메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 9, Issue 2, 2010, Pages 151-175

Public justification and the limits of state action

Author keywords

Coercion; Legitimacy; Liberal neutrality; Public reason

Indexed keywords


EID: 77949538703     PISSN: 1470594X     EISSN: 17413060     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/1470594X09345680     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (34)

References (98)
  • 1
    • 77951897375 scopus 로고
    • Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism
    • Jeremy Waldron, 'Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism', Philosophical Quarterly 147 (1987): 128.
    • (1987) Philosophical Quarterly , vol.147 , pp. 128
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 3
    • 84934348993 scopus 로고
    • Moral Conflict and Political Legitimacy
    • Thomas Nagel, 'Moral Conflict and Political Legitimacy', Philosophy and Public Affairs 16 (1987): 223.
    • (1987) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.16 , pp. 223
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 4
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (New York: Columbia University Press)
    • John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), pp. 139, 214.
    • (1996) Political Liberalism
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 5
    • 33745658702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Moral Basis of Political Liberalism
    • Charles Larmore, 'The Moral Basis of Political Liberalism', Journal of Philosophy 12 (1999): 606-7.
    • (1999) Journal of Philosophy , vol.12 , pp. 606-607
    • Larmore, C.1
  • 6
    • 34248042676 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Disagreement, Asymmetry, and Liberal Legitimacy
    • Jonathan Quong, 'Disagreement, Asymmetry, and Liberal Legitimacy', Politics, Philosophy and Economics 3 (2005): 301.
    • (2005) Politics, Philosophy and Economics , vol.3 , pp. 301
    • Quong, J.1
  • 7
    • 77951914916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • I will use terms such as 'ideal of public justification' and 'principle of public reason' interchangeably. Strictly speaking, the principle of public reason has a narrower role in Rawls's theory - that of helping determine the practical implications of principles of justice already on hand. When citizens disagree about the implications of principles, a common commitment to shared modes of reasoning nonetheless reassures them that they are all indeed interpreting common principles, and not arguing from comprehensive doctrines. As this reference to the exclusion of comprehensive doctrines suggests, however, the first stage of Rawls's theory is framed by a demand for public justifiability which Rawls calls the 'liberal principle of legitimacy'.
  • 9
    • 77951930328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Whereas Rawls justifies public reason by appeal to liberal legitimacy, I will refer to the latter as itself being a principle of public reason, since it excludes reasons from the justification of the exercise of political power without declaring them to be false or logically irrelevant. In adopting this broad usage, I believe I follow Charles Larmore, who says that 'public reason is not one political value among others', but 'envelops all the different elements that make up the ideal of constitutional democracy'.
  • 10
    • 26444489303 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, edited by Samuel Richard Freeman (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • See Charles Larmore, 'Public Reason', in The Cambridge Companion to Rawls, edited by Samuel Richard Freeman (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003).
    • (2003) The Cambridge Companion to Rawls
    • Larmore, C.1
  • 12
    • 0003956640 scopus 로고
    • compare, (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
    • compare Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986), p. 110.
    • (1986) The Morality of Freedom , pp. 110
    • Raz, J.1
  • 13
    • 77952487204 scopus 로고
    • Facing Diversity: The Case of Epistemic Abstinence
    • and Joseph Raz, 'Facing Diversity: The Case of Epistemic Abstinence', Philosophy and Public Affairs 19 (1990): 37, 43.
    • (1990) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.19 , Issue.37 , pp. 43
    • Raz, J.1
  • 14
    • 77951912013 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberal Legitimacy, Reasonable Disagreement and Justice
    • edited by Richard Bellamy and Martin Hollis (Ilford: Frank Cass Publishers)
    • Simon Caney, 'Liberal Legitimacy, Reasonable Disagreement and Justice', in Pluralism and Liberal Neutrality, edited by Richard Bellamy and Martin Hollis (Ilford: Frank Cass Publishers, 1999), p. 29;
    • (1999) Pluralism and Liberal Neutrality , pp. 29
    • Caney, S.1
  • 15
    • 0344529731 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legitimacy, Unanimity, and Perfectionism
    • Joseph Chan, 'Legitimacy, Unanimity, and Perfectionism', Philosophy and Public Affairs 1 (2000): 5-42.
    • (2000) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.1 , pp. 5-42
    • Chan, J.1
  • 16
    • 77951925964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Disagreement, Asymmetry, and Liberal Legitimacy
    • Quong, 'Disagreement, Asymmetry, and Liberal Legitimacy', p. 303.
