-
1
-
-
84977707383
-
Why liberals should support same sex marriage
-
On same-sex marriage, see Adrian Alex Wellington, "Why Liberals Should Support Same Sex Marriage," Journal of Social Philosophy 26 (1995): 5-32;
-
(1995)
Journal of Social Philosophy
, vol.26
, pp. 5-32
-
-
Wellington, A.A.1
-
2
-
-
0033442845
-
The fundamental argument for same-sex marriage
-
Ralph Wedgwood, "The Fundamental Argument for Same-Sex Marriage," Journal of Political Philosophy 7 (1999): 225-42;
-
(1999)
Journal of Political Philosophy
, vol.7
, pp. 225-42
-
-
Wedgwood, R.1
-
3
-
-
34248072344
-
Kant, political liberalism, and the ethics of same-sex relations
-
Kory Schaff, "Kant, Political Liberalism, and the Ethics of Same-Sex Relations," Journal of Social Philosophy 32 (2001): 446-62
-
(2001)
Journal of Social Philosophy
, vol.32
, pp. 446-62
-
-
Schaff, K.1
-
4
-
-
34247670424
-
Equal protection and same-sex marriage
-
and "Equal Protection and Same-Sex Marriage," Journal of Social Philosophy 35 (2004): 133-47;
-
(2004)
Journal of Social Philosophy
, vol.35
, pp. 133-47
-
-
-
5
-
-
34247649820
-
Finding room for same-sex marriage: Toward a more inclusive understanding of a cultural institution
-
and a related argument in Nicholas Buccola, "Finding Room for Same-Sex Marriage: Toward a More Inclusive Understanding of a Cultural Institution," Journal of Social Philosophy 36 (2005): 331-343.
-
(2005)
Journal of Social Philosophy
, vol.36
, pp. 331-343
-
-
Buccola, N.1
-
6
-
-
77951704465
-
Who's afraid of polygamous marriage? Lessons for same-sex marriage advocacy from the history of polygamy
-
On polygamy, see Cheshire Calhoun, "Who's Afraid of Polygamous Marriage? Lessons for Same-Sex Marriage Advocacy from the History of Polygamy," San Diego Law Review 42 (2005): 1023-42;
-
(2005)
San Diego Law Review
, vol.42
, pp. 1023-42
-
-
Calhoun, C.1
-
7
-
-
0039426859
-
Autonomy and perfectionism in Raz's Morality of Freedom
-
Neutrality also underlies the debate over same-sex marriage between Jeff Jordan, David Boonin, and Jason Beyer (see n. 66).
-
and Jeremy Waldron, "Autonomy and Perfectionism in Raz's Morality of Freedom," Southern California Law Review 62 (1988-1989): 1097-1152. Neutrality also underlies the debate over same-sex marriage between Jeff Jordan, David Boonin, and Jason Beyer (see n. 66).
-
(1988)
Southern California Law Review
, vol.62
, pp. 1097-1152
-
-
Waldron, J.1
-
8
-
-
85055302204
-
Liberalism, autonomy, and conjugal love
-
other defenders of marriage-e.g., the new natural lawyers and Roger Scruton-do not aim at following public reason
-
I include the purportedly neutral rationale given in Christopher Bennett, "Liberalism, Autonomy, and Conjugal Love," Res Publica 9 (2003): 285-301; other defenders of marriage-e.g., the new natural lawyers and Roger Scruton-do not aim at following public reason.
-
(2003)
Res Publica
, vol.9
, pp. 285-301
-
-
Bennett, C.1
-
9
-
-
84936072510
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, esp. 157-170
-
The most influential critic is Catharine MacKinnon, Toward a Feminist Theory of the State (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1989), esp. 157-170
-
(1989)
Toward A Feminist Theory of the State
-
-
MacKinnon, C.1
-
10
-
-
85044914543
-
Perfectionism, public reason, and religious accommodation
-
On the conflict between public reason and perfectionism, see Steven Wall, "Perfectionism, Public Reason, and Religious Accommodation," Social Theory and Practice 31 (2005): 281-304.
-
(2005)
Social Theory and Practice
, vol.31
, pp. 281-304
-
-
Wall, S.1
-
11
-
-
79751521620
-
-
ed. Allen W. Wood, trans. Hugh B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), sec. 75
-
The classic source is G. F. W. Hegel [1821], Elements of the Philosophy of Right, ed. Allen W. Wood, trans. Hugh B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), sec. 75, 161A;
-
(1821)
Elements of the Philosophy of Right
-
-
Hegel, G.F.W.1
-
12
-
-
60949836614
-
Against blackstone and the concept of marriage as contract
-
for a more recent example, see Stanley Vodrasta, "Against Blackstone and the Concept of Marriage as Contract," Modern Schoolman 81 (2004): 97-120.
