메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 90, Issue 2, 2010, Pages 949-974

Foxy freedom?

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 77954330308     PISSN: 00068047     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Conference Paper
Times cited : (7)

References (153)
  • 2
    • 77954342788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (forthcoming 2010) Apr. 17, on file with the Boston University Law Review
    • RONALD DWORHN, JUSTICE FOR HEDGEHOGS (forthcoming 2010) (Apr. 17, 2009 manuscript at 228-37, on file with the Boston University Law Review).
    • (2009) Justice For Hedgehogs , pp. 228-237
    • Dworhn, R.1
  • 3
    • 77954331210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (manuscript at 229)
    • See id. (manuscript at 229).
  • 4
    • 77954333172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 5
    • 77954328408 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In fact, as Dworkin recognizes, Berlin may possibly be read to support a more complex understanding, by which many curtailments are too marginal or petty, or too obviously inevitable in any decently ordered form of social life, to generate a demand for express justification
    • In fact, as Dworkin recognizes, Berlin may possibly be read to support a more complex understanding, by which many curtailments are too marginal or petty, or too obviously inevitable in any decently ordered form of social life, to generate a demand for express justification.
  • 6
    • 77954334664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (manuscript at 231)
    • See id. (manuscript at 231).
  • 7
    • 77954321777 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Berlin wrote repeatedly of a frontier dividing an inner core of negative-liberty rights from a more extensive space of descriptive freedom. [T]he issue of individual freedom," Berlin said, is that of the frontiers beyond which public authority ... should not normally be allowed to step
    • Berlin wrote repeatedly of a "frontier" dividing an inner core of negative-liberty rights from a more extensive space of descriptive freedom. "[T]he issue of individual freedom," Berlin said, is that of "the frontiers beyond which public authority ... should not normally be allowed to step."
  • 8
    • 33644676733 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, xli [hereinafter BERLIN, Introduction]. Behind the frontier lies that area for free choice, the diminution of which is incompatible with the existence of anything that can properly be called political . . . liberty
    • ISAIAH BERLIN, Introduction to FOUR ESSAYS ON LIBERTY, supra note 1, at ix, xli [hereinafter BERLIN, Introduction]. Behind the frontier lies that "area for free choice, the diminution of which is incompatible with the existence of anything that can properly be called political . . . liberty."
    • Introduction to Four Essays on Liberty , pp. 9
    • Berlin, I.1
  • 9
    • 77954318489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at xxxvii
    • Id. at xxxvii;
  • 10
    • 77954318976 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also id. at lii writing of a minimum level of opportunity for choice ... below which human activity ceases to be free in any meaningful sense
    • see also id. at lii (writing of a "minimum level of opportunity for choice ... below which human activity ceases to be free in any meaningful sense");
  • 11
    • 77954340534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at lxi writing of a minimum area that men require if... dehumanization is to be averted
    • id. at lxi (writing of a "minimum area that men require if... dehumanization is to be averted");
  • 12
    • 0005029511 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, 124 [hereinafter BERLIN, TWO Concepts] (writing of a certain minimum area of personal freedom that cannot be violated without preventing a minimum development of . . . natural faculties on which human agency depends)
    • ISAIAH BERLIN, Two Concepts of Liberty, in FOUR ESSAYS ON LIBERTY, supra note 1, at 118, 124 [hereinafter BERLIN, TWO Concepts] (writing of "a certain minimum area of personal freedom" that cannot be violated without preventing a "minimum development of . . . natural faculties" on which human agency depends).
    • Two Concepts of Liberty, in Four Essays on Liberty , pp. 118
    • Berlin, I.1
  • 13
    • 77954347410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 232)
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 232).
  • 14
    • 77954343678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 15
    • 30344469787 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Do liberal values conflict?
    • 77-80, 90 Mark Lilla et al. eds.
    • See Ronald Dworkin, Do Liberal Values Conflict?, in THE LEGACY OF ISAIAH BERLIN 73, 77-80, 90 (Mark Lilla et al. eds., 2001) (answering that they do not).
    • (2001) The Legacy of Isaiah Berlin , pp. 73
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 16
    • 77954330671 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, Supra Note 2 (Manuscript at 231)
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 231).
  • 17
    • 77954344176 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 18
    • 77954324972 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In hedgehog solidarity
    • 774-80
    • See C. Edwin Baker, In Hedgehog Solidarity, 90 B.U. L. REV. 759, 774-80 (2010).
    • (2010) B.U. L. Rev. , vol.90 , pp. 759
    • Edwin Baker, C.1
  • 19
    • 77954340212 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 manuscript at 231
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 231).
  • 20
    • 77954345578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 21
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • rev. ed.
    • See JOHN RAWLS, POLITICAL LIBERALISM 291-92 (rev. ed. 1996) (explaining that in the political conception of justice as fairness, the basic liberties "are specified by a list," and "no priority is assigned to liberty as such").
    • (1996) Political Liberalism , pp. 291-292
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 23
    • 77954317878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin makes his difference with Rawls explicit at DWORHN, jupra note 2 (manuscript at 217, 231).
