메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn , Issue , 2010, Pages

Justice: Rights and wrongs

(1)  Wolterstorff, Nicholas a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 84884085163     PISSN: None     EISSN: None     Source Type: Book    
DOI: None     Document Type: Book
Times cited : (156)

References (265)
  • 1
    • 84883952026 scopus 로고
    • Translated by Philip S. Watson, London: SPCK
    • Translated by Philip S. Watson (London: SPCK, 1953), p. 90.
    • (1953) , pp. 90
  • 2
    • 84883988006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Virginia Held, ed., Justice and Care: Essential Readings in Feminist Ethics (Boulder, Colo.; Westview Press, 1995), p. 48. I thank Eleonore Stump for calling this essay to my attention
    • In Virginia Held, ed., Justice and Care: Essential Readings in Feminist Ethics (Boulder, Colo.; Westview Press, 1995), p. 48. I thank Eleonore Stump for calling this essay to my attention.
  • 3
    • 84884109691 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The most balanced and reflective discussion of the abuse of rights-talk in the American political arena that I know of is Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse, by Mary Ann Glendon (New York: Free Press, 1991). Explaining her approach, Glendon says, "The critique of the American rights dialect presented here rejects the radical attack on the very notion of rights that is sometimes heard on both ends of the political spectrum. It is not an assault on specific rights or on the idea of rights in general, but a plea for reevaluation of certain thoughtless, habitual ways of thinking and speaking about rights" (15)
    • The most balanced and reflective discussion of the abuse of rights-talk in the American political arena that I know of is Rights Talk: The Impoverishment of Political Discourse, by Mary Ann Glendon (New York: Free Press, 1991). Explaining her approach, Glendon says, "The critique of the American rights dialect presented here rejects the radical attack on the very notion of rights that is sometimes heard on both ends of the political spectrum. It is not an assault on specific rights or on the idea of rights in general, but a plea for reevaluation of certain thoughtless, habitual ways of thinking and speaking about rights" (15).
  • 4
    • 84861871494 scopus 로고
    • On the Right to be Tribal
    • March
    • "On the Right to be Tribal," Christian Scholar's Review 16, no. 3 (March 1987): 238-39.
    • (1987) Christian Scholar's Review , vol.16 , Issue.3 , pp. 238-239
  • 5
    • 84884066914 scopus 로고
    • See chapter 3 of my Divine Discourse, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See chapter 3 of my Divine Discourse (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995).
    • (1995)
  • 6
    • 84884084187 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the idiolect of some philosophers (e.g., John Rawls in A Theory of Justice), the word "duty" is reserved for normative constraints generated by some human action, whereas "obligation" is reserved for normative constraints not so generated. I will speak in accord with ordinary English, and treat the two terms as synonyms
    • In the idiolect of some philosophers (e.g., John Rawls in A Theory of Justice), the word "duty" is reserved for normative constraints generated by some human action, whereas "obligation" is reserved for normative constraints not so generated. I will speak in accord with ordinary English, and treat the two terms as synonyms.
  • 7
    • 84884035215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in his essay "Rights without Trimmings" (in Matthew H. Kramer, N. E. Simmonds, and Hillel Steiner, A Debate over Rights: Philosophical Enquiries [Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998]), claims to be following W. H. Hohfeld in declaring that, among the various things that are called "rights," claim-rights are those for whom the Principle of Correlatives holds by definition of "a right." On this interpretation, instantiations of the Principle of Correlatives would be analytic truths. In chapter 11 I argue that this is a misinterpretation of Hohfeld. Of course, one could introduce such a concept and call it a concept of rights; but that would not be the same as our concept of a claim-right
    • Matthew H. Kramer, in his essay "Rights without Trimmings" (in Matthew H. Kramer, N. E. Simmonds, and Hillel Steiner, A Debate over Rights: Philosophical Enquiries [Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998]), claims to be following W. H. Hohfeld in declaring that, among the various things that are called "rights," claim-rights are those for whom the Principle of Correlatives holds by definition of "a right." On this interpretation, instantiations of the Principle of Correlatives would be analytic truths. In chapter 11 I argue that this is a misinterpretation of Hohfeld. Of course, one could introduce such a concept and call it a concept of rights; but that would not be the same as our concept of a claim-right.
    • Kramer, M.H.1
  • 8
    • 84883905039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The recent "Restorative Justice" movement should be mentioned here. The criminal justice system, as it normally functions in the United States, charges the accused with having committed a crime against the state; if he is convicted, the state then punishes him. The Restorative Justice movement tries to bring the breach of moral relationship between the accused and the victim back into the picture, both in the trial stage and in the subsequent punishment and rehabilitation stage
    • The recent "Restorative Justice" movement should be mentioned here. The criminal justice system, as it normally functions in the United States, charges the accused with having committed a crime against the state; if he is convicted, the state then punishes him. The Restorative Justice movement tries to bring the breach of moral relationship between the accused and the victim back into the picture, both in the trial stage and in the subsequent punishment and rehabilitation stage.
  • 9
    • 84884053309 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An influential telling of the story is Leo Strauss's Natural Right and History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953). The story, as Strauss tells it, is of what he calls "the classic theory of natural right" losing ground to what he calls "the modern theory of natural right[s]
    • An influential telling of the story is Leo Strauss's Natural Right and History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953). The story, as Strauss tells it, is of what he calls "the classic theory of natural right" losing ground to what he calls "the modern theory of natural right[s]."
  • 10
    • 84884105239 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Concept of Rights in Christian Moral Discourse
    • in Michael Cromartie, ed., A Preserving Grace: Protestants, Catholics, and Natural Law, Grand Rapids: Eerdmans
    • Joan Lockwood O'Donovan, "The Concept of Rights in Christian Moral Discourse," in Michael Cromartie, ed., A Preserving Grace: Protestants, Catholics, and Natural Law (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1997), p. 145.
    • (1997) , pp. 145
    • O'Donovan, J.L.1
  • 11
    • 84883927610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also S. th. II-II, q. 57, art. 1, resp
    • See also S. th. II-II, q. 57, art. 1, resp.
  • 12
    • 84884068818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These points, about the relation of justice to equality, are developed more fully in Joel Feinberg, "Noncomparative Justice," Philosophical Review 83, issue 3 (July 1974). Oliver O'Donovan also argues against justice as equality in chapter 3, "Justice and Equality," in his The Ways of Judgment (Grand Rapids: Wm. B. Eerdmans, 2005)
    • These points, about the relation of justice to equality, are developed more fully in Joel Feinberg, "Noncomparative Justice," Philosophical Review 83, issue 3 (July 1974). Oliver O'Donovan also argues against justice as equality in chapter 3, "Justice and Equality," in his The Ways of Judgment (Grand Rapids: Wm. B. Eerdmans, 2005).
  • 13
    • 84883990239 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chapter 12 in Launching Liberalism: On Lockean Political Philosophy, Lawrence: University Press of Kansas
    • Chapter 12 in Launching Liberalism: On Lockean Political Philosophy (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 2002), p. 317.
    • (2002) , pp. 317
  • 14
    • 0041363067 scopus 로고
    • Justice and Rights
    • in Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • "Justice and Rights," in Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1977), p. 182.
    • (1977) , pp. 182
  • 15
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Theory of Justice
    • rev. ed., Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, rev. ed. (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1999), p. 447.
    • (1999) , pp. 447
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 16
    • 84883971770 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This footnote was called to my attention by Edward Song. I should note that Rawls's position in his later Political Liberalism is explicitly and deliberately not a natural rights position
    • This footnote was called to my attention by Edward Song. I should note that Rawls's position in his later Political Liberalism is explicitly and deliberately not a natural rights position.
  • 17
    • 84884100931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In his Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988), Alasdair MacIntyre also speaks about "different and incompatible conceptions of justice" (ix) and of "conflicting conceptions of justice" (1). He argues, for example, that in the ancient Greeks there was a conflict between the justice of excellence and the justice of effectiveness. What MacIntyre has in mind by conflicting conceptions of justice is what I will call conflicting understandings of the contours of justice-that is, conflicting understandings of which sorts of things are just and which are unjust. The conflict of conceptions that I explore is not a conflict about the contours of justice but a conflict prior to that-a conflict over how we should think about justice
    • In his Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988), Alasdair MacIntyre also speaks about "different and incompatible conceptions of justice" (ix) and of "conflicting conceptions of justice" (1). He argues, for example, that in the ancient Greeks there was a conflict between the justice of excellence and the justice of effectiveness. What MacIntyre has in mind by conflicting conceptions of justice is what I will call conflicting understandings of the contours of justice-that is, conflicting understandings of which sorts of things are just and which are unjust. The conflict of conceptions that I explore is not a conflict about the contours of justice but a conflict prior to that-a conflict over how we should think about justice.
  • 18
    • 84884036217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The passage comes from Book I of Ulpian's Rules and is to be found in the first section of Book One of Justinian's Digest. A recent translation is by Alan Watson, The Digest of Justinian (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press; 1985). Here is Watson's translation of the sentence and the sentence following: "Justice is a steady and enduring will to render unto everyone his right. The basic principles of right are: to live honorably, not to harm any other person, to render to each his own" (no pagination)
    • The passage comes from Book I of Ulpian's Rules and is to be found in the first section of Book One of Justinian's Digest. A recent translation is by Alan Watson, The Digest of Justinian (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press; 1985). Here is Watson's translation of the sentence and the sentence following: "Justice is a steady and enduring will to render unto everyone his right. The basic principles of right are: to live honorably, not to harm any other person, to render to each his own" (no pagination).
  • 19
    • 84884124009 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Where proper English grammar requires "his or her," and where old-fashioned English grammar would allow "his," I instead use "their." Thus, instead of "render to each his or her ius" I say, "render to each their ius." I acknowledge that this use of "their," though becoming more common, is still a grammatical barbarism. But in our present linguistic situation I cannot say "his" nor, for the counterpart reason, can I say " her"; and the constant repetition of "his or her" would be tedious
    • Where proper English grammar requires "his or her," and where old-fashioned English grammar would allow "his," I instead use "their." Thus, instead of "render to each his or her ius" I say, "render to each their ius." I acknowledge that this use of "their," though becoming more common, is still a grammatical barbarism. But in our present linguistic situation I cannot say "his" nor, for the counterpart reason, can I say " her"; and the constant repetition of "his or her" would be tedious.
  • 20
    • 84884066417 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It would appear that I am disagreeing here with the famous analysis of rights by W. N. Hohfeld in Fundamental Legal Conceptions (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1919). On Hohfeld's view, the essential logical structure of a right is not a relation of a person or social entity to a good of that person or entity, but the relation of one person to another person with respect to some act. In chapter 6 we will see that these two approaches coalesce
    • It would appear that I am disagreeing here with the famous analysis of rights by W. N. Hohfeld in Fundamental Legal Conceptions (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1919). On Hohfeld's view, the essential logical structure of a right is not a relation of a person or social entity to a good of that person or entity, but the relation of one person to another person with respect to some act. In chapter 6 we will see that these two approaches coalesce.
  • 21
    • 84884118333 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A second type of exception will be noted at the beginning of chapter 6
    • A second type of exception will be noted at the beginning of chapter 6.
  • 22
    • 84883913877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Or perhaps the right analysis is not that the seat is the good in question but, rather, receiving that which one has purchased
    • Or perhaps the right analysis is not that the seat is the good in question but, rather, receiving that which one has purchased.
  • 23
    • 84884039353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As we shall see in chapter 11, the English word "right" is used not only for legitimate claims but also for permissions
    • As we shall see in chapter 11, the English word "right" is used not only for legitimate claims but also for permissions.
  • 24
    • 84922110824 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I discuss these matters in my essay, "Does Forgiveness Undermine Justice?" in Andrew Dole and Andrew Chignell, eds., God and the Ethics of Belief
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • I discuss these matters in my essay, "Does Forgiveness Undermine Justice?" in Andrew Dole and Andrew Chignell, eds., God and the Ethics of Belief (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), pp. 219-47.
    • (2005) , pp. 219-247
  • 25
    • 84884120966 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I will use the F. M. Cornford translation (New York: Oxford University Press, 1945). Page references to Plato are incorporated into my text; I first give the Cornford page, and then the page from the Stephanus edition in which the passage can be found in the original
    • I will use the F. M. Cornford translation (New York: Oxford University Press, 1945). Page references to Plato are incorporated into my text; I first give the Cornford page, and then the page from the Stephanus edition in which the passage can be found in the original.
  • 26
    • 84883947716 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "So now at last, son of Ariston, said I [Socrates], your commonwealth is established. The next thing is to bring to bear upon it all the light you can get from any quarter, . . . in the hope that we may see where justice is to be found in it and where injustice" (120; 427d)
    • "So now at last, son of Ariston, said I [Socrates], your commonwealth is established. The next thing is to bring to bear upon it all the light you can get from any quarter, . . . in the hope that we may see where justice is to be found in it and where injustice" (120; 427d).
  • 27
    • 84884053599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. the following passage from Leo Strauss: "The premodern natural law doctrines taught the duties of man; if they paid any attention at all to his rights, they conceived of them as essentially derivative from his duties. As has frequently been observed, in the course of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries a much greater emphasis was put on rights than ever had been done before. One may speak of a shift of emphasis from natural duties to natural rights. But quantitative changes of this character become intelligible only when they are seen against the background of a qualitative and fundamental change, not to say that such quantitative changes always become possible only by virtue of a qualitative and fundamental change. The fundamental change [was] from an orientation by natural duties to an orientation by natural rights." (Natural Right and History, p. 182)
    • Cf. the following passage from Leo Strauss: "The premodern natural law doctrines taught the duties of man; if they paid any attention at all to his rights, they conceived of them as essentially derivative from his duties. As has frequently been observed, in the course of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries a much greater emphasis was put on rights than ever had been done before. One may speak of a shift of emphasis from natural duties to natural rights. But quantitative changes of this character become intelligible only when they are seen against the background of a qualitative and fundamental change, not to say that such quantitative changes always become possible only by virtue of a qualitative and fundamental change. The fundamental change [was] from an orientation by natural duties to an orientation by natural rights." (Natural Right and History, p. 182).
  • 28
    • 84883976515 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the discussion by AlasdairMacIntyre in chapter 2 of Whose Justice? Which Rationality?
    • See the discussion by AlasdairMacIntyre in chapter 2 of Whose Justice? Which Rationality?
  • 29
    • 61149562827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Desire of the Nations
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • The Desire of the Nations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1996), p. 262.
    • (1996) , pp. 262
  • 30
    • 0003913651 scopus 로고
    • After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory
    • Notre Dame, University of Notre Dame Press
    • Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (Notre Dame, University of Notre Dame Press, 1981), pp. 66-67.
