-
1
-
-
17444372789
-
Scientific research is a moral duty
-
See
-
See J. Harris, "Scientific Research Is a Moral Duty, "Journal of Medical Ethics 31(2005):242-48.
-
(2005)
Journal of Medical Ethics
, vol.31
, pp. 242-248
-
-
Harris, J.1
-
2
-
-
0021482776
-
Is there a duty to serve as a subject in biomedical research?
-
For a discussion of the history, see
-
For a discussion of the history, see A. L. Caplan, "Is There a Duty to Serve as a Subject in Biomedical Research? "IRB: A Review of Human Subjects Research 6, no. 5(1984):1-5.
-
(1984)
IRB: A Review of Human Subjects Research
, vol.6
, Issue.5
, pp. 1-5
-
-
Caplan, A.L.1
-
3
-
-
0023319217
-
False hopes and best data: Consent to research and the therapeutic misconception
-
P. S. Appelbaum et al., "False Hopes and Best Data: Consent to Research and the Therapeutic Misconception, "Hastings Center Report 12, no. 2(1987):20-24.
-
(1987)
Hastings Center Report
, vol.12
, Issue.2
, pp. 20-24
-
-
Appelbaum, P.S.1
-
4
-
-
0041706886
-
Misunderstanding in clinical research: Distinguishing therapeutic misconception, therapeutic misestimation, and therapeutic optimism, "
-
See also
-
See also S. Horng and C. Grady, "Misunderstanding in Clinical Research: Distinguishing Therapeutic Misconception, Therapeutic Misestimation, and Therapeutic Optimism, "" IRB: Ethics & Human Research 25, no. 2(2003):11-16.
-
(2003)
IRB: Ethics & Human Research
, vol.25
, Issue.2
, pp. 11-16
-
-
Horng, S.1
Grady, C.2
-
5
-
-
84921950401
-
-
See, Oxford, U. K.: Oxford University Press
-
See C. Swanton, Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic View (Oxford, U. K.: Oxford University Press, 2003), 128-60.
-
(2003)
Virtue Ethics: A Pluralistic View
, pp. 128-160
-
-
Swanton, C.1
-
6
-
-
37149057137
-
-
That altruistic behavior requires the presence of this kind of motive is consistent with how the term is used in ordinary English. It also fits well with how the term is used by moral philosophers. There are other characterizations of altruism, however. In the biological literature, altruism is sometimes construed in terms of "fitness-sacrificing" behavior-that is, acting in a manner that sets back one's own reproductive fitness for the sake of advancing the reproductive fitness of another. Altruism is also sometimes identified simply with helpful self-sacrificing behavior. For a critical discussion of these alternative characterizations of altruism, see, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press
-
That altruistic behavior requires the presence of this kind of motive is consistent with how the term is used in ordinary English. It also fits well with how the term is used by moral philosophers. There are other characterizations of altruism, however. In the biological literature, altruism is sometimes construed in terms of "fitness-sacrificing" behavior-that is, acting in a manner that sets back one's own reproductive fitness for the sake of advancing the reproductive fitness of another. Altruism is also sometimes identified simply with helpful self-sacrificing behavior. For a critical discussion of these alternative characterizations of altruism, see R. Joyce, The Evolution of Morality (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2007), 13-19.
-
(2007)
The Evolution of Morality
, pp. 13-19
-
-
Joyce, R.1
-
7
-
-
38849137570
-
Altruism among participants in cancer clinical trials
-
abstract 2103
-
S. Joffe et al., "Altruism among Participants in Cancer Clinical Trials, "Proceedings of the American Society of Clinical Oncology 22(2003):523, abstract 2103.
-
(2003)
Proceedings of the American Society of Clinical Oncology
, vol.22
, pp. 523
-
-
Joffe, S.1
-
8
-
-
84921315955
-
-
See, Oxford, U. K.: Oxford University Press
-
See A. Mele, Motivation and Agency (Oxford, U. K.: Oxford University Press, 2003), 22-23.
