메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 112, Issue 1, 2001, Pages 32-52

A virtue ethical account of right action

(1)  Swanton, Christine a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0038974500     PISSN: 00141704     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1086/322742     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (75)

References (35)
  • 1
    • 0003593197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Most self-consciously, Rosalind Hursthouse in On Virtue Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999).
    • (1999) On Virtue Ethics
    • Hursthouse, R.1
  • 2
    • 0040626135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I thank Linda Zagzebski for this terminological suggestion
    • I thank Linda Zagzebski for this terminological suggestion.
  • 3
    • 0026180513 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Virtue theory and abortion
    • Rosalind Hursthouse, "Virtue Theory and Abortion," Philosophy & Public Affairs 20 (1991): 223-46. An earlier 'qualified judge' account of rightness was offered by Yves R. Simon in The Definition of Moral Virtue, ed. Vukan Kuic (New York: Fordham University Press, 1986): "We say that an action will be the right action under the circumstances if the judgment about what to do is determined, is rendered, by a person of virtuous disposition" (p. 112). Compare also the qualified agent account of rightness proposed by Linda Trinkaus Zagzebski in Virtues of Mind: An Inquiry into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996): "A right act is what a person who is virtuously motivated and who has the understanding of the particular situation that a virtuous person would have, might do in like circumstances. . . . A moral duty is what a person who is virtuously motivated, and who has the understanding of the particular situation that a virtuous person would have, would do in like circumstances" (p. 135).
    • (1991) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.20 , pp. 223-246
    • Hursthouse, R.1
  • 4
    • 0026180513 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Vukan Kuic New York: Fordham University Press
    • Rosalind Hursthouse, "Virtue Theory and Abortion," Philosophy & Public Affairs 20 (1991): 223-46. An earlier 'qualified judge' account of rightness was offered by Yves R. Simon in The Definition of Moral Virtue, ed. Vukan Kuic (New York: Fordham University Press, 1986): "We say that an action will be the right action under the circumstances if the judgment about what to do is determined, is rendered, by a person of virtuous disposition" (p. 112). Compare also the qualified agent account of rightness proposed by Linda Trinkaus Zagzebski in Virtues of Mind: An Inquiry into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996): "A right act is what a person who is virtuously motivated and who has the understanding of the particular situation that a virtuous person would have, might do in like circumstances. . . . A moral duty is what a person who is virtuously motivated, and who has the understanding of the particular situation that a virtuous person would have, would do in like circumstances" (p. 135).
    • (1986) The Definition of Moral Virtue , pp. 112
    • Simon, Y.R.1
  • 5
    • 0026180513 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Rosalind Hursthouse, "Virtue Theory and Abortion," Philosophy & Public Affairs 20 (1991): 223-46. An earlier 'qualified judge' account of rightness was offered by Yves R. Simon in The Definition of Moral Virtue, ed. Vukan Kuic (New York: Fordham University Press, 1986): "We say that an action will be the right action under the circumstances if the judgment about what to do is determined, is rendered, by a person of virtuous disposition" (p. 112). Compare also the qualified agent account of rightness proposed by Linda Trinkaus Zagzebski in Virtues of Mind: An Inquiry into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996): "A right act is what a person who is virtuously motivated and who has the understanding of the particular situation that a virtuous person would have, might do in like circumstances. . . . A moral duty is what a person who is virtuously motivated, and who has the understanding of the particular situation that a virtuous person would have, would do in like circumstances" (p. 135).
    • (1996) Virtues of Mind: An Inquiry into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge , pp. 135
    • Zagzebski, L.T.1
  • 7
    • 84952037548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Agent-based virtue ethics
    • Moral Concepts, ed. Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, Jr., and Howard K. Wettstein Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press
    • Michael Slote, "Agent-Based Virtue Ethics," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 20, Moral Concepts, ed. Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, Jr., and Howard K. Wettstein (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1996), pp. 83-101.
