메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 77, Issue 5-6, 2009, Pages 1478-1520

Future generations: A prioritarian view

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 70449115985     PISSN: 00168076     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (47)

References (211)
  • 1
    • 70449107763 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See WELL-BEING AND EQUITY: A FRAMEWORK FOR POLICY ANALYSIS (forthcoming 2010) [hereinafter, ADLER, WELL-BEING AND EQUITY];
    • See MATTHEW D. ADLER, WELL-BEING AND EQUITY: A FRAMEWORK FOR POLICY ANALYSIS (forthcoming 2010) [hereinafter, ADLER, WELL-BEING AND EQUITY];
    • Adler, M.D.1
  • 2
    • 33846821844 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chris william sanchirico, inequality and uncertainty: Theory and legal applications
    • Matthew D. Adler & Chris William Sanchirico, Inequality and Uncertainty: Theory and Legal Applications, 155 U. PA. L. REV. 279 (2006);
    • (2006) 155 U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.279
    • Adler, M.D.1
  • 4
    • 84869681721 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Well-Being, Inequality and Time: The Time-Slice Problem and Its Policy Implications (Univ. of Pa. Law Sch. Inst, for Law & Econ., Working Paper No. 07-17,2007), available at
    • Matthew D. Adler, Well-Being, Inequality and Time: The Time-Slice Problem and Its Policy Implications (Univ. of Pa. Law Sch. Inst, for Law & Econ., Working Paper No. 07-17,2007), available at http://ssrn.com/abstractsl006871.
    • Adler, M.D.1
  • 5
    • 84869681722 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the appropriate formula for what I call the "core case," where the very same N individuals exist in all outcomes. Variations in the formula for other cases are considered below. See infra Part III.
    • This is the appropriate formula for what I call the "core case," where the very same N individuals exist in all outcomes. Variations in the formula for other cases are considered below. See infra Part III.
  • 6
    • 84869677183 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Formally, a SWF is sensitive to equity if it satisfies the "Pigou-Dalton" principle. Pri-oritarian SWFs are a subset of the SWFs that satisfy this principle. See sources cited supra note 1.
    • Formally, a SWF is sensitive to equity if it satisfies the "Pigou-Dalton" principle. Pri-oritarian SWFs are a subset of the SWFs that satisfy this principle. See sources cited supra note 1.
  • 7
    • 84869688601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • By "possible outcomes," I mean all the outcomes in the outcome set, O, which is relevant to the choice at hand. See infra text accompanying notes 13-15.
    • By "possible outcomes," I mean all the outcomes in the outcome set, O, which is relevant to the choice at hand. See infra text accompanying notes 13-15.
  • 8
    • 84869688600 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Iff' means "if and only if."
    • "Iff' means "if and only if."
  • 9
    • 70449112295 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If individual j exists in outcome x but not y, and has utility ut(x) in x, the effect of the above formula is to assign i a utility level of zero in y, and to take full account of the difference between u.(x) and zero in ranking the two outcomes, as much as if i existed in outcome y.
    • If individual j exists in outcome x but not y, and has utility ut(x) in x, the effect of the above formula is to assign i a utility level of zero in y, and to take full account of the difference between u.(x) and zero in ranking the two outcomes, as much as if i existed in outcome y.
  • 10
    • 70449105648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For reviews of this literature, see Walter Bossert & John A. Weymark, Utility in Social Choice, in 2 HANDBOOK OF UTILITY THEORY 1099 (Salvador Barbera et al. eds., 2004);
    • For reviews of this literature, see Walter Bossert & John A. Weymark, Utility in Social Choice, in 2 HANDBOOK OF UTILITY THEORY 1099 (Salvador Barbera et al. eds., 2004);
  • 11
    • 67649380711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Claude d'Aspremont & Louis Gevers, Social Welfare Functional and Interpersonal Comparability, in 1 HANDBOOK OF SOCIAL CHOICE AND WELFARE 459 (Kenneth J. Arrow et al. eds., 2002).
    • and Claude d'Aspremont & Louis Gevers, Social Welfare Functional and Interpersonal Comparability, in 1 HANDBOOK OF SOCIAL CHOICE AND WELFARE 459 (Kenneth J. Arrow et al. eds., 2002).
  • 13
    • 70449112296 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Christopher Heady, Optimal Taxation as a Guide to Tax Policy, in THE ECONOMICS OF TAX POLICY 23 (Michael P. Devereux ed.
    • Christopher Heady, Optimal Taxation as a Guide to Tax Policy, in THE ECONOMICS OF TAX POLICY 23 (Michael P. Devereux ed., 1996);
    • (1996)
  • 14
    • 70449106694 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nicholas Stern, The Theory of Optimal Commodity and Income Taxation: An Introduction, in THE THEORY OF TAXATION FOR DEVELOPING COUNTRIES 22 (David Newbery & Nicholas Stern eds., 1987).
    • Nicholas Stern, The Theory of Optimal Commodity and Income Taxation: An Introduction, in THE THEORY OF TAXATION FOR DEVELOPING COUNTRIES 22 (David Newbery & Nicholas Stern eds., 1987).
  • 15
    • 70449097422 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See The Incidence of Pollution Control Policies 26-28 (Nat'l Bureau of Econ. Research, Working Paper No. 11438,2005).
    • See Ian W.H. Parry et al., The Incidence of Pollution Control Policies 26-28 (Nat'l Bureau of Econ. Research, Working Paper No. 11438,2005).
    • Parry, I.W.H.1
  • 16
    • 70449088536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • NICHOLAS STERN, THE ECONOMICS OF CLIMATE CHANGE
    • NICHOLAS STERN, THE ECONOMICS OF CLIMATE CHANGE (2007).
    • (2007)
  • 18
    • 70449106695 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 11, at 165-91;
    • See NORDHAUS, supra note 11, at 165-91;
    • Nordhaus1
  • 19
    • 84869668495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Climate Change and Discounting the Future: A Guide for the Perplexed (Reg-Markets Ctr., Working Paper No. 08-19,2008), available at
    • David Weisbach & Cass R. Sunstein, Climate Change and Discounting the Future: A Guide for the Perplexed (Reg-Markets Ctr., Working Paper No. 08-19,2008), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1223448.
    • Weisbach, D.1    Sunstein, C.R.2
  • 20
    • 70449097413 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See sources cited supra note 1. The articles cited there are agnostic as between priori-tarianism and other types of equity-regarding SWFs, but ray forthcoming book defends priori-tarianism.
    • See sources cited supra note 1. The articles cited there are agnostic as between priori-tarianism and other types of equity-regarding SWFs, but ray forthcoming book defends priori-tarianism.
  • 21
    • 70449095509 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id.
    • See id.
  • 22
    • 70449111106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ADLER, WELL-BEING AND EQUITY, supra note 1.
    • See ADLER, WELL-BEING AND EQUITY, supra note 1.
  • 23
    • 70449094277 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Theorists who are concerned about equalizing opportunity for well-being, rather than well-being itself, may see prioritarianism as a rough approximation of the correct moral theory. Hybrid theorists who believe that morality requires the maximization of good consequences, within deontological constraints, may see prioritarianism as one component of a broader moral theory-as may theorists who believe that morality requires attention both to human well-being, and to other considerations, e.g., animal well-being or intrinsic environmental values. See id.
    • Theorists who are concerned about equalizing opportunity for well-being, rather than well-being itself, may see prioritarianism as a rough approximation of the correct moral theory. Hybrid theorists who believe that morality requires the maximization of good consequences, within deontological constraints, may see prioritarianism as one component of a broader moral theory-as may theorists who believe that morality requires attention both to human well-being, and to other considerations, e.g., animal well-being or intrinsic environmental values. See id.
  • 25
    • 0002789980 scopus 로고
    • A reconsideration of the harsanyi-sen debate on utilitarianism
    • Jon Elster & John E. Roemer eds.
    • John A. Weymark, A Reconsideration of the Harsanyi-Sen Debate on Utilitarianism, in INTERPERSONAL COMPARISONS OF WELL-BEING 255,289-97 (Jon Elster & John E. Roemer eds., 1991).