-
(2003)
Motivation and Agency
, pp. 22-23
-
-
Mele, A.1
-
9
-
-
33746013190
-
Rethinking risk-benefit assessment for phase i cancer trials
-
See
-
See S. Joffe and F. G. Miller, "Rethinking Risk-Benefit Assessment for Phase I Cancer Trials, "Journal of Clinical Oncology 24, no. 19(2006):2987-90;
-
(2006)
Journal of Clinical Oncology
, vol.24
, Issue.19
, pp. 2987-2990
-
-
Joffe, S.1
Miller, F.G.2
-
10
-
-
0003424636
-
-
see also, second ed. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press
-
see also R. J. Levine, Ethics and Regulation of Clinical Research, second ed. (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1988), 8-10.
-
(1988)
Ethics and Regulation of Clinical Research
, pp. 8-10
-
-
Levine, R.J.1
-
11
-
-
0034573353
-
Defining and describing benefit appropriately in clinical trials
-
Determining whether a clinical trial offers participants a reasonable expectation of direct therapeutic benefit is far from an easy or straightforward matter. For an excellent discussion of some of the difficulties and uncertainties involved in making these assessments, see
-
Determining whether a clinical trial offers participants a reasonable expectation of direct therapeutic benefit is far from an easy or straightforward matter. For an excellent discussion of some of the difficulties and uncertainties involved in making these assessments, see N. M. P. King, "Defining and Describing Benefit Appropriately in Clinical Trials, "Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 28 (2000), 332-43.
-
(2000)
Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics
, vol.28
, pp. 332-343
-
-
King, N.M.P.1
-
12
-
-
0346756193
-
Ethical issues in research with healthy volunteers: Risk-benefit assessment
-
F. G. Miller, "Ethical Issues in Research with Healthy Volunteers: Risk-Benefit Assessment, "Clinical Pharmacology and Therapeutics 74, no. 6(2003):513-15.
-
(2003)
Clinical Pharmacology and Therapeutics
, vol.74
, Issue.6
, pp. 513-515
-
-
Miller, F.G.1
-
13
-
-
0041920900
-
Ethics of phase i oncology studies: Reexamining the arguments and data
-
While it is widely thought that participation in early-phase oncology trials offers participants no reasonable expectation of direct therapeutic benefit, there is some recent debate on the matter
-
While it is widely thought that participation in early-phase oncology trials offers participants no reasonable expectation of direct therapeutic benefit, there is some recent debate on the matter. Compare M. Agrawal and E. Emanuel, "Ethics of Phase I Oncology Studies: Reexamining the Arguments and Data, "Journal of the American Medical Association 290(2003):1075-82;
-
(2003)
Journal of the American Medical Association
, vol.290
, pp. 1075-1082
-
-
Agrawal, C.M.1
Emanuel, E.2
-
16
-
-
70450278607
-
-
45 CFR 46. 111a (2).
-
CFR
, vol.45-46
, Issue.2
-
-
-
17
-
-
0004260399
-
-
We should allow for the unlikely possibility that a person might give valid, rational consent to participate in a clinical trial that offers no reasonable expectation of direct therapeutic benefit, even if she has no altruistic motive for doing so. For all we know, she might have idiosyncratic preferences. On this matter, see, New York: Oxford University Press, on the distinction between a rational and a "reasonable" decision. Be this as it may, I shall not discuss this kind of case further
-
We should allow for the unlikely possibility that a person might give valid, rational consent to participate in a clinical trial that offers no reasonable expectation of direct therapeutic benefit, even if she has no altruistic motive for doing so. For all we know, she might have idiosyncratic preferences. (On this matter, see J. Feinberg, Harm to Self [New York: Oxford University Press, 1986], 106-113, on the distinction between a rational and a "reasonable" decision.) Be this as it may, I shall not discuss this kind of case further.
-
(1986)
Harm to Self
, pp. 106-113
-
-
Feinberg, J.1
-
18
-
-
0141797654
-
A critique of clinical equipoise: Therapeutic misconception in the ethics of clinical trials
-
F. G. Miller and H. Brody, "A Critique of Clinical Equipoise: Therapeutic Misconception in the Ethics of Clinical Trials, "Hastings Center Report 33, no. 3(2003):19-28.
-
(2003)
Hastings Center Report
, vol.33
, Issue.3
, pp. 19-28
-
-
Miller, F.G.1
Brody, H.2
-
19
-
-
0004157494
-
-
See, New York: Oxford University Press, "exploitation of a person is normally a way of using someone for one's own ends, which is somehow wrongful or blameworthy, whether it wrongs the other person or not."
