메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 27, Issue 1, 2010, Pages 233-275

Coercion, ownership, and the redistributive state: Justificatory liberalism's classical tilt

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 77951915209     PISSN: 02650525     EISSN: 14716437     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0265052509990100     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (58)

References (118)
  • 1
    • 0141922253 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Christopher J. Eberle applies this term to a family of liberal views I describe in the text, which stress that the basic requirement of a just and legitimate state is that it can be justified to all reasonable citizens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Christopher J. Eberle applies this term to a family of liberal views I describe in the text, which stress that the basic requirement of a just and legitimate state is that it can be justified to all reasonable citizens. See Eberle, Religious Conviction in Liberal Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 11-13.
    • (2002) Religious Conviction in Liberal Politics , pp. 11-13
    • Eberle1
  • 2
    • 77952612475 scopus 로고
    • Of the original contract
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See David Hume, "Of the Original Contract," in his Essays Moral, Political, and Literary (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1963), 452-473
    • (1963) Essays Moral, Political, and Literary , pp. 452-473
    • Hume, D.1
  • 3
    • 0003408961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2d ed., trans. John Ladd Indianapolis: Hackett. secs. 42-43. sec. 50 (p. 146)
    • See Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysical Elements of Justice, 2d ed., trans. John Ladd (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1999), secs. 42-43 (pp. 114-17), sec. 50 (p. 146).
    • (1999) The Metaphysical Elements of Justice , pp. 114-117
    • Kant, I.1
  • 4
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • rev. ed. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. (p. 17 of the original edition)
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, rev. ed. (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1999), p. 16 (p. 17 of the original edition).
    • (1999) A Theory of Justice , pp. 16
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 6
    • 0011533193 scopus 로고
    • Second treatise of government
    • ed. Peter Laslett Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. sec. 21.
    • John Locke, Second Treatise of Government, in Two Treatises of Government, ed. Peter Laslett (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1960), sec. 21.
    • (1960) Two Treatises of Government
    • Locke, J.1
  • 7
    • 0004011977 scopus 로고
    • Foundations of the metaphysics of morals
    • ed. and trans. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill Akademie ed., 433-34]
    • Immanuel Kant, Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, ed. and trans. Lewis White Beck (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1959), 52 [Akademie ed., 433-34].
    • (1959) Lewis White Beck , pp. 52
    • Kant, I.1
  • 8
    • 0013274901 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Justice as fairness
    • Samuel Freeman, ed., Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • John Rawls, "Justice as Fairness," in Samuel Freeman, ed., John Rawls: Collected Papers (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 55.
    • (1999) John Rawls: Collected Papers , pp. 55
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 10
    • 84923989522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I explore these dimensions in more detail in my essay "The Idea and Ideal of Capitalism," Tom Beauchamp and George Brenkert, eds., Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • I explore these dimensions in more detail in my essay "The Idea and Ideal of Capitalism," in Tom Beauchamp and George Brenkert, eds., The Oxford Handbook of Business Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009).
    • (2009) The Oxford Handbook of Business Ethics
  • 11
    • 0003460985 scopus 로고
    • The classic work on the economic policy of classical liberal political economy is Lionel Robbins. London: Macmillan
    • The classic work on the economic policy of classical liberal political economy is Lionel Robbins, The Theory of Economic Policy in English Classical Political Economy (London: Macmillan, 1961).
    • (1961) The Theory of Economic Policy in English Classical Political Economy
  • 12
    • 0003764649 scopus 로고
    • Perhaps the most sophisticated classical analysis of the functions of government is Book V of John Stuart Mill
    • Perhaps the most sophisticated classical analysis of the functions of government is Book V of John Stuart Mill, The Principles of Political Economy (1848)
    • (1848) The Principles of Political Economy
  • 13
    • 77952590857 scopus 로고
    • J. M. Robson, ed., Toronto: University of Toronto Press
    • in J. M. Robson, ed., The CollectedWorks of John Stuart Mill (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1977), vol.3.