-
Modern Schoolman
, vol.81
, Issue.2004
, pp. 97-120
-
-
Vodrasta, S.1
-
13
-
-
77952514051
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
On the larger issues, see, e.g., Michael Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 33, 169;
-
(1982)
Liberalism and the Limits of Justice
, vol.33
, pp. 169
-
-
Sandel, M.1
-
14
-
-
84931320334
-
Individual rights and community virtues
-
and the reply by John Tomasi, "Individual Rights and Community Virtues," Ethics 101 (1991): 521-536
-
(1991)
Ethics
, vol.101
, pp. 521-536
-
-
Tomasi, J.1
-
15
-
-
77952537271
-
-
note
-
At the end of 2003, reported by the General Accounting Office (GAO), Dayna K. Shaw, Associate General Counsel, in a letter of January 23, 2004, to Bill Frist. The letter accompanies the 2004 GAO report, labeled "GAO-04-353R Defense of Marriage Act." See also Enclosure I, "Categories of Laws Involving Marital Status," in a letter of January 31, 1997, by Barry R. Bedrick, Associate General Counsel, GAO, to Henry J. Hyde. The letter accompanies the 1997 GAO report, labeled "GAO/OGC-97-116 Defense of Marriage Act."
-
-
-
-
16
-
-
0028047057
-
Gay marriage: A civil right
-
at 112
-
Craig Dean, "Gay Marriage: A Civil Right," Journal of Homosexuality 27 (1994): 111-115, at 112.
-
(1994)
Journal of Homosexuality
, vol.27
, pp. 111-115
-
-
Dean, C.1
-
17
-
-
22544470882
-
Marriage licenses
-
1781, 1783
-
Mary Anne Case, "Marriage Licenses," Minnesota Law Review 89 (2004-2005): 1758-97, 1781, 1783.
-
(2004)
Minnesota Law Review
, vol.89
, pp. 1758-97
-
-
Anne Case, M.1
-
18
-
-
77952471202
-
-
See "State Policies to Promote Marriage," a report prepared for the U.S. Department of Health and Human Services, 2002, available from the USDHHS
-
See "State Policies to Promote Marriage," a report prepared for the U.S. Department of Health and Human Services, 2002, available from the USDHHS.
-
-
-
-
19
-
-
77952492873
-
-
Department of Defense Web site
-
Department of Defense Web site (http://www.dfas.mil/);
-
-
-
-
20
-
-
77952487203
-
Marrying for money
-
April 20-26
-
Nathan McIntire, "Marrying for Money," L.A. Weekly, April 20-26, 2007, 26-27.
-
(2007)
L.A. Weekly
, pp. 26-27
-
-
McIntire, N.1
-
21
-
-
77952508926
-
-
Both quotations are from the 1997 GAO report, Enclosure I
-
Both quotations are from the 1997 GAO report, Enclosure I.
-
-
-
-
22
-
-
77952538935
-
-
note
-
In Marriage: A History (London: Penguin, 2006), Stephanie Coontz shows how this "traditional" ideal developed over the past 150 years, how its flourishing in the 1950s and 1960s was exceptional, and how it failed to apply to large numbers of working-class families.
-
-
-
-
23
-
-
77952539338
-
-
I include these forms of financial assistance here as they are directly targeted to allowing spouses to maintain a relationship
-
I include these forms of financial assistance here as they are directly targeted to allowing spouses to maintain a relationship.
-
-
-
-
24
-
-
0348064124
-
The way we live now: A discussion of contracts and domestic arrangements
-
779-780
-
In 1888, the U.S. Supreme Court wrote that, while "other contracts may be modified, restricted, or enlarged, or entirely released upon the consent of the parties," in marriage, "a relation between the parties is created which they cannot change." This is cited in Carol Weisbrod, "The Way We Live Now: A Discussion of Contracts and Domestic Arrangements," Utah Law Review 2 (1994): 777-815, 779-780
-
Utah Law Review
, vol.2
, Issue.1994
, pp. 777-815
-
-
Weisbrod, C.1
-
25
-
-
84928836981
-
Rethinking the family
-
at 88
-
Will Kymlicka, "Rethinking the Family," Philosophy & Public Affairs 20 (1991): 77-97, at 88.
-
(1991)
Philosophy & Public Affairs
, vol.20
, pp. 77-97
-
-
Kymlicka, W.1
-
26
-
-
0347433736
-
Legal regulation of marriage: Tradition and change
-
Early proponents of contractualization were Lenore Weitzman, "Legal Regulation of Marriage: Tradition and Change," California Law Review 62 (1974): 1169-288;
-
(1974)
California Law Review
, vol.62
, pp. 1169-288
-
-
Weitzman, L.1
-
27
-
-
0038590090
-
Contractual ordering of marriage: A new model for state policy
-
and Marjorie Shultz, "Contractual Ordering of Marriage: A New Model for State Policy," California Law Review 70 (1982): 204-334.