-
See J. Feinberg, Harmless Wrongdoing (New York: Oxford University Press, 1988), 177: "exploitation of a person is normally a way of using someone for one's own ends, which is somehow wrongful or blameworthy, whether it wrongs the other person or not."
-
(1988)
Harmless Wrongdoing
, pp. 177
-
-
Feinberg, J.1
-
21
-
-
0003424636
-
-
A known level of risk would include both an understanding of the likelihood probability that a harm will result and an understanding of its magnitude. See
-
A known level of risk would include both an understanding of the likelihood (probability) that a harm will result and an understanding of its magnitude. See Levine, Ethics and the Regulation of Clinical Research, 37.
-
Ethics and the Regulation of Clinical Research
, pp. 37
-
-
Levine1
-
22
-
-
70450260369
-
-
For the purpose of the thought experiment, we can assume that the trial would be scientifically valid whether it was conducted at one or both sites-even though there would be advantages to conducting the trial at both sites
-
For the purpose of the thought experiment, we can assume that the trial would be scientifically valid whether it was conducted at one or both sites-even though there would be advantages to conducting the trial at both sites.
-
-
-
-
23
-
-
34250622864
-
Facing up to paternalism in research ethics
-
at 32
-
F. G. Miller and A. Wertheimer, "Facing Up to Paternalism in Research Ethics, "Hastings Center Report 37, no. 3(2007):24-34, at 32.
-
(2007)
Hastings Center Report
, vol.37
, Issue.3
, pp. 24-34
-
-
Miller, F.G.1
Wertheimer, A.2
-
24
-
-
0003545165
-
-
For examples of researchers experimenting on themselves, see, Amsterdam, the Netherlands: North-Holland Publishing Company
-
For examples of researchers experimenting on themselves, see C. Fried, Medical Experimentation: Personal Integrity and Social Policy (Amsterdam, the Netherlands: North-Holland Publishing Company, 1974), 167-68.
-
(1974)
Medical Experimentation: Personal Integrity and Social Policy
, pp. 167-168
-
-
Fried, C.1
-
25
-
-
0003740191
-
-
Oxford, U. K.: Clarendon Press
-
D. Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford, U. K.: Clarendon Press, 1984).
-
(1984)
Reasons and Persons
-
-
Parfit, D.1
-
26
-
-
0003445959
-
-
See also, Oxford, U. K.: Clarendon Press
-
See also J. Griffin, Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement, and Moral Importance (Oxford, U. K.: Clarendon Press, 1986)
-
(1986)
Well-Being: its Meaning, Measurement, and Moral Importance
-
-
Griffin, J.1
-
31
-
-
70450251871
-
-
Parfit uses the example to cast doubt on the desire-fulfillment approach to wellbeing
-
Parfit uses the example to cast doubt on the desire-fulfillment approach to wellbeing.
-
-
-
-
32
-
-
85086611042
-
-
Charles Fried pressed this point in his early book on research ethics. The researcher-participant relationship becomes less ethically problematic if it is" a joint venture" rather than a transaction in which one party uses the other to advance his or her purposes. See
-
Charles Fried pressed this point in his early book on research ethics. The researcher-participant relationship becomes less ethically problematic if it is"a joint venture" rather than a transaction in which one party uses the other to advance his or her purposes. See Medical Experimentation: Personal Integrity and Social Policy, 166-72.
-
Medical Experimentation: Personal Integrity and Social Policy
, pp. 166-172
-
-
-
33
-
-
70450263190
-
-
Wertheimer makes a similar point in discussing exploitation and surrogacy contracts. He notes that commercial surrogacy gives rise to concerns about exploitation since it is a transaction between the involved parties. However, if a woman altruistically gives her child to another party, then it is not a transaction. Norms of fair benefit do not apply, and so altruistic, noncommercial surrogacy does not invite the charge of exploitation. See, note
-
Wertheimer makes a similar point in discussing exploitation and surrogacy contracts. He notes that commercial surrogacy gives rise to concerns about exploitation since it is a transaction between the involved parties. However, if a woman altruistically gives her child to another party, then it is not a transaction. Norms of fair benefit do not apply, and so altruistic, noncommercial surrogacy does not invite the charge of exploitation. See Wertheimer, Exploitation, 250, note 8.