    • (1977) The CollectedWorks of John Stuart Mill , pp. 3
  • 14
    • 3242680048 scopus 로고
    • Public and private interests in liberal political economy old and new
    • See also my essay. S.I. Benn and G. F. Gaus, eds., New York: St. Martin's
    • See also my essay "Public and Private Interests in Liberal Political Economy, Old and New," in S. I. Benn and G. F. Gaus, eds., Public and Private in Social Life (New York: St. Martin's, 1983), 192-193
    • (1983) Public and Private in Social Life , pp. 192-193
  • 15
    • 0004273805 scopus 로고
    • It is thus unfortunate that so many have viewed Robert Nozick's somewhat doctrinaire defense of the "night-watchman state" as definitive of the classical liberal tradition. New York: Basic Books
    • It is thus unfortunate that so many have viewed Robert Nozick's somewhat doctrinaire defense of the "night-watchman state" as definitive of the classical liberal tradition. See his Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 25-27.
    • (1974) Anarchy, State, and Utopia , pp. 25-27
  • 16
    • 34247514937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Classical liberalism and libertarianism: The liberty tradition
    • On the relation between libertarianism and classical liberalism. Gerald F. Gaus and Chandran Kukathas, eds. London: Sage Publications
    • On the relation between libertarianism and classical liberalism, see Eric Mack and Gerald Gaus, "Classical Liberalism and Libertarianism: The Liberty Tradition," in Gerald F. Gaus and Chandran Kukathas, eds., Handbook of Political Theory (London: Sage Publications, 2004), 115-130
    • (2004) Handbook of Political Theory , pp. 115-130
    • MacK, E.1    Gaus, G.2
  • 19
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls also believes that a just society would seek reasonable ways to limit wasteful forms of advertising: "the funds now devoted to advertising can be released for investment or for other useful social ends New York: Columbia University Press
    • Rawls also believes that a just society would seek reasonable ways to limit wasteful forms of advertising: "the funds now devoted to advertising can be released for investment or for other useful social ends." John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), 365.
    • (1996) Political Liberalism , pp. 365
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 20
    • 0004168076 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 48;
    • (1999) The Law of Peoples , pp. 48
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 21
    • 3042681013 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Illiberal libertarians: Why libertarianism is not a liberal view
    • Samuel Freeman, "Illiberal Libertarians: Why Libertarianism Is Not a Liberal View," Philosophy and Public Affairs 30 (2001): 105-151
    • (2001) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.30 , pp. 105-151
    • Freeman, S.1
  • 22
    • 0003836741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Erin Kelly Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. 135ff
    • Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, ed. Erin Kelly (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001), 135ff.
    • (2001) Rawls, Justice As Fairness: A Restatement
  • 24
    • 34247522442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Justifying the moral rights of the moderns: A case of old wine in new bottles
    • Gerald F. Gaus, "On Justifying the Moral Rights of the Moderns: A Case of Old Wine in New Bottles," Social Philosophy and Policy 24, no.1 (2007): 84-119.
    • (2007) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.24 , Issue.1 , pp. 84-119
    • Gaus, G.F.1
  • 26
    • 0010194489 scopus 로고
    • Capitalism, 'property-owning democracy,' and the welfare state
    • Amy Gutmann, ed., Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • and Richard Krouse and Michael McPherson, "Capitalism, 'Property-Owning Democracy,' and the Welfare State," in Amy Gutmann, ed., Democracy and the Welfare State (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1988).
    • (1988) Democracy and the Welfare State
    • Krouse, R.1    McPherson, M.2
  • 27
    • 34248040081 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Neo-Republicanism and the civic economy
    • For a discussion of possible policies of such a system
    • For a discussion of possible policies of such a system, see Richard Dagger, "Neo-Republicanism and the Civic Economy," Politics, Philosophy, and Economics 5 (2006): 151-173
    • (2006) Politics, Philosophy, and Economics , vol.5 , pp. 151-173
    • Dagger, R.1
  • 28
    • 0003439620 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Joel Feinberg, Harm to Others (New York: Oxford University Press, 1984), 9.
    • (1984) Harm to Others , pp. 9
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 29
    • 0003709264 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Stanley Benn, A Theory of Freedom (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 87.
    • (1988) A Theory of Freedom , pp. 87
    • Benn, S.1
  • 31
    • 0004081071 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is not to say that the presumption in favor of liberty does not itself have to be argued for Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 379ff
    • This is not to say that the presumption in favor of liberty does not itself have to be argued for. See my Value and Justification (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 379ff.