    • (1996) Midwest Studies in Philosophy , vol.20 , pp. 83-101
    • Slote, M.1
  • 9
    • 0009189022 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Agent-based virtue ethics," and "the justice of caring,"
    • Slote, "Agent-Based Virtue Ethics," and "The Justice of Caring," Social Philosophy and Policy 15 (1998): 171-95.
    • (1998) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.15 , pp. 171-195
    • Slote1
  • 10
    • 0040626049 scopus 로고
    • Monkeying with motives: Agent-basing virtue ethics
    • For further criticism of Slote's failure to incorporate notions of successful relation to the external world in his criterion of rightness, see Julia Driver, "Monkeying with Motives: Agent-Basing Virtue Ethics," Utilitas 7 (1995): 281-88.
    • (1995) Utilitas , vol.7 , pp. 281-288
    • Driver, J.1
  • 11
    • 0004240210 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • W. D. Ross, The Right and the Good (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1930), p. 2.
    • (1930) The Right and the Good , pp. 2
    • Ross, W.D.1
  • 12
    • 0040626060 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Motive and rightness
    • Indeed, I agree with Stephen Sverdlik's view that sometimes the quality of a motive can change the deontic status of an action from right to wrong. See his "Motive and Rightness," Ethics 106 (1996): 327-49.
    • (1996) Ethics , vol.106 , pp. 327-349
    • Sverdlik, S.1
  • 13
    • 0038847933 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Henceforth, 'virtuous act'
    • Henceforth, 'virtuous act'.
  • 14
    • 0003986649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. J. A. K. Thomson New York: Penguin Classics, sec. 2 iv
    • Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, trans. J. A. K. Thomson (New York: Penguin Classics, 1976), p. 97, sec. 2 iv.
    • (1976) Nicomachean Ethics , pp. 97
    • Aristotle1
  • 17
    • 0001157576 scopus 로고
    • Consequentialism
    • ed. Peter Singer Oxford: Blackwell
    • The idea of honoring value is introduced by Philip Pettit in "Consequentialism," in A Companion to Ethics, ed. Peter Singer (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991), pp. 230-40.
    • (1991) A Companion to Ethics , pp. 230-240
    • Pettit, P.1
  • 18
    • 0039440696 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Sverdlik
    • See Sverdlik.
  • 19
    • 0040032818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Audi, p. 180
    • Audi, p. 180.
  • 20
    • 0040032815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The virtues and human nature
    • ed. Roger Crisp Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • Julia Driver, "The Virtues and Human Nature," in How Should One Live? Essays m the Philosophy of Virtue, ed. Roger Crisp (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996), pp. 111-29.
    • (1996) How Should One Live? Essays M the Philosophy of Virtue , pp. 111-129
    • Driver, J.1
  • 21
    • 0033163898 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Modesty and ignorance
    • Julia Driver, "Modesty and Ignorance," Ethics 109 (1999): 827-34, p. 828.
    • (1999) Ethics , vol.109 , pp. 827-834
    • Driver, J.1
  • 22
    • 0004206765 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell
    • Jonathan Dancy, Moral Reasons (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993).
    • (1993) Moral Reasons
    • Dancy, J.1
  • 23
    • 4244037174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 60. Dancy does not mean to imply that we cannot make reasonable estimates on the basis of characteristic (as opposed to universal) properties of things, e.g., the characteristic badness of pain.
    • Moral Reasons , pp. 60
  • 25
    • 0039440682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some varieties of particularism
    • Walter Sinnott-Armstrong thinks that such principles can be turned into universal form provided they are formulated thus: do (or don't do) thus and so provided there are no underminers, reversers, exclusions, and overriders. See his "Some Varieties of Particularism," Metaphilosophy 30 (1999): 1-12, p. 6. For Dancy, however, an 'underminer' is the absence of a background ('enabling') condition and not a reason (a fact accepted by Sinnott-Armstrong). Since moral principles state reasons and not all enabling conditions, the above cannot be a principle (even if a defender of universalizability can appeal to it [as Sinnott-Armstrong claims]). This is made clear in Jonathan Dancy, "Defending Particularism," Metaphilosophy 30 (1999): 25-32, p. 26.