    • (1991) Interpersonal Comparisons of Well-being , vol.255 , pp. 289-297
    • Weymark, J.A.1
  • 28
    • 70449128949 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This means that v(.) produces the very same ranking of life histories, lotteries over life histories, and comparisons of each life history to nonexistence as u(.) iff v(.) = ku(.), where A: is a positive constant.
    • This means that v(.) produces the very same ranking of life histories, lotteries over life histories, and comparisons of each life history to nonexistence as u(.) iff v(.) = ku(.), where A: is a positive constant.
  • 29
    • 84869677715 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "At least as good as" means either better than or equally good as.
    • "At least as good as" means either better than or equally good as.
  • 30
    • 1042279842 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Karsten klint jensen, what is the difference between (Moderate) egalitarianism and prioritarianism?
    • See
    • See Karsten Klint Jensen, What Is the Difference between (Moderate) Egalitarianism and Prioritarianism?, 19 ECON. & PHIL. 89,99 (2003);
    • (2003) 19 Econ. & Phil. , vol.89 , pp. 99
  • 31
    • 84919568344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Equality versus priority: A useful distinction
    • (Daniel Wikler et al. eds., forthcoming) (manuscript at 2, on file with author)
    • John Broome, Equality Versus Priority: A Useful Distinction, in FAIRNESS AND GOODNESS IN HEALTH (Daniel Wikler et al. eds., forthcoming) (manuscript at 2, on file with author);
    • Fairness and Goodness in Health
    • Broome, J.1
  • 33
    • 70449102303 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wlodek Rabinowicz, Prioritarianism and Uncertainty: On the Interpersonal Addition Theorem and the Priority View, in EXPLORING PRACTICAL PHILOSOPHY: FROM ACTION TO VALUES 139,148 (Dan Egonsson et al. eds., 2001);
    • Wlodek Rabinowicz, Prioritarianism and Uncertainty: On the Interpersonal Addition Theorem and the Priority View, in EXPLORING PRACTICAL PHILOSOPHY: FROM ACTION TO VALUES 139,148 (Dan Egonsson et al. eds., 2001);
  • 34
    • 70449129386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Matters of Priority 99-105 (Mar. 2005) (unpublished Ph.D. thesis, The Australian National University) (on file with author).
    • Campbell Brown, Matters of Priority 99-105 (Mar. 2005) (unpublished Ph.D. thesis, The Australian National University) (on file with author).
    • Brown, C.1
  • 35
    • 84869674929 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "The value of the SWF" means complex math equations
    • "The value of the SWF" means complex math equations
  • 36
    • 70449098904 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Brown, supra note 21 at 117-18.
    • See Brown, supra note 21 at 117-18.
  • 37
    • 0003437941 scopus 로고
    • See (presenting a conception of equality that sees each individual as having a distinct claim to well-being, and that gives priority to worse-off individuals);
    • See THOMAS NAGEL, EQUALITY AND PARTIALITY 63-74 (1991) (presenting a conception of equality that sees each individual as having a distinct claim to well-being, and that gives priority to worse-off individuals);
    • (1991) Equality and Partiality , pp. 63-74
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 39
    • 70449102302 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, the individual is at different levels in the two outcomes, so to be more precise, we should say that the strength of the claim is a decreasing function of the average well-being level.
    • Of course, the individual is at different levels in the two outcomes, so to be more precise, we should say that the strength of the claim is a decreasing function of the average well-being level.
  • 40
    • 70449111185 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That is, ul(x)-ul(y) = ui(y)-uj(x).
    • That is, ul(x)-ul(y) = ui(y)-uj(x).
  • 41
    • 70449097414 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That is, u(x) > ut(y) > ufy) > ut(x).
    • That is, u(x) > ut(y) > ufy) > ut(x).
  • 42
    • 84869677714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Louis Kaplow and Steven Shavell use the term "fairness" to mean non-welfarism."
    • Louis Kaplow and Steven Shavell use the term "fairness" to mean non-welfarism."
  • 43
    • 84861616009 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See However, if one views fairness (as I do) as a matter of the equitable satisfaction of individuals' claims to well-being, there is no inconsistency between fairness and welfarism.
    • See Louis KAPLOW & STEVEN SHAVELL, FAIRNESS VERSUS WELFARE 38-45 (2002). However, if one views fairness (as I do) as a matter of the equitable satisfaction of individuals' claims to well-being, there is no inconsistency between fairness and welfarism.
    • (2002) Fairness Versus Welfare , pp. 38-45
    • Kaplow, L.1    Shavell, S.2
  • 44
    • 70449088537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the case of infinite populations, we need to distinguish between different variants of the anonymity axiom. See infra note 84 and accompanying text. But in the finite case, anonymity is straightforward: utility vectors with the same, finite number of entries that are permutations of each other must be ranked as equally good.
    • In the case of infinite populations, we need to distinguish between different variants of the anonymity axiom. See infra note 84 and accompanying text. But in the finite case, anonymity is straightforward: utility vectors with the same, finite number of entries that are permutations of each other must be ranked as equally good.
  • 45
    • 70449125627 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Leximin says to rank two outcomes equally if the utility vectors corresponding to the two are permutations of each other. Otherwise, x is better than y if the worst-off individual in x is better off than the worst-off individual in y; if their well-being levels are equal, then x is better than y if the 2nd-worst-off individual in x is better off than the 2nd-worst-off individual in y; and if their well-being levels are equal, then x is better than y if the 3rd-worst-off individual in x is better off than the 3rd-worst-off individual in y; and so forth.
    • Leximin says to rank two outcomes equally if the utility vectors corresponding to the two are permutations of each other. Otherwise, x is better than y if the worst-off individual in x is better off than the worst-off individual in y; if their well-being levels are equal, then x is better than y if the 2nd-worst-off individual in x is better off than the 2nd-worst-off individual in y; and if their well-being levels are equal, then x is better than y if the 3rd-worst-off individual in x is better off than the 3rd-worst-off individual in y; and so forth.
  • 46
    • 70449132278 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These are the only prioritarian SWFs which are invariant to multiplication of individual utilities by a common positive constant. More precisely, Atkinsonian SWFs are thus invariant if all utilities are nonnegative. No prioritarian SWF is invariant to multiplication of utilities by a common positive constant once negative individual utilities are allowed into the domain of utility vectors. And, quite apart from the invariance issue, the Atkinsonian SWF is not suitable for use with negative utilities because-with negative utilities-the function o(u.(x)) = ()u*~r ' i-r ' is either undefined or, if defined, not both strictly increasing and strictly concave.
    • These are the only prioritarian SWFs which are invariant to multiplication of individual utilities by a common positive constant. More precisely, Atkinsonian SWFs are thus invariant if all utilities are nonnegative. No prioritarian SWF is invariant to multiplication of utilities by a common positive constant once negative individual utilities are allowed into the domain of utility vectors. And, quite apart from the invariance issue, the Atkinsonian SWF is not suitable for use with negative utilities because-with negative utilities-the function o(u.(x)) = ()u*~r ' i-r ' is either undefined or, if defined, not both strictly increasing and strictly concave.
  • 47
    • 70449129376 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Risk Equity, supra note 1, at 41 n.122.
    • See Adler, Risk Equity, supra note 1, at 41 n.122.
    • Adler1
  • 48
    • 70449123218 scopus 로고
    • Utilitarianism, uncertainty and information
    • See, e.g., (Amartya Sen & Bernard Williams eds.
    • See, e.g., Peter J. Hammond, Utilitarianism, Uncertainty and Information, in UTILITARIANISM AND BEYOND 85,90-96 (Amartya Sen & Bernard Williams eds., 1994);
    • (1994) Utilitarianism and Beyond , vol.85 , pp. 90-96
    • Hammond, P.J.1
  • 49
    • 70449108782 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rabi-nowicz, supra note 21;
    • Rabi-nowicz, supra note 21;
  • 50
    • 84869668492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Marc Fleurbaey, Assessing Risky Social Situations (Society for Social Choice and Welfare, Working Paper, Feb. 2008)
    • Marc Fleurbaey, Assessing Risky Social Situations (Society for Social Choice and Welfare, Working Paper, Feb. 2008), http://www.accessecon.com/pubs/ SCW2008/SCW2008-08-00028S.pdf.
