메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 58, Issue 1, 2004, Pages 81-116

Adam Smith's reconstruction of practical reason

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 6344256829     PISSN: 00346632     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (40)

References (196)
  • 1
    • 6344227814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Henceforth, "TMS." Smith first published this work in 1759 and reedited it five times before his death. In the sixth edition (1790) he incorporates a new chapter and develops some topics only alluded to in previous versions. I believe that this last revision contains the most solid evidence for including him in the "practical reason" tradition, in contrast to the sentimentalist school of his time. My references to the book are taken from this last edition (Theory of Moral Sentiments, ed. David Daiches Raphael and Alec Lawrence Macfie [Indianapolis: Liberty Classics, 1976]). Numerical references are to parts, sections, chapters, and, following a colon, paragraphs, as given in this edition. For example, "TMS 2.1.3:4" refers to part 2, section 1, chapter 3, paragraph 4.
    • TMS
  • 2
    • 0004110659 scopus 로고
    • ed. David Daiches Raphael and Alec Lawrence Macfie [Indianapolis: Liberty Classics])
    • Henceforth, "TMS." Smith first published this work in 1759 and reedited it five times before his death. In the sixth edition (1790) he incorporates a new chapter and develops some topics only alluded to in previous versions. I believe that this last revision contains the most solid evidence for including him in the "practical reason" tradition, in contrast to the sentimentalist school of his time. My references to the book are taken from this last edition (Theory of Moral Sentiments, ed. David Daiches Raphael and Alec Lawrence Macfie [Indianapolis: Liberty Classics, 1976]). Numerical references are to parts, sections, chapters, and, following a colon, paragraphs, as given in this edition. For example, "TMS 2.1.3:4" refers to part 2, section 1, chapter 3, paragraph 4.
    • (1976) Theory of Moral Sentiments
  • 3
    • 6344247417 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2.1.3:4, refers to part 2, section 1, chapter 3, paragraph 4
    • Henceforth, "TMS." Smith first published this work in 1759 and reedited it five times before his death. In the sixth edition (1790) he incorporates a new chapter and develops some topics only alluded to in previous versions. I believe that this last revision contains the most solid evidence for including him in the "practical reason" tradition, in contrast to the sentimentalist school of his time. My references to the book are taken from this last edition (Theory of Moral Sentiments, ed. David Daiches Raphael and Alec Lawrence Macfie [Indianapolis: Liberty Classics, 1976]). Numerical references are to parts, sections, chapters, and, following a colon, paragraphs, as given in this edition. For example, "TMS 2.1.3:4" refers to part 2, section 1, chapter 3, paragraph 4.
    • TMS
  • 4
    • 6344231129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 7.3.3
    • See TMS 7.3.3.
    • TMS
  • 5
    • 6344236724 scopus 로고
    • Adam Smith and the infection of David Hume's society
    • Among others, see David Daiches Raphael, "Adam Smith and the Infection of David Hume's Society," Journal of the History of Ideas 30 (1969); Stephen Darwall, "Sympathetic Liberalism: Recent Work on Adam Smith," Philosophy and Public Affairs 28 (1999); Richard Kleer, "Final Causes in Adam Smith's Theory of Moral Sentiments," Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (1995); and James Otteson, Adam Smith's Marketplace of Life (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2002).
    • (1969) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.30
    • Raphael, D.D.1
  • 6
    • 0002216554 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sympathetic liberalism: Recent work on Adam Smith
    • Among others, see David Daiches Raphael, "Adam Smith and the Infection of David Hume's Society," Journal of the History of Ideas 30 (1969); Stephen Darwall, "Sympathetic Liberalism: Recent Work on Adam Smith," Philosophy and Public Affairs 28 (1999); Richard Kleer, "Final Causes in Adam Smith's Theory of Moral Sentiments," Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (1995); and James Otteson, Adam Smith's Marketplace of Life (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2002).
    • (1999) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.28
    • Darwall, S.1
  • 7
    • 0042314200 scopus 로고
    • Final causes in Adam Smith's theory of moral sentiments
    • Among others, see David Daiches Raphael, "Adam Smith and the Infection of David Hume's Society," Journal of the History of Ideas 30 (1969); Stephen Darwall, "Sympathetic Liberalism: Recent Work on Adam Smith," Philosophy and Public Affairs 28 (1999); Richard Kleer, "Final Causes in Adam Smith's Theory of Moral Sentiments," Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (1995); and James Otteson, Adam Smith's Marketplace of Life (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2002).