    • (1981) , pp. 66-67
    • MacIntyre, A.1
  • 31
    • 84884002713 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The article was published by Bowdoin College, Brunswick, Maine, as the Charles F. Adams Lecture of February 28, 1983. The passage quoted occurs on p. 12
    • The article was published by Bowdoin College, Brunswick, Maine, as the Charles F. Adams Lecture of February 28, 1983. The passage quoted occurs on p. 12.
  • 32
    • 84883899736 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Are There Any Natural Rights
    • in After Virtue
    • "Are There Any Natural Rights," in After Virtue, pp. 13 and 14.
  • 33
    • 84884053409 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The need for the condition "if Y is the sort of entity that can have rights" is explained in chapter 17. The principle holds for claim-rights, not for permission-rights. And in a situation in which one does not know all the relevant facts, it holds only if we are thinking of obligation not as what one is culpable for not doing but as what one would be culpable for not doing if one knew all the relevant facts; in the terminology that I use, it holds for full-cognition obligation, not for culpability obligation. These issues are discussed in chapter 11. Duties of charity would seem to constitute exceptions to the principle; my discussion in chapter 17 includes an analysis of such duties
    • The need for the condition "if Y is the sort of entity that can have rights" is explained in chapter 17. The principle holds for claim-rights, not for permission-rights. And in a situation in which one does not know all the relevant facts, it holds only if we are thinking of obligation not as what one is culpable for not doing but as what one would be culpable for not doing if one knew all the relevant facts; in the terminology that I use, it holds for full-cognition obligation, not for culpability obligation. These issues are discussed in chapter 11. Duties of charity would seem to constitute exceptions to the principle; my discussion in chapter 17 includes an analysis of such duties.
  • 34
    • 84883999498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The divine command theory is discussed in chapter 12
    • The divine command theory is discussed in chapter 12.
  • 35
    • 84883919347 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This possibility was suggested to me by one of the readers for Princeton University Press
    • This possibility was suggested to me by one of the readers for Princeton University Press.
  • 36
    • 84884081491 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge; Cambridge University Press
    • Cambridge; Cambridge University Press, 1999.
    • (1999)
  • 37
    • 84884053550 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • S. Th. I-II 91.1
    • S. Th. I-II 91.1.
  • 38
    • 84883963324 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The full passage in which the latter definition occurs is this: the rational creature "has a share of the eternal reason, whereby it has a natural inclination to its proper act and end; and this participation of the eternal law in the rational creature is called the natural law" (S. Th. I-II, 91, 2). The main thought in the preceding five paragraphs of text, and all the quotations unless otherwise indicated, are from S. Th. I-II, 91,2
    • The full passage in which the latter definition occurs is this: the rational creature "has a share of the eternal reason, whereby it has a natural inclination to its proper act and end; and this participation of the eternal law in the rational creature is called the natural law" (S. Th. I-II, 91, 2). The main thought in the preceding five paragraphs of text, and all the quotations unless otherwise indicated, are from S. Th. I-II, 91,2.
  • 39
    • 84884089945 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is a good and lengthy chapter on Aquinas's treatment of justice in Eleonore Stump's Aquinas (London and New York, Routledge, 2003). But Stump does not address the question I am asking
    • There is a good and lengthy chapter on Aquinas's treatment of justice in Eleonore Stump's Aquinas (London and New York, Routledge, 2003). But Stump does not address the question I am asking.
  • 40
    • 84884076862 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I will tell the story as it has been told by those who believe it, namely, in terms of natural rights rather inherent rights
    • I will tell the story as it has been told by those who believe it, namely, in terms of natural rights rather inherent rights.
  • 41
    • 84883935570 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • George is among those who suspects-or charges-the commission of this genetic fallacy. In response to Joan Lockwood O'Donovan's telling of the narrative, he says that "surely no mere historical connection is sufficient to establish that those who reject possessive individualism cannot now deploy the language of rights without thereby importing into their thought features of that philosophy that mark it as antithetical to the value of community and other important human goods. Here, I would suggest, only a logical (or, at a minimum, a very strong psychological) connection will suffice." Robert P. George, "A Response," in Michael Cromartie, ed., A Preserving Grace, Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans
    • Robert P. George is among those who suspects-or charges-the commission of this genetic fallacy. In response to Joan Lockwood O'Donovan's telling of the narrative, he says that "surely no mere historical connection is sufficient to establish that those who reject possessive individualism cannot now deploy the language of rights without thereby importing into their thought features of that philosophy that mark it as antithetical to the value of community and other important human goods. Here, I would suggest, only a logical (or, at a minimum, a very strong psychological) connection will suffice." Robert P. George, "A Response," in Michael Cromartie, ed., A Preserving Grace (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, 1997), p. 157.
    • (1997) , pp. 157
    • Robert, P.1
  • 42
    • 84883970400 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I base my telling on two main sources: Part Two of Brian Tierney, The Idea of Natural Rights: Studies on Natural Rights, Natural Law and Church Law 1150-1625 (Atlanta, Ga.: Scholars Press, 1997), and John Moorman, A History of the Franciscan Order: From Its Origins to the Year 1517 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1968). There is also some helpful information in chapter 2 of Anabel S. Brett, Liberty, Right and Nature: Individual Rights in Later Scholastic Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997)
    • I base my telling on two main sources: Part Two of Brian Tierney, The Idea of Natural Rights: Studies on Natural Rights, Natural Law and Church Law 1150-1625 (Atlanta, Ga.: Scholars Press, 1997), and John Moorman, A History of the Franciscan Order: From Its Origins to the Year 1517 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1968). There is also some helpful information in chapter 2 of Anabel S. Brett, Liberty, Right and Nature: Individual Rights in Later Scholastic Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997).
  • 43
    • 84883956446 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Proprietas, possessio, ususfructus, ius utendi, simplex usus facti
    • Proprietas, possessio, ususfructus, ius utendi, simplex usus facti.
  • 44
    • 84883982951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nicholas is virtually quoting here from Bonaventure's Defense of the Mendicants (Apologia pauperum) of around ten years earlier. In sec. 11 Bonaventure says: "there are four possible relations to temporal goods: property, possession, usufruct, and simple use. The life of mortals may be sustained without the first three, but the last is a necessity. There can, then, be no profession of renunciation of temporal things which extends to their use." Quoted from the translation in O. O'Donovan and J. L. O'Donovan, From Irenaeus to Grotius: A Sourcebook in Christian Political Thought 100-1625, Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans
    • Nicholas is virtually quoting here from Bonaventure's Defense of the Mendicants (Apologia pauperum) of around ten years earlier. In sec. 11 Bonaventure says: "there are four possible relations to temporal goods: property, possession, usufruct, and simple use. The life of mortals may be sustained without the first three, but the last is a necessity. There can, then, be no profession of renunciation of temporal things which extends to their use." Quoted from the translation in O. O'Donovan and J. L. O'Donovan, From Irenaeus to Grotius: A Sourcebook in Christian Political Thought 100-1625 (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, 1999), p. 318.
    • (1999) , pp. 318
  • 45
    • 84884089664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bonaventure had anticipated Ockham's position in his Defense of the Mendicants of around 1269. After distinguishing four kinds of community of goods-those "derived from the right of natural necessity," those "derived from the right of brotherly love," those "derived from the right of worldly civil society," and those "derived from the right of ecclesiastical endowment"-he argued that the Franciscans had renounced the latter two but not the first two. The first cannot be renounced, because it "derives from the right that naturally belongs to man as God's image and noblest creature." The second "absolutely may not be renounced. It derives from a right poured into us by God." Quotations from the translation in O'Donovan and O'Donovan, From Irenaeus to Grotius, p. 317
    • Bonaventure had anticipated Ockham's position in his Defense of the Mendicants of around 1269. After distinguishing four kinds of community of goods-those "derived from the right of natural necessity," those "derived from the right of brotherly love," those "derived from the right of worldly civil society," and those "derived from the right of ecclesiastical endowment"-he argued that the Franciscans had renounced the latter two but not the first two. The first cannot be renounced, because it "derives from the right that naturally belongs to man as God's image and noblest creature." The second "absolutely may not be renounced. It derives from a right poured into us by God." Quotations from the translation in O'Donovan and O'Donovan, From Irenaeus to Grotius, p. 317.
  • 46
    • 84884031988 scopus 로고
    • I am especially indebted here to Part One of Tierney, Idea of Natural Rights, and to pp. 51-57 of Charles J. Reid Jr., "The Canonistic Contribution to the Western Rights Tradition: An Historical Inquiry," in Boston College Law Review 33 no. 1, December
    • I am especially indebted here to Part One of Tierney, Idea of Natural Rights, and to pp. 51-57 of Charles J. Reid Jr., "The Canonistic Contribution to the Western Rights Tradition: An Historical Inquiry," in Boston College Law Review 33 no. 1 (December 1991): 37-92.
    • (1991) , pp. 37-92
  • 47
    • 84884082211 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tierney goes on to say the following: "Villey's argument has been widely and uncritically accepted. Nowadays Ockham is often regarded as the originator of modern rights theories, at least among scholars who seek an origin for them before the seventeenth century" (14)
    • Tierney goes on to say the following: "Villey's argument has been widely and uncritically accepted. Nowadays Ockham is often regarded as the originator of modern rights theories, at least among scholars who seek an origin for them before the seventeenth century" (14).
  • 48
    • 84884000423 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here is one of Tierney's descriptions of the general structure of Villey's argument: "Villey has devised a sort of Manichean universe. There is an Aristotelian thought-world, full of light and sweet reason, and an Ockhamist thought-world, where all is darkness and blind will. The good theory of objective right can flourish only in the first thought-world, the bad theory of subjective rights only in the second. When clear-cut affirmations of individual rights are found in texts before Ockham they have to be dismissed as exceptions or aberrations or mere misunderstandings of vulgar persons who were too ignorant to attach precise meanings to the terms they used in day-to-day discourse" (30-31)
    • Here is one of Tierney's descriptions of the general structure of Villey's argument: "Villey has devised a sort of Manichean universe. There is an Aristotelian thought-world, full of light and sweet reason, and an Ockhamist thought-world, where all is darkness and blind will. The good theory of objective right can flourish only in the first thought-world, the bad theory of subjective rights only in the second. When clear-cut affirmations of individual rights are found in texts before Ockham they have to be dismissed as exceptions or aberrations or mere misunderstandings of vulgar persons who were too ignorant to attach precise meanings to the terms they used in day-to-day discourse" (30-31).
  • 49
    • 84883934550 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I have borrowed the term "crisis" from Leo Strauss, who speaks of "the crisis of modern natural right
    • I have borrowed the term "crisis" from Leo Strauss, who speaks of "the crisis of modern natural right."
  • 50
    • 84944581458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Natural Law and Perfect Community: Contributions of Christian Platonism to Political Theory
    • January
    • Joan Lockwood O'Donovan, "Natural Law and Perfect Community: Contributions of Christian Platonism to Political Theory," Modern Theology 14, no. 1 (January 1998): 20.
    • (1998) Modern Theology , vol.14 , Issue.1 , pp. 20
    • O'Donovan, J.L.1
  • 51
    • 84884068817 scopus 로고
    • In 5 Journal of Law and Religion, 65
    • In 5 Journal of Law and Religion, 65 (1987).
    • (1987)
  • 52
    • 84884096500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.
    • (1999)
  • 53
    • 84883999051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "The Concept of Rights in Christian Moral Discourse," in Cromartie, A Preserving Grace, p. 146. Cf. Richard Tuck, in Natural Rights Theories, p. 2: "Because the meaning of a term such as a right is theory-dependent, . . . we have to be sure about what role the term played in the various theories about politics which engage our attention." "The elucidation of a complex notion such as a right requires a fairly full account of the possible theories about politics which involve the concept."
    • "The Concept of Rights in Christian Moral Discourse," in Cromartie, A Preserving Grace, p. 146. Cf. Richard Tuck, in Natural Rights Theories, p. 2: "Because the meaning of a term such as a right is theory-dependent, . . . we have to be sure about what role the term played in the various theories about politics which engage our attention." "The elucidation of a complex notion such as a right requires a fairly full account of the possible theories about politics which involve the concept."
  • 54
    • 84884064554 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In writing this part of the chapter I have been aided enormously by the extensive historical and bibliographical knowledge of John J. Witte Jr., of the Emory Law School. Those who want a concise history of the idea of rights that, for the most part, ignores the polemic that is my concern here and is based on the latest scholarship should see chapter 1, "Rights," of his God's Joust and God's Justice: Law and Politics in the Western Tradition (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, 2006)
    • In writing this part of the chapter I have been aided enormously by the extensive historical and bibliographical knowledge of John J. Witte Jr., of the Emory Law School. Those who want a concise history of the idea of rights that, for the most part, ignores the polemic that is my concern here and is based on the latest scholarship should see chapter 1, "Rights," of his God's Joust and God's Justice: Law and Politics in the Western Tradition (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, 2006).
  • 55
    • 84884043210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See note 7 above
    • See note 7 above.
  • 56
    • 84884067672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • December 1994. Reid's argument is further fleshed out in, "Roots of a Democratic Church Polity in the History of Canon Law: the Case of Elections in the Church," CLSA Proceedings 6
    • December 1994. Reid's argument is further fleshed out in, "Roots of a Democratic Church Polity in the History of Canon Law: the Case of Elections in the Church," CLSA Proceedings 6 (1998): 150-78.
    • (1998) , pp. 150-178
  • 57
    • 84884001966 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • And it remained commonplace for quite some time after Ockham. For example, Conrad Summenhart, writing about 1500, after remarking that "ius" can mean law (lex), says that "in another sense ius is taken to be the same as a power as when we say a father has a right (ius) as regards his son, or a king as regards his subjects, and men have a right (ius) in their things and possessions" (quoted in Tierney, Idea of Natural Rights, 109)
    • And it remained commonplace for quite some time after Ockham. For example, Conrad Summenhart, writing about 1500, after remarking that "ius" can mean law (lex), says that "in another sense ius is taken to be the same as a power as when we say a father has a right (ius) as regards his son, or a king as regards his subjects, and men have a right (ius) in their things and possessions" (quoted in Tierney, Idea of Natural Rights, 109).
  • 58
    • 84884111010 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rights in Thirteenth-Century Canon Law, 109-36
    • Rights in Thirteenth-Century Canon Law, 109-36.
  • 59
    • 84883926410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In A Ennio Cortese, ed. D. Maffei, Rome
    • In A Ennio Cortese, ed. D. Maffei (Rome, 2001), vol. 1, pp. 506-35.