    • Dworkin makes his difference with Rawls explicit at DWORHN, jupra note 2 (manuscript at 217, 231).
  • 24
    • 77954329474 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (manuscript at 231)
    • Id. (manuscript at 231).
  • 25
    • 77954330997 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 26
    • 77954326421 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (manuscript at 232)
    • Id. (manuscript at 232).
  • 27
    • 77953300624 scopus 로고
    • 467 F. Supp. 990, 991, 997 W.D. Wis.
    • See United States v. Progressive, Inc., 467 F. Supp. 990, 991, 997 (W.D. Wis. 1979) (granting a preliminary injunction against such publication).
    • (1979) United States V. Progressive, Inc.
  • 28
    • 77954316788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The state cannot plausibly be accused, in either case, of acting on the basis of ideas of what does or does not make for a worthy life, or of which social groups do and do not merit first-class consideration
    • The state cannot plausibly be accused, in either case, of acting on the basis of ideas of what does or does not make for a worthy life, or of which social groups do and do not merit first-class consideration.
  • 29
    • 77954348060 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin might find the no-publication law objectionable on grounds of interference with free exchange of information and ideas - exchange on which the legitimacy of democratic government depends
    • Dworkin might find the no-publication law objectionable on grounds of interference with free exchange of information and ideas - exchange on which the legitimacy of democratic government depends.
  • 30
    • 77954336843 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 234)
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 234).
  • 31
    • 77954330502 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here, my point is that he cannot find it objectionable just on grounds of obstruction of a publisher's fundamental liberty of self-expression, self-realization, or autonomy, as some liberal theorists would
    • Here, my point is that he cannot find it objectionable just on grounds of obstruction of a publisher's fundamental liberty of self-expression, self-realization, or autonomy, as some liberal theorists would.
  • 33
    • 0039510928 scopus 로고
    • The value of free speech
    • 593
    • Martin H. Redish, The Value of Free Speech, 130 U. PA. L. REV. 591, 593 (1982).
    • (1982) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.130 , pp. 591
    • Redish, M.H.1
  • 34
    • 77954323317 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKiN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 232)
    • DWORKiN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 232).
  • 35
    • 77954320533 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (manuscript at 230-31)
    • See id. (manuscript at 230-31).
  • 36
    • 77954326084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. For the view that Dworkin's widely known conception of rights as tramps has been, from the start, an excluded reasons (as opposed to a key interests or interests for their own sake) sort of conception
    • Id. For the view that Dworkin's widely known conception of "rights as tramps" has been, from the start, an "excluded reasons" (as opposed to a "key interests" or "interests for their own sake") sort of conception,
  • 37
    • 0346053573 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pildes on Dworkin's theory of rights
    • 304
    • see Jeremy Waldron, Pildes on Dworkin's Theory of Rights, 19 J. LEGAL STUD. 301,304 (2000).
    • (2000) J. Legal Stud. , vol.19 , pp. 301
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 38
    • 77954347408 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 230)
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 230).
  • 39
    • 77954321776 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here, I am much indebted to conversation with Richard Fallon
    • Here, I am much indebted to conversation with Richard Fallon.
  • 40
    • 77954339729 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is certainly true with respect to the question of political curbs on descriptive freedom
    • This is certainly true with respect to the question of political curbs on descriptive freedom.
  • 41
    • 77954328568 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 232)
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 232).
  • 42
    • 77954331209 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Whether Dworkin would insist on the "no regrets" claim with regard to all seeming collisions of normative concepts - such as kindness colliding with honesty in many social situations - is less certain
    • Whether Dworkin would insist on the "no regrets" claim with regard to all seeming collisions of normative concepts - such as kindness colliding with honesty in many social situations - is less certain.
  • 43
    • 77954343693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Is moral reasoning conceptual interpretation?
    • 539
    • See Richard Fallon, Is Moral Reasoning Conceptual Interpretation?, 90 B.U. L. REV. 535,539 (2010).
    • (2010) B.U. L. Rev. , vol.90 , pp. 535
    • Fallon, R.1
  • 45
    • 77954318838 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, supra note 8, at 88-89
    • Dworkin, supra note 8, at 88-89.
  • 46
    • 77954332787 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 29, at 115 "[T]hose who defend Berlin's definition [of liberty] say that although my liberty has been invaded, the invasion is justified in this case, because the wrong done to me is necessary to prevent a greater wrong to others
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 29, at 115 ("[T]hose who defend Berlin's definition [of liberty] say that although my liberty has been invaded, the invasion is justified in this case, because the wrong done to me is necessary to prevent a greater wrong to others.").
  • 48
    • 84937327856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Democracy and rights in south africa: Beyond a constitutional culture of justification
    • 351-52
    • Johan van der Walt & Henk Botha, Democracy and Rights in South Africa: Beyond a Constitutional Culture of Justification, 7 CONSTELLATIONS 341, 351-52 (2000) (maintaining that such an outlook best reflects a commitment to political community).