    • (1995) Journal of the History of Philosophy , vol.33
    • Kleer, R.1
  • 8
    • 6344245597 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Among others, see David Daiches Raphael, "Adam Smith and the Infection of David Hume's Society," Journal of the History of Ideas 30 (1969); Stephen Darwall, "Sympathetic Liberalism: Recent Work on Adam Smith," Philosophy and Public Affairs 28 (1999); Richard Kleer, "Final Causes in Adam Smith's Theory of Moral Sentiments," Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (1995); and James Otteson, Adam Smith's Marketplace of Life (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2002).
    • (2002) Adam Smith's Marketplace of Life
    • Otteson, J.1
  • 9
    • 6344242810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Nonetheless, as will become clearer from what follows, I do not believe that Adam Smith was an Aristotelian. Rather, following Gloria Vivenza's classification of Smith's influences as direct/indirect and conscious/ unconscious (Adam Smith and the Classics [New York: Oxford University Press, 2001], 2), I believe Aristotle's influence was indirect and unconscious. My analysis will only focus on this neglected issue, leaving aside the discussion of other possible, and no less important, influences in this theory (Stoic, Epicurean, Humean, and so forth).
    • (2001) Adam Smith and the Classics , pp. 2
  • 10
    • 6344245603 scopus 로고
    • Aristotle and Adam Smith on justice: Cooperation between ancients and moderns?
    • Laurence Berns, "Aristotle and Adam Smith on Justice: Cooperation between Ancients and Moderns?" Review of Metaphysics 48 (1994): 71-90; Samuel Fleischacker, A Third Concept of Liberty: Judgment and Freedom in Kant and Adam Smith (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999); Charles Griswold, Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1999); and Gloria Vivenza in Adam Smith and the Classics, respectively.
    • (1994) Review of Metaphysics , vol.48 , pp. 71-90
    • Berns, L.1
  • 11
    • 6344259915 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • Laurence Berns, "Aristotle and Adam Smith on Justice: Cooperation between Ancients and Moderns?" Review of Metaphysics 48 (1994): 71-90; Samuel Fleischacker, A Third Concept of Liberty: Judgment and Freedom in Kant and Adam Smith (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999); Charles Griswold, Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1999); and Gloria Vivenza in Adam Smith and the Classics, respectively.
    • (1999) A Third Concept of Liberty: Judgment and Freedom in Kant and Adam Smith
    • Fleischacker, S.1
  • 12
    • 0004211602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Laurence Berns, "Aristotle and Adam Smith on Justice: Cooperation between Ancients and Moderns?" Review of Metaphysics 48 (1994): 71-90; Samuel Fleischacker, A Third Concept of Liberty: Judgment and Freedom in Kant and Adam Smith (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999); Charles Griswold, Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1999); and Gloria Vivenza in Adam Smith and the Classics, respectively.
    • (1999) Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment
    • Griswold, C.1
  • 13
    • 6344242810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • respectively
    • Laurence Berns, "Aristotle and Adam Smith on Justice: Cooperation between Ancients and Moderns?" Review of Metaphysics 48 (1994): 71-90; Samuel Fleischacker, A Third Concept of Liberty: Judgment and Freedom in Kant and Adam Smith (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999); Charles Griswold, Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1999); and Gloria Vivenza in Adam Smith and the Classics, respectively.
    • Adam Smith and the Classics
    • Vivenza, G.1
  • 14
    • 6344285172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment, 141, Griswold affirms that TMS's agent-relative point of view helps to overcome some of modern ethics's counterintuitive conclusions. I agree, but I go one step further: Modern elements in TMS, such as impartiality and universality, also supplement and help its ancient motives in order jointly to give a plausible, complete, and renewed account of ethics.
    • Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment , pp. 141
  • 15
    • 6344258060 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Besides specific studies on Aristotle, only around the 1960s was this ethics reconsidered in the philosophical debate, mainly through the German intellectual movement that has now become famous under the title of "The Rehabilitation of Practical Reason."
    • The Rehabilitation of Practical Reason
  • 16
    • 6344231128 scopus 로고
    • Philosophy in moral practice: Kant and Adam Smith
    • For the originality of Smith's characterization of the impartial spectator, see Samuel Fleischacker, "Philosophy in Moral Practice: Kant and Adam Smith," Kant Studien 82 (1991): 249-69.
    • (1991) Kant Studien , vol.82 , pp. 249-269
    • Fleischacker, S.1
  • 17
    • 6344279742 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.1.3
    • See TMS 1.1.3. For example, in 1.1.3:1: "Upon all occasions his own sentiments are the standards and measures by which he judges of mine."
    • TMS
  • 18
    • 6344288624 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 7.3.intr.3
    • TMS 7.3.intr.:3.
    • TMS
  • 19
    • 6344261394 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 7.3.intr.2
    • TMS 7.3.intr.:2.
    • TMS
  • 20
    • 6344263333 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Ralph Cudworth (1617-88) was an English scholar and a leading member of the Cambridge Platonists.