    • (2001) , vol.1 , pp. 506-535
  • 60
    • 84883992874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A full discussion of the extent to which the Roman jurists employed the concept of a subjective right would look beyond their use of the term "ius" to consider their use of such other terms as "libertas," "dominium," "potestas," and "facultas." On this point, see Witte, God's Joust
    • A full discussion of the extent to which the Roman jurists employed the concept of a subjective right would look beyond their use of the term "ius" to consider their use of such other terms as "libertas," "dominium," "potestas," and "facultas." On this point, see Witte, God's Joust.
  • 61
    • 84884082905 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Donahue finds twenty-five occurrences of "ius naturale" in the Digest. In one instance it clearly refer to a subjective right; in twenty, it clearly refers to objective right; in four, it is ambiguous
    • Donahue finds twenty-five occurrences of "ius naturale" in the Digest. In one instance it clearly refer to a subjective right; in twenty, it clearly refers to objective right; in four, it is ambiguous.
  • 62
    • 84883975951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Recall the point made by Alasdair MacIntyre in a passage quoted in the preceding chapter: a society may ascribe and claim rights even though it lacks the vocabulary of rights
    • Recall the point made by Alasdair MacIntyre in a passage quoted in the preceding chapter: a society may ascribe and claim rights even though it lacks the vocabulary of rights.
  • 63
    • 84884087218 scopus 로고
    • I am quoting from St. John Chrysostom: On Wealth and Poverty, trans. Catharine P. Roth, Crestwood, N.Y.: St. Vladimir's Press
    • I am quoting from St. John Chrysostom: On Wealth and Poverty, trans. Catharine P. Roth (Crestwood, N.Y.: St. Vladimir's Press, 1984), pp. 49-55.
    • (1984) , pp. 49-55
  • 64
    • 0002164621 scopus 로고
    • Ownership: Early Christian Teaching
    • Maryknoll, N.Y.: Orbis Books
    • Charles Avila, Ownership: Early Christian Teaching (Maryknoll, N.Y.: Orbis Books, 1983), p. 50.
    • (1983) , pp. 50
    • Avila, C.1
  • 65
    • 84883994727 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I think there is reason to believe that this was also Locke's view: subjective natural rights are grounded in objective divine law. If so, then the story about origins becomes complicated indeed. Leo Strauss is completely oblivious to the possibility that Locke was in this way carrying on a tradition rather than subverting it. Strauss says that "Locke's teaching on property, and therewith his whole political philosophy, are revolutionary not only with regard to the biblical tradition but with regard to the philosophical tradition as well. Through the shift of emphasis from natural duties or obligations to natural rights, the individual, the ego, has become the center and origin of the moral world . . ." (Natural Right and History, p. 248)
    • I think there is reason to believe that this was also Locke's view: subjective natural rights are grounded in objective divine law. If so, then the story about origins becomes complicated indeed. Leo Strauss is completely oblivious to the possibility that Locke was in this way carrying on a tradition rather than subverting it. Strauss says that "Locke's teaching on property, and therewith his whole political philosophy, are revolutionary not only with regard to the biblical tradition but with regard to the philosophical tradition as well. Through the shift of emphasis from natural duties or obligations to natural rights, the individual, the ego, has become the center and origin of the moral world . . ." (Natural Right and History, p. 248).
  • 66
    • 84883923578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Those who want a theory and rationale for treating the various "books" of the Bible as parts of a single book, The Bible, should see my Divine Discourse (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1995), and my essay, "The Unity behind the Canon" in C. Helmer and C. Landmesser, One Scripture or Many, Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Those who want a theory and rationale for treating the various "books" of the Bible as parts of a single book, The Bible, should see my Divine Discourse (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; 1995), and my essay, "The Unity behind the Canon" in C. Helmer and C. Landmesser, One Scripture or Many (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), pp. 217-32.
    • (2004) , pp. 217-232
  • 67
    • 84884075918 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.
    • (1996)
  • 68
    • 84883920802 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The expression "going straight," said of a reformed criminal, captures precisely what I understand to be the root sense of the term
    • The expression "going straight," said of a reformed criminal, captures precisely what I understand to be the root sense of the term.
  • 69
    • 84883945825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998, p. 41.
    • (1998) , pp. 41
  • 70
    • 84883989303 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On this use of "true," see my essay, "True Words," in Alan G. Padgett and Patrick R. Keifert, But Is It All True? The Bible and the Question of Truth, Grand Rapids, Mich.: Wm. B. Eerdmans
    • On this use of "true," see my essay, "True Words," in Alan G. Padgett and Patrick R. Keifert, But Is It All True? The Bible and the Question of Truth (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Wm. B. Eerdmans, 2006), pp. 34-43.
    • (2006) , pp. 34-43
  • 71
    • 84883982549 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The passage is translated as follows in the NRSV: "Hate evil and love good, and establish justice in the gate
    • The passage is translated as follows in the NRSV: "Hate evil and love good, and establish justice in the gate."
  • 72
    • 84884112093 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The passage reads thus in the NRSV: Cease to do evil, / learn to do good; / seek justice, / rescue the oppressed, / defend the orphan, / plead for the widow
    • The passage reads thus in the NRSV: Cease to do evil, / learn to do good; / seek justice, / rescue the oppressed, / defend the orphan, / plead for the widow.
  • 73
    • 84883948251 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here is the NRSV rendering: And I will restore your judges as at the first, / and your counselors as at the beginning. / Afterward you shall be called the city of righteousness, / the faithful city. / Zion shall be redeemed by justice, / and those in her who repent, by righteousness
    • Here is the NRSV rendering: And I will restore your judges as at the first, / and your counselors as at the beginning. / Afterward you shall be called the city of righteousness, / the faithful city. / Zion shall be redeemed by justice, / and those in her who repent, by righteousness.
  • 74
    • 84884032621 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Isaiah 59:4: No one brings suit justly, / no one goes to law honestly, / they rely on empty pleas, / conceiving mischief and begetting iniquity
    • Cf. Isaiah 59:4: No one brings suit justly, / no one goes to law honestly, / they rely on empty pleas, / conceiving mischief and begetting iniquity.
  • 75
    • 84884100240 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The NRSV has "righteousness" instead of "rectitude."
    • The NRSV has "righteousness" instead of "rectitude."
  • 76
    • 84884104088 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In their emphasis on the widows, the orphans, the sojourners, and the poor, Israel's writers were not unique in the ancient Near East. For a good summary, see Enrique Nardoni, Rise Up, O Judge, Peabody, Mass.: Hendrickson
    • In their emphasis on the widows, the orphans, the sojourners, and the poor, Israel's writers were not unique in the ancient Near East. For a good summary, see Enrique Nardoni, Rise Up, O Judge (Peabody, Mass.: Hendrickson, 2004).
    • (2004)
  • 77
    • 84883925489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Only a handful of Old Testament passages cite all four members of the quartet of the vulnerable, one of those being Zechariah 7:9-10. What is also interesting about this passage is the clear distinction it makes between rendering true juridical judgments and treating the vulnerable with justice. "Thus says the Lord of hosts: Render true judgments, show kindness and mercy to one another; do not oppress the widow, the orphan, the alien, or the poor."
    • Only a handful of Old Testament passages cite all four members of the quartet of the vulnerable, one of those being Zechariah 7:9-10. What is also interesting about this passage is the clear distinction it makes between rendering true juridical judgments and treating the vulnerable with justice. "Thus says the Lord of hosts: Render true judgments, show kindness and mercy to one another; do not oppress the widow, the orphan, the alien, or the poor."
  • 78
    • 84884009739 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Psalm 147:6: "The Lord lifts up the downtrodden, he casts the wicked to the ground."
    • Psalm 147:6: "The Lord lifts up the downtrodden, he casts the wicked to the ground."
  • 79
    • 84883989919 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the Wisdom literature, one now and then comes across the assumption that some poverty is the fault of the poor themselves; they are lazy. For example, Proverbs 6:6-11, which begins with the well-known couplet, "Go to the ant, you lazybones; consider its ways and be wise."
    • In the Wisdom literature, one now and then comes across the assumption that some poverty is the fault of the poor themselves; they are lazy. For example, Proverbs 6:6-11, which begins with the well-known couplet, "Go to the ant, you lazybones; consider its ways and be wise."
  • 80
    • 84884029788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Deut. 15:15
    • See also Deut. 15:15.
  • 81
    • 84883937371 scopus 로고
    • I discuss in some detail this idea of doing something as a memorial in "The Remembrance of Things (Not) Past," in Thomas Flint, ed., Christian Philosophy, Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press
    • I discuss in some detail this idea of doing something as a memorial in "The Remembrance of Things (Not) Past," in Thomas Flint, ed., Christian Philosophy (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1990).
    • (1990)
  • 82
    • 84884012939 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The counterpart, naturally, is that God is displeased by injustice-angered, even: "The Lord saw it, and it displeased him, that there was no justice" (Isaiah 59:15)
    • The counterpart, naturally, is that God is displeased by injustice-angered, even: "The Lord saw it, and it displeased him, that there was no justice" (Isaiah 59:15).
  • 83
    • 84884117119 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Though Novak, as I mentioned, discusses these issues under the rubric of natural law, his definition of "natural law" makes no reference to legislation. Natural law, he suggests, consists of "those norms of human conduct that are universally valid and discernible by all rational persons" (Natural Law in Judaism, p. 1)
    • Though Novak, as I mentioned, discusses these issues under the rubric of natural law, his definition of "natural law" makes no reference to legislation. Natural law, he suggests, consists of "those norms of human conduct that are universally valid and discernible by all rational persons" (Natural Law in Judaism, p. 1).
  • 84
    • 84883951762 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For another example, see Psalm 106:6-7. It is commonly thought that Psalm 51 is a psalm of David after he had been convicted by the prophet Nathan of wrongdoing in the Bathsheba episode. What many commentators note is that David is willing to confess that he has wronged God but appears unwilling to confess that he has wronged Bathsheba and her husband
    • For another example, see Psalm 106:6-7. It is commonly thought that Psalm 51 is a psalm of David after he had been convicted by the prophet Nathan of wrongdoing in the Bathsheba episode. What many commentators note is that David is willing to confess that he has wronged God but appears unwilling to confess that he has wronged Bathsheba and her husband.
  • 85
    • 84884046470 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988.
    • (1988)
  • 86
    • 84883941660 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is a permission-right rather than a claim-right; the distinction will be explained in chapter 11
    • This is a permission-right rather than a claim-right; the distinction will be explained in chapter 11.
  • 87
    • 84883909147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In chapter 16 I discuss what constitutes the image of God
    • In chapter 16 I discuss what constitutes the image of God.
  • 88
    • 84884055321 scopus 로고
    • Nashville: Abingdon Press
    • Nashville: Abingdon Press, 1991.
    • (1991)
  • 89
    • 84884033014 scopus 로고
    • Translated by Philip S. Watson, London: SPCK
    • Translated by Philip S. Watson (London: SPCK, 1953).
    • (1953)
  • 90
    • 84883901958 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. p. 250: For Judaism, "love to God is the deepest and most inward expression of man's relation to God which the Old Testament knows. Even so, fellowship between God and man is based on justice and regulated by the Law. Nomos is the controlling idea, and love has its place within the legal framework. Christianity, however, effects a complete revolution." See also pp. 70-71
    • Cf. p. 250: For Judaism, "love to God is the deepest and most inward expression of man's relation to God which the Old Testament knows. Even so, fellowship between God and man is based on justice and regulated by the Law. Nomos is the controlling idea, and love has its place within the legal framework. Christianity, however, effects a complete revolution." See also pp. 70-71.
  • 91
    • 84883963142 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Passages such as this make it pretty clear that the conception of justice Nygren was working with was that of justice as grounded in inherent rights. In what way his argument would have to be revised if he were thinking in terms of justice as right order is a nice question
    • Passages such as this make it pretty clear that the conception of justice Nygren was working with was that of justice as grounded in inherent rights. In what way his argument would have to be revised if he were thinking in terms of justice as right order is a nice question.
  • 92
    • 84883902669 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Tal Brewer called this point to my attention. A few pages back, I separated Nygren's argument that agape does not aim to do what justice requires from his argument that agape is in no way motivated by recognition of the worth of persons. Nygren was probably not making that separation
    • Tal Brewer called this point to my attention. A few pages back, I separated Nygren's argument that agape does not aim to do what justice requires from his argument that agape is in no way motivated by recognition of the worth of persons. Nygren was probably not making that separation.
  • 93
    • 84884019167 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nygren acknowledges that John does speak often and freely of our love for God. This, he says, constitutes "an incipient weakening" (153) of the Agape-motif. It contains "perils . . . for the nature and content of the Christian Agape motif"; it harbors the "danger that the unmotivated nature of Divine love may be insufficiently recognised" (153). It is especially in this forthright elevation of Paul and demotion of John that one sees Nygren's pronounced Marcionite tendencies
    • Nygren acknowledges that John does speak often and freely of our love for God. This, he says, constitutes "an incipient weakening" (153) of the Agape-motif. It contains "perils . . . for the nature and content of the Christian Agape motif"; it harbors the "danger that the unmotivated nature of Divine love may be insufficiently recognised" (153). It is especially in this forthright elevation of Paul and demotion of John that one sees Nygren's pronounced Marcionite tendencies.
  • 94
    • 84883923284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As I mentioned earlier, retributive rights are permission-rights rather than claim-rights. They have corresponding claim-rights, however. Corresponding to the retributive permission- right to impose hard treatment on the one who wronged one is the claim-right to be free to impose hard treatment
    • As I mentioned earlier, retributive rights are permission-rights rather than claim-rights. They have corresponding claim-rights, however. Corresponding to the retributive permission- right to impose hard treatment on the one who wronged one is the claim-right to be free to impose hard treatment.
  • 95
    • 84883936731 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In my forthcoming Love and Justice, I develop in considerable detail what here I merely indicate
    • In my forthcoming Love and Justice, I develop in considerable detail what here I merely indicate.
  • 96
    • 84883968982 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Outka, Agape
    • See Outka, Agape.
  • 97
    • 84883953938 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In my forthcoming book Love and Justice, I do discuss at some length the intertwinement of love and justice in Romans
    • In my forthcoming book Love and Justice, I do discuss at some length the intertwinement of love and justice in Romans.
  • 98
    • 84883949837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I thank Sue Rozeboom for providing me with a list of all occurrences of dik-stem words in the New Testament, as well as with data from the Septuagint that I will be referring to a bit later
    • I thank Sue Rozeboom for providing me with a list of all occurrences of dik-stem words in the New Testament, as well as with data from the Septuagint that I will be referring to a bit later.
  • 99
    • 84884071995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • San Francisco: HarperCollins
    • San Francisco: HarperCollins, 1996.