  • 51
    • 0002380531 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Elchanan ben-porath et al., on the measurement of inequality under uncertainty
    • See, e.g.
    • See, e.g., Elchanan Ben-Porath et al., On the Measurement of Inequality under Uncertainty, 75 J. ECON. THEORY 194 (1997);
    • (1997) 75 J. Econ. Theory , vol.194
  • 52
    • 0001307129 scopus 로고
    • Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics, and interpersonal comparisons of utility: Comment
    • Peter A. Diamond, Cardinal Welfare, Individualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility: Comment, 75 J. POL. ECON. 765 (1967);
    • (1967) 75 J. Pol. Econ. , vol.765
    • Diamond, P.A.1
  • 53
    • 44949148922 scopus 로고
    • Quadratic social welfare functions
    • Larry G. Epstein & Uzi Segal, Quadratic Social Welfare Functions, 100 J. POL. ECON. 691 (1992).
    • (1992) 100 J. Pol. Econ. , vol.691
    • Epstein, L.G.1    Segal, U.2
  • 54
    • 70449129375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The dispute about the appropriate application of a social welfare function under conditions of uncertainty is fully reviewed
    • supra note 1.
    • The dispute about the appropriate application of a social welfare function under conditions of uncertainty is fully reviewed in ADLER, WELL-BEING AND EQUITY, supra note 1.
    • Adler, Well-being and Equity
  • 56
    • 41049107294 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Discounting and the time preference rate
    • John Creedy & Ross Guest, Discounting and the Time Preference Rate, 84 ECON. REC 109 (2008);
    • (2008) 84 Econ. Rec , vol.109
    • Creedy, J.1    Guest, R.2
  • 57
    • 34248371289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Discounting: A review of the basic economics
    • Geoffrey Heal, Discounting: A Review of the Basic Economics, 74 U. CHI. L. REV. 59 (2007).
    • (2007) 74 U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.59
    • Heal, G.1
  • 58
    • 70449102313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is a vast literature about discounting.
    • There is a vast literature about discounting.
  • 59
    • 70449097423 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., supra note 12, at 3 n.7.
    • See, e.g., Weisbach & Sunstein, supra note 12, at 3 n.7.
    • Weisbach1    Sunstein2
  • 60
    • 70449111196 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a discussion of discounting and cost-benefit analysis
    • For a discussion of discounting and cost-benefit analysis,
  • 61
    • 70449089512 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 18, at 173-77. One argument for discounting in the context of cost-benefit analysis-that it is a way to compensate for the fact that future generations will be richer and have a lower marginal utility of consumption-is unavailing in the SWF context, because the marginal utility of consumption is already reflected in the utility function u(x). See infra text accompanying notes 46-48.
    • See ADLER & POSNER, supra note 18, at 173-77. One argument for discounting in the context of cost-benefit analysis-that it is a way to compensate for the fact that future generations will be richer and have a lower marginal utility of consumption-is unavailing in the SWF context, because the marginal utility of consumption is already reflected in the utility function u(x). See infra text accompanying notes 46-48.
    • Adler1    Posner2
  • 62
    • 0033127822 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Environmental regulation, cost-benefit analysis, and the discounting of human lives
    • Ricky Revesz draws a similar distinction. See (arguing that "discounting raises analytically distinct issues in the cases of latent harms and harms to future generations").
    • Ricky Revesz draws a similar distinction. See Richard L. Revesz, Environmental Regulation, Cost-Benefit Analysis, and the Discounting of Human Lives, 99 COLUM. L. REV. 941, 948 (1999) (arguing that "discounting raises analytically distinct issues in the cases of latent harms and harms to future generations").
    • (1999) 99 Colum. L. Rev. , vol.941 , pp. 948
    • Revesz, R.L.1
  • 63
    • 70449084292 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As already explained, I am assuming the completeness and convergence of extended preferences in this Article to simplify the analysis.
    • As already explained, I am assuming the completeness and convergence of extended preferences in this Article to simplify the analysis.
  • 64
    • 70449091440 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying note 18.
    • See supra text accompanying note 18.
  • 65
    • 70449119585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This could be a vector of consumptions of different goods or a single consumption amount.
    • This could be a vector of consumptions of different goods or a single consumption amount.
  • 68
    • 70449093312 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a full discussion of formulas for social choice that take account of individuals' lifetime utility, birth dates, and length of life
    • For a full discussion of formulas for social choice that take account of individuals' lifetime utility, birth dates, and length of life,
  • 69
    • 70449102312 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 34, at 253-71. A variation on this formula puts the discount rate inside rather than outside the g-N function, i.e., 'V g(D(b(x' i))u. (x)) ? Other variations make the discount factor a function of some date other than the individual's birth date, e.g., his death date, or the date midway between birth and death. My arguments against interpersonal discounting apply to all these variations.
    • See BLACKORBY ET AL., supra note 34, at 253-71. A variation on this formula puts the discount rate inside rather than outside the g-N function, i.e., 'V g(D(b(x' i))u. (x)) ? Other variations make the discount factor a function of some date other than the individual's birth date, e.g., his death date, or the date midway between birth and death. My arguments against interpersonal discounting apply to all these variations.
    • Blackorby1
  • 70
    • 70449107762 scopus 로고
    • See Consequentialism Implies a Zero Rate of Intergenerational Discount, in JUSTICE BETWEEN AGE GROUPS AND GENERATIONS 162 (Peter Laslett & James S. Fishkin eds.
    • See Tyler Cowen, Consequentialism Implies a Zero Rate of Intergenerational Discount, in JUSTICE BETWEEN AGE GROUPS AND GENERATIONS 162 (Peter Laslett & James S. Fishkin eds., 1992);
    • (1992)
    • Cowen, T.1
  • 71
    • 70449097421 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JOHN BROOME, WEIGHING LIVES 127
    • JOHN BROOME, WEIGHING LIVES 127 (2004);
    • (2004)
  • 72
    • 70449098902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 34, at 253-59.
    • BLACKORBY ET AL., supra note 34, at 253-59.
    • Blackorby1
  • 73
    • 70449106693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Cowen, supra note 43, at 164.
    • See Cowen, supra note 43, at 164.
  • 74
    • 70449132277 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To be sure, the deliberates who wanted to be impartial vis-a-vis some proper subset of the world's population would presumably want to be sensitive to the fact that harms and benefits to persons outside the community of interest might, in turn, affect the well-being of individuals inside the community of interest-for example, because these insiders care about the outsiders. However, such impacts would show up in the utility function of the insiders.
    • To be sure, the deliberates who wanted to be impartial vis-a-vis some proper subset of the world's population would presumably want to be sensitive to the fact that harms and benefits to persons outside the community of interest might, in turn, affect the well-being of individuals inside the community of interest-for example, because these insiders care about the outsiders. However, such impacts would show up in the utility function of the insiders.
  • 75
    • 70449111195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 18, at 173-77.
    • See ADLER & POSNER, supra note 18, at 173-77.
    • Adler1    Posner2
  • 76
    • 70449123235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Whether the prioritarian SWF would, in fact, approve the policy would depend on the utility levels of the future and present individuals.
    • Whether the prioritarian SWF would, in fact, approve the policy would depend on the utility levels of the future and present individuals.
  • 77
    • 84869671306 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I assume here that the ranking of actions in the choice set A is a function of probability numbers expressing the probability that a given action a in this set would yield a given outcome x in the outcome set O-probability numbers of the form jt (x) -as well as the utility function M(.) that maps each outcome onto a utility vector, and the SWF X"1 g(u(x)) tnat produces a ranking of those vectors. The probability term n (x) is what I am calling, roughly, the probability of an outcome "conditional" on a choice. Whether jr (*) is, strictly, a conditional probability implicates the debate between so-called "causal" and "evidential" decision theory, which I need not further discuss here.
    • I assume here that the ranking of actions in the choice set A is a function of probability numbers expressing the probability that a given action a in this set would yield a given outcome x in the outcome set O-probability numbers of the form jt (x) -as well as the utility function M(.) that maps each outcome onto a utility vector, and the SWF X"1 g(u(x)) tnat produces a ranking of those vectors. The probability term n (x) is what I am calling, roughly, the probability of an outcome "conditional" on a choice. Whether jr (*) is, strictly, a conditional probability implicates the debate between so-called "causal" and "evidential" decision theory, which I need not further discuss here.