    • (1990) Value and Justification
  • 33
    • 0004081071 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I consider such a presumption in some detail
    • I consider such a presumption in some detail in Value and Justification, 381-386
    • Value and Justification , pp. 381-386
  • 34
    • 24944549049 scopus 로고
    • Are Property rights problematic?
    • and I argue this point in more detail in October
    • Loren E. Lomasky and I argue this point in more detail in "Are Property Rights Problematic?" The Monist 73 (October, 1990): 483-503.
    • (1990) The Monist , vol.73 , pp. 483-503
    • Lomasky, L.E.1
  • 36
    • 84923218804 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political liberty: Integrating five conceptions of autonomy
    • John Christman and Joel Anderson, eds., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Rainer Frost, "Political Liberty: Integrating Five Conceptions of Autonomy," in John Christman and Joel Anderson, eds., Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 240 n. 24.
    • (2005) Autonomy and the Challenges to Liberalism , vol.240 , Issue.24
    • Frost, R.1
  • 37
    • 35148879560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The way in which morality involves claims to authority over others is a central theme of Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • The way in which morality involves claims to authority over others is a central theme of Stephen Darwall, The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2006).
    • (2006) The Second-Person Standpoint: Morality, Respect, and Accountability
    • Darwall, S.1
  • 40
    • 84859841703 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an excellent survey, see Scott Anderson's entry on "Coercion" Spring edition, ed. Edward N. Zalta
    • For an excellent survey, see Scott Anderson's entry on "Coercion" in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2006 edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta, http://plato. stanford.edu/archives/spr2006/ entries/coercion/.
    • (2006) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • 41
    • 77952631994 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is not to say that coercion against noncitizens does not require justification; it simply falls outside the scope of the Political Liberty Principle, which specifies a necessary, not a sufficient, condition for justified coercion
    • This is not to say that coercion against noncitizens does not require justification; it simply falls outside the scope of the Political Liberty Principle, which specifies a necessary, not a sufficient, condition for justified coercion.
  • 42
    • 0003804620 scopus 로고
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. 277ff
    • See Alan Wertheimer, Coercion (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1987), 277ff.
    • (1987) Coercion
    • Wertheimer, A.1
  • 43
    • 77952613355 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I defend this interpretation of Hobbes in Value and Justification, 275ff.
    • I defend this interpretation of Hobbes in Value and Justification, 275ff.
  • 44
    • 0003408961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant's view is complex; though we have private rights in the state of nature, because there is no impartial judge about their contours, the state of nature also is characterized by an absence of public claims of justice; the idea of the social contract is to establish public justice and rights. [Akademie ed., 312]
    • Kant's view is complex; though we have private rights in the state of nature, because there is no impartial judge about their contours, the state of nature also is characterized by an absence of public claims of justice; the idea of the social contract is to establish public justice and rights. Kant, Metaphysical Elements of Justice, 115-116 [Akademie ed., 312].
    • Metaphysical Elements of Justice , pp. 115-116
    • Kant1
  • 46
    • 77952639763 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To be sure, there may be an intelligible sense in which I still might be said to coerce you: "If you don't do what I want, I will pick up your possession the next time you put it down!" Again, though, a general account of coercion (if one is to be had) is not my aim.
    • To be sure, there may be an intelligible sense in which I still might be said to coerce you: "If you don't do what I want, I will pick up your possession the next time you put it down!" Again, though, a general account of coercion (if one is to be had) is not my aim.
  • 47
    • 77952607004 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The Public Justification Principle supposes that a justified law must be genuinely authoritative: it is endorsed by all members of the public as binding-as generating obligations to obey. A bona fide law is not simply an act of state coercion, but an act of state authority, and so binds citizens. This is the legal expression of Kant's notion of the realm of ends, in which recognizing the law's authority over us is consistent with each person's acting on her own reasons. Contemporary political philosophy is deeply skeptical that the law generally has justified authority to direct citizens' acts. To many, the most the law could hope to achieve is a certain legitimacy, in the sense that the laws of the state are morally permissible acts of coercion, but do not in general bind citizens to obey. Thus, in place of the Public Justification Principle, we might adopt a Weak Public Justification Principle: "L is a justified coercive law only if each and every member of the public P has conclusive reason(s) R to accept that coercive acts enforcing L are morally permissible." The Weak Public Justification Principle does not suppose that laws are acts of self-legislation which all citizens have reason to obey, but simply that force and coercion by the state are permissible-though resisting them may be permissible too. For many, that is enough-indeed, the most that can be hoped for. I am dubious. The concept of law implied by this view renders laws too much like coercive demands in Hobbes's state of nature: they are not wrong, but neither is it in principle wrong to ignore them, or even fight back. However, I leave this matter unresolved in this essay. If one is convinced that the most we can hope for is such "legitimacy," one can substitute the weak version of the Public Justification Principle in what follows: the essence of the analysis is not affected.
