especially chap. 4 and 7
    • See David Miller, Principles of Social Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2003, especially chap. 4 and 7
    • Miller, D.1
  • 12
    • 84924493781 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Elements of Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006, part 2
    • David Schmidtz, Elements of Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006, part 2.
    • Schmidtz, D.1
  • 13
    • 78650687438 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Miller reviews corroborating empirical evidence that indicates differential desert claims based on differential productivity enjoy wide popular appeal. Principles of Social Justice, chap. 4.
    • Miller reviews corroborating empirical evidence that indicates differential desert claims based on differential productivity enjoy wide popular appeal. Principles of Social Justice, chap. 4.
  • 14
    • 78650681268 scopus 로고
    • Social Justice. Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • See David Miller, Social Justice. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1976, 98
    • (1976) , pp. 98
    • Miller, D.1
  • 15
    • 78650709012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Principles of Social Justice, 67.
    • Principles of Social Justice, 67.
  • 16
    • 78650684209 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Miller, Principles of Social Justice, 51.
    • Miller, Principles of Social Justice, 51.
  • 17
    • 78650711886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 1999, 41.
    • Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 1999, 41.
  • 18
    • 78650684210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Principles of Social Justice, 51.
    • Principles of Social Justice, 51.
  • 19
    • 0041906967 scopus 로고
    • Classic examples of such distortions are illustrated in Daniel Kahneman & Amos Tversky, "Choices, values, and frames."American Psychologist
    • Classic examples of such distortions are illustrated in Daniel Kahneman & Amos Tversky, "Choices, values, and frames."American Psychologist, 39 (1984): 341-350.
    • (1984) , vol.39 , pp. 341-350
  • 20
    • 78650709612 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press
    • John Rawls, Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press, 2005, 300.
    • (2005) , pp. 300
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 21
    • 78650696259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Principles of Social Justice, 61.
    • Principles of Social Justice, 61.
  • 22
    • 78650711364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Miller, Principles of Social Justice, chap. 4.
    • See Miller, Principles of Social Justice, chap. 4.
  • 23
    • 78650702973 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Scheffler, "Responsibility, Reactive Attitudes, and Liberalism in Philosophy and Politics."
    • See Scheffler, "Responsibility, Reactive Attitudes, and Liberalism in Philosophy and Politics."
  • 24
    • 78650691142 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This formulation owes much to the account presented in Vallentyne, "Brute Luck Equality and Desert."
    • This formulation owes much to the account presented in Vallentyne, "Brute Luck Equality and Desert."
  • 25
    • 78650686698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality. Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • Ronald Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2002, 73.
    • (2002) , pp. 73
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 26
    • 78650683412 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Theory of Justice, 1999, 89.
    • A Theory of Justice, 1999, 89.
  • 27
    • 78650699009 scopus 로고
    • Rawls's views about desert are a matter of exegetical controversy, but one common reading interprets Rawls as endorsing the brute luck constraint on desert. George Sher interprets Rawls's claim thusly: "If one person does not deserve to have X while another does not [have X], and if having X enables the first person to.... do Y while the second does not, then the first person does not deserve to have or do Y while the second does not." George Sher, Desert. Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • Rawls's views about desert are a matter of exegetical controversy, but one common reading interprets Rawls as endorsing the brute luck constraint on desert. George Sher interprets Rawls's claim thusly: "If one person does not deserve to have X while another does not [have X], and if having X enables the first person to.... do Y while the second does not, then the first person does not deserve to have or do Y while the second does not." George Sher, Desert. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987, 26
    • (1987) , pp. 26
  • 28
    • 78650712097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Serena Olsaretti writes similarly, "Rawls's concern.... is not that of identifying the necessary conditions for desert in general. Rather, it is with casting doubt on the claim that the unequal distribution of talents and effort-making capacity may justifiably give rise to inequalities in deserts. His aim is to reject the view that the morally arbitrary and differential possession of attributes may give rise to differential deserts." Olsaretti, Liberty, Desert, and the Market
    • Serena Olsaretti writes similarly, "Rawls's concern.... is not that of identifying the necessary conditions for desert in general. Rather, it is with casting doubt on the claim that the unequal distribution of talents and effort-making capacity may justifiably give rise to inequalities in deserts. His aim is to reject the view that the morally arbitrary and differential possession of attributes may give rise to differential deserts." Olsaretti, Liberty, Desert, and the Market, 25-26.
  • 29
    • 78650703390 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Olsaretti writes, "The defensible principle of desert is one which does not make the magnitude of people's unequal deserts depend on unchosen, and unequally distributed, factors." Olsaretti, Liberty, Desert, and the Market, 28. Peter Vallentyne recommends similarly that "the differential influence of brute luck on the distribution of benefits be neutralized. Thus, if benefits are distributed on the basis of desert, brute luck egalitarianism requires that the desert base (that which determines how much one deserves) be something that is not differentially affected by one's brute luck." Vallentyne, "Brute Luck Equality and Desert," 172. Vallentyne concludes, "Desert is not affected by brute luck factors. This is not to claim that it is incoherent for desert to be so affected; it is only to claim that such a desert theory does not yield a plausible theory of justice."
