메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 7, Issue 1, 2010, Pages 74-104

Constructivism and practical reason: On intersubjectivity, abstraction, and judgment

Author keywords

Agnosticism; John Rawls; Moral realism and antirealism; Onora O'Neill; Original position; Thinness and thickness

Indexed keywords


EID: 73949112078     PISSN: 17404681     EISSN: 17455243     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1163/174046809X12544019606102     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (20)

References (45)
  • 1
    • 24144478785 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constructivism in Rawls and Kant
    • Samuel Freeman ed, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Onora O'Neill, 'Constructivism in Rawls and Kant', in Samuel Freeman (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Rawls (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), pp. 347-36 (348)
    • (2002) The Cambridge Companion to Rawls , Issue.348 , pp. 347-436
    • O'Neill, O.1
  • 2
    • 24144455887 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constructivism vs. Contractualism
    • (December),(321)
    • O'Neill, 'Constructivism vs. Contractualism', Ratio 16.4 (December 2003), pp. 319-31 (321)
    • (2003) Ratio , vol.16 , Issue.4 , pp. 319-331
    • O'Neill1
  • 5
    • 0040202098 scopus 로고
    • Skepticism about Practical Reason
    • (January)
    • Christine Korsgaard, 'Skepticism about Practical Reason', Journal of Philosophy 83.1 (January 1986), pp. 5-25. Korsgaard offers a distinction between two forms of skepticism about practical reason - that is, skepticism about the extent to which action can be directed by reason: the first (1), content skepticism, concerns the bearing of 'formal' rational considerations on deliberation and choice; the second (2), motivational skepticism, points at whether reason can ever be a motivation for action
    • (1986) Journal of Philosophy , vol.83 , Issue.1 , pp. 5-25
    • Korsgaard, C.1
  • 6
    • 79957431256 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Normativity and Practical Judgment
    • (November)
    • O. O'Neill, 'Normativity and Practical Judgment', Journal of Moral Philosophy 4.3 (November 2007), pp. 393-405
    • (2007) Journal of Moral Philosophy , vol.4 , Issue.3 , pp. 393-405
    • O'Neill, O.1
  • 7
    • 33845390409 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constructing Justice for Existing Practice: Rawls and the Status Quo
    • [July] esp. pp. 298-302
    • While most of the literature on constructivism concentrates on (1) anti-realist methodological commitments and (2) a focus on selection procedures, a partially different understanding of constructivism has been recently proposed. Both Aaron James ('Constructing Justice for Existing Practice: Rawls and the Status Quo', Philosophy and Public Affairs 33.3 [July 2005], pp. 281-316; esp. pp. 298-302)
    • (2005) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.33 , Issue.3 , pp. 281-316
    • James, A.1
  • 8
    • 49749132352 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Very Idea of Cosmopolitan Justice: Constructivism and International Agency
    • esp. pp. 3-5
    • and Saladin Meckled-Garcia ('On the Very Idea of Cosmopolitan Justice: Constructivism and International Agency', Journal of Political Philosophy, forthcoming, http://www.blackwell-synergy.com/toc/jopp/0/0, esp. pp. 3-5), put the emphasis on the interpretivist dimension of the constructivist methodology, whilst not denying its reliance on selection procedures
    • Journal of Political Philosophy
    • Meckled-Garcia, S.1
  • 9
    • 79957361758 scopus 로고
    • Interpretive Concepts
    • [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press]
    • Constructivism, understood in this way, is a strategy to cash out the specific normative principles that (ought to) regulate specific social practices, given the specific values served by, and agents participating in, each practice (for an account of interpretivism, see Ronald Dworkin, 'Interpretive Concepts', in Law's Empire [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986], pp. 45-86)
    • (1986) Law's Empire , pp. 45-86
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 10
    • 1842795953 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Facts and Principles
    • (Summer), at p. 213
    • G.A. Cohen, 'Facts and Principles', Philosophy and Public Affairs 31.3 (Summer 2003), pp. 211-45; at p. 213 n. 2
    • (2003) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.31 , Issue.2-3 , pp. 211-245
    • Cohen, G.A.1
  • 11
    • 79957141156 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constructivism in Ethics
    • E. Craig ed, London: Routledge, accessed 12 July 2007
    • O. O'Neill, 'Constructivism in Ethics', in E. Craig (ed.), Routledge Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (London: Routledge), http://www.rep.routledge. com/article/L014SECT1 (accessed 12 July 2007)
    • Routledge Encyclopaedia of Philosophy