    • Quong1
  • 17
    • 62449194186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberal neutrality: A compelling and radical principle
    • edited by Stephen Wall and George Klosko (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield)
    • Gerald F. Gaus, 'Liberal Neutrality: A Compelling and Radical Principle', in Perfectionism and Neutrality: Essays in Liberal Theory, edited by Stephen Wall and George Klosko (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2003), p. 138.
    • (2003) Perfectionism and Neutrality: Essays in Liberal Theory , pp. 138
    • Gerald, F.1
  • 18
    • 62449194186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberal Neutrality on the Good: An Autopsy
    • edited by Stephen Wall and George Klosko (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield)
    • Richard Arneson, 'Liberal Neutrality on the Good: An Autopsy', in Perfectionism and Neutrality: Essays in Liberal Theory, edited by Stephen Wall and George Klosko (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2003).
    • (2003) Perfectionism and Neutrality: Essays in Liberal Theory
    • Arneson, R.1
  • 19
    • 77951927499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • My summary of Gaus's argument draws heavily on Gaus's 'Liberal Neutrality', which presents the public justifiability principle as a 'consensus' rather than a 'convergence' theory (or is at least ambiguous between the two). I have since come to realize that Gaus is in fact committed to a convergence view. The difference between these two approaches concerns the requirement of reasonable acceptability of coercion. The 'consensus' interpretation is that all reasonable, fully rational, and moral (or otherwise) qualified points of view must accept a particular set of reasons that is sufficient to justify some coercive law. The 'convergence' position is that all reasonable or qualified points of view must accept some set of reasons that is sufficient to justify the law, but not necessarily the same set. The consensus view is dominant;
  • 20
    • 0242599530 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political Liberalism and David M. Estlund, 'The Insularity of the Reasonable: Why Political Liberalism Must Admit the Truth'
    • see, for example
    • see, for example, Rawls, Political Liberalism and David M. Estlund, 'The Insularity of the Reasonable: Why Political Liberalism Must Admit the Truth', Ethics 108 (1998): 252-75.
    • (1998) Ethics , vol.108 , pp. 252-75
    • Rawls, R.1
  • 21
    • 77951910498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • For the distinction itself.
  • 23
    • 0040974183 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral Conflict and Political Legitimacy
    • and Nagel, 'Moral Conflict and Political Legitimacy', p. 218.
    • Nagel, N.1
  • 25
    • 77951919750 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • What I call the 'measurement' and 'aggregation' problems apply to both versions, I believe, but some of the arguments in Section 4 may need to be reformulated.
  • 26
    • 77951911705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberal Neutrality
    • Gaus, 'Liberal Neutrality', p. 143.
    • Gaus, G.1
  • 27
    • 77951881348 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Similarly, Michael Blake argues that although coercion is presumptively forbidden, we can justify it against this presumption by demonstrating that the rule licensing the coercion is not one those coerced could reasonably reject.
  • 28
    • 77951916802 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Distributive Justice, State Coercion, and Autonomy
    • See
    • See Michael Blake, 'Distributive Justice, State Coercion, and Autonomy', Philosophy and Public Affairs 3 (2002): 274-5.
    • (2002) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.3 , pp. 274-5
    • Blake, M.1
  • 29
    • 77951883374 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • As Michael Blake puts it, we justify coercion by showing that the rule licensing the coercion is one to which those coerced could not reasonably withhold their consent.
  • 30
    • 69849106021 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Distributive Justice, State Coercion, and Autonomy
    • See
    • See Blake, 'Distributive Justice, State Coercion, and Autonomy', pp. 274-5.
    • Blake, B.1
  • 32
    • 77951918527 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • 'Insofar as any reason is rationally rejectable, the minimal principle of neutrality [T8] deems that reason unacceptable as a justification of government action. Government thus must be neutral with respect to citizens' reasons that are rationally rejectable by others.'
  • 34
    • 77951889781 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gaus cites T.H. Green as an advocate of paternalism justified by the claim that much paternalism would be accepted by fully rational moral persons
    • Gaus cites T.H. Green as an advocate of paternalism justified by the claim that much paternalism would be accepted by fully rational moral persons.
    • Gaus, G.1
  • 35
    • 77951911387 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gaus cites T.H. Green as an advocate of paternalism justified by the claim that much paternalism would be accepted by fully rational moral persons
    • Ibid., pp. 151-3.