  • 78
    • 70449119583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 1. Further, my assumption that the ranking of actions in the choice set is a function of the n (x) values, the utility function, and the SWF is more generic than the specific claim that this information is integrated via the EU formula-an issue I leave open in this Article.
    • See ADLER, WELL-BEING AND EQUITY, supra note 1. Further, my assumption that the ranking of actions in the choice set is a function of the n (x) values, the utility function, and the SWF is more generic than the specific claim that this information is integrated via the EU formula-an issue I leave open in this Article.
    • Well-being and Equity
    • Adler1
  • 79
    • 70449108789 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying notes 32-33.
    • See supra text accompanying notes 32-33.
  • 80
    • 70449105647 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 48.
    • See supra note 48.
  • 81
    • 70449129384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One variation on the uncertainty argument for discounting points to an extinction risk. See STERN, supra note 10, at 50-54;
    • One variation on the uncertainty argument for discounting points to an extinction risk. See STERN, supra note 10, at 50-54;
  • 82
    • 50249137123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Antoine Bommier & Stephane Zuber, Can Preferences for Catastrophe Avoidance Reconcile Social Discounting with Intergenerational Equity?, 31 SOC. CHOICE & WELFARE 415
    • Antoine Bommier & Stephane Zuber, Can Preferences for Catastrophe Avoidance Reconcile Social Discounting with Intergenerational Equity?, 31 SOC. CHOICE & WELFARE 415 (2008);
    • (2008)
  • 83
    • 55949118682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Discounting climate change
    • This argument moves outside the core case. Instead, the date after which individuals no longer exist, and the number of individuals who exist, can vary across outcomes. If the existence of a given generation is likelier than succeeding generations, and less likely than preceding generations, then an argument for ranking outcomes with a discount factor to reflect this extinction risk arises. However, a more transparent and flexible approach to taking account of extinction risk would seem to be ranking outcomes without a discount factor, and incorporating the risk into the representation of each action as a probability distribution across outcomes. The flexibility of this approach would be particularly advantageous, it would seem, if we wish to allow the extinction risk to vary depending on which policy is undertaken (e.g., whether or not we take steps to mitigate a catastrophic event), rather than being exogenous.
    • Partha Dasgupta, Discounting Climate Change, 37 J. RISK & UNCERTAINTY 141,160 (2008). This argument moves outside the core case. Instead, the date after which individuals no longer exist, and the number of individuals who exist, can vary across outcomes. If the existence of a given generation is likelier than succeeding generations, and less likely than preceding generations, then an argument for ranking outcomes with a discount factor to reflect this extinction risk arises. However, a more transparent and flexible approach to taking account of extinction risk would seem to be ranking outcomes without a discount factor, and incorporating the risk into the representation of each action as a probability distribution across outcomes. The flexibility of this approach would be particularly advantageous, it would seem, if we wish to allow the extinction risk to vary depending on which policy is undertaken (e.g., whether or not we take steps to mitigate a catastrophic event), rather than being exogenous.
    • (2008) 37 J. Risk & Uncertainty , vol.141 , pp. 160
    • Dasgupta, P.1
  • 84
    • 70449094288 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There certainly can be societies that are immoral in some fundamental sense, e.g., racist, and are also seen by some of the members of these societies to be immoral.
    • There certainly can be societies that are immoral in some fundamental sense, e.g., racist, and are also seen by some of the members of these societies to be immoral.
  • 85
    • 51249153652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Discounting the future, yet again
    • See
    • See Geoffrey Brennan, Discounting the Future, Yet Again, 6 POL., PHIL. & ECON. 259, 268 (2007).
    • (2007) 6 Pol., Phil. & Econ. , vol.259 , pp. 268
    • Brennan, G.1
  • 86
    • 70449091439 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This premise is to simplify the analysis, and might mean that without consumption individuals die prematurely and end up with a life no better than nonexistence; or that they subsist but end up with a life no better than nonexistence.
    • This premise is to simplify the analysis, and might mean that without consumption individuals die prematurely and end up with a life no better than nonexistence; or that they subsist but end up with a life no better than nonexistence.
  • 87
    • 70449102310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Take any two individuals, one better off, one worse off. Consider the ratio between the change in the value of the SWF produced by giving a small increment of utility to the worse-off individual, and the change produced by giving a small increment to the better-off individual. That ratio increases without limit as y increases.
    • Take any two individuals, one better off, one worse off. Consider the ratio between the change in the value of the SWF produced by giving a small increment of utility to the worse-off individual, and the change produced by giving a small increment to the better-off individual. That ratio increases without limit as y increases.
  • 89
    • 70449115163 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at 40-45.
    • Adler, Risk Equity, supra note 1, at 40-45.
    • Risk Equity
    • Adler1
  • 90
    • 70449111105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To show this formally, let us denote by S the stock of resources held by the current generation, and N the number of individuals in each generation. The leader of the current generation chooses some amount c for the first-generation individuals to consume. With an interest rate of r, this yields (5-c)(l+r) for the future generation. If the leader makes this decision using the Atkinsonian SWF, without discounting the future generation's utility, she chooses c so as to maximize complex math equations
    • To show this formally, let us denote by S the stock of resources held by the current generation, and N the number of individuals in each generation. The leader of the current generation chooses some amount c for the first-generation individuals to consume. With an interest rate of r, this yields (5-c)(l+r) for the future generation. If the leader makes this decision using the Atkinsonian SWF, without discounting the future generation's utility, she chooses c so as to maximize complex math equations
  • 91
    • 61449524838 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The value of a person
    • See, e.g., [hereinafter BROOME, Value];
    • See, e.g., JOHN BROOME, The Value of a Person, in ETHICS OUT OF ECONOMICS 228 (1999) [hereinafter BROOME, Value];
    • (1999) Ethics Out of Economics , vol.228
    • Broome, J.1
  • 92
    • 70449089500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 43;
    • BROOME, supra note 43;
    • Broome1
  • 93
    • 70449084293 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DAVID HEYD, GENETHICS (1992);
    • DAVID HEYD, GENETHICS (1992);
  • 94
    • 70449094287 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 41, at 351-79;
    • PARFIT, supra note 41, at 351-79;
    • Parfit
  • 96
    • 34548523681 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Krister Bykvist, The Benefits of Coming into Existence, 135 PHIL. STUD. 335 (2007);
    • Krister Bykvist, The Benefits of Coming into Existence, 135 PHIL. STUD. 335 (2007);
  • 97
    • 34250330834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Caspar Hare, Voices from Another World: Must We Respect the Interests of People Who Do Not, and Will Never, Exist?, 117 ETHICS 498 (2007);
    • Caspar Hare, Voices from Another World: Must We Respect the Interests of People Who Do Not, and Will Never, Exist?, 117 ETHICS 498 (2007);
  • 98
    • 34548542622 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nils Holtug, On the Value of Coming into Existence, 5 J. ETHICS 361 (2001);
    • Nils Holtug, On the Value of Coming into Existence, 5 J. ETHICS 361 (2001);
  • 99
    • 0002174957 scopus 로고
    • The paradox of future individuals
    • Gregory S. Kavka, The Paradox of Future Individuals, 11 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 93, 93-94 (1981);
    • (1981) 11 Phil. & Pub. Aff. , vol.93 , pp. 93-94
    • Kavka, G.S.1
  • 100
    • 0003103693 scopus 로고
    • Utilitarianism and new generations
    • Jan Narverson, Utilitarianism and New Generations, 76 MIND 62 (1967);
    • (1967) 76 Mind , vol.62
    • Narverson, J.1
  • 102
    • 0000435250 scopus 로고
    • The non-identity problem
    • James Woodward, The Non-Identity Problem, 96 ETHICS 804 (1986).
    • (1986) 96 Ethics 804
    • Woodward, J.1
  • 103
    • 70449089511 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 57, at 93-94 (citations omitted).
    • Kavka, supra note 57, at 93-94 (citations omitted).
    • Kavka1
  • 104
    • 84869686430 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 41, at 355-56 (distinguishing between "Same People Choices" and "Different People Choices" and, within the latter category, between "Same Number Choices" and "Different Number Choices").