    • O'Neill, O.1
  • 12
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [New York: Columbia University Press]
    • I take it that Rawls's account of the burdens of judgment, which are the main source of reasonable disagreement, is a way of articulating this idea. Unlike prejudice, biases and self-interest, the burdens of judgment are impediments to our judgments that even fully reasonable agents cannot be expected to overcome. Such burdens include, among others, the complexity of empirical evidence, the vagueness of moral concepts, and the way in which our 'history' and identity influence our moral intuitions (John Rawls, Political Liberalism [New York: Columbia University Press, 1993], pp. 54-58)
    • (1993) Political Liberalism , pp. 54-58
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 16
    • 38349156554 scopus 로고
    • Contractarian Constructivism
    • (April)
    • See Ronald Milo, 'Contractarian Constructivism', Journal of Philosophy 4.92 (April 1995), pp. 181-204
    • (1995) Journal of Philosophy , vol.4 , Issue.92 , pp. 181-204
    • Milo, R.1
  • 17
    • 79957017948 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kant's Moral Constructivism and his Conception of Legislation
    • Not all Kantian scholars, however, agree on a constructivist reading of Kant's moral philosophy. See, for instance, Patrick Kain, 'Kant's Moral Constructivism and his Conception of Legislation', The Paideia Project Online (1999), http://www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/TEth/TEthKain.htm
    • (1999) The Paideia Project Online
    • Kain, P.1
  • 18
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Oxford: Oxford University Press, rev. edn)
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, rev. edn, 1999), p. 10
    • (1999) A Theory of Justice , pp. 10
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 19
    • 84970771869 scopus 로고
    • The Procedural Republic and the Unencumbered Self
    • (Winter) at p. 82
    • Michael Sandel, 'The Procedural Republic and the Unencumbered Self', Political Theory 12.1 (Winter 1984), pp. 81-96; at p. 82
    • (1984) Political Theory , vol.12 , Issue.1 , pp. 81-96
    • Sandel, M.1
  • 20
    • 33845205223 scopus 로고
    • Rawlsian Constructivism in Moral Theory
    • esp. p. 73
    • See, for instance, David O. Brink, 'Rawlsian Constructivism in Moral Theory', Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (1987), pp. 71-90; esp. p. 73
    • (1987) Canadian Journal of Philosophy , vol.17 , pp. 71-90
    • Brink, D.O.1
  • 22
    • 0001501318 scopus 로고
    • Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory
    • (September)
    • J. Rawls, 'Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory', The Journal of Philosophy 77.9 (September 1980), pp. 515-72
    • (1980) The Journal of Philosophy , vol.77 , Issue.9 , pp. 515-572
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 23
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lectures I-III
    • Political Liberalism, Lectures I-III, pp. 3-129
    • Political Liberalism , pp. 3-129
  • 26
    • 0010985104 scopus 로고
    • Michael J. Meyer and William A. Parent [eds, The Constitution of Rights [Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press]
    • This strategy shares several theoretical features with Alan Gewirth's 'dialectically necessary method' (Alan Gewirth, 'Human Dignity as the Basis of Rights', in Michael J. Meyer and William A. Parent [eds.], The Constitution of Rights [Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 1992], pp. 10-46)
    • (1992) Human Dignity as the Basis of Rights , pp. 10-46
    • Gewirth, A.1
  • 27
    • 84975992288 scopus 로고
    • Political Ideals and Political Practice
    • (January) esp. pp. 40-45
    • On this issue, see, e.g., Robert E. Goodin, 'Political Ideals and Political Practice', British Journal of Political Science 25.1 (January 1995), pp. 37-56; esp. pp. 40-45
    • (1995) British Journal of Political Science , vol.25 , Issue.1 , pp. 37-56
    • Goodin, R.E.1
  • 28
    • 43249174367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Abstraction, Idealization, and Oppression
    • Lisa H. Schwartzman, 'Abstraction, Idealization, and Oppression', Metaphilosophy 37.5 (2006), pp. 565-88
    • (2006) Metaphilosophy , vol.37 , Issue.5 , pp. 565-588
    • Schwartzman, L.H.1
  • 29
    • 79957119936 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 573
    • See also Schwartzman, 'Abstraction, Idealization, and Oppression', pp. 570, 573. According to Schwartzman, every process of abstraction requires us to make' selective omissions', that is, to decide what is relevant to theorizing about justice and what is not, and therefore necessarily implies a certain degree of idealization
    • Abstraction, Idealization, and Oppression , pp. 570
    • Schwartzman1
  • 30
    • 0003875144 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • O. O'Neill, Bounds of Justice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), p. 138