    • Gaus, G.1
  • 37
    • 77951921445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Thus, after recognizing that reasonable people can disagree over 'levels of public provision of education and health care, social security, defense policy, environmental preservation, and a host of other things that liberal societies determine by legislative action', Nagel argued that in many of these areas citizens can nonetheless appeal to a 'common ground of justification'. People disagree on many such issues due to differences 'in judgment over the preponderant weight of reasons bearing on an issue', rather than (as with religious questions, for example) due to 'a bare confrontation between incompatible personal points of view' or 'a pure confrontation between personal moral convictions'.
  • 39
    • 77951934827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Jonathan Quong and Micah Schwartzmann have shown that Rawls's political liberalism is similarly open to reasonable disagreement about matters of justice.
  • 41
    • 77951925964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Disagreement, Asymmetry, and Liberal Legitimacy
    • Quong, 'Disagreement, Asymmetry, and Liberal Legitimacy', p. 316.
    • Quong1
  • 42
    • 0039031609 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The idea of public reason revisited
    • compare, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • compare John Rawls, 'The Idea of Public Reason Revisited', in The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), p. 169.
    • (1999) The Law of Peoples , pp. 169
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 43
    • 77951911705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberal Neutrality
    • Gaus, 'Liberal Neutrality', p. 138,
    • Gaus, G.1
  • 44
    • 85011525698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Neutralizing Perfection: Hurka on Liberal Neutrality
    • citing
    • citing Daniel M. Weinstock, 'Neutralizing Perfection: Hurka on Liberal Neutrality', Dialogue 38 (1999): 53.
    • (1999) Dialogue , vol.38 , pp. 53
    • Weinstock, D.M.1
  • 45
    • 0039898123 scopus 로고
    • Indirect Perfectionism: Kymlicka on Liberal Neutrality
    • Thomas Hurka, 'Indirect Perfectionism: Kymlicka on Liberal Neutrality', Journal of Political Philosophy 3 (1995): 49.
    • (1995) Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.3 , pp. 49
    • Hurka, T.1
  • 50
    • 0040974183 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral Conflict and Political Legitimacy
    • Nagel, 'Moral Conflict and Political Legitimacy', p. 233.
    • Nagel, N.1
  • 51
    • 77951922110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberal Legitimacy, Reasonable Disagreement and Justice
    • compare
    • compare Caney, 'Liberal Legitimacy, Reasonable Disagreement and Justice', p. 28.
  • 52
    • 0040974183 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral Conflict and Political Legitimacy
    • Nagel, 'Moral Conflict and Political Legitimacy', p. 234.
    • Nagel, N.1
  • 53
    • 69849106021 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Distributive Justice, State Coercion, and Autonomy
    • Blake, 'Distributive Justice, State Coercion, and Autonomy', p. 277.
    • Blake, B.1
  • 54
    • 0004191128 scopus 로고
    • Oxford and New York: Clarendon Press and Oxford University Press
    • Blake cites Jeremy Waldron, The Right to Private Property (Oxford and New York: Clarendon Press and Oxford University Press, 1988).
    • (1988) The Right to Private Property
    • Blake, B.1    Waldron, J.2
  • 55
    • 59549102387 scopus 로고
    • as well as, Note
    • as well as Shelley v. Kraemer, 334 US 1 (1948), the US Supreme Court case that found that enforcement of contracts involved state action, and hence that constitutional demands for equal protection ruled out enforcement of contracts involving racial restrictions.
    • (1948) Shelley v. Kraemer
  • 56
    • 77951911705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberal Neutrality
    • Gaus, 'Liberal Neutrality', p. 153.
    • Gaus, G.1
  • 57
    • 77951911705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberal Neutrality
    • Ibid., p. 159.
    • Gaus, G.1
  • 58
    • 77951935407 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Thanks to Will Kymlicka for pressing this objection.
  • 59
    • 0037822451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Steven Wall's distinction between two kinds of perfectionism; Steven Wall, Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press
    • See Steven Wall's distinction between two kinds of perfectionism; Steven Wall, Liberalism, Perfectionism and Restraint (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998), p. 12.
    • (1998) Liberalism, Perfectionism and Restraint , pp. 12
  • 60
    • 33646034681 scopus 로고
    • Institutional Argument is Diminished by the Limited Examination of the Issues of Principle
    • See, for example
    • See, for example, Joshua Cohen, 'Institutional Argument is Diminished by the Limited Examination of the Issues of Principle', Journal of Politics 1 (1991): 221-5.