    • (2000) Constellations , vol.7 , pp. 341
    • Van Johan, D.W.1    Botha, H.2
  • 49
    • 77954335381 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 29, at 109-10
    • DWORKIN, supra note 29, at 109-10;
  • 50
    • 77954326085 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, supra note 8, at 81
    • Dworkin, supra note 8, at 81.
  • 51
    • 0141644981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See WILLIAM A. GALSTON, LIBERAL PLURALISM 6-7 (2002) (defending the compatibility of value pluralism with the existence of "right answers in specific cases"). Berlin did deny the possibility of crisply demonstrable best choices. He said there could be no "clear-cut" or "certain" decisions, no "conclusive," "discoverable, " or objectively true solutions according to "hard-and-fast" rules or "universal maxims" or "patterns."
    • (2002) Liberal Pluralism , pp. 6-7
    • Galston, W.A.1
  • 52
    • 77954342276 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BERLIN, Introduction, supra note 5, at xlix-li
    • BERLIN, Introduction, supra note 5, at xlix-li;
  • 53
    • 77954316941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BERLIN, supra note 5, 170. But that is not yet to say that you and I can have no defensible, publicly respectable grounds for judging some resolutions right and others wrong, some "justifiable" or "rational" and others not
    • BERLIN, Two Concepts, supra note 5, at 126, 170. But that is not yet to say that you and I can have no defensible, publicly respectable grounds for judging some resolutions right and others wrong, some "justifiable" or "rational" and others not.
    • Two Concepts , pp. 126
  • 54
    • 79957107478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BERLIN, supra note 5
    • BERLIN, Introduction, supra note 5, at l;
    • Introduction
  • 55
    • 77954316941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BERLIN, supra note 5, Nor is it yet to excuse us from the obligation to make the right choices: Berlin scruples not to call "unjust and immoral" a system that founds the freedom of some on the misery of others
    • BERLIN, Two Concepts, supra note 5, at 132. Nor is it yet to excuse us from the obligation to make the right choices: Berlin scruples not to call "unjust and immoral" a system that founds the freedom of some on the misery of others.
    • Two Concepts , pp. 132
  • 56
    • 77954343856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 125.
    • See id. at 125.
  • 57
    • 77954328406 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • He writes of curtailments of freedom that any "sane or decent society" must impose, and historical "failures" to provide the minimum social conditions for effective enjoyment of liberty
    • He writes of curtailments of freedom that any "sane or decent society" must impose, and historical "failures" to provide the minimum social conditions for effective enjoyment of liberty.
  • 58
    • 77954326251 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BERLIN, Introduction, supra note 5, at lvi-lvii
    • BERLIN, Introduction, supra note 5, at lvi-lvii.
  • 59
    • 77954330670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • He calls "overwhelmingly strong" the case for coercive "intervention ... to secure conditions for... at least a minimum degree of... liberty for individuals
    • He calls "overwhelmingly strong" the case for coercive "intervention ... to secure conditions for... at least a minimum degree of... liberty for individuals."
  • 60
    • 77954340374 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at xlv-xlvi
    • Id. at xlv-xlvi.
  • 61
    • 77954330996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see DWORKIN, supra note 29, at 115 "Given that some people ... want to kill on some occasions, is any wrong done to them by preventing them from doing so
    • But see DWORKIN, supra note 29, at 115 ("Given that some people ... want to kill on some occasions, is any wrong done to them by preventing them from doing so?").
  • 63
    • 77954323959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. passim
    • See id. passim.
  • 64
    • 34547953418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Balancing and the structure of constitutional rights
    • 461
    • For recent, spirited arguments in the negative, see Kai Möller, Balancing and the Structure of Constitutional Rights, 5 INT'L J. CONST. L. 453, 461 (2007);
    • (2007) Int'l J. Const. L. , vol.5 , pp. 453
    • Möller, K.1
  • 65
    • 67650547942 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Proportionality: An assault on human rights?
    • 489-90
    • Stavros Tsakyrakis, Proportionality: An Assault on Human Rights?, 7 INT'L J. CONST. L. 468, 489-90 (2009).
    • (2009) Int'l J. Const. L. , vol.7 , pp. 468
    • Tsakyrakis, S.1
  • 66
    • 77954333171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 217)
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 217).
  • 67
    • 77954342455 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Waldron, supra note 25, at 303, 307 (affirming tension or incompatibility between Dworkin's conception of general liberty rights and justification by balancing). The same tension does not, however, necessarily attach to rights of expressive and communicative freedoms, on Dworkin's account Respect for those freedoms, Dworkin says, is required by their service to "a variety of principles and purposes," among which is assurance of the free exchange of information and ideas on which depend, in part, the attractions of certain dovetailing conceptions of democracy and self-government that Dworkin also commends
    • See Waldron, supra note 25, at 303, 307 (affirming tension or incompatibility between Dworkin's conception of general liberty rights and justification by balancing). The same tension does not, however, necessarily attach to rights of expressive and communicative freedoms, on Dworkin's account Respect for those freedoms, Dworkin says, is required by their service to "a variety of principles and purposes," among which is assurance of the free exchange of information and ideas on which depend, in part, the attractions of certain dovetailing conceptions of democracy and self-government that Dworkin also commends.