    • (1996)
  • 100
    • 84883972655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The passage in Isaiah of which Matthew gives a near-quotation, 42:1-4, goes as follows: Here is my servant, whom I uphold, / My chosen, in whom my soul delights; / I have put my spirit upon him; / he will bring forth justice to the nations. / He will not cry or lift up his voice, / or make it heard in the streets; / a bruised reed he will not break, / and a dimly burning wick he will not quench; / he will faithfully bring forth justice. / He will not grow faint or be crushed / Until he has established justice in the earth
    • The passage in Isaiah of which Matthew gives a near-quotation, 42:1-4, goes as follows: Here is my servant, whom I uphold, / My chosen, in whom my soul delights; / I have put my spirit upon him; / he will bring forth justice to the nations. / He will not cry or lift up his voice, / or make it heard in the streets; / a bruised reed he will not break, / and a dimly burning wick he will not quench; / he will faithfully bring forth justice. / He will not grow faint or be crushed / Until he has established justice in the earth.
  • 101
    • 84884078612 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The NRSV has "righteous."
    • The NRSV has "righteous."
  • 102
    • 84883986870 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The NRSV translates "dikaios" in these two passages as "righteous." That seems to me clearly a mistranslation. Of course Jesus was righteous, or upright. But the point that is relevant when Jesus' execution is spoken of is not that he was of righteous character but that he was innocent of the charges. Furthermore, to translate "dikaios" as "righteous" is to obscure the connection with the passages from Luke's gospel that are cited in the preceding paragraph
    • The NRSV translates "dikaios" in these two passages as "righteous." That seems to me clearly a mistranslation. Of course Jesus was righteous, or upright. But the point that is relevant when Jesus' execution is spoken of is not that he was of righteous character but that he was innocent of the charges. Furthermore, to translate "dikaios" as "righteous" is to obscure the connection with the passages from Luke's gospel that are cited in the preceding paragraph.
  • 103
    • 84883960153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Matthew's citation of Isaiah goes as follows: Land of Zebulun, land of Naphtali, / on the road by the sea, across the Jordan, Galilee of the Gentiles- / the people who sat in darkness have seen a great light, / and for those who sat in the region and shadow of death / light has dawned (Matt. 4:15-16)
    • Matthew's citation of Isaiah goes as follows: Land of Zebulun, land of Naphtali, / on the road by the sea, across the Jordan, Galilee of the Gentiles- / the people who sat in darkness have seen a great light, / and for those who sat in the region and shadow of death / light has dawned (Matt. 4:15-16).
  • 104
    • 84884067804 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jesus does, though, identify himself as Lord (kurios; e.g., John 13:14) and regularly allows himself to be so identified. This would have come to very nearly the same thing as king, basileus
    • Jesus does, though, identify himself as Lord (kurios; e.g., John 13:14) and regularly allows himself to be so identified. This would have come to very nearly the same thing as king, basileus.
  • 105
    • 84883915868 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The narrative as given above follows John 18:33 through 19:22
    • The narrative as given above follows John 18:33 through 19:22.
  • 106
    • 84884037619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The NRSV has "the righteous."
    • The NRSV has "the righteous."
  • 107
    • 84884032749 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is how N. T. Wright, among others, interprets the healings in his Jesus and the Victory of God (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1996). "For a first-century Jew, most if not all of the works of healing . . . could be seen as the restoration to membership in Israel of those who, through sickness or whatever, had been excluded as ritually unclean. The healings thus function in exact parallel with the welcome of sinners, and this, we may be quite sure, was what Jesus himself intended. . . . Jesus' healing miracles must be seen clearly as bestowing the gift of shalom, wholeness, on those who lacked it, bringing not only physical health but renewed membership in the people of YHWH" (191-92)
    • This is how N. T. Wright, among others, interprets the healings in his Jesus and the Victory of God (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1996). "For a first-century Jew, most if not all of the works of healing . . . could be seen as the restoration to membership in Israel of those who, through sickness or whatever, had been excluded as ritually unclean. The healings thus function in exact parallel with the welcome of sinners, and this, we may be quite sure, was what Jesus himself intended. . . . Jesus' healing miracles must be seen clearly as bestowing the gift of shalom, wholeness, on those who lacked it, bringing not only physical health but renewed membership in the people of YHWH" (191-92).
  • 108
    • 84884035943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf., among other such passages, Luke 15:1-2: "Now all the tax collectors and sinners were coming near to listen to him. And the Pharisees and the scribes were grumbling and saying, 'This fellow welcomes sinners and eats with them.' "
    • Cf., among other such passages, Luke 15:1-2: "Now all the tax collectors and sinners were coming near to listen to him. And the Pharisees and the scribes were grumbling and saying, 'This fellow welcomes sinners and eats with them.' "
  • 109
    • 84883986958 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Mark 12:14: "Teacher, we know that you are sincere, and show deference to no one; for you do not regard people with partiality, but teach the way of God in accordance with truth." And Luke 20:21: "Teacher, we know that you are right in what you say and teach, and you show deference to no one, but teach the way of God in accordance with truth."
    • Cf. Mark 12:14: "Teacher, we know that you are sincere, and show deference to no one; for you do not regard people with partiality, but teach the way of God in accordance with truth." And Luke 20:21: "Teacher, we know that you are right in what you say and teach, and you show deference to no one, but teach the way of God in accordance with truth."
  • 110
    • 84883954614 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note the locution "sins against me." This is surely a synonym of "wrongs me."
    • Note the locution "sins against me." This is surely a synonym of "wrongs me."
  • 111
    • 84884068103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chris Eberle called my attention to the need for the latter of the two qualifications. His example was that of a legislative body that confers the right to polygamous marriages on the citizenry, even though it believes, correctly, that polygamous marriages are not a good thing. It does so in order to quiet the clamor
    • Chris Eberle called my attention to the need for the latter of the two qualifications. His example was that of a legislative body that confers the right to polygamous marriages on the citizenry, even though it believes, correctly, that polygamous marriages are not a good thing. It does so in order to quiet the clamor.
  • 112
    • 84884055894 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I assume that one can have a right to a state of affairs that does not presently exist, and hence that there are such states of affairs. Though this is highly controversial among metaphysicians, here is not the place to defend the assumption. Another way to go would be to conceive of states of affairs as entities that can either obtain or not obtain. On that conception, what I am assuming is not that one can have a right to a state of affairs that does not presently exist but to the obtaining of a state of affairs that exists but does not presently obtain
    • I assume that one can have a right to a state of affairs that does not presently exist, and hence that there are such states of affairs. Though this is highly controversial among metaphysicians, here is not the place to defend the assumption. Another way to go would be to conceive of states of affairs as entities that can either obtain or not obtain. On that conception, what I am assuming is not that one can have a right to a state of affairs that does not presently exist but to the obtaining of a state of affairs that exists but does not presently obtain.
  • 113
    • 84883951615 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca: Cornell University Press
    • Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1990.
    • (1990)
  • 114
    • 84884016109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In chapter 17 I make the ordinary concept more precise at a certain point
    • In chapter 17 I make the ordinary concept more precise at a certain point.
  • 115
    • 84883914233 scopus 로고
    • I am using the translation in The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, ed. by Jonathan Barnes, Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • I am using the translation in The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, ed. by Jonathan Barnes (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984).
    • (1984)
  • 116
    • 84884098978 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A good introduction to the issues here is the chapter on "Presentism" in Trenton Merricks's Truth and Ontology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007). Merricks would hold that a good deal of what I say about time in the section above is ontologically indefensible, because every extant theory of time entails the falsehood of at least some of those things. My response is that a condition of adequacy for a theory of time is that it not entail the falsehood of any of these things. My view is that there is not now and never has been an adequate theory of time
    • A good introduction to the issues here is the chapter on "Presentism" in Trenton Merricks's Truth and Ontology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007). Merricks would hold that a good deal of what I say about time in the section above is ontologically indefensible, because every extant theory of time entails the falsehood of at least some of those things. My response is that a condition of adequacy for a theory of time is that it not entail the falsehood of any of these things. My view is that there is not now and never has been an adequate theory of time.
  • 117
    • 52649120537 scopus 로고
    • in an interesting article called to my attention by Kelly Sorenson, finds it important for an understanding of well-being to distinguish, as I do, between a person and the person's life. The use he makes of the distinction is quite different from mine, however. See "Me and My Life," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society
    • Shelly Kagan, in an interesting article called to my attention by Kelly Sorenson, finds it important for an understanding of well-being to distinguish, as I do, between a person and the person's life. The use he makes of the distinction is quite different from mine, however. See "Me and My Life," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 94 (1994): 309-24.
    • (1994) , vol.94 , pp. 309-324
    • Kagan, S.1
  • 118
    • 84884097524 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The best theory of the good presently available, in my judgment, is that developed by Robert Adams in his Finite and Infinite Goods: A Framework for Ethics, Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • The best theory of the good presently available, in my judgment, is that developed by Robert Adams in his Finite and Infinite Goods: A Framework for Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999).
    • (1999)
  • 119
    • 84883923265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is true, for example, of the subtle, thorough, and up-to-date discussion of wellbeing in chapter 2 of Mark C. Murphy's Natural Law and Practical Rationality, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • This is true, for example, of the subtle, thorough, and up-to-date discussion of wellbeing in chapter 2 of Mark C. Murphy's Natural Law and Practical Rationality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001).
    • (2001)
  • 120
    • 84884018084 scopus 로고
    • Well-Being
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • James Griffin, Well-Being (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), pp. 317-18, n. 5.
    • (1986) , Issue.5 , pp. 317-318
    • Griffin, J.1
  • 121
    • 0004275697 scopus 로고
    • The Fragility of Goodness
    • See, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See Martha Nussbaum, The Fragility of Goodness (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), p. 6, n.
    • (1986) , vol.6
    • Nussbaum, M.1
  • 122
    • 84883935381 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle remarks that "those who say that the victim on the rack or the man who falls into great misfortunes is happy if he is good, are, whether they mean to or not, talking nonsense" (Nichomachean Ethics, VII.13; 1153b 19-21). From the context it is clear that what he has in mind is not that they are speaking linguistic nonsense and hence asserting no proposition, but that the proposition they are asserting is patently false
    • Aristotle remarks that "those who say that the victim on the rack or the man who falls into great misfortunes is happy if he is good, are, whether they mean to or not, talking nonsense" (Nichomachean Ethics, VII.13; 1153b 19-21). From the context it is clear that what he has in mind is not that they are speaking linguistic nonsense and hence asserting no proposition, but that the proposition they are asserting is patently false.
  • 123
    • 84884065470 scopus 로고
    • The only dissenter of whom I am aware is John M. Cooper, who proposes translating "eudaimonia" as "flourishing." See his Reason and Human Good in Aristotle, Indianapolis: Hackett
    • The only dissenter of whom I am aware is John M. Cooper, who proposes translating "eudaimonia" as "flourishing." See his Reason and Human Good in Aristotle (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1986).
    • (1986)
  • 124
    • 84883909320 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Annas translates this last phrase as "doing well"; that seems to me definitely the better translation. Morality of Happiness, p. 44
    • Annas translates this last phrase as "doing well"; that seems to me definitely the better translation. Morality of Happiness, p. 44.
  • 125
    • 84884119328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. the following passage from Alasdair MacIntyre, pre-eminent among our present eudaimonists: "What constitutes a good reason for my doing this rather than that, for my acting from this particular desire rather than that, is that my doing this rather than that serves my good, will contrribute to my flourishing qua human being." Dependent Rational Animals (Chicago and LaSalle: Open Court, 1999), p. 86. On page 159 of the same book, MacIntyre argues that once my virtue of generosity is in place, I will find in "gross and urgent need sufficient reason to act." But I will have cultivated the virtue for the above agent-centered reason
    • Cf. the following passage from Alasdair MacIntyre, pre-eminent among our present eudaimonists: "What constitutes a good reason for my doing this rather than that, for my acting from this particular desire rather than that, is that my doing this rather than that serves my good, will contrribute to my flourishing qua human being." Dependent Rational Animals (Chicago and LaSalle: Open Court, 1999), p. 86. On page 159 of the same book, MacIntyre argues that once my virtue of generosity is in place, I will find in "gross and urgent need sufficient reason to act." But I will have cultivated the virtue for the above agent-centered reason.
  • 126
    • 84883907725 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to Annas, the small group of Cyrenaics was the only exception
    • According to Annas, the small group of Cyrenaics was the only exception.
  • 127
    • 84884057837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The hyperbole continues: "The sure signs of raving madness are a bold and threatening look, a gloomy countenance, a grim visage, a rapid pace, restless hands, change of colour, heavy and frequent sighing. The marks of anger are the same: eyes ablaze and glittering, a deep flush over all the face as blood boils up from the vitals, quivering lips, teeth pressed together, bristling hair standing on end, breath drawn in and hissing, the crackle of writhing limbs, groans and bellowing, speech broken off with the words barely uttered, hands struck together too often, feet stamping the ground, the whole body in violent motion 'menacing mighty wrath in mien,' the hideous horrifying face of swollen self-degradation-you would hardly know whether to call the vice hateful or ugly" (I,1; pp. 17-18). In describing anger, Seneca appears to have had his eye on the person who has lost his temper!
    • The hyperbole continues: "The sure signs of raving madness are a bold and threatening look, a gloomy countenance, a grim visage, a rapid pace, restless hands, change of colour, heavy and frequent sighing. The marks of anger are the same: eyes ablaze and glittering, a deep flush over all the face as blood boils up from the vitals, quivering lips, teeth pressed together, bristling hair standing on end, breath drawn in and hissing, the crackle of writhing limbs, groans and bellowing, speech broken off with the words barely uttered, hands struck together too often, feet stamping the ground, the whole body in violent motion 'menacing mighty wrath in mien,' the hideous horrifying face of swollen self-degradation-you would hardly know whether to call the vice hateful or ugly" (I,1; pp. 17-18). In describing anger, Seneca appears to have had his eye on the person who has lost his temper!
  • 128
    • 84883966546 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Diogenes Laertius in Inwood and Gerson, Hellenistic Philosophy, pp. 198-99: "There are also three good states [of the soul], joy, caution, and wish. And joy is opposite to pleasure, being a reasonable elation; and caution to fear, being a reasonable avoidance. For the wise man will not be afraid in any way, but will be cautious. They say that wish is opposite to desire, being a reasonable striving. So just as there are certain passions which are forms of the primary ones, so too there are good states subordinate to the primary; forms of wish are good will, kindliness, acceptance, contentment; forms of caution are respect, sanctity; forms of joy are enjoyment, good spirits, tranquillity."