-
(1982)
California Law Review
, vol.70
, pp. 204-334
-
-
Shultz, M.1
-
28
-
-
77952510575
-
Just marriage
-
ed. Joshua Cohen and Deborah Chasman (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
-
Both proposals retain a marriage contract, which sets out domestic aspirations as well as legally enforceable obligations and is constrained by public policy. See criticism of contractualizing marriage in Mary Lyndon Shanley, "Just Marriage," in Shanley's Just Marriage, ed. Joshua Cohen and Deborah Chasman (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), 3-30.
-
(2004)
Shanley's Just Marriage
, pp. 3-30
-
-
Lyndon Shanley, M.1
-
29
-
-
77952527926
-
Postscript
-
New York: New Press
-
Case, "Marriage Licenses," 1773. Where caretaking is involved, privacy rights may protect caretaker autonomy; see Martha Fineman, "Postscript," in her The Autonomy Myth: A Theory of Dependency (New York: New Press, 2004);
-
(2004)
The Autonomy Myth: A Theory of Dependency
-
-
Fineman, M.1
-
30
-
-
33846315814
-
Parents' rights and the value of the family
-
and Harry Brighouse and Adam Swift, "Parents' Rights and the Value of the Family," Ethics 117 (2006): 80-108.
-
(2006)
Ethics
, vol.117
, pp. 80-108
-
-
Brighouse, H.1
Swift, A.2
-
31
-
-
20444452158
-
Homosexuality and the PIB argument
-
responds at length to the "polygamy, incest, bestiality" argument against same-sex marriage, an argument made by John Finnis among others
-
John Corvino, in "Homosexuality and the PIB Argument," Ethics 115 (2005): 501-534, responds at length to the "polygamy, incest, bestiality" argument against same-sex marriage, an argument made by John Finnis among others.
-
(2005)
Ethics
, vol.115
, pp. 501-534
-
-
Corvino, J.1
-
32
-
-
77952478246
-
-
For example, Kansas Code §21-3517, Ohio Code §§2907.03
-
For example, Kansas Code §21-3517, Ohio Code §§2907.03.
-
-
-
-
33
-
-
84937278709
-
Against marriage and motherhood
-
On legal access rights, see Claudia Card, "Against Marriage and Motherhood," Hypatia 11 (1996): 1-23.
-
(1996)
Hypatia
, vol.11
, pp. 1-23
-
-
Card, C.1
-
34
-
-
29244465988
-
-
Fineman argues for abolishing marriage as a legal category and replacing it with a legal framework for caretakers; thus her proposal would shift many relations now governed by marriage to the realm of contract, labor, and tort law
-
On how equity, partnership, labor, and tort law might apply, see Fineman, Autonomy Myth, 134-135 Fineman argues for abolishing marriage as a legal category and replacing it with a legal framework for caretakers; thus her proposal would shift many relations now governed by marriage to the realm of contract, labor, and tort law.
-
Autonomy Myth
, pp. 134-135
-
-
Fineman1
-
35
-
-
77952531842
-
-
Their exclusion is overdetermined: parents or guardians have rights regarding minors in their care, with which minimal marriage contracts might conflict. See Brighouse and Swift, "Parents' Rights."
-
Their exclusion is overdetermined: parents or guardians have rights regarding minors in their care, with which minimal marriage contracts might conflict. See Brighouse and Swift, "Parents' Rights."
-
-
-
-
36
-
-
77952507744
-
-
note
-
How many close relationships can one have? Apparently the social networking site Facebook limits users to 5,000 "friends"; most of these would presumably be mere acquaintances. I suspect the actual number of sustainable caring relationships is much lower. It might be objected that this criterion raises the bar as contrasted with current marriage, which does not require a caring relationship. It might be responded that, in immigration cases, spouses are required to document their intimacy and shared history. Although it would be impractical and invasive for the state to undertake such investigations in every case, it does not seem undesirable, in theory, to make such a relationship a criterion for legal marriage (ruling out, for instance, mail-order brides).
-
-
-
-
37
-
-
77952471565
-
-
a 2001 publication of the Law Commission of Canada, available at, examines the feasibility of self-designation (32-36) and other questions of institutional design. Thanks to Rachel Buddeberg for drawing my attention to this document
-
"Beyond Conjugality: Recognizing and Supporting Close Personal Adult Relationships," a 2001 publication of the Law Commission of Canada, available at http://www.samesexmarriage.ca/docs/beyond-conjugality.pdf, examines the feasibility of self-designation (32-36) and other questions of institutional design. Thanks to Rachel Buddeberg for drawing my attention to this document.