    • See PARFIT, supra note 41, at 355-56 (distinguishing between "Same People Choices" and "Different People Choices" and, within the latter category, between "Same Number Choices" and "Different Number Choices").
    • Parfit
  • 105
    • 70449135586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a recent discussion of the person-affecting principle with reference to prioritarian-ism
    • For a recent discussion of the person-affecting principle with reference to prioritarian-ism,
  • 106
    • 70449088549 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 21. Seminal discussions of the principle and its implications for population policy include Narveson's and Parfit's.
    • See Holtug, supra note 21. Seminal discussions of the principle and its implications for population policy include Narveson's and Parfit's.
    • Holtug1
  • 107
    • 70449135588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 41, at 391-417;
    • See PARFIT, supra note 41, at 391-417;
    • Parfit
  • 108
    • 70449123234 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 57.
    • Narveson, supra note 57.
    • Narveson1
  • 109
    • 70449129382 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note that we have reasoned ourselves to this conclusion independent of whether potential nonexistents have very good or very bad lives in outcomes where they exist. 62
    • Note that we have reasoned ourselves to this conclusion independent of whether potential nonexistents have very good or very bad lives in outcomes where they exist. 62
  • 110
    • 70449088550 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Value, supra note 57.
    • See BROOME, Value, supra note 57.
    • Broome1
  • 111
    • 70449091436 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 41, at 378,447.
    • PARFIT, supra note 41, at 378,447.
    • Parfit
  • 112
    • 70449088548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nils Holtug argues, in a different way, that an individual can be better or worse off existing or not existing, and therefore that non-identity problems do not jeopardize the person-affecting principle.
    • Nils Holtug argues, in a different way, that an individual can be better or worse off existing or not existing, and therefore that non-identity problems do not jeopardize the person-affecting principle.
  • 113
    • 70449102311 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 57;
    • See Holtug, supra note 57;
    • Holtug1
  • 114
    • 70449111113 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 21;
    • Holtug, supra note 21;
    • Holtug1
  • 115
    • 79956667365 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Utility, Priority and Possible People, 11 UTILITAS 16 (1999) [hereinafter Holtug, Utility).
    • Nils Holtug, Utility, Priority and Possible People, 11 UTILITAS 16 (1999) [hereinafter Holtug, Utility).
    • Holtug, N.1
  • 116
    • 70449115162 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To be sure, where an outcome set involves potential nonexistents, one needs to ask: whose extended preferences should we look to in comparing life histories? In the core case, one looks to the extended preferences of the N individuals. What happens outside the core case? I lack space to pursue that question here.
    • To be sure, where an outcome set involves potential nonexistents, one needs to ask: whose extended preferences should we look to in comparing life histories? In the core case, one looks to the extended preferences of the N individuals. What happens outside the core case? I lack space to pursue that question here.
  • 117
    • 70449084299 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Broome denies that a life history can be better or worse for a person than nonexistence. He therefore pursues a different approach to fixing the zero level, which identifies a neutral level for continuing to live, and then defines a neutral life as one which is constantly at this neutral level.
    • John Broome denies that a life history can be better or worse for a person than nonexistence. He therefore pursues a different approach to fixing the zero level, which identifies a neutral level for continuing to live, and then defines a neutral life as one which is constantly at this neutral level.
  • 118
    • 70449119584 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 43, at 66-68,233-35,241-53.
    • See BROOME, supra note 43, at 66-68,233-35,241-53.
    • Broome1
  • 119
    • 0004133667 scopus 로고
    • See Dasgupta's approach is actually somewhat more complicated than simply ranking the outcomes relative to each population. For a clear description and critical discussion, see BROOME, Value, supra note 57;
    • See PARTHA DASGUFTA, AN INQUIRY INTO WELL-BEING AND DESTITUTION 377-97 (1993). Dasgupta's approach is actually somewhat more complicated than simply ranking the outcomes relative to each population. For a clear description and critical discussion, see BROOME, Value, supra note 57;
    • (1993) An Inquiry into Well-being and Destitution , pp. 377-397
    • Dasgufta, P.1
  • 120
    • 70449091438 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 43, at 157-63.
    • BROOME, supra note 43, at 157-63.
    • Broome1
  • 121
    • 70449125626 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 57.
    • See Parsons, supra note 57.
    • Parsons1
  • 122
    • 70449128953 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 57.
    • See Hare, supra note 57.
    • Hare1
  • 123
    • 70449135591 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note that this could happen in two ways: (1) by following the approach I recommend (coupling the person-affecting principle with the position that nonexistence can be better or worse for a person than existence), or (2) by following an impersonal approach.
    • Note that this could happen in two ways: (1) by following the approach I recommend (coupling the person-affecting principle with the position that nonexistence can be better or worse for a person than existence), or (2) by following an impersonal approach.
  • 124
    • 70449089499 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying notes 60-63.
    • See supra text accompanying notes 60-63.
  • 125
    • 70449123219 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 41, at 381-90. There is a substantial literature on the repugnant conclusion and other population-size problems. Two recent, authoritative contributions, which also cite much of the prior literature, are BLACKORBY ET AL., supra note 34, at 129-208;
    • See PARFTT, supra note 41, at 381-90. There is a substantial literature on the repugnant conclusion and other population-size problems. Two recent, authoritative contributions, which also cite much of the prior literature, are BLACKORBY ET AL., supra note 34, at 129-208;
    • Parftt1
  • 126
    • 34347272675 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 43. For discussions with specific reference to prioritarianism, see Campbell Brown, Prioritarianism for Variable Populations, 134 PHIL. STUD. 325 (2007);
    • and BROOME, supra note 43. For discussions with specific reference to prioritarianism, see Campbell Brown, Prioritarianism for Variable Populations, 134 PHIL. STUD. 325 (2007);
    • Broome1
  • 127
    • 70449111116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Utility, supra note 64;
    • Holtug, Utility, supra note 64;
    • Holtug1
  • 128
    • 70449128954 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 21, at 187-223.
    • Brown, supra note 21, at 187-223.
    • Brown1
  • 129
    • 84869671307 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Outcome sets are structured to be responsive to decisionmakers' bounded rationality and thus may well exclude some logically possible outcomes. So, strictly, the worry is that there is some possible outcome set which includes both an x in which everyone lives at level L, and a y in which everyone lives at L*, arbitrarily close to zero-and that the "total" formula, applied to this outcome set, ranks y over x.
    • Outcome sets are structured to be responsive to decisionmakers' bounded rationality and thus may well exclude some logically possible outcomes. So, strictly, the worry is that there is some possible outcome set which includes both an x in which everyone lives at level L, and a y in which everyone lives at L*, arbitrarily close to zero-and that the "total" formula, applied to this outcome set, ranks y over x.
  • 130
    • 70449088539 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • More precisely, the claims in this paragraph as well as the remaining paragraphs in this Section are true if the strictly increasing and concave function used by the prioritarian to trans-N(x) form individual utility-the g(.) function in the formula complex math equations
    • More precisely, the claims in this paragraph as well as the remaining paragraphs in this Section are true if the strictly increasing and concave function used by the prioritarian to trans-N(x) form individual utility-the g(.) function in the formula complex math equations
  • 131
    • 70449132267 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 21, at 210-17
    • See Brown, supra note 21, at 210-17
    • Brown1
  • 132
    • 70449098895 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Utility, supra note 64, at 32-35.
    • Holtug, Utility, supra note 64, at 32-35.
    • Holtug1
  • 133
    • 70449119576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 34, at 129-208.
    • BLACKORBY ET AL., supra note 34, at 129-208.
    • Blackorby1
  • 134
    • 70449123220 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 172.
    • See id. at 172.
  • 135
    • 84869671300 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • discuss separability-across-persons under the heading of various "independence" axioms. See id at 159-60.
    • Blackorby, Bossert, and Donaldson discuss separability-across-persons under the heading of various "independence" axioms. See id at 159-60.
    • Blackorby1    Bossert2    Donaldson3
  • 136
    • 70449135580 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • They generalize this formula by contemplating a range of critical levels.
    • They generalize this formula by contemplating a range of critical levels.