  • 68
    • 77954343855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 234)
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 234).
  • 69
    • 77954330995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Given this complex and partly instrumentalist valuation of the expressive and communicative liberties within Dworkin's entire scheme of dovetailing conceptions of political values, it seems that balancing judgments - perhaps lightly disguised as categorizations (e.g., differentiating restrictions on time and place from total suppression, or commercial speech from political speech) - may often be in order in regard to them, without attributing any independent value to descriptive freedom as such, and hence without signaling the sort of conflict among major, liberal-political values that Dworkin aims to avoid. For this reason, I have mainly refrained, in what follows, from citing instances of free-speech balancing as tests of intuitions regarding the valuation of descriptive freedom as such.
  • 70
    • 77954338815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 232)
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 232).
  • 71
    • 77954323318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part I.B
    • See supra Part I.B.
  • 72
    • 77954344305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying notes 16-22
    • See supra text accompanying notes 16-22.
  • 73
    • 77954341957 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Must the no-spit law grant an exemption on Yom Kippur, for observant Jews whose obligation to keep a fast on that day (as they understand it) prohibits them from swallowing their saliva? The answer appears to be "no," but you cannot know that before you have applied the test
    • Must the no-spit law grant an exemption on Yom Kippur, for observant Jews whose obligation to keep a fast on that day (as they understand it) prohibits them from swallowing their saliva? The answer appears to be "no," but you cannot know that before you have applied the test.
  • 74
    • 77954328730 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 232)
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 232).
  • 75
    • 77954320850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (manuscript at 230) "Certainly it is regrettable when people are punished for disobeying the law: it harms those who are punished and it ought to dismay those who do the punishing
    • See id. (manuscript at 230) ("Certainly it is regrettable when people are punished for disobeying the law: it harms those who are punished and it ought to dismay those who do the punishing.").
  • 76
    • 77954344175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If the constriction of options were regarded as a harming for which justification is required, would that be tantamount to conceding that non-constricted, descriptive freedom is a political-moral value
    • If the constriction of options were regarded as a harming for which justification is required, would that be tantamount to conceding that non-constricted, descriptive freedom is a political-moral value?
  • 77
    • 77954348238 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DWORHN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 232)
    • See DWORHN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 232).
  • 78
    • 77954328069 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (manuscript at 204)
    • See id. (manuscript at 204).
  • 79
    • 0031587707 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Assisted suicide: The philosophers' brief
    • Mar. 27, available at
    • See Ronald Dworkin et al., Assisted Suicide: The Philosophers' Brief, N.Y. REV. BOOKS, Mar. 27, 1997, at 41, 46, available at http://www.nybooks.com/ articles/1237(contending that "a state grievously ... harms such people when it prohibits [their] escape [by assisted suicide from]... what they regard as indignity"). The Briefs authors go on to argue that the state may not justify this coercive constriction of choice by taking sides in an "essentially ethical and religious controversy" over whether anyone really is harmed by it.
    • (1997) N.Y. Rev. Books , pp. 41-46
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 80
    • 77954327205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 81
    • 77954326420 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The point, for now, is simply that the authors apparently consider the constriction to be a harm
    • The point, for now, is simply that the authors apparently consider the constriction to be a harm.
  • 82
    • 77954335714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I was unable to write "special class of harms that call for a special (or stronger) form of justification." As we have already noticed
    • I was unable to write "special class of harms that call for a special (or stronger) form of justification." As we have already noticed,
  • 83
    • 77954318653 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see supra Part LG, and will see further below
    • see supra Part LG, and will see further below
  • 84
    • 77954318165 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see infra Parts II.D-E
    • , see infra Parts II.D-E,
  • 85
    • 77954343403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin does not and cannot recognize any form of further justification beyond generic justification. State measures failing the generic, justificatory test are wrongful, period
    • Dworkin does not and cannot recognize any form of further justification beyond generic justification. State measures failing the generic, justificatory test are wrongful, period.
  • 87
    • 77954330501 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 95-97
    • See id. at 95-97.
  • 88
    • 77954332627 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That is, as distinguished from the equal protection branch
    • That is, as distinguished from the equal protection branch.
  • 89
    • 77952394462 scopus 로고
    • 367 U.S. 497, 543 (Harlan, J., dissenting). Might Justice Harlan's language possibly be read to envisage an excluded-reasons understanding of protected liberty, as opposed to some sort of balancing approach? Readers who try will find themselves straining to get there
    • Poe v. Ullman, 367 U.S. 497, 543 (1961) (Harlan, J., dissenting). Might Justice Harlan's language possibly be read to envisage an excluded-reasons understanding of protected liberty, as opposed to some sort of balancing approach? Readers who try will find themselves straining to get there.
    • (1961) Poe V. Ullman
  • 90
    • 0012043543 scopus 로고
    • 198 U.S. 45, 56
    • Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45, 56 (1905).