    • (1991) Journal of Politics , vol.1 , pp. 221-5
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 61
    • 0347843183 scopus 로고
    • Abortion: Whose Right?
    • cited by Rawls, Political Liberalism
    • Judith Jarvis Thomson, 'Abortion: Whose Right?' Boston Review 3 (1995), cited by Rawls, Political Liberalism, p. lvi n. 31.
    • (1995) Boston Review , vol.3 , Issue.31
    • Thomson, J.J.1
  • 62
    • 77951881630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Abortion, Natural Law, and Liberal Discourse: A Response to John Finnis
    • and edited by Robert P. George and Christopher Wolfe (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press)
    • and Jeffrey Reiman, 'Abortion, Natural Law, and Liberal Discourse: A Response to John Finnis', in Natural Law and Public Reason, edited by Robert P. George and Christopher Wolfe (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2000).
    • (2000) Natural Law and Public Reason
    • Reiman, J.1
  • 63
    • 77951890071 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • One might argue that there is still the imposition of a conception of the good in the case of abortion. Here, the ambiguity of the term 'conception of the good' becomes important. Above, we were thinking of a conception of what is the best life for me. But if we think in terms of a conception of human flourishing in general, or a comprehensive moral doctrine, then we could try to argue that in the case of abortion, there is still the imposition of a conception of the good. But I think that now the argument has shifted in a subtle way. The state is not imposing on me a particular conception of what is good for me, it is defining the scope of my duty not to harm others according to a contestable moral doctrine about who counts as a person. Is this wrong? To answer 'yes', we need to appeal to the demand for public justifiability. For the intuitions about the wrong of paternalism that were doing the work above will no longer do the same work here.
  • 64
    • 77951920861 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Any heightened standard of justification, such as conclusiveness, must involve a presumption against one of the options, because with a heightened standard, it will be possible that both the cases for and against action fail. The only alternative would be randomization.
  • 65
    • 77951903745 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • then we could say that even if we ended up adopting what would otherwise be a reasonably rejectable policy, we did not base our decision on any reasonably rejectable reason, because we did not use any reasons at all - we simply flipped a coin. On randomization as a solution to the potential 'incompleteness' of public reason.
  • 66
    • 3042559269 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Alleged Incompleteness of Public Reason
    • see
    • see Andrew Williams, 'The Alleged Incompleteness of Public Reason', Res Publica 2 (2000): 210-11.
    • (2000) Res Publica , vol.2 , pp. 210-11
    • Williams, A.1
  • 67
    • 77951902582 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Randomization may seem a sensible option for a series of one-off, local decisions, because in the long run, no one view wins all the time. For an ongoing policy or general rule, however, it will seem unfair that we randomize once, and the policy is set forever more. Periodic re-randomization, or alternation of policies would solve this problem, but at the expense of confusion and uncertainty of various kinds. How would randomization apply to the definition of marriage, for example?
  • 68
    • 77951925068 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • A comparison with Rawls's difference principle may be helpful. To justify a given level of inequality, it is not sufficient to show that that the least well off are better off than they would be in a state of nature. To justify all of the inequality, we would have to show that each extra bit of inequality helps, or at least does not harm, theleast well off.
  • 69
    • 77951916518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • 'Will anyone argue that abortion should be left to private judgment, so that people who judge it as homicide are entitled to use force to prevent their fellow citizens engaging in it (just as they are entitled to use force to prevent infanticide or sexual intercourse between adults and eight-year-old boys)?'.
  • 70
    • 33747620914 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Abortion, natural law, and public reason
    • See, edited by Robert P. George and Christopher Wolfe (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press)
    • See John Finnis, 'Abortion, Natural Law, and Public Reason', in Natural Law and Public Reason, edited by Robert P. George and Christopher Wolfe (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 2000), p. 75.
    • (2000) Natural Law and Public Reason , pp. 75
    • Finnis, J.1
  • 71
    • 77951901047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • I owe this point to Peter de Marneffe's insightful comments on an earlier version of this article.
  • 72
    • 0001342380 scopus 로고
    • What's Wrong with Negative Liberty
    • (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • Charles Taylor, 'What's Wrong with Negative Liberty', in Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), p. 219.
    • (1985) Philosophy and The Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers , vol.2 , pp. 219
    • Taylor, C.1
  • 73
    • 0344885684 scopus 로고
    • Rawls on Liberty and Its Priority
    • compare
    • compare H.L.A. Hart, 'Rawls on Liberty and Its Priority', University of Chicago Law Review 3 (1973): 534-55.