  • 137
    • 84869669541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 219-21, 248-52. They also consider other sorts of variations, for example "restricted" and "number-sensitive" critical-level views.
    • See id. at 219-21, 248-52. They also consider other sorts of variations, for example "restricted" and "number-sensitive" critical-level views.
  • 138
    • 70449097420 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 136-51,165-71. John Broome argues for critical-level utilitarianism.
    • See id. at 136-51,165-71. John Broome argues for critical-level utilitarianism.
  • 139
    • 70449093302 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 43, at 254-64.
    • See BROOME, supra note 43, at 254-64.
    • Broome1
  • 140
    • 70449111114 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, the inequality-aversion parameter in the Atkinsonian SWF.
    • For example, the inequality-aversion parameter in the Atkinsonian SWF.
  • 141
    • 70449128950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 34, at 166 (discussing properties of critical-level generalized utilitarianism, in particular where the critical level is positive).
    • BLACKORBY ET AL., supra note 34, at 166 (discussing properties of critical-level generalized utilitarianism, in particular where the critical level is positive).
    • Blackorby1
  • 142
    • 84869669542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • However, it should be noted that difficulties arise in marrying "total" prioritarianism 1 N with the complex math equations
    • However, it should be noted that difficulties arise in marrying "total" prioritarianism 1 N with the complex math equations
  • 143
    • 70449088547 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If one accepts the argument in this case, then it also surely works where the individuals in x do not exist in y and others take their place.
    • If one accepts the argument in this case, then it also surely works where the individuals in x do not exist in y and others take their place.
  • 144
    • 0000263697 scopus 로고
    • The evaluation of infinite utility streams
    • See
    • See Peter A. Diamond, The Evaluation of Infinite Utility Streams, 33 ECONOMETRICA 170 (1965);
    • (1965) 33 Econometrica , vol.170
    • Diamond, P.A.1
  • 145
    • 0000737101 scopus 로고
    • Stationary ordinal utility and impatience
    • Tjalling C. Koopmans, Stationary Ordinal Utility and Impatience, 28 ECONOMETRICA 287 (1960);
    • (1960) 28 Econometrica , vol.287
    • Koopmans, T.C.1
  • 146
    • 70449132268 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • F.P. Ramsey, A Mathematical Theory of Saving, 38 ECON. J. 543 (1928).
    • F.P. Ramsey, A Mathematical Theory of Saving, 38 ECON. J. 543 (1928).
  • 147
    • 70449106682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The economic theory literature on infinite utility streams is very large. Recent contributions include: Geir Asheim, Tapan Mitra & Bertil Tungodden, A New Equity Condition for Infinite Utility Streams and the Possibility of Being Paretian, in INTERGENERATIONAL EQUITY AND SUSTAINABILITY 55 (John Roemer & Kotaro Suzumura eds., 2007);
    • The economic theory literature on infinite utility streams is very large. Recent contributions include: Geir Asheim, Tapan Mitra & Bertil Tungodden, A New Equity Condition for Infinite Utility Streams and the Possibility of Being Paretian, in INTERGENERATIONAL EQUITY AND SUSTAINABILITY 55 (John Roemer & Kotaro Suzumura eds., 2007);
  • 148
    • 2942754039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Geir B. Asheim & Bertil Tungodden, Resolving Distributional Conflicts Between Generations, 24 ECON. THEORY 221 (2004);
    • Geir B. Asheim & Bertil Tungodden, Resolving Distributional Conflicts Between Generations, 24 ECON. THEORY 221 (2004);
  • 149
    • 70449089502 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Claude d'Aspremont, Formal Welfarism and Intergenerational Equity, in INTERGENERATIONAL EQUITY AND SUSTAINABILITY 113 (John Roemer & Kotaro Suzumura eds., 2007);
    • Claude d'Aspremont, Formal Welfarism and Intergenerational Equity, in INTERGENERATIONAL EQUITY AND SUSTAINABILITY 113 (John Roemer & Kotaro Suzumura eds., 2007);
  • 150
    • 36448942584 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kuntal Banerjee & Tapan Mitra, On the Continuity of Ethical Social Welfare Orders on Infinite Utility Streams, 30 SOC. CHOICE & WELFARE 1 (2008);
    • Kuntal Banerjee & Tapan Mitra, On the Continuity of Ethical Social Welfare Orders on Infinite Utility Streams, 30 SOC. CHOICE & WELFARE 1 (2008);
  • 151
    • 33748883441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kuntal Banerjee, On the Equity-Efficiency Trade off in Aggregating Infinite Utility Streams, 93 ECON. LETTERS 63 (2006);
    • Kuntal Banerjee, On the Equity-Efficiency Trade off in Aggregating Infinite Utility Streams, 93 ECON. LETTERS 63 (2006);
  • 152
    • 33748541115 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kuntal Banerjee, On the Extension of the Utilitarian and Suppes-Sen Social Welfare Relations to Infinite Utility Streams, 27 SOC. CHOICE & WELFARE 327 (2006) [hereinafter Banerjee, On the Extension of the Utilitarian];
    • Kuntal Banerjee, On the Extension of the Utilitarian and Suppes-Sen Social Welfare Relations to Infinite Utility Streams, 27 SOC. CHOICE & WELFARE 327 (2006) [hereinafter Banerjee, On the Extension of the Utilitarian];
  • 153
    • 34047261114 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the impatience implications of paretian social welfare functions
    • Kuntal Banerjee & Tapan Mitra, On the Impatience Implications of Paretian Social Welfare Functions, 43 J. MATH. ECON. 236 (2007);
    • (2007) 43 J. Math. Econ. , vol.236
    • Banerjee, K.1    Mitra, T.2
  • 154
    • 0141922700 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aggregating Infinite Utility Streams with Intergenerational Equity: The Impossibility of Being Paretian, 71 ECONOMETRICA 1557 (2003) [hereinafter Basu & Mitra, Aggregating Infinite Utility Streams];
    • Kaushik Basu & Tapan Mitra, Aggregating Infinite Utility Streams with Intergenerational Equity: The Impossibility of Being Paretian, 71 ECONOMETRICA 1557 (2003) [hereinafter Basu & Mitra, Aggregating Infinite Utility Streams];
    • Basu, K.1    Mitra, T.2
  • 155
    • 70449091431 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Possibility Theorems for Equitably Aggregating Infinite Utility Streams, in INTERGENERATIONAL EQUITY AND SUSTAINABILITY 69 (John Roemer & Kotaro Suzumura eds., 2007);
    • Kaushik Basu & Tapan Mitra, Possibility Theorems for Equitably Aggregating Infinite Utility Streams, in INTERGENERATIONAL EQUITY AND SUSTAINABILITY 69 (John Roemer & Kotaro Suzumura eds., 2007);
    • Basu, K.1    Mitra, T.2
  • 156
    • 33847033436 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Utilitarianism for infinite utility streams: A new welfare criterion and its axiomatic characterization
    • [hereinafter Basu & Mitra, Utilitarianism for Infinite Utility Streams];
    • Kaushik Basu & Tapan Mitra, Utilitarianism for Infinite Utility Streams: A New Welfare Criterion and its Axiomatic Characterization, 133 J. ECON. THEORY 350 (2007) [hereinafter Basu & Mitra, Utilitarianism for Infinite Utility Streams];
    • (2007) 133 J. Econ. Theory , vol.350
    • Basu, K.1    Mitra, T.2
  • 157
    • 34250652552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ordering infinite utility streams
    • Walter Bossert et al., Ordering Infinite Utility Streams, 135 J. ECON. THEORY 579 (2007);
    • (2007) 135 J. Econ. Theory , vol.579
    • Bossert, W.1
  • 158
    • 21344447418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An axiomatic approach to sustainable development
    • Graciela Chichilnisky, An Axiomatic Approach to Sustainable Development, 13 SOC. CHOICE & WELFARE 231 (1996);
    • (1996) 13 Soc. Choice & Welfare , vol.231
    • Chichilnisky, G.1
  • 159
    • 64249163894 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the impossibility of representing infinite utility streams
    • Juan Alfonso Crespo et al., On the Impossibility of Representing Infinite Utility Streams, 40 ECON. THEORY 47 (2009);
    • (2009) 40 Econ. Theory 47
    • Crespo, J.A.1
  • 160
    • 0042429124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intertemporal equity and the extension of the ramsey criterion
    • Marc Fleurbaey & Philippe Michel, Intertemporal Equity and the Extension of the Ramsey Criterion, 39 J. MATH. ECON. 777 (2003);
    • (2003) 39 J. Math. Econ. , vol.777
    • Fleurbaey, M.1    Michel, P.2
  • 161
    • 47849130231 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Continuity and egalitarianism in the evaluation of infinite utility streams
    • Chiaki Hara et al., Continuity and Egalitarianism in the Evaluation of Infinite Utility Streams, 31 SOC. CHOICE & WELFARE 179 (2008);
    • (2008) 31 Soc. Choice & Welfare , vol.179
    • Hara, C.1
  • 162
    • 0039503994 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intertemporal objective functions: Strong pareto versus anonymity
    • Luc Lauwers, Intertemporal Objective Functions: Strong Pareto Versus Anonymity, 35 MATH. SOC. SCI. 37 (1998);
    • (1998) 35 Math. Soc. Sci. , vol.37
    • Lauwers, L.1
  • 163
    • 70349941447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the existence of paretian social welfare quasi-orderings for infinite utility streams with extended anonymity
    • (John Roemer & Kotaro Suzumura eds.