    • (2000) Bounds of Justice , pp. 138
    • O'Neill, O.1
  • 31
    • 55449116225 scopus 로고
    • J.D. Evans [ed, Moral Philosophy and Contemporary Problems [London: Royal Institute of Philosophy] esp. p. 56
    • An important exception is her 'Abstraction, Idealisation and Ideology in Ethics', where she seems to refer to a more traditional notion of idealization (O. O'Neill, 'Abstraction, Idealisation and Ideology in Ethics', in J.D. Evans [ed.], Moral Philosophy and Contemporary Problems [London: Royal Institute of Philosophy, 1987], pp. 55-69; esp. p. 56). However, her use of the term in all later writings is significantly different
    • (1987) Abstraction, Idealisation and Ideology in Ethics , pp. 55-69
    • O'Neill, O.1
  • 32
    • 0003851654 scopus 로고
    • (trans. N. Kemp Smith; London: Macmillan) A132-3/B171-2; A134/B173
    • Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason (trans. N. Kemp Smith; London: Macmillan, [1787] 1973), A132-3/B171-2; A134/B173. Indeed, this holds for all kinds of principles and for all theoretical matters, not only in the realm of moral theorizing
    • (1787) Critique of Pure Reason
    • Kant, I.1
  • 34
    • 1842745538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One could raise the objection that abstract and perfectly general principles of intersubjective justifiability, like Kant's categorical imperative or O'Neill's principles of injury and coercion, are the most fundamental principles of Rawls's approach, as well. Indeed, they are the principles that demand the adoption of the original position in the rst place (on this, see also Cohen, 'Facts and Principles'). I think, however, that such principlfies are best conceived as methodological, rather than as proper substantive outputs of Rawls's constructivism. From a constructivist/agnostic perspective, intersubjective justifiability is a theoretical constraint, which an appropriate normative theory ought to respect, rather than an element, let alone a prescription, of such a theory. This issue is discussed in detail in Ronzoni and Valentini, 'On the Meta-ethical Status of Constructivism'
    • Facts and Principles
    • Cohen1
  • 36
    • 79957389853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Such an understanding of the original position as judgment-informed is also consistent with the slightly different connotation of the role of practical judgment that O'Neill has more recently stressed (O'Neill, 'Normativity and Practical Judgment', esp. pp. 401-405). Judgment, O'Neill has recently contended, is not simply a matter of 'picking' between a wider set of actions that a principle seems to allow: this would make the virtue of making good judgments a quasimagical quality. Moreover, it cannot be equated exclusively with the talent of reading the details of the situation
    • Normativity and Practical Judgment , pp. 401-405
    • O'Neill1
  • 38
    • 0003836741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Erin Kelly London and Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press
    • J. Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, ed. Erin Kelly (London and Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press, 2001), pp. 162-68
    • (2001) Justice as Fairness: A Restatement , pp. 162-168
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 39
    • 68249120569 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Apparent Paradox of Rawlsian Ideal Theory
    • (September)
    • For a more detailed discussion of this point, see also Laura Valentini, 'On the Apparent Paradox of Rawlsian Ideal Theory', The Journal of Political Philosophy, 17.3 (September 2009), pp. 332-355
    • (2009) The Journal of Political Philosophy , vol.17 , Issue.3 , pp. 332-355
    • Valentini, L.1
  • 41
    • 0004248343 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca: Cornell University Press
    • Thomas W. Pogge, Realizing Rawls (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1989), pp. 211-80
    • (1989) Realizing Rawls , pp. 211-280
    • Pogge, T.W.1
  • 43
    • 79957190973 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On this point, see Valentini, 'On the Apparent Paradox of Rawlsian Ideal Theory'. Valentini argues that, unlike Rawls's domestic theory, which is fruitfully open to potential revisions and modifications, his theory of international justice is constructed in a way that obscures the very problem of international justice from the outset. In the light of the argument made in this paper we could reformulate Valentini's point and claim that, if she is right, this might be due to a bad (short-sighted or excessively rigid) exercise of judgment
    • Apparent Paradox of Rawlsian Ideal Theory
    • Valentini1
  • 45
    • 0003867020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • and Timothy M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998])
    • (1998) What We Owe to Each Other
    • Scanlon, T.M.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.