    • (1999) Metaphilosophy , vol.30 , pp. 1-12
    • Sinnott-Armstrong, W.1
  • 26
    • 38949101670 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Defending particularism
    • Walter Sinnott-Armstrong thinks that such principles can be turned into universal form provided they are formulated thus: do (or don't do) thus and so provided there are no underminers, reversers, exclusions, and overriders. See his "Some Varieties of Particularism," Metaphilosophy 30 (1999): 1-12, p. 6. For Dancy, however, an 'underminer' is the absence of a background ('enabling') condition and not a reason (a fact accepted by Sinnott-Armstrong). Since moral principles state reasons and not all enabling conditions, the above cannot be a principle (even if a defender of universalizability can appeal to it [as Sinnott-Armstrong claims]). This is made clear in Jonathan Dancy, "Defending Particularism," Metaphilosophy 30 (1999): 25-32, p. 26.
    • (1999) Metaphilosophy , vol.30 , pp. 25-32
    • Dancy, J.1
  • 28
    • 0039440698 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An example suggested to me in conversation by Jonathan Dancy
    • An example suggested to me in conversation by Jonathan Dancy.
  • 29
    • 0040032811 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Varieties of virtue ethics
    • Justin Oakley, "Varieties of Virtue Ethics," Ratio 9 (1996): 128-52.
    • (1996) Ratio , vol.9 , pp. 128-152
    • Oakley, J.1
  • 30
    • 0040626062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 136.
    • Ratio , pp. 136
  • 31
    • 0040626052 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Principle ethics, particularism and another possibility
    • Soran Reader, "Principle Ethics, Particularism and Another Possibility," Philosophy 72 (1997): 269-96, p. 275.
    • (1997) Philosophy , vol.72 , pp. 269-296
    • Reader, S.1
  • 32
    • 0003593197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For more on a virtue ethical understanding of "irresolvable dilemmas," see Hursthouse, On Virtue Ethics.
    • On Virtue Ethics
    • Hursthouse1
  • 33
  • 34
    • 0038847861 scopus 로고
    • London: Chatto & Windus
    • It will have been noticed that I admit a large range of virtues, including efficiency. I cannot argue here for this view, but if we can think of a dithering, muddling, vacillating, pusillanimous person as having those features as part of character, we can surely think of efficiency as a virtue. For example, see a claim concerning the notoriously inefficient Tallis in Iris Murdoch's A Fairly Honourable Defeat (London: Chatto & Windus, 1970), p. 13: "I do think a reasonable amount of efficiency is an aspect of morals. There's a sort of ordered completeness of life and an intelligent use of one's talents which is the mark of a man." For more on the rule-based aspect of virtue ethics, see Hursthouse, "Normative Virtue Ethics," pp. 19-36.
    • (1970) A Fairly Honourable Defeat , pp. 13
    • Murdoch, I.1
  • 35
    • 3142679947 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It will have been noticed that I admit a large range of virtues, including efficiency. I cannot argue here for this view, but if we can think of a dithering, muddling, vacillating, pusillanimous person as having those features as part of character, we can surely think of efficiency as a virtue. For example, see a claim concerning the notoriously inefficient Tallis in Iris Murdoch's A Fairly Honourable Defeat (London: Chatto & Windus, 1970), p. 13: "I do think a reasonable amount of efficiency is an aspect of morals. There's a sort of ordered completeness of life and an intelligent use of one's talents which is the mark of a man." For more on the rule-based aspect of virtue ethics, see Hursthouse, "Normative Virtue Ethics," pp. 19-36.
    • Normative Virtue Ethics , pp. 19-36
    • Hursthouse1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.