-
Beyond Conjugality: Recognizing and Supporting Close Personal Adult Relationships
-
-
-
38
-
-
0003624191
-
-
New York: Columbia University Press
-
See John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), 212-54
-
(1993)
Political Liberalism
, pp. 212-254
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
39
-
-
0347873666
-
The idea of public reason revisited
-
and "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited," University of Chicago Law Review 64 (1997): 765-807.
-
(1997)
University of Chicago Law Review
, vol.64
, pp. 765-807
-
-
-
40
-
-
0003624191
-
-
It should be noted that citizens can invoke comprehensive doctrines in debate (e.g., referring to God) so long as their views are independently supported by public reason; Rawls, Political Liberalism, 252.
-
Political Liberalism
, pp. 252
-
-
Rawls1
-
41
-
-
0003624191
-
-
Many versions of this principle have been defended; here I introduce Rawls's later formulation, which complements his account of public reason. See Rawls, Political Liberalism, 190-95;
-
Political Liberalism
, pp. 190-95
-
-
Rawls1
-
42
-
-
0004048289
-
-
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), and sec. 50.
-
for comparison, John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), at p. 94, and sec. 50.
-
(1971)
A Theory of Justice
, pp. 94
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
43
-
-
0004088293
-
-
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), chap. 2
-
See also the careful critical discussion of variant neutrality principles in George Sher, Beyond Neutrality: Perfectionism and Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), chap. 2.
-
(1997)
Beyond Neutrality: Perfectionism and Politics
-
-
Sher, G.1
-
45
-
-
0003956640
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
See Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986), 114-24;
-
(1986)
The Morality of Freedom
, pp. 114-24
-
-
Raz, J.1
-
46
-
-
77951900150
-
Neutrality and responsibility
-
Steven Wall, "Neutrality and Responsibility," Journal of Philosophy 98 (2001): 389-410.
-
(2001)
Journal of Philosophy
, vol.98
, pp. 389-410
-
-
Wall, S.1
-
48
-
-
84935435325
-
Liberal individualism and liberal neutrality
-
and in Will Kymlicka, "Liberal Individualism and Liberal Neutrality," Ethics 99 (1989): 883-905.
-
(1989)
Ethics
, vol.99
, pp. 883-905
-
-
Kymlicka, W.1
-
49
-
-
77952475028
-
-
it also applies to citizens in political contexts
-
Rawls, Political Liberalism, 252; it also applies to citizens in political contexts.
-
Political Liberalism
, vol.252
-
-
Rawls1
-
50
-
-
0002169876
-
-
Sher, Beyond Neutrality, 36. This exposition follows Sher at 28. Sher raises problems with defining "conception of the good"
-
Beyond Neutrality
, pp. 36
-
-
Sher1
-
51
-
-
0002169876
-
-
This exposition follows Sher at 28. Sher raises problems with defining conception of the good" but as judgments regarding sexual behavior and relationships are commonly given as examples of such conceptions, I set this aside. See Sher, Beyond Neutrality, 37-43;
-
Beyond Neutrality
, pp. 37-43
-
-
Sher1
-
52
-
-
63849086576
-
-
and "The Idea" 779
-
Rawls, Theory of Justice, 331, and "The Idea," 779.
-
Theory of Justice
, pp. 331
-
-
Rawls1
-
54
-
-
0002169876
-
-
apply neutrality more extensively to all policy; in such theories, I would not face the objection
-
Rawls, in Theory of Justice, and other neutral liberals (see Sher, Beyond Neutrality, 31-34) apply neutrality more extensively to all policy; in such theories, I would not face the objection.
-
Beyond Neutrality
, pp. 31-34
-
-
Sher1
-
56
-
-
77952525389
-
-
The Idea Ibid., 788.
-
The Idea
, pp. 788
-
-
-
58
-
-
0003981612
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
Ronald Dworkin, A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985), 191;
-
(1985)
A Matter of Principle
, pp. 191
-
-
Dworkin, R.1
-
62
-
-
77952520707
-
-
See Adèle Mercier's affidavit for the petitioners in Halpern v. Canada, A.G. on the meaning of the word 'marriage', filed in the Ontario Superior Court of Justice, Court files 684/00, 30/2001, November.
-
See Adèle Mercier's affidavit for the petitioners in Halpern v. Canada, A.G. on the meaning of the word 'marriage', filed in the Ontario Superior Court of Justice, Court files 684/00, 30/2001, November.
-
-
-
-
64
-
-
0003750156
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
William Galston, Liberal Purposes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), 283-89.
-
(1991)
Liberal Purposes
, pp. 283-89
-
-
Galston, W.1
-
65
-
-
34250641529
-
Traditionalism, pluralism, and same-sex marriage
-
386
-
Recent findings of benefits of two-parent families are reported in Amy Wax, "Traditionalism, Pluralism, and Same-Sex Marriage," Rutgers Law Review 59 (2006-2007): 377-412, 386.