    • (1905) Lochner V. New York
  • 91
    • 77954326253 scopus 로고
    • 165 U.S. 578, 588-90
    • Allgeyer v. Louisiana, 165 U.S. 578, 588-90 (1897).
    • (1897) Allgeyer V. Louisiana
  • 92
    • 0000351211 scopus 로고
    • The origin and scope of the american doctrine of constitutional law
    • 144
    • See James B. Thayer, The Origin and Scope of the American Doctrine of Constitutional Law, 7 HARV. L. REV. 129, 144 (1893) (maintaining, on the basis of principles of democracy, that courts should defer to legislative judgments of constitutionality, except in instances of "clear mistake").
    • (1893) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.7 , pp. 129
    • Thayer, J.B.1
  • 93
    • 0038321671 scopus 로고
    • 476 U.S. 693, 700
    • Bowen v. Roy, 476 U.S. 693, 700 (1986).
    • (1986) Bowen V. Roy
  • 94
    • 72649105493 scopus 로고
    • 505 U.S. 833, 874 (joint opinion of O'Connor, Kennedy, Souter, JJ.)
    • Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 874 (1992) (joint opinion of O'Connor, Kennedy, Souter, JJ.).
    • (1992) Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. V. Casey
  • 95
    • 77954336184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Because, say, "a woman who aborts an early pregnancy does not show the respect for human life that her dignity demands
    • Because, say, "a woman who aborts an early pregnancy does not show the respect for human life that her dignity demands."
  • 96
    • 77954328567 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 237)
    • DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 237).
  • 97
    • 77954331558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For Dworkin's own rejection, see id. (manuscript at 236)
    • For Dworkin's own rejection, see id. (manuscript at 236),
  • 99
    • 77953271218 scopus 로고
    • 432 U.S. 464, 473-74
    • Maher v. Roe, 432 U.S. 464, 473-74 (1977).
    • (1977) Maher V. Roe
  • 100
    • 0344928501 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The supreme court, 2002 term - Foreword: Fashioning the legal constitution: Culture, courts, and law
    • 8-9
    • See Robert Post, The Supreme Court, 2002 Term - Foreword: Fashioning the Legal Constitution: Culture, Courts, and Law, 117 HARV. L. REV. 4, 8-9 (2003) (defining constitutional culture as "the beliefs and values of nonjudicial actors" regarding "the substance of the Constitution," and positing "a continuous exchange between constitutional law and constitutional culture").
    • (2003) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.117 , pp. 4
    • Post, R.1
  • 101
    • 77954322433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin (if we read him that way) would not stand alone in favoring a redescription or reconstruction of "tiers" as a doctrine turning on excluded reasons
    • Dworkin (if we read him that way) would not stand alone in favoring a redescription or reconstruction of "tiers" as a doctrine turning on excluded reasons.
  • 102
    • 21844508359 scopus 로고
    • Avoiding balancing: The role of exclusionary reasons in constitutional law
    • 722
    • See, e.g., Richard H. Pildes, Avoiding Balancing: The Role of Exclusionary Reasons in Constitutional Law, 45 HASTINGS L.J. 711, 722 (1994);
    • (1994) Hastings L.J. , vol.45 , pp. 711
    • Pildes, R.H.1
  • 103
    • 77954317705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The structural conception of rights and judicial balancing
    • 195-96
    • Richard H. Pildes, The Structural Conception of Rights and Judicial Balancing, 6 REV. CONST. STUD. 179,195-96 (2001). But Pildes also (as of 2000) opined that the key-interest or "immunities" view of constitutional rights enjoys a "wide embrace" among liberal political philosophers, along with a dominance in contemporary American political culture, encouraged by "the Supreme Court's discourse of rights."
    • (2001) Rev. Const. Stud. , vol.6 , pp. 179
    • Pildes, R.H.1
  • 104
    • 0346053574 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin's two conceptions of rights
    • 311
    • Richard H. Pildes, Dworkin's Two Conceptions of Rights, 29 J. LEGAL STUD. 309, 311 (2000).
    • (2000) J. Legal Stud. , vol.29 , pp. 309
    • Pildes, R.H.1
  • 105
    • 77954326419 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfG] [Federal Constitutional Court] Nov. 5, 1980, 55 Entscheidungen des Bundesverfassungsgerichts [BVerfGE] 159 (F.R.G.). For a brief description of the case in English
    • See Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfG] [Federal Constitutional Court] Nov. 5, 1980, 55 Entscheidungen des Bundesverfassungsgerichts [BVerfGE] 159 (F.R.G.). For a brief description of the case in English,
  • 106
    • 64949142766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Proportionality in Canadian and German constitutional jurisprudence
    • 389 n.23
    • see Dieter Grimm, Proportionality in Canadian and German Constitutional Jurisprudence, 57 U. TORONTO LJ. 383, 389 n.23 (2007).