    • (1973) University of Chicago Law Review , vol.3 , pp. 534-55
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 74
    • 0040755522 scopus 로고
    • What Rights Do We Have?
    • (London: Duckworth)
    • and Ronald Dworkin, 'What Rights Do We Have?' in Taking Rights Seriously (London: Duckworth, 1978).
    • (1978) Taking Rights Seriously
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 75
    • 77951931212 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • The last part of this paragraph summarizes a personal communication from Gaus, but for related argument.
  • 76
    • 34247522442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Justifying the Moral Rights of the Moderns: A Case of Old Wine in New Bottles
    • see
    • see Gerald F. Gaus, 'On Justifying the Moral Rights of the Moderns: A Case of Old Wine in New Bottles', Social Philosophy and Policy 1 (2007): 91-3.
    • (2007) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.1 , pp. 91-3
    • Gaus, G.F.1
  • 78
    • 77951911705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberal Neutrality
    • Gaus, 'Liberal Neutrality', p. 139.
    • Gaus, G.1
  • 79
    • 0004241736 scopus 로고
    • (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
    • Susan Hurley, Natural Reasons (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989), p. 133.
    • (1989) Natural Reasons , pp. 133
    • Hurley, S.1
  • 81
    • 77951886897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • I draw here on Alistair Macleod, 'Freedom, Autonomy, and Coercion: A Note on Bruce Landesman's "Global Economic Inequality, Partiality, and Coercion"', paper presented at the AMINTAPHIL Conference on 'Coercion, Justice, and Democracy', St Louis, MO, November 2006.
    • (2006)
  • 82
    • 77951910794 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Coercion, justice, and democracy
    • edited by David Reidy and Walter Riker (London: Springer Science and Business Media)
    • Alistair Macleod, 'Coercion, Justice, and Democracy', in Coercion and the State, edited by David Reidy and Walter Riker (London: Springer Science and Business Media, 2008), p. 66.
    • (2008) Coercion and The State , pp. 66
    • Macleod, A.1
  • 83
    • 77951911705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberal Neutrality
    • Gaus, 'Liberal Neutrality', p. 141.
    • Gaus, G.1
  • 84
    • 77951911705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberal Neutrality
    • Ibid., p. 146.
    • Gaus, G.1
  • 87
    • 77951930902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Roles of Religious Conviction in a Publicly Justified Polity
    • Gaus and Vallier, 'The Roles of Religious Conviction in a Publicly Justified Polity', p. 52.
    • Gaus, G.1    Vallier, V.2
  • 88
    • 77951930902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Roles of Religious Conviction in a Publicly Justified Polity
    • Ibid., p. 63.
    • Gaus, G.1    Vallier, V.2
  • 89
    • 77951900449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note
    • Peter de Marneffe and Alyssa Bernstein made this point in discussion.
  • 90
    • 77951911705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberal Neutrality
    • Gaus, 'Liberal Neutrality', p. 143.
    • Gaus, G.1
  • 91
    • 0039787672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberal Neutrality
    • Gaus, 'Liberal Neutrality', p. 149.
  • 92
    • 79751508994 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant's Moral Philosophy
    • Edward N. Zalta (editor), (Stanford, CA: Stanford University)
    • Edward N. Zalta (editor), 'Kant's Moral Philosophy', The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, spring 2004 edn. (Stanford, CA: Stanford University, 2004).
    • (2004) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2004 Edn
  • 93
    • 77951924157 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Neutralizing Perfection
    • Weinstock, 'Neutralizing Perfection', p. 55.
  • 94
    • 77951915951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legitimacy, Unanimity, and Perfectionism
    • compare
    • compare Chan, 'Legitimacy, Unanimity, and Perfectionism', pp. 10-18.
    • Chan1
  • 95
    • 77951911705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberal Neutrality
    • Gaus, 'Liberal Neutrality'.
    • Gaus, G.1
  • 96
    • 77951911705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberal Neutrality
    • Ibid., pp. 157-8.
    • Gaus, G.1
  • 97
    • 10844289838 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paternalism, Unconscionability Doctrine, and Accommodation
    • Compare Seana
    • Compare Seana Valentine Shiffrin, 'Paternalism, Unconscionability Doctrine, and Accommodation', Philosophy and Public Affairs 3 (2000): 205-50.
    • (2000) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.3 , pp. 205-50
    • Shiffrin, V.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.