    • See Diogenes Laertius in Inwood and Gerson, Hellenistic Philosophy, pp. 198-99: "There are also three good states [of the soul], joy, caution, and wish. And joy is opposite to pleasure, being a reasonable elation; and caution to fear, being a reasonable avoidance. For the wise man will not be afraid in any way, but will be cautious. They say that wish is opposite to desire, being a reasonable striving. So just as there are certain passions which are forms of the primary ones, so too there are good states subordinate to the primary; forms of wish are good will, kindliness, acceptance, contentment; forms of caution are respect, sanctity; forms of joy are enjoyment, good spirits, tranquillity."
  • 129
    • 84883939086 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Seneca's Letters to Lucilius, 72, 4-5: "It is those who are still short of perfection whose happiness can be broken off; the joy of a wise man, on the other hand, is a woven fabric, rent by no chance happening and by no change of fortune; at all times and in all places he is at peace. For his joy depends on nothing external and looks for no boon from man or fortune. His happiness is something within himself; it would depart from his soul if it enter in from the outside; it is born there."
    • Cf. Seneca's Letters to Lucilius, 72, 4-5: "It is those who are still short of perfection whose happiness can be broken off; the joy of a wise man, on the other hand, is a woven fabric, rent by no chance happening and by no change of fortune; at all times and in all places he is at peace. For his joy depends on nothing external and looks for no boon from man or fortune. His happiness is something within himself; it would depart from his soul if it enter in from the outside; it is born there."
  • 130
    • 84883944390 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The most thorough discussion of the Stoics on emotion is now Richard Sorabji, Emotion and Peace of Mind: From Stoic Agitation to Christian Temptation
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • The most thorough discussion of the Stoics on emotion is now Richard Sorabji, Emotion and Peace of Mind: From Stoic Agitation to Christian Temptation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).
    • (2000)
  • 131
    • 84884049351 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I will not enter the tangled question of what these "impressions" are. The Stoics uniformly regarded them as not the product of volition; the way they usually speak of them implies that they have propositional content
    • I will not enter the tangled question of what these "impressions" are. The Stoics uniformly regarded them as not the product of volition; the way they usually speak of them implies that they have propositional content.
  • 132
    • 84883934657 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Irwin, "Socratic Paradox," p. 172: "The Stoics assume (with Aristotle) that every good must contribute to happiness, and hence that every good in itself must be a part of happiness."
    • Cf. Irwin, "Socratic Paradox," p. 172: "The Stoics assume (with Aristotle) that every good must contribute to happiness, and hence that every good in itself must be a part of happiness."
  • 133
    • 61049510638 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What exactly these immediate reactions, these pre-emotions (propatheiai), are remained obscure in the Stoics. I am persuaded by an article of Sarah C. Byers that Augustine, mainly in his sermons, advanced beyond the Stoics on this point. See "Augustine and the Cognitive Cause of Stoic 'Preliminary Passions' (Propatheiai)," Journal of the History of Philosophy 41, no. 4, (2003): 433-48. The article was brought to my attention by Eric Gregory
    • What exactly these immediate reactions, these pre-emotions (propatheiai), are remained obscure in the Stoics. I am persuaded by an article of Sarah C. Byers that Augustine, mainly in his sermons, advanced beyond the Stoics on this point. See "Augustine and the Cognitive Cause of Stoic 'Preliminary Passions' (Propatheiai)," Journal of the History of Philosophy 41, no. 4, (2003): 433-48. The article was brought to my attention by Eric Gregory.
  • 134
    • 84884103382 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. de Ira II, 3: "Thus it is that even the bravest man often turns pale as he puts on his armour, that the knees of even the fiercest soldier tremble a little as the signal is given for battle, that a great general's heart is in his mouth before the lines have charged against one another, that the most eloquent orator goes numb at the fingers as he prepares to speak" (p. 44)
    • Cf. de Ira II, 3: "Thus it is that even the bravest man often turns pale as he puts on his armour, that the knees of even the fiercest soldier tremble a little as the signal is given for battle, that a great general's heart is in his mouth before the lines have charged against one another, that the most eloquent orator goes numb at the fingers as he prepares to speak" (p. 44).
  • 135
    • 84883922164 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Diogenes Laertius, in Inwood and Gerson, Hellenistic Philisophy, p. 195
    • Diogenes Laertius, in Inwood and Gerson, Hellenistic Philisophy, p. 195.
  • 136
    • 84883937359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am using the translation by R. W. Dyson published by Cambridge University Press, 1998. Augustine is expressing his skepticism concerning the Stoic claim that the trembling and the pallor are not genuine emotions but only immediate bodily reactions. Cicero's views (along with Carneades's) are cited in Irwin, "Socratic Paradox," p. 153
    • I am using the translation by R. W. Dyson published by Cambridge University Press, 1998. Augustine is expressing his skepticism concerning the Stoic claim that the trembling and the pallor are not genuine emotions but only immediate bodily reactions. Cicero's views (along with Carneades's) are cited in Irwin, "Socratic Paradox," p. 153.
  • 137
    • 84884061269 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bowlin, in Contingency and Fortune, says throughout his book that whereas Aquinas worked with a "functional" view of the virtues, the Stoics did not. That seems to me mistaken. Bowlin's Stoics look more like modern Kantians than like ancient virtue theorists
    • Bowlin, in Contingency and Fortune, says throughout his book that whereas Aquinas worked with a "functional" view of the virtues, the Stoics did not. That seems to me mistaken. Bowlin's Stoics look more like modern Kantians than like ancient virtue theorists.
  • 138
    • 84883913449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Admittedly, some Stoics did apparently take it as true. Consider, for example, Sextus Empiricus's way of speaking of the indifferents: "that which can be used well and badly would be indifferent. Virtue is always used well; vice is always used badly; but health and bodily things can be used sometimes well and sometimes badly, and that is why they would be indifferent." In Inwood and Gerson, Hellenistic Philisophy, p. 256; see also Diogenes Laertius on p. 195
    • Admittedly, some Stoics did apparently take it as true. Consider, for example, Sextus Empiricus's way of speaking of the indifferents: "that which can be used well and badly would be indifferent. Virtue is always used well; vice is always used badly; but health and bodily things can be used sometimes well and sometimes badly, and that is why they would be indifferent." In Inwood and Gerson, Hellenistic Philisophy, p. 256; see also Diogenes Laertius on p. 195.
  • 139
    • 84883982830 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • From de Brevitate Vitae 22.4; quoted by Irwin, "Socratic Paradox," p. 176
    • From de Brevitate Vitae 22.4; quoted by Irwin, "Socratic Paradox," p. 176.
  • 140
    • 84884064243 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the discussion in Irwin, "Socratic Paradox," pp. 160-64; and in Annas, Morality of Happiness, pp. 96-115
    • See the discussion in Irwin, "Socratic Paradox," pp. 160-64; and in Annas, Morality of Happiness, pp. 96-115.
  • 141
    • 84884124585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On this point I am following especially Irwin's discussion in "Socratic Paradox," pp. 164-68
    • On this point I am following especially Irwin's discussion in "Socratic Paradox," pp. 164-68.
  • 142
    • 84883955791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • They themselves were fond of using archery as their example
    • They themselves were fond of using archery as their example.
  • 143
    • 84883912079 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. de Ira III, 34 (p. 109): "Believe me, they are trivial things which make us flare up in a far from trivial way, the sort of things which rouse children to quarrels and brawls. None of those things, which we handle with such ill humour, is serious or important. And there, I tell you, lies the start of your insane anger. You attach great value to little things. 'He wanted to take my inheritance.' 'He denounced me to the man whom I had long been courting for his last will and testament.' 'He fancied my mistress.' "
    • Cf. de Ira III, 34 (p. 109): "Believe me, they are trivial things which make us flare up in a far from trivial way, the sort of things which rouse children to quarrels and brawls. None of those things, which we handle with such ill humour, is serious or important. And there, I tell you, lies the start of your insane anger. You attach great value to little things. 'He wanted to take my inheritance.' 'He denounced me to the man whom I had long been courting for his last will and testament.' 'He fancied my mistress.' "
  • 144
    • 84884069994 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant thought of the moral life primarily in terms of obligation rather than virtue, and thus in terms of will rather than skill; but allowing for those differences, what he says in Section I of Grounding for the Metaphysic of Morals is pure Stoicism: "Even if, by some especially unfortunate fate or by the niggardly provision of stepmotherly nature, [the] will should be wholly lacking in the power to accomplished its purpose . . . yet would it, like a jewel, still shine by its own light as something which has its full value in itself. Its usefulness or fruitlessness can neither augment nor diminish this value." Trans. J. W. Ellington (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981)
    • Kant thought of the moral life primarily in terms of obligation rather than virtue, and thus in terms of will rather than skill; but allowing for those differences, what he says in Section I of Grounding for the Metaphysic of Morals is pure Stoicism: "Even if, by some especially unfortunate fate or by the niggardly provision of stepmotherly nature, [the] will should be wholly lacking in the power to accomplished its purpose . . . yet would it, like a jewel, still shine by its own light as something which has its full value in itself. Its usefulness or fruitlessness can neither augment nor diminish this value." Trans. J. W. Ellington (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981).
  • 145
    • 84884037962 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle was of the view that becoming virtuous is also heavily dependant on fortune, especially the good fortune of living in a virtuous community; Aquinas followed him in this regard. See Bowlin, Contingency and Fortune, 168ff
    • Aristotle was of the view that becoming virtuous is also heavily dependant on fortune, especially the good fortune of living in a virtuous community; Aquinas followed him in this regard. See Bowlin, Contingency and Fortune, 168ff.
  • 146
    • 84884038034 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See especially City of God, XIX, 4. There is a superb analysis of Augustine's thought on this matter in chapters 2 to 4 of JamesWetzel, Augustine and the Limits of Virtue (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992)
    • See especially City of God, XIX, 4. There is a superb analysis of Augustine's thought on this matter in chapters 2 to 4 of JamesWetzel, Augustine and the Limits of Virtue (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992).
  • 147
    • 84884005426 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thus also the Stoic admiration for the icy coldness of the response to the news of the death of his son attributed to Anaxagoras by our sources: "I was already aware that I had begotten a mortal." For the sources, see Nussbaum, Therapy of Desire, p. 363, n. 19
    • Thus also the Stoic admiration for the icy coldness of the response to the news of the death of his son attributed to Anaxagoras by our sources: "I was already aware that I had begotten a mortal." For the sources, see Nussbaum, Therapy of Desire, p. 363, n. 19.
  • 148
    • 84884120193 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bowlin, Contingency and Fortune, p. 206
    • Bowlin, Contingency and Fortune, p. 206.
  • 149
    • 84884050285 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In chapter 1 I noted that though Aquinas thinks of justice as rendering to each what is due him or her, he nowhere gives an account of something's being due a person. (The same is true for MacIntyre's discussion in Dependent Rational Animals.) I think that this lacuna is not accidental
    • In chapter 1 I noted that though Aquinas thinks of justice as rendering to each what is due him or her, he nowhere gives an account of something's being due a person. (The same is true for MacIntyre's discussion in Dependent Rational Animals.) I think that this lacuna is not accidental.
  • 150
    • 84884112943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am using the translation by J. F. Shaw in Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, ed. Philip Schaff, vol. 2 (rpt., Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, 1979)
    • I am using the translation by J. F. Shaw in Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, ed. Philip Schaff, vol. 2 (rpt., Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, 1979).
  • 151
    • 84883946999 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Whether Augustine's early thought is more Stoic or Platonist is a matter of much controversy; see James Wetzel, Augustine and the Limits of Virtue, for a very good discussion of the issue. I agree with Wetzel's judgment that, in his early career, "Augustine's sensibilities in ethics are fundamentally Stoic. He refuses to accept the intrusion of fortune into the idea of beatitude" (50). But I think that Augustine incorporated rather more Platonic and neo-Platonic themes into his Stoic outlook than Wetzel concedes or takes note of
    • Whether Augustine's early thought is more Stoic or Platonist is a matter of much controversy; see James Wetzel, Augustine and the Limits of Virtue, for a very good discussion of the issue. I agree with Wetzel's judgment that, in his early career, "Augustine's sensibilities in ethics are fundamentally Stoic. He refuses to accept the intrusion of fortune into the idea of beatitude" (50). But I think that Augustine incorporated rather more Platonic and neo-Platonic themes into his Stoic outlook than Wetzel concedes or takes note of.
  • 152
    • 84884086690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am using the translation by R. S. Pine-Coffin in St. Augustine, Confessions (1961; rpt., London: Penguin Books, 1984)
    • I am using the translation by R. S. Pine-Coffin in St. Augustine, Confessions (1961; rpt., London: Penguin Books, 1984).
  • 153
    • 84884016358 scopus 로고
    • Eighty-three Different Questions, trans. David L. Mosher, Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press
    • Eighty-three Different Questions, trans. David L. Mosher (Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press, 1977), p. 66.
    • (1977) , pp. 66
  • 154
    • 84883990359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. De beata vita 2.11. Question: "What must a person take to himself in order to be blessed?" Answer: "It must be something ever enduring, that neither hangs on fortune, nor is exposed to any mishaps."
    • Cf. De beata vita 2.11. Question: "What must a person take to himself in order to be blessed?" Answer: "It must be something ever enduring, that neither hangs on fortune, nor is exposed to any mishaps."
  • 155
    • 84884113375 scopus 로고
    • Translation of John H. S. Burleigh in The Library of Christian Classics, vol. 6: Augustine's Earlier Writings, Philadelphia: Westminster Press
    • Translation of John H. S. Burleigh in The Library of Christian Classics, vol. 6: Augustine's Earlier Writings (Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1953), p. 251.
    • (1953) , pp. 251
  • 156
    • 84883930139 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here is a passage from one of those earliest works, de Quantitate Animae. Augustine is describing the seventh and final stage of the ascent of the soul: "We have now arrived at the vision and contemplation of the truth, which is the seventh and final step. Nor is it a step any longer, but a kind of stopping place to which these steps lead up. What its joys are, what the full enjoyment of the highest and true good is like, what serenity and eternity is in the air-how can I describe all this? It has been described by certain great and incomparable souls, insofar as they thought it ought to be described, souls whom we believe to have seen these things, and to be seeing them still" (76). I am using Nussbaum's translation, Upheavals of Thought, p. 534
    • Here is a passage from one of those earliest works, de Quantitate Animae. Augustine is describing the seventh and final stage of the ascent of the soul: "We have now arrived at the vision and contemplation of the truth, which is the seventh and final step. Nor is it a step any longer, but a kind of stopping place to which these steps lead up. What its joys are, what the full enjoyment of the highest and true good is like, what serenity and eternity is in the air-how can I describe all this? It has been described by certain great and incomparable souls, insofar as they thought it ought to be described, souls whom we believe to have seen these things, and to be seeing them still" (76). I am using Nussbaum's translation, Upheavals of Thought, p. 534.
