-
1
-
-
0003593197
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Most self-consciously, Rosalind Hursthouse in On Virtue Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999).
-
(1999)
On Virtue Ethics
-
-
Hursthouse, R.1
-
2
-
-
0040626135
-
-
I thank Linda Zagzebski for this terminological suggestion
-
I thank Linda Zagzebski for this terminological suggestion.
-
-
-
-
3
-
-
0026180513
-
Virtue theory and abortion
-
Rosalind Hursthouse, "Virtue Theory and Abortion," Philosophy & Public Affairs 20 (1991): 223-46. An earlier 'qualified judge' account of rightness was offered by Yves R. Simon in The Definition of Moral Virtue, ed. Vukan Kuic (New York: Fordham University Press, 1986): "We say that an action will be the right action under the circumstances if the judgment about what to do is determined, is rendered, by a person of virtuous disposition" (p. 112). Compare also the qualified agent account of rightness proposed by Linda Trinkaus Zagzebski in Virtues of Mind: An Inquiry into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996): "A right act is what a person who is virtuously motivated and who has the understanding of the particular situation that a virtuous person would have, might do in like circumstances. . . . A moral duty is what a person who is virtuously motivated, and who has the understanding of the particular situation that a virtuous person would have, would do in like circumstances" (p. 135).
-
(1991)
Philosophy & Public Affairs
, vol.20
, pp. 223-246
-
-
Hursthouse, R.1
-
4
-
-
0026180513
-
-
ed. Vukan Kuic New York: Fordham University Press
-
Rosalind Hursthouse, "Virtue Theory and Abortion," Philosophy & Public Affairs 20 (1991): 223-46. An earlier 'qualified judge' account of rightness was offered by Yves R. Simon in The Definition of Moral Virtue, ed. Vukan Kuic (New York: Fordham University Press, 1986): "We say that an action will be the right action under the circumstances if the judgment about what to do is determined, is rendered, by a person of virtuous disposition" (p. 112). Compare also the qualified agent account of rightness proposed by Linda Trinkaus Zagzebski in Virtues of Mind: An Inquiry into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996): "A right act is what a person who is virtuously motivated and who has the understanding of the particular situation that a virtuous person would have, might do in like circumstances. . . . A moral duty is what a person who is virtuously motivated, and who has the understanding of the particular situation that a virtuous person would have, would do in like circumstances" (p. 135).
-
(1986)
The Definition of Moral Virtue
, pp. 112
-
-
Simon, Y.R.1
-
5
-
-
0026180513
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Rosalind Hursthouse, "Virtue Theory and Abortion," Philosophy & Public Affairs 20 (1991): 223-46. An earlier 'qualified judge' account of rightness was offered by Yves R. Simon in The Definition of Moral Virtue, ed. Vukan Kuic (New York: Fordham University Press, 1986): "We say that an action will be the right action under the circumstances if the judgment about what to do is determined, is rendered, by a person of virtuous disposition" (p. 112). Compare also the qualified agent account of rightness proposed by Linda Trinkaus Zagzebski in Virtues of Mind: An Inquiry into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996): "A right act is what a person who is virtuously motivated and who has the understanding of the particular situation that a virtuous person would have, might do in like circumstances. . . . A moral duty is what a person who is virtuously motivated, and who has the understanding of the particular situation that a virtuous person would have, would do in like circumstances" (p. 135).
-
(1996)
Virtues of Mind: An Inquiry into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge
, pp. 135
-
-
Zagzebski, L.T.1
-
7
-
-
84952037548
-
Agent-based virtue ethics
-
Moral Concepts, ed. Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, Jr., and Howard K. Wettstein Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press
-
Michael Slote, "Agent-Based Virtue Ethics," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 20, Moral Concepts, ed. Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, Jr., and Howard K. Wettstein (Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1996), pp. 83-101.
-
(1996)
Midwest Studies in Philosophy
, vol.20
, pp. 83-101
-
-
Slote, M.1
-
9
-
-
0009189022
-
"Agent-based virtue ethics," and "the justice of caring,"
-
Slote, "Agent-Based Virtue Ethics," and "The Justice of Caring," Social Philosophy and Policy 15 (1998): 171-95.