  • 48
    • 84900150274 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reasonable rejection and neutrality of justification
    • Steven Wall and George Klosko, eds., Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield
    • See George Klosko, "Reasonable Rejection and Neutrality of Justification," in Steven Wall and George Klosko, eds., Perfectionism and Neutrality: Essays in Liberal Theory (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2003), 178.
    • (2003) Perfectionism and Neutrality: Essays in Liberal Theory , pp. 178
    • Klosko, G.1
  • 49
    • 77952588517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls adds: "within the framework of free institutions of a constitutional regime" (Political Liberalism, xviii)
    • Rawls adds: "within the framework of free institutions of a constitutional regime" (Political Liberalism, xviii).
  • 51
    • 77952636112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Their procedure . . . is to let each person propose principles . . ." (Rawls, "Justice as Fairness," 53).
    • "Their procedure . . . is to let each person propose principles . . ." (Rawls, "Justice as Fairness," 53).
  • 54
    • 77952650182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The deliberative problem supposes that we can identify laws that regulate an "area" of social life, or as Rawls termed it, a "practice" ("Justice as Fairness," 47). I set aside for now how to identify these areas in any precise way.
    • The deliberative problem supposes that we can identify laws that regulate an "area" of social life, or as Rawls termed it, a "practice" ("Justice as Fairness," 47). I set aside for now how to identify these areas in any precise way.
  • 56
    • 77952627237 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • for the formal, political procedure. New York: Oxford University Press
    • for the formal, political procedure, see Gerald Gaus, Justificatory Liberalism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1996), part III.
    • (1996) Justificatory Liberalism , Issue.PART III
    • Gaus, G.1
  • 59
    • 77952592141 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Robert Lawson, with seth norton, economic freedom of the world 2008
    • Adapted from www.freetheworld.com. Used with permission of the Fraser Institute
    • Adapted from James D. Gwartney and Robert Lawson, with Seth Norton, Economic Freedom of the World: 2008 Annual Report (Economic Freedom Network, 2008), p. 21. Digital copy available from www.fraserinstitute.org; www.freetheworld.com. Used with permission of the Fraser Institute.
    • (2008) Annual Report , pp. 21
    • Gwartney, J.D.1
  • 60
    • 77952652658 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For information on Freedom House
    • For information on Freedom House, see www.freedomhouse.org.
  • 62
    • 77952662371 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Norton economic freedom of the world: 2008 annual report; Heritage foundation
    • data Used with permission of Freedom House, the Fraser Institute, and the Heritage Foundation. Note that the scores in columns (2) and (4) are on a scale from 100 (highest protection of property rights/most overall economic freedom) to 0 (lowest protection/least economic freedom)
    • Gwartney, Lawson, and Norton, Economic Freedom of the World: 2008 Annual Report; Heritage Foundation, "Index of Economic Freedom," 2008 data, http://www.heritage.org/Index/. Used with permission of Freedom House, the Fraser Institute, and the Heritage Foundation. Note that the scores in columns (2) and (4) are on a scale from 100 (highest protection of property rights/most overall economic freedom) to 0 (lowest protection/least economic freedom).
    • (2008) Index of Economic Freedom
    • Lawson, G.1
  • 63
    • 77952663189 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Figure 2 is adapted from Gwartney, Lawson, and Norton. Digital copy available from www. freetheworld.com. Used with permission of the Fraser Institute
    • Figure 2 is adapted from Gwartney, Lawson, and Norton, Economic Freedom of theWorld: 2008 Annual Report, p. 21. Digital copy available from www.fraserinstitute.org; www. freetheworld.com. Used with permission of the Fraser Institute.