  • 157
    • 84884118734 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Throughout the subsequent discussion, I use "enjoy" to stand for an experience that is positively valorized (I explain this shortly), not as a synonym for the Latin "fruere" as that is used by Augustine in his famous formula "uti, non frui" (On Christian Doctrine, Book I). Augustine explains "fruere" as follows: "to enjoy a thing is to rest with satisfaction in it for its own sake" (OCD I, 4). Augustine consistently held the view that though other things may be enjoyed, in my sense of "enjoy," only God is to be the object of fruere. What confuses those of us who read Augustine in English is that a number of different words in Augustine's Latin are translated as "to enjoy," including, then, "fruere."
    • Throughout the subsequent discussion, I use "enjoy" to stand for an experience that is positively valorized (I explain this shortly), not as a synonym for the Latin "fruere" as that is used by Augustine in his famous formula "uti, non frui" (On Christian Doctrine, Book I). Augustine explains "fruere" as follows: "to enjoy a thing is to rest with satisfaction in it for its own sake" (OCD I, 4). Augustine consistently held the view that though other things may be enjoyed, in my sense of "enjoy," only God is to be the object of fruere. What confuses those of us who read Augustine in English is that a number of different words in Augustine's Latin are translated as "to enjoy," including, then, "fruere."
  • 158
    • 84883928739 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On True Religion, xlvii, sec. 93
    • On True Religion, xlvii, sec. 93.
  • 159
    • 84883913277 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One finds a similarly lyrical passage in another of Augustine's late writings, de Trinitate VIII, iii, 4-5. For a lyrical passage on the wonders of human creativity, see City of God XXII, 24
    • One finds a similarly lyrical passage in another of Augustine's late writings, de Trinitate VIII, iii, 4-5. For a lyrical passage on the wonders of human creativity, see City of God XXII, 24.
  • 160
    • 0004255852 scopus 로고
    • Methods of Ethics
    • 6th ed., London: Macmillan
    • Henry Sidgwick, Methods of Ethics, 6th ed. (London: Macmillan, 1901), p. 110.
    • (1901) , pp. 110
    • Sidgwick, H.1
  • 161
    • 84884062722 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In his discussion of such cases in Finite and Infinite Goods, Robert Adams appears to hold that it is only the subsequent savoring of such experiences that we find enjoyable. See p. 96
    • In his discussion of such cases in Finite and Infinite Goods, Robert Adams appears to hold that it is only the subsequent savoring of such experiences that we find enjoyable. See p. 96.
  • 162
    • 84884030011 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, especially, Hannah Arendt, Love and Saint Augustine (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996); John Burnaby, Amos Dei: A Study in the Religion of St. Augustine, 3rd ed. (London, 1960); and Oliver O'Donovan, The Problem of Self-Love in Augustine (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1980)
    • See, especially, Hannah Arendt, Love and Saint Augustine (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996); John Burnaby, Amos Dei: A Study in the Religion of St. Augustine, 3rd ed. (London, 1960); and Oliver O'Donovan, The Problem of Self-Love in Augustine (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1980).
  • 163
    • 84883958337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nygren interprets Platonic eros as self-love. When expounding Nygren in chapter 4, I did not call attention to the fact that that interpretation, on my view, is a serious mistake. When I am gripped by some piece of music, it is the music that I love, not myself
    • Nygren interprets Platonic eros as self-love. When expounding Nygren in chapter 4, I did not call attention to the fact that that interpretation, on my view, is a serious mistake. When I am gripped by some piece of music, it is the music that I love, not myself.
  • 164
    • 84884094699 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Confessions X, 21-22
    • Confessions X, 21-22.
  • 165
    • 84884009799 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Wetzel, Augustine and the Limits of Virtue, p. 124: "the ideal of invulnerability in ethics remains the lodestone of Augustine's philosophical interests."
    • Cf. Wetzel, Augustine and the Limits of Virtue, p. 124: "the ideal of invulnerability in ethics remains the lodestone of Augustine's philosophical interests."
  • 166
    • 84884056712 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "[A]lthough a man who is sorry for the sufferings of others deserves praise for his charity, nevertheless, if his pity is genuine, he would prefer that there should be no cause for his sorrow. . . . Sorrow may therefore be commendable but never desirable" (Confessions III, 2)
    • "[A]lthough a man who is sorry for the sufferings of others deserves praise for his charity, nevertheless, if his pity is genuine, he would prefer that there should be no cause for his sorrow. . . . Sorrow may therefore be commendable but never desirable" (Confessions III, 2).
  • 167
    • 84884035946 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am using the translation by R. W. Dyson in Augustine, The City of God against the Pagans (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998)
    • I am using the translation by R. W. Dyson in Augustine, The City of God against the Pagans (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998).
  • 168
    • 84883901678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Wetzel, Augustine and the Limits of Virtue, p. 104: "Augustine's sharpest break from the Stoic ideal of apatheia comes with his recognition that virtue and grief are compatible. Often, in fact, grief is the necessary and appropriate affective form of virtue."
    • Cf. Wetzel, Augustine and the Limits of Virtue, p. 104: "Augustine's sharpest break from the Stoic ideal of apatheia comes with his recognition that virtue and grief are compatible. Often, in fact, grief is the necessary and appropriate affective form of virtue."
  • 169
    • 84883938198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In his Retractions, Augustine discusses this passage and says that he should not have said "hate temporal relationships." Had our forebears done this, we, their descendents, would never have been born and God's company of the elect would not have been filled up. I find it surprising that Augustine makes no corrections in the doctrine of love that he expounds in the passage
    • In his Retractions, Augustine discusses this passage and says that he should not have said "hate temporal relationships." Had our forebears done this, we, their descendents, would never have been born and God's company of the elect would not have been filled up. I find it surprising that Augustine makes no corrections in the doctrine of love that he expounds in the passage.
  • 170
    • 84883977094 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In my interpretation of Augustine on this point I am disagreeing with Wetzel, who interprets Augustine as saying, "When the Christian saint grieves, it is not for the loss of material well-being, but for personal failures of vision and love" (Augustine and the Limits of Virtue, p. 109)
    • In my interpretation of Augustine on this point I am disagreeing with Wetzel, who interprets Augustine as saying, "When the Christian saint grieves, it is not for the loss of material well-being, but for personal failures of vision and love" (Augustine and the Limits of Virtue, p. 109).
  • 171
    • 84883975175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It sounds less thin when read in conjunction with the following story that Elie Wiesel told about himself, as reported by Martha Nussbaum in The Therapy of Desire (p. 403): "Wiesel was a child in one of the Nazi death camps. On the day the Allied forces arrived, the first member of the liberating army he saw was a very large black officer. Walking into the camp and seeing what was there to be seen, this man began to curse, shouting at the top of his voice. As the child Wiesel watched, he went on shouting and cursing for a very long time. And the child Wiesel thought, watching him, now humanity has come back. Now, with that anger, humanity has come back."
    • It sounds less thin when read in conjunction with the following story that Elie Wiesel told about himself, as reported by Martha Nussbaum in The Therapy of Desire (p. 403): "Wiesel was a child in one of the Nazi death camps. On the day the Allied forces arrived, the first member of the liberating army he saw was a very large black officer. Walking into the camp and seeing what was there to be seen, this man began to curse, shouting at the top of his voice. As the child Wiesel watched, he went on shouting and cursing for a very long time. And the child Wiesel thought, watching him, now humanity has come back. Now, with that anger, humanity has come back."
  • 172
    • 84884058457 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Augustine's fullest treatment of "right feelings in the lives of righteous men" is in City of God, XIV, 9
    • Augustine's fullest treatment of "right feelings in the lives of righteous men" is in City of God, XIV, 9.
  • 173
    • 84883929646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Augustine continues in a bitingly caustic vein: "They believe that their wise man-that is, he whom, in their amazing vanity, they describe as such-even if he becomes blind, deaf and dumb; even if he falls victim to every other ill that can be described or imagined; even if he is compelled to put himself to death: that such a man would not shrink from calling such a life, beset with such ills, a happy one! O happy life, that seeks the aid of death to put an end to it!"
    • Augustine continues in a bitingly caustic vein: "They believe that their wise man-that is, he whom, in their amazing vanity, they describe as such-even if he becomes blind, deaf and dumb; even if he falls victim to every other ill that can be described or imagined; even if he is compelled to put himself to death: that such a man would not shrink from calling such a life, beset with such ills, a happy one! O happy life, that seeks the aid of death to put an end to it!"
  • 174
    • 0038014343 scopus 로고
    • Augustine of Hippo
    • London: Faber & Faber, The above is the theme of chapter 15 of Brown's biography
    • Peter Brown, Augustine of Hippo (London: Faber & Faber, 1967), p. 156. The above is the theme of chapter 15 of Brown's biography.
    • (1967) , pp. 156
    • Brown, P.1
  • 175
    • 84883899869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example: "if the soul loves them and wishes to be with them and find its rest in them, it is torn by desires that can destroy it. In these things there is no place to rest" (Confessions IV, 10)
    • For example: "if the soul loves them and wishes to be with them and find its rest in them, it is torn by desires that can destroy it. In these things there is no place to rest" (Confessions IV, 10).
  • 176
    • 84884030184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Markus's essay, "Marius Victorinus and Augustine," in The Cambridge History of Later Greek and Early Medieval Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970)
    • In Markus's essay, "Marius Victorinus and Augustine," in The Cambridge History of Later Greek and Early Medieval Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970).
  • 177
    • 84883991722 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
    • (2001)
  • 178
    • 84884007817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant was expressing a very precise understanding of the Stoic position when he remarked, "It was a sublime way of representing the wise man, as the Stoic conceived him, when he let the wise one say: I wish I had a friend, not that he might give me help in poverty, sickness, captivity, and so on, but in order that I might stand by him and save a human being. But for all that, the very same wise man, when his friend is not to be saved, says to himself: What's it to me? i.e., he rejected commiseration." Doctrine of Virtue 34, trans. J. W. Ellington, in Immanuel Kant, Ethical Philosophy (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1983)
    • Kant was expressing a very precise understanding of the Stoic position when he remarked, "It was a sublime way of representing the wise man, as the Stoic conceived him, when he let the wise one say: I wish I had a friend, not that he might give me help in poverty, sickness, captivity, and so on, but in order that I might stand by him and save a human being. But for all that, the very same wise man, when his friend is not to be saved, says to himself: What's it to me? i.e., he rejected commiseration." Doctrine of Virtue 34, trans. J. W. Ellington, in Immanuel Kant, Ethical Philosophy (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1983).
  • 179
    • 84884123203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the following passage one sees Nussbaum moving back and forth between the worth of persons and the worth of the lives of persons: "To the pro-compassion tradition, differences in class and rank create differences in the worth or success of lives. To grant this much, the anti-compassion position holds, is to grant that the world and its morally irrelevant happenings can in effect forge different ranks and conditions of humanity. The believer in equal human worth should not acknowledge this: she should take her bearings from that basic human endowment that is not unequally distributed and she should honor that equal basic endowment by treating that, and that only, as the measure of a life" (359; emphasis added)
    • In the following passage one sees Nussbaum moving back and forth between the worth of persons and the worth of the lives of persons: "To the pro-compassion tradition, differences in class and rank create differences in the worth or success of lives. To grant this much, the anti-compassion position holds, is to grant that the world and its morally irrelevant happenings can in effect forge different ranks and conditions of humanity. The believer in equal human worth should not acknowledge this: she should take her bearings from that basic human endowment that is not unequally distributed and she should honor that equal basic endowment by treating that, and that only, as the measure of a life" (359; emphasis added).
  • 180
    • 84884029513 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle on the Goods of Fortune
    • in Aristotle's Ethics, ed. Terence Irwin, New York and London: Garland, The article is reprinted from The Philosophical Review 94, no. 2 (April 1985)
    • John M. Cooper, "Aristotle on the Goods of Fortune," in Aristotle's Ethics, ed. Terence Irwin (New York and London: Garland, 1995), p. 189. The article is reprinted from The Philosophical Review 94, no. 2 (April 1985).
    • (1995) , pp. 189
    • Cooper, J.1
  • 181
    • 84884081517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I mentioned, in chapter 6, that in his book Well-Being James Griffin entertains the suggestion that the problems and perplexities that he is confronting in his analysis are due to the fact that he and others are tacitly working with two distinct understandings of wellbeing. One of those is clearly that of the life that is good for the person whose life it is- the satisfying life, as I have called it. Apparently, the other is that of the life that goes well. On p. 7 Griffin himself speaks of well-being as "what it is for a single life to go well."
    • I mentioned, in chapter 6, that in his book Well-Being James Griffin entertains the suggestion that the problems and perplexities that he is confronting in his analysis are due to the fact that he and others are tacitly working with two distinct understandings of wellbeing. One of those is clearly that of the life that is good for the person whose life it is- the satisfying life, as I have called it. Apparently, the other is that of the life that goes well. On p. 7 Griffin himself speaks of well-being as "what it is for a single life to go well."
  • 182
    • 84884069977 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some theorists speak instead of preferences; others speak of interests. Desires, preferences, and interests seem to me distinct states of the self. Nonetheless, the criticisms I lodge against the desire-satisfaction theory have obvious analogues for preference-satisfaction and interest-satisfaction theories
    • Some theorists speak instead of preferences; others speak of interests. Desires, preferences, and interests seem to me distinct states of the self. Nonetheless, the criticisms I lodge against the desire-satisfaction theory have obvious analogues for preference-satisfaction and interest-satisfaction theories.
  • 183
    • 84884114967 scopus 로고
    • 6th ed.; London: Macmillan
    • 6th ed.; London: Macmillan, 1901.
    • (1901)
  • 184
    • 0004293486 scopus 로고
    • Well-Being
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • James Griffin, Well-Being (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), p. 10.
    • (1986) , pp. 10
    • Griffin, J.1
  • 185
    • 84884061236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
    • (2001)
  • 186
    • 84884085736 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Facts and Values," in Philosophical Topics 14, p. 16. Quoted in Murphy, Natural Law, p. 51
    • "Facts and Values," in Philosophical Topics 14, p. 16. Quoted in Murphy, Natural Law, p. 51.
  • 187
    • 84884021130 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is an excellent discussion of deformed desires and the insuperable difficulty these pose for the informed-desire account of well-being in chapter 2 of Martha Nussbaum's Women and Human Development (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000)
    • There is an excellent discussion of deformed desires and the insuperable difficulty these pose for the informed-desire account of well-being in chapter 2 of Martha Nussbaum's Women and Human Development (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000).
  • 188
    • 84884102778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Finite and Infinite Goods, p. 93
    • Finite and Infinite Goods, p. 93.