-
Exploitation
, vol.250
, pp. 8
-
-
Wertheimer1
-
35
-
-
0348078979
-
Evidence for altruism: The lady is still waiting
-
See
-
See R. M. Sorrentino, "Evidence for Altruism: The Lady Is Still Waiting, "Psychological Inquiry 2, no. 2(1991):147-50.
-
(1991)
Psychological Inquiry
, vol.2
, Issue.2
, pp. 147-150
-
-
Sorrentino, R.M.1
-
36
-
-
69249096065
-
Why altruism, even though it exists, cannot be demonstrated by social psychological experiments
-
L. Wallach and M. A. Wallach, "Why Altruism, Even Though it Exists, Cannot Be Demonstrated by Social Psychological Experiments, "Psychological Inquiry 2, no. 2(1991):153-55.
-
(1991)
Psychological Inquiry
, vol.2
, Issue.2
, pp. 153-155
-
-
Wallach, L.1
Wallach, M.A.2
-
37
-
-
0003548018
-
-
See, second ed. Oxford, U. K.: Oxford University Press, It is also possible that, at least with respect to some possible trials- such as those that study social psychological phenomena-limiting recruitment to altruistic patients would inject bias into the study sample
-
See J. Berg et al., Informed Consent: Legal Theory and Clinical Practice, second ed. (Oxford, U. K.: Oxford University Press, 2001), 297-98. It is also possible that, at least with respect to some possible trials- such as those that study social psychological phenomena-limiting recruitment to altruistic patients would inject bias into the study sample.
-
(2001)
Informed Consent: Legal Theory and Clinical Practice
, pp. 297-298
-
-
Berg, J.1
-
40
-
-
31544473150
-
A critique of clinical equipoise, "and l. A. Jansen," a closer look at the bad deal trial: Beyond clinical equipoise, "
-
See
-
See Miller and Brody, "A Critique of Clinical Equipoise, "and L. A. Jansen," A Closer Look at the Bad Deal Trial: Beyond Clinical Equipoise, "" Hastings Center Report 35, no. 5(2005):29-36.
-
(2005)
Hastings Center Report
, vol.35
, Issue.5
, pp. 29-36
-
-
Miller1
Brody2
-
41
-
-
70450269191
-
-
Miller and Wertheimer appreciate the force of this question. They suggest that high-risk research might be ruled out in order to safeguard public confidence and public support for clinical research. This is a sensible concern, but as Miller and Wertheimer acknowledge, it rests on a calculation of benefits and costs. And it is not obvious how this calculation would come out. See
-
Miller and Wertheimer appreciate the force of this question. They suggest that high-risk research might be ruled out in order to safeguard public confidence and public support for clinical research. This is a sensible concern, but as Miller and Wertheimer acknowledge, it rests on a calculation of benefits and costs. And it is not obvious how this calculation would come out. See "Facing Up to Paternalism in Research Ethics, "32-33.
-
Facing Up to Paternalism in Research Ethics
, pp. 32-33
-
-
-
42
-
-
84972017713
-
Selflessness and loss of self
-
For a range of examples that involve self-abnegation or "loss of self, "see
-
For a range of examples that involve self-abnegation or "loss of self, "see J. Hampton, "Selflessness and Loss of Self, "Social Philosophy and Policy 10, no. 1(1993):135-65.
-
(1993)
Social Philosophy and Policy
, vol.10
, Issue.1
, pp. 135-165
-
-
Hampton, J.1
-
44
-
-
10844289838
-
Paternalism, unconscionability doctrine, and accommodation
-
S. V. Shiffrin makes a similar point in her discussion of the "unconscionability doctrine" in the law. Shiffrin argues that if a judge refuses to enforce an unconscionable contract that was entered into voluntarily by all the parties, then it does not follow that the judge behaves paternalistically. Rather, the judge's concern may be "to avoid complicity with exploitation. See
-
S. V. Shiffrin makes a similar point in her discussion of the "unconscionability doctrine" in the law. Shiffrin argues that if a judge refuses to enforce an unconscionable contract that was entered into voluntarily by all the parties, then it does not follow that the judge behaves paternalistically. Rather, the judge's concern may be "to avoid complicity with exploitation. "See S. V. Shiffrin, "Paternalism, Unconscionability Doctrine, and Accommodation, "Philosophy and Public Affairs 29, no. 3(2000):230.
-
(2000)
Philosophy and Public Affairs
, vol.29
, Issue.3
, pp. 230
-
-
Shiffrin, S.V.1
|