    • Economic Freedom of TheWorld: 2008 Annual Report , pp. 21
  • 64
    • 77952638876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The data in table 3 are from Freedom House
    • The data in table 3 are from Freedom House, "Freedom in the World, 2008: Subscores (Civil Rights)," http://www. freedomhouse.org/template.cfm? page=414&year=2008;
    • Freedom in the World 2008: Subscores (Civil Rights)
  • 65
    • 0004013319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Heritage Foundation. data. Used with permission of Freedom House and the Heritage Foundation
    • and Heritage Foundation, "Index of Economic Freedom," 2008 data. Used with permission of Freedom House and the Heritage Foundation.
    • (2008) Index of Economic Freedom
  • 68
    • 77952596001 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sources: Jean-Marc Burniaux, Flavio Padrini, and Nicola Brandt, Labour Market Performance, Income Inequality, and Poverty in OECD Countries, OECD Economics Department Working Paper No. 500
    • Sources: Jean-Marc Burniaux, Flavio Padrini, and Nicola Brandt, Labour Market Performance, Income Inequality, and Poverty in OECD Countries, OECD Economics Department Working Paper No.500 (ECO/WKP, 2006), 44;
    • (2006) ECO/WKP , pp. 44
  • 70
    • 77952644121 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wealth Inequality, income redistribution, and growth in fifteen oecd countries
    • Royal Economic Society
    • Daniela Sonedda, "Wealth Inequality, Income Redistribution, and Growth in Fifteen OECD Countries," Royal Economic Society Annual Conference (2003), Royal Economic Society, 21; http://ideas.repec.org/e/pso158.html.
    • (2003) Royal Economic Society Annual Conference , pp. 21
    • Sonedda, D.1
  • 73
    • 0003836741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Even less compelling is the claim that inequalities in the value of political rights are simply allowed under capitalism: the question is what economic systems are conducive to a free society
    • Even less compelling is the claim that inequalities in the value of political rights are simply allowed under capitalism: the question is what economic systems are conducive to a free society. Cf. Rawls, Justice as Fairness, 139.
    • Justice As Fairness , pp. 139
    • Rawls1
  • 75
    • 77952634345 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Digital copy available from. www.freetheworld.com.
    • Economic Freedom Network. Digital copy available fromwww.fraserinstitute. org, www.freetheworld.com.
    • Economic Freedom Network
  • 79
    • 77952635226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant, property, and the general will
    • Norman Geras and Robert Walker eds., New York: St. Martin's 71ff
    • See also Hillel Steiner, "Kant, Property, and the General Will," in Norman Geras and Robert Walker, eds., The Enlightenment and Modernity (New York: St. Martin's, 2000), 71ff.
    • (2000) The Enlightenment and Modernity
    • Steiner, H.1
  • 80
    • 77952601542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is certainly Mill's view in his discussion of private property in Book II of Principles of Political Economy
    • This is certainly Mill's view in his discussion of private property in Book II of Principles of Political Economy.
  • 81
    • 77952609033 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Robert Audi further explicates this idea of degrees of coercion in his Religious Commitment and Secular Reason (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2000), 87-88.
    • Robert Audi further explicates this idea of degrees of coercion in his Religious Commitment and Secular Reason (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 87-88.
  • 82
    • 53149100930 scopus 로고
    • The Interest of liberty in the scales
    • Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • Joel Feinberg, "The Interest of Liberty in the Scales," in his Rights, Justice, and the Bounds of Liberty (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1980), 36.
    • (1980) Rights, Justice, and the Bounds of Liberty , pp. 36
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 84
    • 0004161626 scopus 로고
    • Hayek actually seems to go so far as to say that you are not coerced at all in this case. Ibid
    • Hayek actually seems to go so far as to say that you are not coerced at all in this case. Ibid., 141. 1960
    • (1960) The Constitution of Liberty , pp. 141
    • Hayek, F.A.1
  • 86
    • 0004218365 scopus 로고
    • Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press
    • Jan Narveson, The Libertarian Idea (Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press, 1988), 66.
    • (1988) The Libertarian Idea , pp. 66
    • Narveson, J.1
  • 89
    • 84974232152 scopus 로고
    • Property, rights, and freedom
    • As I have tried to show in
    • As I have tried to show in "Property, Rights, and Freedom," Social Philosophy and Policy 11, no.2 (1994): 209-240
    • (1994) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.11 , Issue.2 , pp. 209-240
  • 91
    • 77952603867 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • accessed July 28 2008)
    • Will Wilkinson, The Fly Bottle, http://www.willwilkinson.net/flybottle/ 2008/05/30/please-discuss/(accessed July 28, 2008).