-
(2006)
Rutgers Law Review
, vol.59
, pp. 377-412
-
-
Wax, A.1
-
66
-
-
77952475027
-
Promoting cooperative parenting: Programs and prospects
-
at 266 n. 9
-
Paul R. Amato and Alan Booth, cited in Marsha Garrison, "Promoting Cooperative Parenting: Programs and Prospects," Journal of Law and Family Studies 9 (2007): 265-79, at 266 n. 9.
-
(2007)
Journal of Law and Family Studies
, vol.9
, pp. 265-79
-
-
Garrison, M.1
-
67
-
-
84937294003
-
Parental divorce, marital conflict, and offspring well-being during early adulthood
-
which finds that children of high-conflict marriages benefit significantly from divorce, so effects of divorce are not simply "additive."
-
See also Paul R. Amato, Laura Spencer Loomis, and Alan Booth, "Parental Divorce, Marital Conflict, and Offspring Well-Being during Early Adulthood," Social Forces 73 (1995): 895-915, which finds that children of high-conflict marriages benefit significantly from divorce, so effects of divorce are not simply "additive."
-
(1995)
Social Forces
, vol.73
, pp. 895-915
-
-
Amato, P.R.1
Spencer Loomis, L.2
Booth, A.3
-
68
-
-
84937297693
-
Mothers, citizenship, and independence: A critique of pure family values
-
See Iris Marion Young, "Mothers, Citizenship, and Independence: A Critique of Pure Family Values," Ethics 105 (1995): 535-556
-
(1995)
Ethics
, vol.105
, pp. 535-556
-
-
Young, I.M.1
-
69
-
-
77952470433
-
-
at the Becker-Posner blog
-
See Gary Becker, at the Becker-Posner blog, http://www.becker-posner- blog.com/archives/2007/03/should-marriage-1.html;
-
-
-
Becker, G.1
-
71
-
-
0004233528
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
On the Court review, see Martha Nussbaum, Sex and Social Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 205.
-
(1999)
Sex and Social Justice
, vol.205
-
-
Nussbaum, M.1
-
72
-
-
77952519183
-
Harm prevention and the benefits of marriage
-
For more on harm-to-children arguments, see Eric M. Cave, "Harm Prevention and the Benefits of Marriage," Journal of Social Philosophy 35 (2004): 233-243
-
(2004)
Journal of Social Philosophy
, vol.35
, pp. 233-243
-
-
Cave, E.M.1
-
73
-
-
77952505331
-
-
Moreover, Garrison reports that inadequate evidence exists as to the success of marital conflict reduction under the Healthy Marriage Initiative, studies have not been done on the worst-off demographics, studies show that 25 percent of couples are worse off after therapy, and posttherapy divorce rates remain high ("Promoting Cooperative Parenting," 273-75).
-
Promoting Cooperative Parenting
, pp. 273-75
-
-
-
77
-
-
77952507743
-
-
U.S. Department of Justice, NCJ 207846
-
According to U.S. Department of Justice statistics, of the "roughly 3.5 million violent crimes committed against family members during 1998 to 2000 48.9% were crimes against a spouse 84% of victims of spousal abuse were female" Matthew R. Durose, Caroline Wolf Harlow, Patrick A. Langan, Mark Motivans, Ramona R. Rantala, and Erica L. Smith, Bureau of Justice Statistics, Family Violence Statistics: Including Statistics on Strangers and Acquaintances, U.S. Department of Justice, NCJ 207846 (2005), 8, 1.
-
(2005)
Bureau of Justice Statistics, Family Violence Statistics: Including Statistics on Strangers and Acquaintances
, vol.8
, pp. 1
-
-
Durose, M.R.1
Harlow, C.W.2
Langan, P.A.3
Motivans, M.4
Rantala, R.R.5
Smith, E.L.6
-
80
-
-
77952495609
-
-
Bennett has similar difficulties explaining why his rationale restricts marriage to pairs, in "Liberalism."
-
Bennett has similar difficulties explaining why his rationale restricts marriage to pairs, in "Liberalism."
-
-
-
-
83
-
-
77952535376
-
-
reprinted in Andrew Sullivan, ed. (New York: Vintage)
-
reprinted in Andrew Sullivan, ed., Same-Sex Marriage: Pro and Con (New York: Vintage, 2004), 122-28.
-
(2004)
Same-Sex Marriage: Pro and Con
, pp. 122-28
-
-
-
85
-
-
77952524634
-
The public supports of love
-
Shanley. Emma Goldman and Voltairine De Cleyre are earlier critics of state regulation of sexuality and the possessiveness and dependence of marriage
-
and Drucilla Cornell, "The Public Supports of Love," in Shanley, Just Marriage, 81-86. Emma Goldman and Voltairine De Cleyre are earlier critics of state regulation of sexuality and the possessiveness and dependence of marriage.