    • Olsaretti writes, "The defensible principle of desert is one which does not make the magnitude of people's unequal deserts depend on unchosen, and unequally distributed, factors." Olsaretti, Liberty, Desert, and the Market, 28. Peter Vallentyne recommends similarly that "the differential influence of brute luck on the distribution of benefits be neutralized. Thus, if benefits are distributed on the basis of desert, brute luck egalitarianism requires that the desert base (that which determines how much one deserves) be something that is not differentially affected by one's brute luck." Vallentyne, "Brute Luck Equality and Desert," 172. Vallentyne concludes, "Desert is not affected by brute luck factors. This is not to claim that it is incoherent for desert to be so affected; it is only to claim that such a desert theory does not yield a plausible theory of justice."
  • 30
    • 78650692685 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue, 91.
    • Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue, 91.
  • 31
    • 84935413249 scopus 로고
    • "On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice."Ethics, 931
    • G.A. Cohen, "On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice."Ethics, 931 99, (1989): 906-44.
    • (1989) , vol.99 , pp. 906-944
    • Cohen, G.A.1
  • 32
    • 78650712670 scopus 로고
    • The Constitution of Liberty. Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • F.A. Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1960, 94.
    • (1960) , pp. 94
    • Hayek, F.A.1
  • 33
    • 78650711186 scopus 로고
    • Morals by Agreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • David Gauthier, Morals by Agreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986, 220.
    • (1986) , pp. 220
    • Gauthier, D.1
  • 34
    • 78650698401 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Treatise of Human Nature, book 3, part 3, section 4; An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, Appendix 4.
    • David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, book 3, part 3, section 4; An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, Appendix 4.
    • Hume, D.1
  • 35
    • 78650682271 scopus 로고
    • Social Justice. Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Social Justice. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1976, 96.
    • (1976) , pp. 96
  • 36
    • 78650685392 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Principles of Social Justice, chap. 4.
    • Principles of Social Justice, chap. 4.
  • 37
    • 78650709207 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Genetic endowment is typically fielded as a straightforward case of brute luck. For example, Dworkin claims that differences in wealth produced by differences "traceable to genetic luck" are unfair, 92. Vallentyne explicitly mentions genes as brute luck factors, 170.
    • Genetic endowment is typically fielded as a straightforward case of brute luck. For example, Dworkin claims that differences in wealth produced by differences "traceable to genetic luck" are unfair, 92. Vallentyne explicitly mentions genes as brute luck factors, 170.
  • 38
    • 0031515980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Insensitivity to the value of human life: a study of psychophysical numbing."Journal of Risk and Uncertainty
    • David Fetherstonhaugh, Paul Slovic, Stephen Johnson, & James Friedrich, "Insensitivity to the value of human life: a study of psychophysical numbing."Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 14 (1997): 283-300
    • (1997) , vol.14 , pp. 283-300
    • Fetherstonhaugh, D.1    Slovic, P.2    Johnson, S.3    Friedrich, J.4
  • 39
    • 19944368304 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "The 'identified victim' effect: an identified group or just a single individual?"Journal of Behavioral Decision Making
    • Tehila Kogut & Ilana Ritov. "The 'identified victim' effect: an identified group or just a single individual?"Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 18 (2005): 157-167
    • (2005) , vol.18 , pp. 157-167
    • Kogut, T.1    Ritov, I.2
  • 40
    • 30344474586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "The Devil You Know: The Effects of Identifiability on Punishment."Journal of Behavioral Decision Making
    • Deborah Small & George Loewenstein, "The Devil You Know: The Effects of Identifiability on Punishment."Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 18 (2005): 311-318.
    • (2005) , vol.18 , pp. 311-318
    • Small, D.1    Loewenstein, G.2
  • 41
    • 58649090384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Moral Responsibility and Determinism: The Cognitive Science of Folk Intuitions."Noûs
    • Shaun Nichols & Joshua Knobe, "Moral Responsibility and Determinism: The Cognitive Science of Folk Intuitions."Noûs, 41 (2007): 663-685.
    • (2007) , vol.41 , pp. 663-685
    • Nichols, S.1    Knobe, J.2
  • 42
    • 18144370957 scopus 로고
    • For discussion of desert and responsibility, see Fred Feldman, "Desert: Reconsideration of Some Received Wisdom."Mind
    • For discussion of desert and responsibility, see Fred Feldman, "Desert: Reconsideration of Some Received Wisdom."Mind 104, no. 413 (1995): 63-77
    • (1995) , vol.104 , Issue.413 , pp. 63-77
  • 43
    • 53149121733 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Responsibility as a Condition for Desert."Mind
    • Fred Feldman, "Responsibility as a Condition for Desert."Mind 105, no. 417 (1996): 165-168
    • (1996) , vol.105 , Issue.417 , pp. 165-168
    • Feldman, F.1
  • 44
    • 78650714455 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For further discussion of the significance of the abstract/concrete distinction, see Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, "Abstract + Concrete = Paradox." In Experimental Philosophy, edited by Joshua Knobe and Shaun Nichols. Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • For further discussion of the significance of the abstract/concrete distinction, see Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, "Abstract + Concrete = Paradox." In Experimental Philosophy, edited by Joshua Knobe and Shaun Nichols. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.