    • (2007) U. Toronto Lj. , vol.57 , pp. 383
    • Grimm, D.1
  • 107
    • 77954347760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On that score, it may have as much going for it as a law prohibiting non-medically certified opticians from duplicating broken spectacle lenses, or replacing lenses into new frames, without a doctor's prescription
    • On that score, it may have as much going for it as a law prohibiting non-medically certified opticians from duplicating broken spectacle lenses, or replacing lenses into new frames, without a doctor's prescription.
  • 109
    • 77954327390 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The order of the steps is variable, at judicial convenience
    • The order of the steps is variable, at judicial convenience.
  • 110
    • 72649084972 scopus 로고
    • 405 U.S. 438,453
    • Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U.S. 438,453 (1972).
    • (1972) Eisenstadt V. Baird
  • 111
    • 18444393325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 539 U.S. 558,565
    • Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558,565 (2003).
    • (2003) Lawrence V. Texas
  • 114
    • 77954321014 scopus 로고
    • 436 U.S. 371
    • In Baldwin v. Montana Fish & Game Commission, 436 U.S. 371 (1978), the Court held recreational hunting not to be a "fundamental" right or interest that brings into play the guarantee against state-citizenship-based discrimination contained in U.S. CONST, art. IV, §
    • (1978) Baldwin V. Montana Fish & Game Commission
  • 115
    • 77954347409 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Baldwin, 436 U.S. at 388. Assuming that the standard of "fundamental" for purposes of that clause differs from the due process/liberty standard, the latter is almost surely the tighter of the two. Jonathan Varat points out that, "[i]f it took a fundamental equal protection interest to activate the protection of the [interstate] privileges and immunities clause, the clause would be rendered superfluous
    • Baldwin, 436 U.S. at 388. Assuming that the standard of "fundamental" for purposes of that clause differs from the due process/liberty standard, the latter is almost surely the tighter of the two. Jonathan Varat points out that, "[i]f it took a fundamental equal protection interest to activate the protection of the [interstate] privileges and immunities clause, the clause would be rendered superfluous."
  • 116
    • 0346481881 scopus 로고
    • State citizenship and interstate equality
    • 513
    • Jonathan D. Varat State "Citizenship" and Interstate Equality, 48 U. CHI. L. REV. 487, 513 (1981). The same would apparently hold if it took a fundamental due process/liberty interest.
    • (1981) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.48 , pp. 487
    • Varat, J.D.1
  • 117
    • 77954329473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Contentions that recreational hunting is a sufficiently "fundamental" interest to beget heightened scrutiny of legislation restricting or regulating it have some purchase in American constitutional culture
    • Contentions that recreational hunting is a sufficiently "fundamental" interest to beget heightened scrutiny of legislation restricting or regulating it have some purchase in American constitutional culture.
  • 118
    • 77954321256 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legislative review: Game and fish
    • 138-42
    • See, e.g., Jeffrey S. Bazinet, Legislative Review: Game and Fish, 18 GA. ST. U. L. REV. 134, 138-42 (2001) (describing state legislation that declares a "fundamental right" of Georgia citizens to "hunt trap, and fish," and that arguably prescribes a heightened level of judicial scrutiny for locally imposed restrictions on these activities).
    • (2001) Ga. St. U. L. Rev. , vol.18 , pp. 134
    • Bazinet, J.S.1
  • 119
    • 77954344463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part I.B.
    • See supra Part I.B.
  • 120
    • 60950414566 scopus 로고
    • 461 U.S. 574
    • In Bob Jones University v. United States, 461 U.S. 574 (1983), the Court found that the government's interest in "eradicating racial discrimination ... substantially outweighs whatever burden [exclusion from a broadly available tax exemption for educational
    • (1983) Bob Jones University V. United States
  • 121
    • 77954323620 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • institutions places on [the private university's] exercise of... religious beliefs." Id. at 604
    • institutions] places on [the private university's] exercise of... religious beliefs." Id. at 604.
  • 122
    • 3843050115 scopus 로고
    • 468 U.S. 609 the Court found that a state's interest in its antidiscrimination policy could justify its incursion (through its civil rights law) on the "expressive" (but not, in that case, "intimate") associations interest of the Jaycees. Id. at 628
    • In Roberts v. United States Jaycees, 468 U.S. 609 (1984), the Court found that a state's interest in its antidiscrimination policy could justify its incursion (through its civil rights law) on the "expressive" (but not, in that case, "intimate") associations interest of the Jaycees. Id. at 628.
    • (1984) Roberts V. United States Jaycees
  • 123
    • 37249012363 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 530 U.S. 640 the Court found a like interest insufficient to justify what it found to be a graver incursion on an expressive-associational interest of the Scouts. Id. at 656. In Boraas, 416 U.S. 1 (1974), the Court held that a municipality's interest in avoiding evils of congestion, burdens on service capacities, and the like, could justify a limit on the size of groups of unrelated persons (such as students attending a nearby college) that could occupy a single dwelling. Id. at 5, 7
    • In Boy Scouts of America v. Dale, 530 U.S. 640 (2000), the Court found a like interest insufficient to justify what it found to be a graver incursion on an expressive-associational interest of the Scouts. Id. at 656. In Boraas, 416 U.S. 1 (1974), the Court held that a municipality's interest in avoiding evils of congestion, burdens on service capacities, and the like, could justify a limit on the size of groups of unrelated persons (such as students attending a nearby college) that could occupy a single dwelling. Id. at 5, 7.