-
Just Marriage
, pp. 81-86
-
-
Cornell, D.1
-
86
-
-
24944452520
-
-
New York: Pantheon
-
Laura Kipnis, Against Love (New York: Pantheon, 2003);
-
(2003)
Against Love
-
-
Kipnis, L.1
-
87
-
-
34247448996
-
Marital pluralism: Making marriage safer for love
-
compare Friedrich von Schlegel's novel Lucinde (1799) and Eric M. Cave, "Marital Pluralism: Making Marriage Safer for Love," Journal of Social Philosophy 34 (2003): 331-347
-
(2003)
Journal of Social Philosophy
, vol.34
, pp. 331-347
-
-
Cave, E.M.1
-
89
-
-
3142717072
-
Compulsory heterosexuality and lesbian existence
-
ed. Albert Gelpi and Barbara Charlesworth Gelpi (London: Norton)
-
Adrienne Rich [1980], "Compulsory Heterosexuality and Lesbian Existence," in Adrienne Rich's Poetry and Prose, ed. Albert Gelpi and Barbara Charlesworth Gelpi (London: Norton, 1993), 203-224
-
(1980)
Adrienne Rich's Poetry and Prose
, pp. 203-224
-
-
Rich, A.1
-
90
-
-
61949347470
-
Monogamy: A critique
-
John McMurtry, "Monogamy: A Critique," Monist 56 (1972): 587-599
-
(1972)
Monist
, vol.56
, pp. 587-599
-
-
McMurtry, J.1
-
91
-
-
77952469679
-
-
New York: HarperCollins
-
See Sasha Cagen, Quirkyalone (New York: HarperCollins, 2006);
-
(2006)
Quirkyalone
-
-
Cagen, S.1
-
92
-
-
77952535734
-
-
Time and The Economist reported in 2000 on the growing number of unmarried urbanites.
-
Cagen writes, 18, that Time and The Economist reported in 2000 on the growing number of unmarried urbanites.
-
-
-
-
93
-
-
77952532737
-
Foreword
-
rev. ed., New York: Vintage
-
Toni Morrison, "Foreword," in Beloved (1987; rev. ed., New York: Vintage, 2004), xvi-xvii.
-
(1987)
Beloved
-
-
Morrison, T.1
-
94
-
-
0040930179
-
Revolutionary parenting
-
Boston: South End
-
bell hooks, "Revolutionary Parenting," in her Feminist Theory: From Margin to Center (Boston: South End, 1984), 133-146
-
(1984)
Feminist Theory: From Margin to Center
, pp. 133-146
-
-
-
95
-
-
84882692300
-
It's all in the family: Intersections of gender, race, and nation
-
62
-
Patricia Hill Collins, "It's All in the Family: Intersections of Gender, Race, and Nation," Hypatia 13 (1998): 62-82, 62.
-
(1998)
Hypatia
, vol.13
, pp. 62-82
-
-
Hill Collins, P.1
-
96
-
-
77952470062
-
Beyond diversity: Exploring the ways in which the discourse of race has shaped the institution of the nuclear family
-
ed. Enakshi Dua and Angela Robertson (Toronto:Women's Press)
-
See also Enakshi Dua, "Beyond Diversity: Exploring the Ways in Which the Discourse of Race Has Shaped the Institution of the Nuclear Family," in Scratching the Surface, ed. Enakshi Dua and Angela Robertson (Toronto:Women's Press, 1999), 237-259
-
(1999)
Scratching the Surface
, pp. 237-259
-
-
Dua, E.1
-
99
-
-
39449127273
-
51% of Women Are Now Living without Spouse
-
January 16; an editorial ("Can a 15-Year-Old Be a 'Woman without a Spouse'?" published February 11, 2007) criticized the data but acknowledged that revised calculations showed a majority of spouseless women
-
"51% of Women Are Now Living without Spouse," New York Times, January 16, 2007; an editorial ("Can a 15-Year-Old Be a 'Woman without a Spouse'?" published February 11, 2007) criticized the data but acknowledged that revised calculations showed a majority of spouseless women.
-
(2007)
New York Times
-
-
-
101
-
-
77952533511
-
-
consider and reject harm-based arguments for restricting marriage; I direct the reader to their able refutations
-
and Cave, "Harm Prevention," consider and reject harm-based arguments for restricting marriage; I direct the reader to their able refutations.
-
Harm Prevention
-
-
Cave1
-
102
-
-
0004339288
-
-
Raz's suggested argument for marriage might thus be extended to adult care networks. See Raz, Morality of Freedom, 161-162
-
Morality of Freedom
, pp. 161-162
-
-
Raz1
-
103
-
-
84977712351
-
Is it wrong to discriminate on the basis of homosexuality?
-
See Jeff Jordan, "Is It Wrong to Discriminate on the Basis of Homosexuality?" Journal of Social Philosophy 26 (1995): 39-52.