    • Tapan Mitra & Kaushik Basu, On the Existence of Paretian Social Welfare Quasi-Orderings for Infinite Utility Streams with Extended Anonymity, in INTERGENERATIONAL EQUITY AND SUSTAINABILITY 85 (John Roemer & Kotaro Suzumura eds., 2007);
    • (2007) Intergenerational Equity and Sustainability , vol.85
    • Mitra, T.1    Basu, K.2
  • 164
    • 0000314580 scopus 로고
    • Equity among generations
    • Lars-Gunnar Svensson, Equity Among Generations, 48 ECONOMETRICA 1 251 (1980);
    • (1980) 48 Econometrica , vol.1 , Issue.251
    • Svensson, L.-G.1
  • 165
    • 70449097416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intergenerational equity: Immediate impatience, universal indifference, and impossibility
    • John Roemer & Kotaro Suzumura eds.
    • Yongsheng Xu, Pareto Principle and Intergenerational Equity: Immediate Impatience, Universal Indifference, and Impossibility, in INTERGENERATIONAL EQUITY AND SUSTAINABILITY 100 (John Roemer & Kotaro Suzumura eds., 2007);
    • (2007) Intergenerational Equity and Sustainability , vol.100
    • Xu, Y.1    Principle, P.2
  • 166
    • 34250731242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Can intergenerational equity be operationalized?
    • William Zame, Can Intergenerational Equity be Operationalized?, 2 THEORETICAL ECON. 187 (2007);
    • (2007) 2 Theoretical Econ. , vol.187
    • Zame, W.1
  • 167
    • 70449108783 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Claude d'Aspremont & Kuntal Banerjee, Generalized Time-Invariant Overtaking, (Department des sciences 6conomiques de l'Universite' catholique de Louvain, Working Paper No. 2008039, 2008);
    • Geir B. Asheim, Claude d'Aspremont & Kuntal Banerjee, Generalized Time-Invariant Overtaking, (Department des sciences 6conomiques de l'Universite' catholique de Louvain, Working Paper No. 2008039, 2008);
    • Asheim, G.B.1
  • 168
    • 70449107756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the Possibility of Continuous, Paretian, and Egalitarian Evaluation of Infinite Utility Streams (Andrew Young Sch. of Policy Studies Research Paper Series No. 07-12,2007), available at
    • Chiaki Hara, Kotaro Suzumura & Tomoichi Shinotsuka, On the Possibility of Continuous, Paretian, and Egalitarian Evaluation of Infinite Utility Streams (Andrew Young Sch. of Policy Studies Research Paper Series No. 07-12,2007), available at
    • Hara, C.1    Suzumura, K.2    Shinotsuka, T.3
  • 169
    • 10844235016 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is also a smaller philosophical literature of infinity problems. This literature is more general than the economic theory literature just cited, because it discusses the problem of ranking worlds with an infinite number of "locations" of utility-whether or not those are organized in the form of a "stream" that begins with an initial period and never ends. See, e.g., Donniell Fishkind et al., New Inconsistencies in Infinite Utilitarianism: Is Every World Good, Bad or Neutral?, 80 AUSTRALASIAN J. PHIL. 178 (2002);
    • There is also a smaller philosophical literature of infinity problems. This literature is more general than the economic theory literature just cited, because it discusses the problem of ranking worlds with an infinite number of "locations" of utility-whether or not those are organized in the form of a "stream" that begins with an initial period and never ends. See, e.g., Donniell Fishkind et al., New Inconsistencies in Infinite Utilitarianism: Is Every World Good, Bad or Neutral?, 80 AUSTRALASIAN J. PHIL. 178 (2002);
  • 170
    • 10844280599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Infinite utilitarianism: More is always better
    • Luc Lauwers & Peter Vallentyne, Infinite Utilitarianism: More Is Always Better, 20 ECON. & PHIL. 307 (2004);
    • (2004) 20 Econ. & Phil. , vol.307
    • Lauwers, L.1    Vallentyne, P.2
  • 171
    • 10844294416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Transcending the infinite utility debate
    • Tim Mulgan, Transcending the Infinite Utility Debate, 80 AUSTRALASIAN J. PHIL. 164 (2002);
    • (2002) 80 Australasian J. Phil. , vol.164
    • Mulgan, T.1
  • 172
    • 0008188250 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Infinite value and finitely additive value theory
    • Peter Vallentyne & Shelly Kagan, Infinite Value and Finitely Additive Value Theory, 94 J. PHIL. 5 (1997).
    • (1997) 94 J. Phil. , vol.5
    • Vallentyne, P.1    Kagan, S.2
  • 173
    • 70449095516 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Formally, the weak anonymity axiom can be articulated as follows. Consider the set T = (1,2,...), which denotes the periods in a utility stream. Function p is a permutation if it is a bijection (one-to-one, onto mapping) from T onto itself. It is a finite permutation if all but a finite number of elements of T ate mapped onto themselves. complex math equations.
    • Formally, the weak anonymity axiom can be articulated as follows. Consider the set T = (1,2,...), which denotes the periods in a utility stream. Function p is a permutation if it is a bijection (one-to-one, onto mapping) from T onto itself. It is a finite permutation if all but a finite number of elements of T ate mapped onto themselves. complex math equations.
  • 174
    • 70449129377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 83, at 581;
    • Bossert et al., supra note 83, at 581;
    • Bossert1
  • 175
    • 70449097415 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 83, at 782;
    • Fleurbaey & Michel, supra note 83, at 782;
    • Fleurbaey1    Michel2
  • 176
    • 70449132269 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 83, at 1252. The strong anonymity axiom requires indifference to any permutation, even one that is not finite.
    • Svensson, supra note 83, at 1252. The strong anonymity axiom requires indifference to any permutation, even one that is not finite.
    • Svensson1
  • 177
    • 70449119578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., supra note 83, at 782-83. For a full discussion of possible anonymity requirements in the infinity context, and their consistency with various forms of the Pareto principle, see id.
    • See, e.g., Fleurbaey & Michel, supra note 83, at 782-83. For a full discussion of possible anonymity requirements in the infinity context, and their consistency with various forms of the Pareto principle, see id.
    • Fleurbaey1    Michel2
  • 178
    • 70449132270 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 82.
    • See Diamond, supra note 82.
    • Diamond1
  • 179
    • 70449135582 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Throughout the discussion of infinite utility streams, this is what I mean by the principle of Pareto superiority.
    • Throughout the discussion of infinite utility streams, this is what I mean by the principle of Pareto superiority.
  • 180
    • 70449132271 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Aggregating Infinite Utility Streams, supra note 83.
    • See Basu & Mitra, Aggregating Infinite Utility Streams, supra note 83.
    • Basu1    Mitra2
  • 181
    • 70449106683 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Some scholars in the infinite-utility-stream literature have investigated the possibility of relaxing completeness.
    • Some scholars in the infinite-utility-stream literature have investigated the possibility of relaxing completeness.