  • 189
    • 84884080627 scopus 로고
    • New Haven: Yale University Press
    • New Haven: Yale University Press, 1920.
    • (1920)
  • 190
    • 84883903877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An excellent discussion of the two theories is to be found in the three essays in Matthew H. Kramer, N. E. Simmonds, and Hillel Steiner, A Debate over Rights: Philosophical Enquiries (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998)
    • An excellent discussion of the two theories is to be found in the three essays in Matthew H. Kramer, N. E. Simmonds, and Hillel Steiner, A Debate over Rights: Philosophical Enquiries (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998).
  • 191
    • 84883974138 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Though these are the principal ways, they are not, as we will see in chapter 14, the only ways
    • Though these are the principal ways, they are not, as we will see in chapter 14, the only ways.
  • 192
    • 84884058507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The essay is the first chapter in Ramsey's little book, Christian Ethics and the Sit-In (New York: Association Press, 1961)
    • The essay is the first chapter in Ramsey's little book, Christian Ethics and the Sit-In (New York: Association Press, 1961).
  • 193
    • 84883916312 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kramer et al., in A Debate over Rights, prefer to call Hohfeld's privileges liberties. But as will shortly become clear, what we would normally cite as an example of a liberty to which one has a right is a combination of a permission-right and a claim-right. My right to the liberty of walking on the New Haven Green is a combination of my permission-right to walk there and my claim-right to being free from interference in walking there
    • Kramer et al., in A Debate over Rights, prefer to call Hohfeld's privileges liberties. But as will shortly become clear, what we would normally cite as an example of a liberty to which one has a right is a combination of a permission-right and a claim-right. My right to the liberty of walking on the New Haven Green is a combination of my permission-right to walk there and my claim-right to being free from interference in walking there.
  • 194
    • 84884062448 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To the best of my knowledge, every present-day writer would affirm this thesis
    • To the best of my knowledge, every present-day writer would affirm this thesis.
  • 195
    • 84883958393 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If it was Hohfeld's intent to define a "power" as the capacity to bring about an alteration in someone's claim-rights or permission-rights, rather than, assuming that we know what a power is, to observe that that capacity for alteration is characteristic of powers, then Hohfeldian powers are a very untidy class. Many Hohfeldian powers will be what the medieval Latins called a potestas. But we also alter people's claim-rights and permission-rights by giving them gifts and by wronging them. I think it likely that Hohfeld was thinking of a power as a potestas; and that, in spite of the fact that I can alter someone's normative status by giving them gifts or wronging them, he would not call such actions "powers."
    • If it was Hohfeld's intent to define a "power" as the capacity to bring about an alteration in someone's claim-rights or permission-rights, rather than, assuming that we know what a power is, to observe that that capacity for alteration is characteristic of powers, then Hohfeldian powers are a very untidy class. Many Hohfeldian powers will be what the medieval Latins called a potestas. But we also alter people's claim-rights and permission-rights by giving them gifts and by wronging them. I think it likely that Hohfeld was thinking of a power as a potestas; and that, in spite of the fact that I can alter someone's normative status by giving them gifts or wronging them, he would not call such actions "powers."
  • 196
    • 84883952296 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Feinberg, Social Philosophy, p. 63
    • Feinberg, Social Philosophy, p. 63.
  • 197
    • 84884117546 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The example was offered to me by Robert Adams
    • The example was offered to me by Robert Adams.
  • 198
    • 84884101320 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The example was offered to me by Geoffrey Cupit
    • The example was offered to me by Geoffrey Cupit.
  • 199
    • 84883949711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It must be kept in mind that in such contexts, "person" is to be understood as short for "person or social entity."
    • It must be kept in mind that in such contexts, "person" is to be understood as short for "person or social entity."
  • 200
    • 84883956627 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kramer, in "Rights without Trimmings," considers, and effectively answers, other objections to the weak Hohfeld thesis. I have concentrated on those that are especially important for our discussion in subsequent chapters
    • Kramer, in "Rights without Trimmings," considers, and effectively answers, other objections to the weak Hohfeld thesis. I have concentrated on those that are especially important for our discussion in subsequent chapters.
  • 201
    • 84883962838 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In chapter 17 I argue that the thesis holds good for social entities as well as persons and human beings
    • In chapter 17 I argue that the thesis holds good for social entities as well as persons and human beings.
  • 202
    • 84884004412 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In chapter 6 of my Divine Discourse I discuss different aspects of the theory from those that I discuss here
    • In chapter 6 of my Divine Discourse I discuss different aspects of the theory from those that I discuss here.
  • 203
    • 84883950379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This fact has led to the quixotic claim by Derrida and other participants in the recent flurry of discussions about "the gift" that one can never give a true gift, because always some return is required, if of nothing else, then at least of gratitude. See Jacques Derrida, The Gift of Death, trans. David Wills (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995). My own view is that, rather than treating this argument as revealing the surprising truth, hitherto unnoticed, that there can be no true gift, one should instead treat it as a reductio ad absurdum argument against the assumption that something is not a true gift if gratitude is (morally) required
    • This fact has led to the quixotic claim by Derrida and other participants in the recent flurry of discussions about "the gift" that one can never give a true gift, because always some return is required, if of nothing else, then at least of gratitude. See Jacques Derrida, The Gift of Death, trans. David Wills (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995). My own view is that, rather than treating this argument as revealing the surprising truth, hitherto unnoticed, that there can be no true gift, one should instead treat it as a reductio ad absurdum argument against the assumption that something is not a true gift if gratitude is (morally) required.
  • 204
    • 84884118375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What I am here calling an office, I called, in chapter 5 of my Divine Discourse (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995) a standing. I have changed terminology so that here I could highlight the distinction between an office, on the one hand, and its attendant powers, obligations, and rights, on the other, and have the word "standing" available for the latter
    • What I am here calling an office, I called, in chapter 5 of my Divine Discourse (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995) a standing. I have changed terminology so that here I could highlight the distinction between an office, on the one hand, and its attendant powers, obligations, and rights, on the other, and have the word "standing" available for the latter.
  • 205
    • 84884002419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Philip Quinn has discussed the divine-fiat view in some of his essays. For references, and for critique, see Mark C. Murphy, "Theological Voluntarism," in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2002 edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta
    • Philip Quinn has discussed the divine-fiat view in some of his essays. For references, and for critique, see Mark C. Murphy, "Theological Voluntarism," in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2002 edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta, http://plato.stanford.edu/ archives/fall2002entries/voluntarism-theoological.
  • 206
    • 84884092186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The person who holds that God generates obligations in human beings by sheer fiat would presumably not want to say that this is true for all obligations; God does generate some obligations by the issuing of explicit commands. So one way of fitting things together would be to say that God generates by sheer fiat our standing obligation to obey such commands as God may issue, and generates all other obligations by the issuing of commands
    • The person who holds that God generates obligations in human beings by sheer fiat would presumably not want to say that this is true for all obligations; God does generate some obligations by the issuing of explicit commands. So one way of fitting things together would be to say that God generates by sheer fiat our standing obligation to obey such commands as God may issue, and generates all other obligations by the issuing of commands.
  • 207
    • 84883929621 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I elaborate this view much more fully in chapter 4 of my Divine Discourse
    • I elaborate this view much more fully in chapter 4 of my Divine Discourse.
  • 208
    • 84884020336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For the sake of economy of words, I continue to speak of "life-goods," when what I have in mind is "life- or history-goods."
    • For the sake of economy of words, I continue to speak of "life-goods," when what I have in mind is "life- or history-goods."
  • 209
    • 84884003691 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The example was presented to me by Chris Eberle as a counter-example to an earlier attempt of mine to articulate an account of rights
    • The example was presented to me by Chris Eberle as a counter-example to an earlier attempt of mine to articulate an account of rights.
  • 210
    • 84883905284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To the best of my knowledge, it was Ronald Dworkin who first used the metaphor of rights as trumps. See his article, "Rights as Trumps," in Jeremy Waldron, ed., Theories of Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984). An older way of making the same point is to say that rights are peremptory
    • To the best of my knowledge, it was Ronald Dworkin who first used the metaphor of rights as trumps. See his article, "Rights as Trumps," in Jeremy Waldron, ed., Theories of Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984). An older way of making the same point is to say that rights are peremptory.
  • 211
    • 84883971517 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge University Press
    • Cambridge University Press, 1988.
    • (1988)
  • 212
    • 84883958547 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hampton goes on to quote a passage to the same effect from the chapter by Jeffrie G. Murphy that preceded hers in the book: "One reason we so deeply resent moral injuries done to us is not simply that they hurt us in some tangible or sensible way; it is because such injuries are also messages-symbolic communications. They are ways a wrongdoer has of saying to us, "I count but you do not," "I can use you for my purposes," or "I am here up high and you are there down below." Intentional wrongdoing insults us and attempts (sometimes successfully) to degrade us-and thus it involves a kind of injury that is not merely tangible and sensible. It is moral injury, and we care about such injuries."
    • Hampton goes on to quote a passage to the same effect from the chapter by Jeffrie G. Murphy that preceded hers in the book: "One reason we so deeply resent moral injuries done to us is not simply that they hurt us in some tangible or sensible way; it is because such injuries are also messages-symbolic communications. They are ways a wrongdoer has of saying to us, "I count but you do not," "I can use you for my purposes," or "I am here up high and you are there down below." Intentional wrongdoing insults us and attempts (sometimes successfully) to degrade us-and thus it involves a kind of injury that is not merely tangible and sensible. It is moral injury, and we care about such injuries."
  • 213
    • 84884087869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The locution "respecting a person" seems to me ambiguous as between treating with respect and acting out of respect
    • The locution "respecting a person" seems to me ambiguous as between treating with respect and acting out of respect.
  • 214
    • 84884053570 scopus 로고
    • Reprinted in David Lyons, ed., Rights, Belmont, Calif.: Wadsworth
    • Reprinted in David Lyons, ed., Rights (Belmont, Calif.: Wadsworth, 1979), p. 112.
    • (1979) , pp. 112
  • 215
    • 0009993153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant's Ethical Thought
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Allen W. Wood, Kant's Ethical Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999).
    • (1999)
    • Wood, A.W.1
  • 216
    • 84884104902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • From Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. C. B. Macpherson (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1965), chap. 10, para. 16
    • From Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. C. B. Macpherson (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1965), chap. 10, para. 16.
  • 217
    • 84884107449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The examples I gave in chapter 11, about life guards and drowning swimmers, are also apropos here
    • The examples I gave in chapter 11, about life guards and drowning swimmers, are also apropos here.
  • 218
    • 84883903466 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in Kant's Ethical Thought, says that "as [Christine] Korsgaard has emphasized, Kantian ethics breaks with the utilitarian tradition most fundamentally by denying that the most basic objects of value are states of affairs, and [by denying] that 'the business of morality is to bring something about" (141). I agree with what Wood is getting at here; but this is not the right way to put it. It is the business of morality to bring something about, because there is no other way to acknowledge the worth of entities than by bringing something about
    • Allen Wood, in Kant's Ethical Thought, says that "as [Christine] Korsgaard has emphasized, Kantian ethics breaks with the utilitarian tradition most fundamentally by denying that the most basic objects of value are states of affairs, and [by denying] that 'the business of morality is to bring something about" (141). I agree with what Wood is getting at here; but this is not the right way to put it. It is the business of morality to bring something about, because there is no other way to acknowledge the worth of entities than by bringing something about.
    • Wood, A.1
  • 219
    • 2442466833 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Encyclopedia of Genocide
    • Quoted in Michael Perry, Toward a Theory of Human Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), chapter 1
    • Israel W. Charney, ed., Encyclopedia of Genocide (1999), p. 28. Quoted in Michael Perry, Toward a Theory of Human Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), chapter 1.
    • (1999) , pp. 28
    • Charney, I.W.1
  • 220
    • 84883993796 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Report by Julie Flint, Observer (March 3, 1991). Quoted by Jonathan Glover, Humanity: A Moral History of the Twentieth Century, New Haven: Yale University Press
    • Report by Julie Flint, Observer (March 3, 1991). Quoted by Jonathan Glover, Humanity: A Moral History of the Twentieth Century (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2000), p. 32.
    • (2000) , pp. 32
  • 221
    • 84883954364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Random House
    • New York: Random House, 2001.
    • (2001)
  • 222
    • 84883907844 scopus 로고
    • This aspect of the story was told by Jacques Maritain, who was a participant in the discussions at a certain stage. See his Man and the State, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, chapter 4
    • This aspect of the story was told by Jacques Maritain, who was a participant in the discussions at a certain stage. See his Man and the State (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1951), chapter 4.
    • (1951)
  • 223
    • 84884021977 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Article 1 of the Declaration reads in its totality as follows: "All human beings are born free and equal in dignity and rights. They are endowed with reason and conscience and should act towards one another in a spirit of brotherhood." The ideas of equality, of being endowed with reason and conscience, and of acting toward one another in a spirit of brotherhood are not picked up in either of the two Covenants
    • Article 1 of the Declaration reads in its totality as follows: "All human beings are born free and equal in dignity and rights. They are endowed with reason and conscience and should act towards one another in a spirit of brotherhood." The ideas of equality, of being endowed with reason and conscience, and of acting toward one another in a spirit of brotherhood are not picked up in either of the two Covenants.
  • 224
    • 84883932691 scopus 로고
    • Are There Any Natural Rights?: The Charles F. Adams Lecture of February 28, published by Bowdoin College, Bowdoin, Maine
    • Alasdair MacIntyre, "Are There Any Natural Rights?: The Charles F. Adams Lecture of February 28, 1983," published by Bowdoin College, Bowdoin, Maine.
    • (1983)
    • MacIntyre, A.1
  • 225
    • 84884057697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here is the article's full statement of the right to education: "Everyone has the right to education. Education shall be free, at least in the elementary and fundamental stages. Elementary education shall be compulsory. Technical and professional education shall be made generally available and higher education shall be equally accessible to all on the basis of merit." The article then goes on to make some comments about the goals of education
    • Here is the article's full statement of the right to education: "Everyone has the right to education. Education shall be free, at least in the elementary and fundamental stages. Elementary education shall be compulsory. Technical and professional education shall be made generally available and higher education shall be equally accessible to all on the basis of merit." The article then goes on to make some comments about the goals of education.
  • 226
    • 84883969112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the best way to think of what it is for a benefit right to be universal. As for negative or freedom rights, the best way to think of what it is for them to be universal is that everybody always has the right against everybody
    • This is the best way to think of what it is for a benefit right to be universal. As for negative or freedom rights, the best way to think of what it is for them to be universal is that everybody always has the right against everybody.