-
(1995)
Journal of Social Philosophy
, vol.26
, pp. 39-52
-
-
Jordan, J.1
-
104
-
-
26444543529
-
Same-sex marriage and the argument from public disagreement
-
David Boonin ("Same-Sex Marriage and the Argument from Public Disagreement," Journal of Social Philosophy 30 [1999]: 251-59)
-
(1999)
Journal of Social Philosophy
, vol.30
, pp. 251-59
-
-
Boonin, D.1
-
105
-
-
34247443169
-
Public dilemmas and gay marriage: Contra Jordan
-
respond
-
Jason A. Beyer ("Public Dilemmas and Gay Marriage: Contra Jordan," Journal of Social Philosophy 33 [2002]: 9-16) respond.
-
(2002)
Journal of Social Philosophy
, vol.33
, pp. 9-16
-
-
Beyer, J.A.1
-
106
-
-
33750501708
-
John rawls, justice in the family, and justice of the family
-
Veronique Munoz-Dardé, "John Rawls, Justice in the Family, and Justice of the Family," Philosophical Quarterly 48 (1998): 335-52;
-
(1998)
Philosophical Quarterly
, vol.48
, pp. 335-52
-
-
Munoz-Dardé, V.1
-
108
-
-
61149625616
-
-
see also discussion in Rawls, "The Idea," 787-894.
-
The Idea
, pp. 787-894
-
-
Rawls1
-
109
-
-
77952493234
-
Why unilateral divorce has no place in a free society
-
ed. Robert P. George and Jean Bethke Elshtain (Dallas: Spence) 75
-
Jennifer Roback Morse, "Why Unilateral Divorce Has No Place in a Free Society," in The Meaning of Marriage, ed. Robert P. George and Jean Bethke Elshtain (Dallas: Spence, 2006), 74-99, 75.
-
(2006)
The Meaning of Marriage
, pp. 74-99
-
-
Roback Morse, J.1
-
110
-
-
77952520359
-
-
and chap. 2.
-
Coontz, Marriage, 10, and chap. 2.
-
Marriage
, pp. 10
-
-
Coontz1
-
112
-
-
77952512450
-
-
he cites Leslie Green, at n. 14
-
See Wedgwood, "The Fundamental Argument"; he cites Leslie Green, 236, at n. 14;
-
The Fundamental Argument
, pp. 236
-
-
Wedgwood1
-
113
-
-
84913596996
-
-
cf. Raz, Morality, 307-313
-
Morality
, pp. 307-313
-
-
Raz1
-
115
-
-
85055359837
-
-
For example, Galston, Liberal Purposes. While Galston's influential version challenged neutrality, a neutrality-respecting version is possible. For critical discussion, see Young, "Mothers";
-
Mothers
-
-
Young1
-
117
-
-
0002868117
-
Political liberalism, justice, and gender
-
Susan Moller Okin, "Political Liberalism, Justice, and Gender," Ethics 105 (1994): 23-43.
-
(1994)
Ethics
, vol.105
, pp. 23-43
-
-
Okin, S.M.1
-
118
-
-
85044809332
-
Liberalism, adaptive preferences, and gender equality
-
See Ann Levey, "Liberalism, Adaptive Preferences, and Gender Equality," Hypatia 20 (2005): 127-143
-
(2005)
Hypatia
, vol.20
, pp. 127-143
-
-
Levey, A.1
-
119
-
-
77952476248
-
-
Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for Ethics for this point
-
Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for Ethics for this point.
-
-
-
-
120
-
-
0039688242
-
-
New York: Routledge
-
See Eva Kittay, Love's Labor (New York: Routledge, 1999).
-
(1999)
Love's Labor
-
-
Kittay, E.1
-
124
-
-
0003624191
-
-
also 178-82, 187-190
-
Political Liberalism, Ibid., 75-76; also 178-82, 187-190
-
Political Liberalism
, pp. 75-76
-
-
-
125
-
-
84921273026
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
For more detailed, and critical, discussion of various definitions proposed in the literature, see Virginia Held, The Ethics of Care: Personal, Political, and Global (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), 29-43.
-
(2006)
The Ethics of Care: Personal, Political, and Global
, pp. 29-43
-
-
Held, V.1
-
126
-
-
29244465988
-
-
Such caretaking has costs for caretakers; this speaks to the need for dependent caretaking frameworks, for which there have recently been a number of arguments; see Fineman, The Autonomy Myth;
-
The Autonomy Myth;
-
-
Fineman1
-
129
-
-
0003624191
-
-
As almost everyone will need care at some point, excluding this fact about human life is problematic, but I do not pursue this here; it is tangential to my main point about caring relationships
-
Rawls suggests that adult dependency be dealt with at the legislative stage under the assumption that citizens are normally able to cooperate (Rawls, Political Liberalism, 184-86). As almost everyone will need care at some point, excluding this fact about human life is problematic, but I do not pursue this here; it is tangential to my main point about caring relationships.