    • The Fly Bottle
    • Wilkinson, W.1
  • 92
    • 77952604308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wilkinson is suggesting a topic for discussion, and the claim is based on theories of freedom commonly held by classical liberals
    • Wilkinson is suggesting a topic for discussion, and the claim is based on theories of freedom commonly held by classical liberals.
  • 94
    • 77952661487 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Deterrent value of imposing prison sentences for tax crimes
    • Winter
    • quoted in Liezl Walker, "The Deterrent Value of Imposing Prison Sentences for Tax Crimes," New England Journal of Criminal and Civil Confinement 26 (Winter 2000): 1.
    • (2000) New England Journal of Criminal and Civil Confinement , vol.26 , pp. 1
    • Walker, L.1
  • 95
    • 77952667171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FS-2005-2014, March (accessed July 28 2008)
    • "Understanding the Tax Gap" (FS-2005-2014, March 2005), Internal Revenue Service, http://www.irs.gov/newsroom/article/0,id=137246,00. html (accessed July 28, 2008).
    • (2005) Understanding the Tax Gap
  • 99
    • 0039838409 scopus 로고
    • It might be objected that this must be wrong: whereas the criminal law seeks to render options less eligible in order to deter, an effective tax law (putting aside sin taxes) must hope that citizens continue with the activity in order for revenue to be generated. The will of the state is not for citizens to refrain, but to persist, so they are not being coerced in Hayek's sense. Coercion thus may seem to require an intention to deter people from the act, but that is exactly what the state does not seek to do with taxation-and that is why the state does not close off options, but only makes them more difficult to pursue. One who threatens, however, need not wish to deter, for often enough those making the threat hope that the target will not give in to the threat. In 1918, for example, Germany issued an ultimatum to the neutral Dutch, demanding the right to ship materials across their territory, and threatening the Netherlands and Dutch ships in its colonies if the demand was not met. At the time, this threat was seen by many observers as a pretext; they believed that Germany hoped the Netherlands would not give in to the threat but would instead enter the war. What Germany's intentions were did not nullify the coercive threat. See The New York Times, April 23 and 28, 1918.
    • (1918) The New York Times
  • 100
    • 77952641113 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • By comparing only flat-tax states, I have greatly simplified the analysis. With variablerate taxation, what constitutes a high-tax country depends on the combined score on several dimensions. Consider a study of fifteen OECD countries from the period of 1974 to 1997 (Australia, Belgium, Canada, Denmark, Finland, France, Germany, Italy, Japan, the Netherlands, Norway, Spain, Sweden, the United Kingdom, and the United States). We might define a high-tax country as one that has highly progressive rates and high marginal tax rates. On that definition, the high-tax states are Sweden, the United States, Finland, the United Kingdom, the Netherlands, and Belgium; the low-tax states are Spain, Australia, Norway, Germany, Japan, and Italy. If we define a high-tax state as one that has a high average personal tax rate and a high degree of progressivity, the high-tax states are Belgium, Canada, and France; Germany, Norway, and Denmark are low on both dimensions
    • By comparing only flat-tax states, I have greatly simplified the analysis. With variablerate taxation, what constitutes a high-tax country depends on the combined score on several dimensions. Consider a study of fifteen OECD countries from the period of 1974 to 1997 (Australia, Belgium, Canada, Denmark, Finland, France, Germany, Italy, Japan, the Netherlands, Norway, Spain, Sweden, the United Kingdom, and the United States). We might define a high-tax country as one that has highly progressive rates and high marginal tax rates. On that definition, the high-tax states are Sweden, the United States, Finland, the United Kingdom, the Netherlands, and Belgium; the low-tax states are Spain, Australia, Norway, Germany, Japan, and Italy. If we define a high-tax state as one that has a high average personal tax rate and a high degree of progressivity, the high-tax states are Belgium, Canada, and France; Germany, Norway, and Denmark are low on both dimensions. Sonedda, "Wealth Inequality, Income Redistribution, and Growth in Fifteen OECD Countries," 19-20.