  • 227
    • 0001956628 scopus 로고
    • Human Rights, Rationality, and Sentimentality
    • in Stephen Shute and Susan Hurley, eds., On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures, New York: Basic Books, 1993
    • Richard Rorty, "Human Rights, Rationality, and Sentimentality," in Stephen Shute and Susan Hurley, eds., On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures 1993 (New York: Basic Books, 1993), pp. 112-13.
    • (1993) , pp. 112-113
    • Rorty, R.1
  • 228
    • 84883971308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is of course an irony in claiming that we are "the flexible, protean, self-shaping animal" in the course of arguing that we have no nature
    • There is of course an irony in claiming that we are "the flexible, protean, self-shaping animal" in the course of arguing that we have no nature.
  • 229
    • 84884082982 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The "whistling in the dark" phrase occurs in the following passage: "The secular philosophical tradition speaks of inalienable rights, inalienable dignity and of persons as ends in themselves. These are, I believe, ways of whistling in the dark, ways of trying to make secure to reason what reason cannot finally underwrite. Religious traditions speak of the sacredness of each human being, but I doubt that sanctity is a concept that has a secure home outside those traditions." Raimond Gaita, Thinking about Love and Truth and Justice (2000), p. 5. The passage is quoted in chapter 1 of Michael Perry's Toward a Theory of Human Rights
    • The "whistling in the dark" phrase occurs in the following passage: "The secular philosophical tradition speaks of inalienable rights, inalienable dignity and of persons as ends in themselves. These are, I believe, ways of whistling in the dark, ways of trying to make secure to reason what reason cannot finally underwrite. Religious traditions speak of the sacredness of each human being, but I doubt that sanctity is a concept that has a secure home outside those traditions." Raimond Gaita, Thinking about Love and Truth and Justice (2000), p. 5. The passage is quoted in chapter 1 of Michael Perry's Toward a Theory of Human Rights.
  • 230
    • 84884011407 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Among the scholars in recent years who have argued that a secular account of human rights is impossible, prominent is Michael Perry, in his Toward a Theory of Human Rights. Though my argument takes a form different from his, I have learned a good deal from his discussion
    • Among the scholars in recent years who have argued that a secular account of human rights is impossible, prominent is Michael Perry, in his Toward a Theory of Human Rights. Though my argument takes a form different from his, I have learned a good deal from his discussion.
  • 231
    • 84884107267 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On occasion I will speak of the theorist as grounding rights, when what I always mean, strictly speaking, is the theorist revealing the ground of the rights in question
    • On occasion I will speak of the theorist as grounding rights, when what I always mean, strictly speaking, is the theorist revealing the ground of the rights in question.
  • 232
    • 84884021000 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.
    • (1999)
  • 233
    • 84884108005 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant, Groundwork, Academy 439. Translation by Mary J. McGregor in McGregor, Immanuel Kant: Practical Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Kant, Groundwork, Academy 439. Translation by Mary J. McGregor in McGregor, Immanuel Kant: Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), p. 88.
    • (1996) , pp. 88
  • 234
    • 84884076849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Quoted from the Metaphysics of Morals (Academy 6: 463), Kant's Ethical Thought, in Wood, p. 134
    • Quoted from the Metaphysics of Morals (Academy 6: 463), Kant's Ethical Thought, in Wood, p. 134.
  • 235
    • 84884004714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago and La Salle, Ill., Open Court Press
    • Chicago and La Salle, Ill., Open Court Press, 1999.
    • (1999)
  • 236
    • 0027915807 scopus 로고
    • Life Is Sacred. That's the Easy Part
    • New York Times Magazine, May 16
    • Ronald Dworkin, "Life Is Sacred. That's the Easy Part," New York Times Magazine, May 16, 1993, p. 36.
    • (1993) , pp. 36
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 237
    • 0003867869 scopus 로고
    • Life's Dominion: An Argument about Abortion
    • Euthanasia, and Individual Freedom, New York: Knopf
    • Ronald Dworkin, Life's Dominion: An Argument about Abortion, Euthanasia, and Individual Freedom (New York: Knopf, 1993), p. 195.
    • (1993) , pp. 195
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 238
    • 84883973714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • 239
    • 84884050306 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am using "instrumentally" here to cover not only causes but logical and physical conditions
    • I am using "instrumentally" here to cover not only causes but logical and physical conditions.
  • 240
    • 84884101930 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The introduction of moral permission at this point is where I go beyond what Gewirth actually says
    • The introduction of moral permission at this point is where I go beyond what Gewirth actually says.
  • 241
    • 84883996309 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gewirth takes note of the problem and discusses it briefly on pp. 54-55. His solution is that "generic rights must be proportional to the degree to which [human beings] have the abilities of agency" (55). I think he means "have or will have the abilities of agency." He does not consider what this implies for the rights of those who do not and never will have the abilities of agency
    • Gewirth takes note of the problem and discusses it briefly on pp. 54-55. His solution is that "generic rights must be proportional to the degree to which [human beings] have the abilities of agency" (55). I think he means "have or will have the abilities of agency." He does not consider what this implies for the rights of those who do not and never will have the abilities of agency.
  • 242
    • 84884016263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The parallelism occurs again in Genesis 5:1-2, though this time with "likeness" rather than "image": "When God created humankind, he made them in the likeness of God. Male and female he created them."
    • The parallelism occurs again in Genesis 5:1-2, though this time with "likeness" rather than "image": "When God created humankind, he made them in the likeness of God. Male and female he created them."
  • 243
    • 84884000757 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Barth's discussion is to be found in his Church Dogmatics III/I, pp. 183-206
    • Barth's discussion is to be found in his Church Dogmatics III/I, pp. 183-206.
  • 244
    • 84884008126 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I think it is an open question whether exercising dominion is mandated or whether it is permitted as part of a blessing-thus whether the rhetorical force is imperative, "Have dominion," or optative, "May you have dominion." I am myself inclined toward the latter interpretation
    • I think it is an open question whether exercising dominion is mandated or whether it is permitted as part of a blessing-thus whether the rhetorical force is imperative, "Have dominion," or optative, "May you have dominion." I am myself inclined toward the latter interpretation.
  • 245
    • 84884108473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, See esp. chap. 3
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002. See esp. chap. 3.
    • (2002)
  • 246
    • 84883906565 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is also the view defended by Michael Perry in Toward a Theory of Human Rights
    • This is also the view defended by Michael Perry in Toward a Theory of Human Rights.
  • 247
    • 84883951670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When I speak of aspects of things, I have in mind not some property they possess but their possession of the property, and not some action they perform but their performance of the action. Aspects of things are thus not universals but abstract particulars. They are cases of universals. The medieval philosophers called them qualia; a good many philosophers in recent years have called them tropes. Aristotle identified them as things present in things. Thus the relation that I called aspect of is the same as what Aristotle called present in. In English, we typically refer to aspects of things with gerundives: "his being hungry," for example
    • When I speak of aspects of things, I have in mind not some property they possess but their possession of the property, and not some action they perform but their performance of the action. Aspects of things are thus not universals but abstract particulars. They are cases of universals. The medieval philosophers called them qualia; a good many philosophers in recent years have called them tropes. Aristotle identified them as things present in things. Thus the relation that I called aspect of is the same as what Aristotle called present in. In English, we typically refer to aspects of things with gerundives: "his being hungry," for example.
  • 248
    • 84884054049 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Instrumental worth" is a standard piece of terminology in the philosophical literature. There are two quite different phenomena that it is used to refer to. What one might mean by attributing instrumental worth to something is that it causes something of worth. Alternatively, one might have in mind the structure of human action. Some things we choose to bring about because we think there is a chance that bringing them about will cause something else that we want to happen; we choose it as means to a chosen end. Sometimes what is meant by attributing instrumental worth to something is that it has the role of means in the structure of human action. I think that my not signaling this distinction in the text above will not produce confusion; signaling it would only add complication
    • "Instrumental worth" is a standard piece of terminology in the philosophical literature. There are two quite different phenomena that it is used to refer to. What one might mean by attributing instrumental worth to something is that it causes something of worth. Alternatively, one might have in mind the structure of human action. Some things we choose to bring about because we think there is a chance that bringing them about will cause something else that we want to happen; we choose it as means to a chosen end. Sometimes what is meant by attributing instrumental worth to something is that it has the role of means in the structure of human action. I think that my not signaling this distinction in the text above will not produce confusion; signaling it would only add complication.
  • 249
    • 84884095449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I think that such entities as universities, banks, and states are more naturally called institutions than organizations. But in the writings of sociologists one finds the word "institution" used in quite a different way-in such expressions as "the institution of the family." I do not include the family (whatever that may be) among what I call social entities. So I will call universities, banks, states, and the like organizations. I do wish to include particular families among social entities; they are distinct examples of what I call groups
    • I think that such entities as universities, banks, and states are more naturally called institutions than organizations. But in the writings of sociologists one finds the word "institution" used in quite a different way-in such expressions as "the institution of the family." I do not include the family (whatever that may be) among what I call social entities. So I will call universities, banks, states, and the like organizations. I do wish to include particular families among social entities; they are distinct examples of what I call groups.
  • 250
    • 84883972867 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If we are thinking in terms of J. L. Austin's categories of locutionary, illocutionary, and perlocutionary acts, then, given that institutions and organizations are capable of performing illocutionary acts, they are also capable of performing perlocutionary acts. And Austin thinks of perlocutionary acts as causally generated. This, then, would be an exception to what is said above
    • If we are thinking in terms of J. L. Austin's categories of locutionary, illocutionary, and perlocutionary acts, then, given that institutions and organizations are capable of performing illocutionary acts, they are also capable of performing perlocutionary acts. And Austin thinks of perlocutionary acts as causally generated. This, then, would be an exception to what is said above.
  • 251
    • 84884075795 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The story is told excellently in Dan A. Oren, Joining the Club: A History of Jews and Yale (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2000). Oren's book is full of examples of the attribution of rational agency to Yale University
    • The story is told excellently in Dan A. Oren, Joining the Club: A History of Jews and Yale (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2000). Oren's book is full of examples of the attribution of rational agency to Yale University.
  • 252
    • 84883947453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Though our duties toward inanimate objects that do not have rights against us is not an exception to our principle of correlatives, it is an exception to the strong Hohfeld thesis discussed in chapter 11
    • Though our duties toward inanimate objects that do not have rights against us is not an exception to our principle of correlatives, it is an exception to the strong Hohfeld thesis discussed in chapter 11.
  • 253
    • 84974286205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I thus disagree with G.E.M. Anscombe's thesis, in her well-known essay "Modern Moral Philosophy" (Philosophy 33 [1958]), that the concept of obligation is intrinsically connected with the idea of someone issuing legislation
    • I thus disagree with G.E.M. Anscombe's thesis, in her well-known essay "Modern Moral Philosophy" (Philosophy 33 [1958]), that the concept of obligation is intrinsically connected with the idea of someone issuing legislation.
  • 254
    • 84883991192 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On this usage, social entities have moral obligations but not moral rights
    • On this usage, social entities have moral obligations but not moral rights.
  • 255
    • 84883927808 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Adams, Finite and Infinite Goods, 243-44 and 266-67
    • Adams, Finite and Infinite Goods, 243-44 and 266-67.
  • 256
    • 84884109649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Essay Concerning Human Understanding I, iii, 12-13, and II, xxviii. 8. In my John Locke and the Ethics of Belief (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), I called Locke's theory of obligation a divine command theory. I now think that it is instead a divine requirement theory
    • See Essay Concerning Human Understanding I, iii, 12-13, and II, xxviii. 8. In my John Locke and the Ethics of Belief (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), I called Locke's theory of obligation a divine command theory. I now think that it is instead a divine requirement theory.
  • 257
    • 84884088851 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • His reasons for rejecting the counterfactual option are to be found on p. 246
    • His reasons for rejecting the counterfactual option are to be found on p. 246.
  • 258
    • 84883917121 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The parable occurs in Matthew 18: 21-35. The language about torture must surely also be understood as hyperbolic
    • The parable occurs in Matthew 18: 21-35. The language about torture must surely also be understood as hyperbolic.
  • 259
    • 84883988353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in "Rights without Trimmings," offers some suggestions as to how a secularist might understand duties of charity. "If we suppose that there is indeed a general duty of charitableness, there are numerous candidates for the role of holding the correlative right. People who belong to the major faiths can attribute the right to God, whereas humanists can attribute it to our overall species. Someone less prone to flights of fancy can ascribe the right to each person's community, broadly or narrowly defined. No matter where exactly we locate the right, we certainly can locate it somewhere without strain." In Kramer et al., A Debate over Rights, p. 25, n. 11. I leave it to the reader to decide whether it really is as easy as Kramer suggests it is for the humanist to find a holder for the right correlative to a general duty of charitableness
    • Matthew H. Kramer, in "Rights without Trimmings," offers some suggestions as to how a secularist might understand duties of charity. "If we suppose that there is indeed a general duty of charitableness, there are numerous candidates for the role of holding the correlative right. People who belong to the major faiths can attribute the right to God, whereas humanists can attribute it to our overall species. Someone less prone to flights of fancy can ascribe the right to each person's community, broadly or narrowly defined. No matter where exactly we locate the right, we certainly can locate it somewhere without strain." In Kramer et al., A Debate over Rights, p. 25, n. 11. I leave it to the reader to decide whether it really is as easy as Kramer suggests it is for the humanist to find a holder for the right correlative to a general duty of charitableness.
    • Kramer, M.H.1
  • 260
    • 84883915204 scopus 로고
    • The Jewish Question
    • in David McLellan, Karl Marx: Selected Writings, Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • "The Jewish Question," in David McLellan, Karl Marx: Selected Writings (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977), p. 54.
    • (1977) , pp. 54
  • 261
    • 84883948608 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Psalm 96:8: "Ascribe to the Lord the glory due his name."
    • Psalm 96:8: "Ascribe to the Lord the glory due his name."
  • 262
    • 0003839704 scopus 로고
    • Consequences of Pragmatism
    • Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, xlii
    • Consequences of Pragmatism (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1982), xlii.
    • (1982)
  • 263
    • 84883951636 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rorty, "Human Rights, Rationality, and Sentimentality," pp. 133-34
    • Rorty, "Human Rights, Rationality, and Sentimentality," pp. 133-34.
  • 264
    • 84883937192 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Antjie Krog's Country of My Skull: Guilt, Sorrow, and the Limits of Forgiveness in the New South Africa (New York: Three Rivers, 2000)
    • See Antjie Krog's Country of My Skull: Guilt, Sorrow, and the Limits of Forgiveness in the New South Africa (New York: Three Rivers, 2000).
  • 265
    • 84883960839 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Luke 10:30-37
    • Luke 10:30-37.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.