    • (2000) Boy Scouts of America V. Dale
  • 124
    • 72549111030 scopus 로고
    • 431 U.S. 494 the Court rejected a like justification for a prohibition (in rough effect) of habitation of a single dwelling by a sizeable extended (as distinguished from nuclear) family, the plurality observing that the "importance" of the state's interests must be "carefully" examined when the state intrudes on "choices concerning family living arrangements." Id. at 499 (plurality)
    • In Moore v. City of East Cleveland, 431 U.S. 494 (1977), the Court rejected a like justification for a prohibition (in rough effect) of habitation of a single dwelling by a sizeable extended (as distinguished from nuclear) family, the plurality observing that the "importance" of the state's interests must be "carefully" examined when the state intrudes on "choices concerning family living arrangements." Id. at 499 (plurality).
    • (1977) Moore V. City of East Cleveland
  • 125
    • 28944448260 scopus 로고
    • 321 U.S. 158 the Court, while affirming the existence of "a private realm of family life which the state cannot enter" without special justification, upheld application of a state's child-labor law to prevent a guardian's enlistment of her ward in the distribution of religious tracts. Id. at 166
    • In Prince v. Massachusetts, 321 U.S. 158 (1944), the Court, while affirming the existence of "a private realm of family life which the state cannot enter" without special justification, upheld application of a state's child-labor law to prevent a guardian's enlistment of her ward in the distribution of religious tracts. Id. at 166.
    • (1944) Prince V. Massachusetts
  • 126
    • 0038321691 scopus 로고
    • 406 U.S. 205 the Court (it would seem) decided that the difference between the state's interest in an eighth-grade- and a tenth-gradeeducated citizenry could possibly be make-or-break for the state's attempted justification of restriction of the religious-freedom and familial-associational interests of Wisconsin's Old-Order Amish community. Id. at 234
    • In Wisconsin v. Yoder, 406 U.S. 205 (1972), the Court (it would seem) decided that the difference between the state's interest in an eighth-grade- and a tenth-gradeeducated citizenry could possibly be make-or-break for the state's attempted justification of restriction of the religious-freedom and familial-associational interests of Wisconsin's Old-Order Amish community. Id. at 234.
    • (1972) Wisconsin V. Yoder
  • 127
    • 77950396126 scopus 로고
    • 494 U.S. 872, 881 declining to disapprove the "balancing" test in Yoder. For more on Smith, see infra note 91
    • See also Employment Div. v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872, 881 (1990) (declining to disapprove the "balancing" test in Yoder). For more on Smith, see infra note 91.
    • (1990) Employment Div. V. Smith
  • 128
    • 77954337763 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Thus, the decisions in Roberts, 468 U.S. at 628, Bob Jones, 461 U.S. at 604, Boraas, 416 U.S. at 5, 7, and Prince, 321 U.S. at 166, upholding the proffered, public-interest justifications sufficient, are all consistent, in result if not in rhetoric, with Dworkin's suggestion that only laws "adopted for certain reasons" violate liberty. See supra text accompanying note 10. And, conversely, the Court's findings in Dale, 530 U.S. at 656, Moore, 431 U.S. at 499, and Yoder, 406 U.S. at 234, of the insufficiency of the state's alleged, public-moral interests to justify the incidentally related incursions into ethical self-determination might plausibly be reconstructed as the Court's detection of an unacceptable degree of likelihood that those alleged interests were drapery for an underlying disfavor on the lawmakers' parts for certain ethical choices and views.
  • 129
    • 77954343241 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part I.B
    • See supra Part I.B.
  • 130
    • 72649084972 scopus 로고
    • Specifically, "the decision whether to bear or beget a child." 405 U.S. 438, 453
    • Specifically, "the decision whether to bear or beget a child." Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U.S. 438, 453 (1972).
    • (1972) Eisenstadt V. Baird
  • 131
    • 77954319517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 185-86, 233)
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 185-86, 233).
  • 132
    • 72449122327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If necessary in order to ensure conformity to the "principle of abstraction" proposed by Dworkin as a part of liberal equality, the Malthus Act might provide for marketability of the four-children-per-person allowance - a "tradeable cap." See
    • If necessary in order to ensure conformity to the "principle of abstraction" proposed by Dworkin as a part of liberal equality, the Malthus Act might provide for marketability of the four-children-per-person allowance - a "tradeable cap." See RONALD DWORKIN, SOVEREIGN VIRTUE: THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF EQUALITY 147-48 (2002).
    • (2002) Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality , pp. 147-148
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 133
    • 77954331208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part I.F
    • See supra Part I.F.
  • 134
    • 77954338655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 236).
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 236).
  • 135
    • 77954326252 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (manuscript at 231-33) (arguing that laws that deny liberty for people to "decide for themselves what kind of life is good for them" are not justified).