-
(1998)
Social Philosophy and Policy
, vol.15
, pp. 171-195
-
-
Slote1
-
10
-
-
0040626049
-
Monkeying with motives: Agent-basing virtue ethics
-
For further criticism of Slote's failure to incorporate notions of successful relation to the external world in his criterion of rightness, see Julia Driver, "Monkeying with Motives: Agent-Basing Virtue Ethics," Utilitas 7 (1995): 281-88.
-
(1995)
Utilitas
, vol.7
, pp. 281-288
-
-
Driver, J.1
-
11
-
-
0004240210
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
W. D. Ross, The Right and the Good (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1930), p. 2.
-
(1930)
The Right and the Good
, pp. 2
-
-
Ross, W.D.1
-
12
-
-
0040626060
-
Motive and rightness
-
Indeed, I agree with Stephen Sverdlik's view that sometimes the quality of a motive can change the deontic status of an action from right to wrong. See his "Motive and Rightness," Ethics 106 (1996): 327-49.
-
(1996)
Ethics
, vol.106
, pp. 327-349
-
-
Sverdlik, S.1
-
13
-
-
0038847933
-
-
Henceforth, 'virtuous act'
-
Henceforth, 'virtuous act'.
-
-
-
-
14
-
-
0003986649
-
-
trans. J. A. K. Thomson New York: Penguin Classics, sec. 2 iv
-
Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, trans. J. A. K. Thomson (New York: Penguin Classics, 1976), p. 97, sec. 2 iv.
-
(1976)
Nicomachean Ethics
, pp. 97
-
-
Aristotle1
-
17
-
-
0001157576
-
Consequentialism
-
ed. Peter Singer Oxford: Blackwell
-
The idea of honoring value is introduced by Philip Pettit in "Consequentialism," in A Companion to Ethics, ed. Peter Singer (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991), pp. 230-40.
-
(1991)
A Companion to Ethics
, pp. 230-240
-
-
Pettit, P.1
-
18
-
-
0039440696
-
-
See Sverdlik
-
See Sverdlik.
-
-
-
-
19
-
-
0040032818
-
-
Audi, p. 180
-
Audi, p. 180.
-
-
-
-
20
-
-
0040032815
-
The virtues and human nature
-
ed. Roger Crisp Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
Julia Driver, "The Virtues and Human Nature," in How Should One Live? Essays m the Philosophy of Virtue, ed. Roger Crisp (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996), pp. 111-29.
-
(1996)
How Should One Live? Essays M the Philosophy of Virtue
, pp. 111-129
-
-
Driver, J.1
-
21
-
-
0033163898
-
Modesty and ignorance
-
Julia Driver, "Modesty and Ignorance," Ethics 109 (1999): 827-34, p. 828.
-
(1999)
Ethics
, vol.109
, pp. 827-834
-
-
Driver, J.1
-
22
-
-
0004206765
-
-
Oxford: Blackwell
-
Jonathan Dancy, Moral Reasons (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993).
-
(1993)
Moral Reasons
-
-
Dancy, J.1
-
23
-
-
4244037174
-
-
Ibid., p. 60. Dancy does not mean to imply that we cannot make reasonable estimates on the basis of characteristic (as opposed to universal) properties of things, e.g., the characteristic badness of pain.
-
Moral Reasons
, pp. 60
-
-
-
25
-
-
0039440682
-
Some varieties of particularism
-
Walter Sinnott-Armstrong thinks that such principles can be turned into universal form provided they are formulated thus: do (or don't do) thus and so provided there are no underminers, reversers, exclusions, and overriders. See his "Some Varieties of Particularism," Metaphilosophy 30 (1999): 1-12, p. 6. For Dancy, however, an 'underminer' is the absence of a background ('enabling') condition and not a reason (a fact accepted by Sinnott-Armstrong). Since moral principles state reasons and not all enabling conditions, the above cannot be a principle (even if a defender of universalizability can appeal to it [as Sinnott-Armstrong claims]). This is made clear in Jonathan Dancy, "Defending Particularism," Metaphilosophy 30 (1999): 25-32, p. 26.
