메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 6, Issue 1, 2009, Pages 50-69

Agent-based virtue ethics and the problem of action guidance

Author keywords

Action guidance; Agent based virtue ethics; Hypothetical agent based virtue ethics; Right action; Virtuous motive

Indexed keywords


EID: 74249091491     PISSN: 17404681     EISSN: 17455243     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1163/174552409X365928     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (27)

References (23)
  • 1
    • 60949596718 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Virtue Ethics and Right Action
    • Ramon Das uses this case in his critique of agent-based virtue ethics. See Das, 'Virtue Ethics and Right Action', Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81.3 (2003), pp. 330-34
    • (2003) Australasian Journal of Philosophy , vol.81 , Issue.3 , pp. 330-334
    • Das1
  • 2
    • 0040626060 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Motive and Rightness
    • For further discussion see Steven Sverdlik, 'Motive and Rightness', Ethics 106.2 (1996), pp. 327-49
    • (1996) Ethics , vol.106 , Issue.2 , pp. 327-349
    • Sverdlik, S.1
  • 3
    • 0003593197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Rosalind Hursthouse, On Virtue Ethics (New York: Oxford University Press, 1999)
    • (1999) On Virtue Ethics
    • Hursthouse, R.1
  • 4
    • 0038974500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Virtue Ethical Account of Right Action
    • Christine Swanton, 'A Virtue Ethical Account of Right Action', Ethics 112.1 (2001), p. 36
    • (2001) Ethics , vol.112 , Issue.1 , pp. 36
    • Swanton, C.1
  • 5
    • 84952037548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Agent-Based Virtue Ethics
    • .A. French, T.E. Uehling Jr. and H.K. Wettstein eds, Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press
    • See Michael Slote, 'Agent-Based Virtue Ethics', in P.A. French, T.E. Uehling Jr. and H.K. Wettstein (eds.), Moral Concepts (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1996), pp. 83-101
    • (1996) Moral Concepts , pp. 83-101
    • Slote, M.1
  • 6
    • 79957071008 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • his Morals from Motives (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001).
    • Also see his Morals from Motives (New York: Oxford University Press, 2001)
  • 7
    • 0142220962 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Morals from Motives , p. 38. For the sake of clarity and simplicity I have made subtle changes to the formulations provided by Slote. Most notably, I've included 'because' in brackets to make it clear that Slote thinks that virtuous motive is what makes an act right.
    • See Slote, 'Agent-Based Virtue Ethics', pp. 83-101 and Morals from Motives , p. 38. For the sake of clarity and simplicity I have made subtle changes to the formulations provided by Slote. Most notably, I've included 'because' in brackets to make it clear that Slote thinks that virtuous motive is what makes an act right
    • Agent-Based Virtue Ethics , pp. 83-101
    • Slote1
  • 8
    • 74249096356 scopus 로고
    • ed. and trans. D. Ross Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press
    • Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics , ed. and trans. D. Ross (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 1925), II.4
    • (1925) The Nicomachean Ethics
    • Aristotle1
  • 11
    • 74249088654 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to Hursthouse, 'A virtue is a character trait a human being needs for eudaimonia, to flourish or live well', On Virtue Ethics, p. 29.
    • According to Hursthouse, 'A virtue is a character trait a human being needs for eudaimonia, to flourish or live well', On Virtue Ethics, p. 29
  • 12
    • 79957280131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a discussion of this problem Das, 'Virtue Ethics and Right Action', pp. 330-34.
    • For a discussion of this problem see Das, 'Virtue Ethics and Right Action', pp. 330-34
  • 13
    • 0004240210 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • W.D. Ross, The Right and the Good (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1930), p. 2
    • (1930) The Right and the Good , pp. 2
    • Ross, W.D.1
  • 15
    • 77953541406 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Against Agent-Based Virtue Ethics
    • For example, see Michael Brady, 'Against Agent-Based Virtue Ethics', Philosophical Papers 33.1 (2004), pp. 1-10
    • (2004) Philosophical Papers , vol.33 , Issue.1 , pp. 1-10
    • Brady, M.1
  • 16
    • 3142778285 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hypothetical Agent-Based Virtue Ethics
    • Scott Gelfand, 'Hypothetical Agent-Based Virtue Ethics', Southwest Philosophy Review 17.1 (2000), pp. 87-89
    • (2000) Southwest Philosophy Review , vol.17 , Issue.1 , pp. 87-89
    • Gelfand, S.1
  • 17
    • 51849085981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An Unsolved Problem for Slote's Agent-Based Virtue Ethics
    • Dan Jacobson, 'An Unsolved Problem for Slote's Agent-Based Virtue Ethics', Philosophical Studies 111.1 (2002), pp. 54-55
    • (2002) Philosophical Studies , vol.111 , Issue.1 , pp. 54-55
    • Jacobson, D.1
  • 19
    • 79957321738 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to the autism objection an account that ties rightness to actual motive seems committed to the view that it doesn't really matter what a person does, as long as his motives are good. Slote responds to this by saying that 'a benevolent person is typically capable of choosing many actions that fail to express or exhibit her (inner state of ) benevolence'. Likewise, he argues that a thoroughly malevolent person may still have it within his power to refrain from hurting someone, 'even if we can be sure that he won't in fact exercise that power'. Morals from Motives , pp. 16-17
    • Morals from Motives , pp. 16-17
  • 20
    • 0003619765 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Cambridge University Press
    • For example, in defending consequentialism against Bernard Williams's (B. Williams and J.J.C. Smart, Utilitarianism : For and Against (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp. 97-116)
    • (1973) Utilitarianism : For and Against , pp. 97-116
    • Williams, B.1    Smart, J.J.C.2
  • 21
    • 84875336363 scopus 로고
    • Alienation, Consequentialism, and the Demands of Morality
    • 'alienation objection', Peter Railton distinguishes between subjective and objective consequentialism. The first prescribes following a particular mode of deliberation in action, that is, it says that whenever one faces a choice of actions, one should attempt to determine which act of those available would most promote the good, and then act accordingly. By contrast, objective consequentialism is the view that the criterion of right action is whether it in fact would most promote the good of those acts available to the agent, with the result that he would not always use a cost-benefit analysis to decide what to do in particular situations. See Railton, 'Alienation, Consequentialism, and the Demands of Morality', Philosophy and Public Affairs 13 (1984), pp. 152-53
    • (1984) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.13 , pp. 152-153
    • Railton1
  • 22
    • 79957383334 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Morals from Motives, p. 39, where Slote argues that 'motive is at least relevant to the moral character of any action' (his italics).
    • See Morals from Motives, p. 39, where Slote argues that 'motive is at least relevant to the moral character of any action' (his italics)
  • 23
    • 79957043830 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Action, Das notes that one way to avoid the circularity objection is 'to give an account of acting well grounded entirely in inner states of the agent, and indeed, this is exactly what an agent-based account does
    • On p. 332 of 'Virtue Ethics and Right Action', Das notes that one way to avoid the circularity objection is 'to give an account of acting well grounded entirely in inner states of the agent', and indeed, this is exactly what an agent-based account does
    • 332 of 'Virtue Ethics and Right
    • On, P.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.