  • 182
    • 70449093308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Asheim & Tungodden, supra note 83;
    • See, e.g., Asheim & Tungodden, supra note 83;
  • 183
    • 70449115155 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Utilitarianism for Infinite Utility Streams, supra note 83;
    • Basu & Mitra, Utilitarianism for Infinite Utility Streams, supra note 83;
    • Basu1    Mitra2
  • 184
    • 70449106692 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bossert et al., supra note 83;
    • Bossert et al., supra note 83;
  • 185
    • 70449093310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hara et al., supra note 83.
    • Hara et al., supra note 83.
  • 186
    • 70449111112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ADLER, WELL-BEING AND EQUITY, supra note 1;
    • See ADLER, WELL-BEING AND EQUITY, supra note 1;
  • 187
    • 70449107761 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also ADLER & POSNER, supra note 18, at 161-62 (arguing that outcomes may be incomparable with respect to overall well-being).
    • See also ADLER & POSNER, supra note 18, at 161-62 (arguing that outcomes may be incomparable with respect to overall well-being).
  • 188
    • 70449125624 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Svensson, supra note 83;
    • See Svensson, supra note 83;
  • 189
    • 70449088545 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Bossert et al., supra note 83, at 579-80.
    • See also Bossert et al., supra note 83, at 579-80.
  • 190
    • 84963090885 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The overtaking criterion originates with von Weizsacker & Atsumi. See Hiroshi Atsumi, Neoclassical Growth and the Efficient Program of Capital Accumulation, 32 REV. ECON. STUD. 127 (1965);
    • The overtaking criterion originates with von Weizsacker & Atsumi. See Hiroshi Atsumi, Neoclassical Growth and the Efficient Program of Capital Accumulation, 32 REV. ECON. STUD. 127 (1965);
  • 191
    • 0002224201 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Carl Christian von Weizsacker, Existence of Optimal Programs of Accumulation for an Infinite Time Horizon, 32 REV. ECON. STUD. 85 (1965). For recent discussions, see Asheim & Tungodden, supra note 83, at 226-28;
    • Carl Christian von Weizsacker, Existence of Optimal Programs of Accumulation for an Infinite Time Horizon, 32 REV. ECON. STUD. 85 (1965). For recent discussions, see Asheim & Tungodden, supra note 83, at 226-28;
  • 192
    • 70449135587 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Banerjee, On the Extension of the Utilitarian, supra note 83, at 333-35;
    • Banerjee, On the Extension of the Utilitarian, supra note 83, at 333-35;
  • 193
    • 70449135585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Basu & Mitra, Utilitarianism for Infinite Utility Streams, supra note 83, at 356-63;
    • Basu & Mitra, Utilitarianism for Infinite Utility Streams, supra note 83, at 356-63;
  • 194
    • 70449123231 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 83, at 786-87;
    • Fleurbaey & Michel, supra note 83, at 786-87;
    • Fleurbaey1    Michel2
  • 195
    • 84869674925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 83, at 1253. For a variation on the overtaking criterion, see Asheim et al., supra note 83 ("generalized time-invariant overtaking").
    • Svensson, supra note 83, at 1253. For a variation on the overtaking criterion, see Asheim et al., supra note 83 ("generalized time-invariant overtaking").
    • Svensson1
  • 197
    • 70449107760 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Asheim & Tungodden, supra note 83, at 229. Asheim and Tungod-den provide a simpler example of the conflict. The example I provide here, however, involves a case in which one stream is a permutation of another, yet is strictly better in all but a single time period.
    • See Asheim & Tungodden, supra note 83, at 229. Asheim and Tungod-den provide a simpler example of the conflict. The example I provide here, however, involves a case in which one stream is a permutation of another, yet is strictly better in all but a single time period.
  • 198
    • 70449123230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • However, I will assume that an individual is born on the very same date in all outcomes where she exists. Although this assumption is not entailed by the nature of personal identity
    • However, I will assume that an individual is born on the very same date in all outcomes where she exists. Although this assumption is not entailed by the nature of personal identity,
  • 199
    • 70449105640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see supra text accompanying note 44, relaxing the assumption creates difficulties for the priori-tarian overtaking criterion as presented here. Note that, if some individual is born later in outcome x than outcome y, outcome x might be Pareto superior to y and yet the sum N(x,T) NW > V1 g(u(x)) nught be less than the sum V1 g(u (v)), for values of T in between the in-(=1 /=i dividual's birth date in y and x. This might yield inconsistencies between the prioritarian overtaking criterion and the principle of Pareto superiority if an infinite number of individuals have different birth dates in x and y. Similar difficulties can arise with the Pareto indifference principle. How it might be possible to relax the assumption that an individual is born on the very same date in all outcomes where she exists is a question I leave for another day.
    • see supra text accompanying note 44, relaxing the assumption creates difficulties for the priori-tarian overtaking criterion as presented here. Note that, if some individual is born later in outcome x than outcome y, outcome x might be Pareto superior to y and yet the sum N(x,T) NW > V1 g(u(x)) nught be less than the sum V1 g(u (v)), for values of T in between the in-(=1 /=i dividual's birth date in y and x. This might yield inconsistencies between the prioritarian overtaking criterion and the principle of Pareto superiority if an infinite number of individuals have different birth dates in x and y. Similar difficulties can arise with the Pareto indifference principle. How it might be possible to relax the assumption that an individual is born on the very same date in all outcomes where she exists is a question I leave for another day.
  • 200
    • 70449115161 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part I.
    • See supra Part I.
  • 201
    • 70449111191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For purposes of applying these criteria to an outcome set with potential nonexistents, who exist in some but not all outcomes, such individuals should be assigned a utility of zero in the outcomes where they do not exist. Then Pareto indifference requires that outcome x be ranked as equally good as y if (1) every individual who exists in both outcomes is equally well off in both, and (2) every individual who exists in one but not both outcomes has a utility of zero in the outcome where she exists. Pareto superiority requires that outcome x be ranked as better than outcome y if the utility assigned each individual in x is at least as great as the utility assigned her in y, and there are some individuals assigned strictly greater utility-where, by "the utility assigned to each individual," I mean that individual's utility if she exists, or zero if she does not. Pigou-Dalton means that if x and y are identical, except that ut(y) = U,(AT)+AU, ufy) = ut(x)-Au, ut(x) > ufy) > u,(y) > ut(x), where these utilities are the utilities assigned to individuals i and / in outcomes x and y, then y is better than x. Separability means that the ranking of x and y does not depend on which utilities are assigned to individuals who are assigned the same utilities in both outcomes.
  • 202
    • 70449119579 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • By these terms, in this context, I mean the following. Given an outcome set, there is a set of all individuals who exist in at least one of the outcomes. A permutation is a bijection (one-to-one, onto mapping) from this set onto itself. A finite permutation is a permutation with the property that only a finite number of individuals are mapped onto different individuals. An infinite permutation is a permutation which is not finite. The utilities assigned individuals in outcome y are a permutation of the utilities assigned individuals in outcome x if there is some permutation p such that each individual's utility in x is the utility of individual p(t) in y. If there exists a finite such p, then y is a finite permutation of x. Less formally, y is a finite permutation of x if there is some finite subset of all the individuals (those who exist in at least one outcome), such that the utilities assigned to those individuals in y are a rearrangement of the utilities assigned to them in x, and all individuals not in the subset are assigned the very same utilities in y and x.
  • 203
    • 70449119580 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part I.
    • See supra Part I.
  • 204
    • 70449111190 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part II.
    • See supra Part II.
  • 205
    • 70449132275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part III.A.
    • See supra Part III.A.
  • 206
    • 70449098901 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part III.B.
    • See supra Part III.B.
  • 207
    • 70449093309 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part III.C.
    • See supra Part III.C.
  • 208
    • 70449084298 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying notes 46-56.
    • See supra text accompanying notes 46-56.
  • 209
    • 70449132276 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying notes 42-45.
    • See supra text accompanying notes 42-45.
  • 210
    • 70449115160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying notes 64-67,80-81.
    • See supra text accompanying notes 64-67,80-81.
  • 211
    • 70449089510 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra text accompanying notes 96-97.
    • See supra text accompanying notes 96-97.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.