-
(1999)
Metaphilosophy
, vol.30
, pp. 1-12
-
-
Sinnott-Armstrong, W.1
-
26
-
-
38949101670
-
Defending particularism
-
Walter Sinnott-Armstrong thinks that such principles can be turned into universal form provided they are formulated thus: do (or don't do) thus and so provided there are no underminers, reversers, exclusions, and overriders. See his "Some Varieties of Particularism," Metaphilosophy 30 (1999): 1-12, p. 6. For Dancy, however, an 'underminer' is the absence of a background ('enabling') condition and not a reason (a fact accepted by Sinnott-Armstrong). Since moral principles state reasons and not all enabling conditions, the above cannot be a principle (even if a defender of universalizability can appeal to it [as Sinnott-Armstrong claims]). This is made clear in Jonathan Dancy, "Defending Particularism," Metaphilosophy 30 (1999): 25-32, p. 26.
-
(1999)
Metaphilosophy
, vol.30
, pp. 25-32
-
-
Dancy, J.1
-
28
-
-
0039440698
-
-
An example suggested to me in conversation by Jonathan Dancy
-
An example suggested to me in conversation by Jonathan Dancy.
-
-
-
-
29
-
-
0040032811
-
Varieties of virtue ethics
-
Justin Oakley, "Varieties of Virtue Ethics," Ratio 9 (1996): 128-52.
-
(1996)
Ratio
, vol.9
, pp. 128-152
-
-
Oakley, J.1
-
30
-
-
0040626062
-
-
Ibid., p. 136.
-
Ratio
, pp. 136
-
-
-
31
-
-
0040626052
-
Principle ethics, particularism and another possibility
-
Soran Reader, "Principle Ethics, Particularism and Another Possibility," Philosophy 72 (1997): 269-96, p. 275.
-
(1997)
Philosophy
, vol.72
, pp. 269-296
-
-
Reader, S.1
-
32
-
-
0003593197
-
-
For more on a virtue ethical understanding of "irresolvable dilemmas," see Hursthouse, On Virtue Ethics.
-
On Virtue Ethics
-
-
Hursthouse1
-
33
-
-
0004233558
-
-
New York: Random House
-
William Styron, Sophie's Choice (New York: Random House, 1979).
-
(1979)
Sophie's Choice
-
-
Styron, W.1
-
34
-
-
0038847861
-
-
London: Chatto & Windus
-
It will have been noticed that I admit a large range of virtues, including efficiency. I cannot argue here for this view, but if we can think of a dithering, muddling, vacillating, pusillanimous person as having those features as part of character, we can surely think of efficiency as a virtue. For example, see a claim concerning the notoriously inefficient Tallis in Iris Murdoch's A Fairly Honourable Defeat (London: Chatto & Windus, 1970), p. 13: "I do think a reasonable amount of efficiency is an aspect of morals. There's a sort of ordered completeness of life and an intelligent use of one's talents which is the mark of a man." For more on the rule-based aspect of virtue ethics, see Hursthouse, "Normative Virtue Ethics," pp. 19-36.
-
(1970)
A Fairly Honourable Defeat
, pp. 13
-
-
Murdoch, I.1
-
35
-
-
3142679947
-
-
It will have been noticed that I admit a large range of virtues, including efficiency. I cannot argue here for this view, but if we can think of a dithering, muddling, vacillating, pusillanimous person as having those features as part of character, we can surely think of efficiency as a virtue. For example, see a claim concerning the notoriously inefficient Tallis in Iris Murdoch's A Fairly Honourable Defeat (London: Chatto & Windus, 1970), p. 13: "I do think a reasonable amount of efficiency is an aspect of morals. There's a sort of ordered completeness of life and an intelligent use of one's talents which is the mark of a man." For more on the rule-based aspect of virtue ethics, see Hursthouse, "Normative Virtue Ethics," pp. 19-36.
-
Normative Virtue Ethics
, pp. 19-36
-
-
Hursthouse1
|