    • Wealth Inequality, Income Redistribution, and Growth in Fifteen OECD Countries , pp. 19-20
    • Sonedda1
  • 102
    • 77952604883 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is merely for purposes of exposition; a cardinal analysis is not required.
    • This is merely for purposes of exposition; a cardinal analysis is not required.
  • 103
    • 77952661488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • All this was implicit in our original ordinalist idea of an eligible set. Alaw is only in the eligible set if each member of the public believes its benefits outweigh its costs compared to a condition of liberty. If a member of the public holds that a law has negative net costs, he has no reason to accept it. And one of the costs to be considered is the cost of coercion: if the law is really in the eligible set, the costs of coercion have been conclusively justified to all
    • All this was implicit in our original ordinalist idea of an eligible set. Alaw is only in the eligible set if each member of the public believes its benefits outweigh its costs compared to a condition of liberty. If a member of the public holds that a law has negative net costs, he has no reason to accept it. And one of the costs to be considered is the cost of coercion: if the law is really in the eligible set, the costs of coercion have been conclusively justified to all.
  • 104
    • 77952665068 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am grateful to Paul Gomberg for this point
    • I am grateful to Paul Gomberg for this point.
  • 105
    • 77949538703 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Public justification and the limits of state action
    • forthcoming. I respond to Lister's arguments in the same issue of the journal.
    • See Andrew Lister, "Public Justification and the Limits of State Action," Politics, Philosophy, and Economics, forthcoming. I respond to Lister's arguments in the same issue of the journal.
    • Politics, Philosophy, and Economics
    • Lister, A.1
  • 107
    • 77952623344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See for example Mill's discussion of the proper bounds of moral sanctions in Auguste Comte and Positivism. 337ff.
    • See for example Mill's discussion of the proper bounds of moral sanctions in Auguste Comte and Positivism, in Mill, Collected Works, vol.5, 337ff.
    • Collected Works , vol.5
    • Mill1
  • 109
    • 77952594169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We must keep in mind that the members of the public deliberate about whether to accept the law as the basis for justified claims on each other. To say that there is "no law" is not to say that there is no social practice that allows us to coordinate our actions, but that there is no law that grounds justified claims on each other. Consequently, to say that there is "no law" is not to say that there will be chaos.
    • We must keep in mind that the members of the public deliberate about whether to accept the law as the basis for justified claims on each other. To say that there is "no law" is not to say that there is no social practice that allows us to coordinate our actions, but that there is no law that grounds justified claims on each other. Consequently, to say that there is "no law" is not to say that there will be chaos.
  • 111
    • 85052167342 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Controversial values and state neutrality in on liberty
    • I try to show just how broad this range is in my essay. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. C. L. Ten, ed.
    • I try to show just how broad this range is in my essay "Controversial Values and State Neutrality in On Liberty," in C. L. Ten, ed., Mill's "On Liberty": A Critical Guide (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009).
    • (2009) Mill's "on Liberty": A Critical Guide
  • 112
    • 84884507992 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls suggests that one way to avoid the resulting indeterminacy is "to choose some social position by reference to which the pattern of expectations as a whole is to be judged."From this point on, the focus becomes the representative person of the least advantaged social position. Freeman, ed., John Rawls: Collected Papers
    • Rawls suggests that one way to avoid the resulting indeterminacy is "to choose some social position by reference to which the pattern of expectations as a whole is to be judged." From this point on, the focus becomes the representative person of the least advantaged social position. Rawls, "Distributive Justice," in Freeman, ed., John Rawls: Collected Papers, 137.
    • Distributive Justice , pp. 137
    • Rawls1
  • 113
    • 84871647310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "The restrictions on particular information in the original position are, then, of fundamental importance. Without them we would not be able to work out any definite theory of justice at all. rev. ed.
    • "The restrictions on particular information in the original position are, then, of fundamental importance. Without them we would not be able to work out any definite theory of justice at all." Rawls, A Theory of Justice, rev. ed., 121.
    • A Theory of Justice , pp. 121
    • Rawls1
  • 118
    • 0003001215 scopus 로고
    • What is enlightenment?
    • Hans Reiss, ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See also Kant, "What Is Enlightenment?" in Hans Reiss, ed., Kant's PoliticalWritings, trans. H. B. Nisbett (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977), 54-60.
    • (1977) Kant's Political Writings, Trans. H. B. Nisbett , pp. 54-60
    • Kant1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.