    • See id. (manuscript at 231-33) (arguing that laws that deny liberty for people to "decide for themselves what kind of life is good for them" are not justified).
  • 136
    • 77954345192 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Just as Dworkin has foreseen we might say. See id. (manuscript at 232)
    • Just as Dworkin has foreseen we might say. See id. (manuscript at 232).
  • 137
    • 77954319788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part I.F
    • See supra Part I.F.
  • 138
    • 0000316467 scopus 로고
    • The empty idea of equality
    • 594-96
    • Cf. Peter Westen, The Empty Idea of Equality, 95 HARV. L. REV. 537, 594-96 (1982).
    • (1982) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.95 , pp. 537
    • Westen, P.1
  • 139
    • 77954332626 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 11)
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 2 (manuscript at 11).
  • 140
    • 77954336842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For those persuaded by Dworkin that normative liberty, along with other prime political-moral principles, is an inescapably "interpretive" concept, whose content can be ascertained only through the coherentist work of conceptual ascent and so on, a claim that every regulatory withdrawal from descriptive freedom violates liberty must appear extremely unlikely to be right. Such claims must be treating liberty differently - as something like a culturally determined, "criterial" concept - thus placing themselves in direct and profound philosophical disagreement with Dworkin.
  • 142
    • 77954318652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 9-21
    • Id. at 9-21.
  • 143
    • 0038321692 scopus 로고
    • Perhaps somewhat suggestive along these lines is the political response to the Supreme Court's 1990 transition, when dealing with claims of constitutional rights to religious exemptions from ethically neutral regulatory legislation, from the "balancing" approach of 374 U.S. 398, 403 to the "excluded reasons" approach of Employment
    • Perhaps somewhat suggestive along these lines is the political response to the Supreme Court's 1990 transition, when dealing with claims of constitutional rights to religious exemptions from ethically neutral regulatory legislation, from the "balancing" approach of Sherbert v. Verner, 374 U.S. 398, 403 (1963), to the "excluded reasons" approach of Employment
    • (1963) Sherbert V. Verner
  • 144
    • 77954344796 scopus 로고
    • 494 U.S. 872, 879-82 which seems more in line with Dworkin's view. Congress has restored the balancing test for federal government actions
    • Division v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872, 879-82 (1989), which seems more in line with Dworkin's view. Congress has restored the balancing test for federal government actions,
    • (1989) Division V. Smith
  • 145
    • 11144237730 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 42 U.S.C. §§2000bb-1, 2000bb-2 and sought to do so for state government actions as well, see Pub. L. No. 103-141, §5, 107 Stat. 1488, 1489 (1993) (codified as amended at 42 U.S.C. §2000bb-2);
    • see Religious Freedom Restoration Act of 1993, 42 U.S.C. §§2000bb-1, 2000bb-2 (2006), and sought to do so for state government actions as well, see Pub. L. No. 103-141, §5, 107 Stat. 1488, 1489 (1993) (codified as amended at 42 U.S.C. §2000bb-2);
    • (2006) Religious Freedom Restoration Act of 1993
  • 146
    • 77954340707 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 521 U.S. 507, 513 denying congressional authority to impose a balancing test on the states
    • City of Boerne v. Flores, 521 U.S. 507, 513 (1997) (denying congressional authority to impose a balancing test on the states).
    • (1997) City of Boerne V. Flores
  • 147
    • 77954321603 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 76 and accompanying text
    • See supra note 76 and accompanying text.
  • 148
    • 77954332355 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Baker, supra note 11, at 760
    • See Baker, supra note 11, at 760.
  • 149
    • 77954333950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It may be nothing more than the value of avoidance of harms in general, but a value it is
    • It may be nothing more than the value of avoidance of harms in general, but a value it is.
  • 150
    • 34548581802 scopus 로고
    • 302 U.S. 319, 325
    • See, e.g., Palko v. Connecticut, 302 U.S. 319, 325 (1937).
    • (1937) Palko V. Connecticut
  • 151
    • 0002498750 scopus 로고
    • Peter Laslett ed., Cambridge Univ. Press 1690
    • See JOHN LOCKE, TWO TREATISES OF GOVERNMENT 288 (Peter Laslett ed., Cambridge Univ. Press 1963) (1690).
    • (1963) Two Treatises of Government , pp. 288
    • Locke, J.1
  • 152
    • 77954337937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part II.D
    • See supra Part II.D.
  • 153
    • 77954345577 scopus 로고
    • The communist control act of 1954: A proposed legalpolitical theory of free speech
    • 188 offering a parallel defense for certain laws prohibiting advocacy of overthrow of the United States government by force and support of organizations engaged in such advocacy
    • Cf. Carl A. Auerbach, The Communist Control Act of 1954: A Proposed LegalPolitical Theory of Free Speech, 23 U. CHI. L. REV. 173, 188 (1956) (offering a parallel defense for certain laws prohibiting advocacy of overthrow of the United States government by force and support of organizations engaged in such advocacy).
    • (1956) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.23 , pp. 173
    • Auerbach, C.A.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.