    • (2008)
  • 45
    • 78650687993 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The statistical details are as follows. In the abstract condition, the mean response to the desert question was 2.78; the mean response to the fairness question was 2.72 (4 is the midpoint between "strongly disagree" and "strongly agree"). In the concrete singers case, the mean response to the desert question was 4.57, and the mean response to fairness was 4.71; for concrete jugglers, the mean responses for desert and fairness were 4.86 and 5.5. The differences between abstract and concrete were significant in all cases. People agreed more strongly with the claim that the singer deserved the extra money (t(30)=2.51, p<.05) and that the juggler deserved the extra money (t(30)=3.09, p<.01). Similarly, people agreed more strongly with the claim that it was fair for the singer to get the extra money (t(30)=2.89, p<.01) and also that it was fair for the jugglers to get more money (t(30)=4.74, p<.001).
    • The statistical details are as follows. In the abstract condition, the mean response to the desert question was 2.78; the mean response to the fairness question was 2.72 (4 is the midpoint between "strongly disagree" and "strongly agree"). In the concrete singers case, the mean response to the desert question was 4.57, and the mean response to fairness was 4.71; for concrete jugglers, the mean responses for desert and fairness were 4.86 and 5.5. The differences between abstract and concrete were significant in all cases. People agreed more strongly with the claim that the singer deserved the extra money (t(30)=2.51, p<.05) and that the juggler deserved the extra money (t(30)=3.09, p<.01). Similarly, people agreed more strongly with the claim that it was fair for the singer to get the extra money (t(30)=2.89, p<.01) and also that it was fair for the jugglers to get more money (t(30)=4.74, p<.001).
  • 46
    • 78650686186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Small & Loewenstein 2005.
    • Small & Loewenstein 2005.
  • 47
    • 84921385773 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral Skepticisms. Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Moral Skepticisms. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006, 203.
    • (2006) , pp. 203
    • Sinnott-Armstrong, W.1
  • 48
    • 78650714070 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1982, part IV.2.3. Smith even suggests that ordinary judgments about the connection between luck and merit are sensitive to whether one is considering them in an abstract or concrete light, albeit in a way different from the treatment offered here. The Theory of Moral Sentiments, part II.3.Introduction.
    • Adam Smith, The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1982, part IV.2.3. Smith even suggests that ordinary judgments about the connection between luck and merit are sensitive to whether one is considering them in an abstract or concrete light, albeit in a way different from the treatment offered here. The Theory of Moral Sentiments, part II.3.Introduction.
    • Smith, A.1
  • 49
    • 78650688579 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Social Justice, 88.
    • Social Justice, 88.
  • 50
    • 78650705465 scopus 로고
    • See also Smith, II.i.I and Joel Feinberg, "Justice and Personal Desert." In Doing and Deserving, 55-94. Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • See also Smith, II.i.I and Joel Feinberg, "Justice and Personal Desert." In Doing and Deserving, 55-94. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1970, 70-71.
    • (1970) , pp. 70-71
  • 51
    • 78650713498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Theory of Justice
    • A Theory of Justice, 1999, 41.
    • (1999) , pp. 41
  • 52
    • 78650695601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Miller's understanding of a theory of justice is similar to Rawls's. Like Rawls, Miller draws on the linguistic analogy, suggesting that "someone who has an implicit grasp of.... the 'grammar' of justice will understand the norms of appropriateness" governing principles of social justice. Principles of Social Justice, 35. Elsewhere Miller writes, "All morally competent adults have a well-developed sense of justice that enables them to cope with the practical questions they confront from day to day. How should my neighbor and I share the cost of the new fence that will run between our properties? Which child in my class ought to get the academic prize? Should I give Smith, my employee, the leave he has asked for to look after his sick mother? We know how to think about such questions, and we can answer them without any knowledge of the many abstract theories of justice that political philosophers from Plato to Rawls have advanced."
    • Miller's understanding of a theory of justice is similar to Rawls's. Like Rawls, Miller draws on the linguistic analogy, suggesting that "someone who has an implicit grasp of.... the 'grammar' of justice will understand the norms of appropriateness" governing principles of social justice. Principles of Social Justice, 35. Elsewhere Miller writes, "All morally competent adults have a well-developed sense of justice that enables them to cope with the practical questions they confront from day to day. How should my neighbor and I share the cost of the new fence that will run between our properties? Which child in my class ought to get the academic prize? Should I give Smith, my employee, the leave he has asked for to look after his sick mother? We know how to think about such questions, and we can answer them without any knowledge of the many abstract theories of justice that political philosophers from Plato to Rawls have advanced."
  • 53
    • 78650712292 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Olsaretti, Liberty, Desert, and the Market, 72.
    • Olsaretti, Liberty, Desert, and the Market, 72.
  • 54
    • 78650692112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Miller, Principles of Social Justice, chap 4.
    • Miller, Principles of Social Justice, chap 4.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.