-
Political Liberalism
, pp. 184-86
-
-
Rawls1
-
130
-
-
77952499508
-
-
There are differences: Fineman and Kittay argue for state support for dependent caretakers, which would not be appropriate in nondependent caring relationships
-
There are differences: Fineman and Kittay argue for state support for dependent caretakers, which would not be appropriate in nondependent caring relationships.
-
-
-
-
132
-
-
34147197324
-
The best of times, the worst of times: The place of close relationships in psychology and our daily lives
-
this was Perlman's 2006 presidential address to the Canadian Psychological Association
-
For a survey of psychological benefits of interpersonal relationships, see Daniel Perlman, "The Best of Times, the Worst of Times: The Place of Close Relationships in Psychology and Our Daily Lives," Canadian Psychology 48 (2007): 7-18 (this was Perlman's 2006 presidential address to the Canadian Psychological Association).
-
(2007)
Canadian Psychology
, vol.48
, pp. 7-18
-
-
Perlman, D.1
-
133
-
-
77952510980
-
-
on centrality; quotation from 11. Perlman also notes the devastating psychological effects of abuse and exploitation; however, that bad relationships are injurious does not make good ones less important
-
See Perlman, "The Best of Times," 7-8, on centrality; quotation from 11. Perlman also notes the devastating psychological effects of abuse and exploitation; however, that bad relationships are injurious does not make good ones less important.
-
The Best of Times
, pp. 7-8
-
-
Perlman1
-
134
-
-
38349192674
-
Moral neutrality and primary goods
-
See Adina Schwartz, "Moral Neutrality and Primary Goods," Ethics 83 (1973): 294-307;
-
(1973)
Ethics
, vol.83
, pp. 294-307
-
-
Schwartz, A.1
-
135
-
-
0002040744
-
Rawls on justice
-
Thomas Nagel, "Rawls on Justice," Philosophical Review 82 (1973): 220-34;
-
(1973)
Philosophical Review
, vol.82
, pp. 220-34
-
-
Nagel, T.1
-
138
-
-
4344656234
-
-
London: Free Press
-
See, e.g., Roger Scruton, Sexual Desire (London: Free Press, 1986), 358;
-
(1986)
Sexual Desire
, pp. 358
-
-
Scruton, R.1
-
139
-
-
70449928017
-
'Same-sex marriage' and 'Moral neutrality'
-
ed. Christopher Wolfe (Dallas: Spence)
-
Robert George, "'Same-Sex Marriage' and 'Moral Neutrality'," in Homosexuality and American Public Life, ed. Christopher Wolfe (Dallas: Spence, 2000), 141-153
-
(2000)
Homosexuality and American Public Life
, pp. 141-153
-
-
George, R.1
-
140
-
-
85055309830
-
'Ideal theory' as ideology
-
For discussion of the difficulties here, see Charles Mills, "'Ideal Theory' as Ideology," Hypatia 20 (2005): 165-184
-
(2005)
Hypatia
, vol.20
, pp. 165-184
-
-
Mills, C.1
-
143
-
-
77952478922
-
-
note
-
"State Policies to Promote Marriage," 1. See also the 1996 U.S. Personal Responsibility and Work Opportunity Reconciliation Act, Title I, Sec. 101 (findings and related congressional testimony asserting pressing public interest in maintaining our current understanding of marriage.)
-
-
-
-
146
-
-
77952506107
-
-
See online documents at
-
See online documents at http://www.aahmi.net/.
-
-
-
-
150
-
-
77952532641
-
Interpersonal obligation, spousal support, and the social nature of intimacy
-
paper presented at the, Birmingham, June 29 to July 1
-
Lucinda Ferguson, "Interpersonal Obligation, Spousal Support, and the Social Nature of Intimacy," paper presented at the 2007 Applied Philosophy annual conference, Philosophy and the Family, Birmingham, June 29 to July 1.
-
2007 Applied Philosophy Annual Conference, Philosophy and the Family
-
-
Ferguson, L.1
-
151
-
-
62449239436
-
Privatizing marriage
-
at 384
-
Cass Sunstein and Richard Thaler, "Privatizing Marriage," Monist 91 (2008): 377-387, at 384.
-
(2008)
Monist
, vol.91
, pp. 377-387
-
-
Sunstein, C.1
Thaler, R.2
-
152
-
-
77952509299
-
Polygamy and monogamy in marriage markets
-
enlarged ed. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)
-
See Gary Becker, "Polygamy and Monogamy in Marriage Markets," in his A Treatise on the Family, enlarged ed. (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), 80-107.
-
(1993)
A Treatise on the Family
, pp. 80-107
-
-
Becker, G.1
|