  • 21
    • 6344238469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 7.3.2:7
    • TMS 7.3.2:7. He accepts the role of reason in the induction of general rules of morality, though.
    • TMS
  • 22
    • 6344288625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 7.3.2.5
    • TMS 7.3.2:5.
    • TMS
  • 23
    • 6344290993 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 7.2.1:35, 39 and 43
    • See, for instance, TMS 7.2.1:35, 39 and 43.
    • TMS
  • 24
    • 6344285173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 7.2.1:14
    • See TMS 7.2.1:14.
    • TMS
  • 25
    • 6344266789 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 4.1:9
    • TMS 4.1:9.
    • TMS
  • 26
    • 6344233028 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 4.2:2
    • TMS 4.2:2.
    • TMS
  • 28
    • 6344242811 scopus 로고
    • Utility and morality: Adam Smith's critique of Hume
    • Marie A. Martin, in "Utility and Morality: Adam Smith's Critique of Hume," Hume Studies 16 (1990): 107-20, affirms that one of Smith's main oppositions to his friend's system was precisely the role of reason. If good and evil were to depend on utility, they would depend on the calculation of reason.
    • (1990) Hume Studies , vol.16 , pp. 107-120
    • Martin, M.A.1
  • 29
    • 6344290992 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 7.3.1
    • See TMS 7.3.1. Smith has discarded this system before talking of rationalism. However, since it exceeds the boundaries my topic, I have bypassed it.
    • TMS
  • 30
    • 6344261393 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Although Smith uses something like this discarding method in part 7, the real justification of this system, expounded in the previous six parts, relies on empirical observation.
  • 31
    • 6344254235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 7.3.2:7
    • TMS 7.3.2:7.
    • TMS
  • 32
    • 6344256170 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.3:22
    • TMS 3.3:22.
    • TMS
  • 33
    • 6344247418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.3:28 (my emphasis)
    • TMS 3.3:28 (my emphasis).
    • TMS
  • 34
    • 6344225904 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 7.2.intr.2
    • TMS 7.2.intr.:2.
    • TMS
  • 35
    • 6344251558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 1
    • See TMS 3, chap. 1. Charles Griswold (Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment, 46) contrasts "moral" to intellectual sentiments (wonder, surprise, and admiration). Without rejecting that distinction, I believe that it is also correct, and particularly useful, to compare moral with nonmoral or premoral sentiments. Indeed, it would even be possible to draw an analogy between this contrast and Kant's will and good will, where the latter is informed and justified by reason, and thus, properly moral. On the other hand, by grounding moral conduct on sentiments (though informed sentiments), Smith correctly suggests that the simple intellectual recognition of the good is not enough for ethical praxis.
    • TMS , pp. 3
  • 36
    • 0004211602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See TMS 3, chap. 1. Charles Griswold (Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment, 46) contrasts "moral" to intellectual sentiments (wonder, surprise, and admiration). Without rejecting that distinction, I believe that it is also correct, and particularly useful, to compare moral with nonmoral or premoral sentiments. Indeed, it would even be possible to draw an analogy between this contrast and Kant's will and good will, where the latter is informed and justified by reason, and thus, properly moral. On the other hand, by grounding moral conduct on sentiments (though informed sentiments), Smith correctly suggests that the simple intellectual recognition of the good is not enough for ethical praxis.
    • Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment , pp. 46
    • Griswold, C.1
  • 37
    • 6344251559 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.1.3:1
    • TMS 1.1.3:1.
    • TMS
  • 38
    • 6344252460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 7.4:33
    • TMS 7.4:33.
    • TMS
  • 40
    • 6344250387 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nature and philosophy: Adam Smith on Stoicism, aesthetic reconciliation and imagination
    • ed. Knud Haakonssen (Brookfield: Ashgate, Darthmouth)
    • Charles Griswold, "Nature and Philosophy: Adam Smith on Stoicism, Aesthetic Reconciliation and Imagination," in Adam Smith, ed. Knud Haakonssen (Brookfield: Ashgate, Darthmouth, 1998), 30. Nonetheless, Griswold does not believe that there is a coincidence between Smith and Aristotle in this point, for he seems to fear that this interpretation would lead one to say that Smith's theory is intuitionist. He supports this claim by saying: "It would be tempting to infer (as many have in discussing Aristotle) that 'perception' should be understood as immediate apprehension or intuition, especially in light of Smith's remark that 'it belongs to feeling and sentiment only to judge'.... This would be a mistake, for even quite simple cases of moral perception or feeling involve, for Smith, reflection and interpretation"; Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment, 192. However, I do not know of, and Griswold makes no reference to, any Aristotelian scholar who defends the idea that Aristotle was an intuitionist. Moral perception in Aristotle, just as in Adam Smith, involves at least habitual reflection and interpretation. If this were not the case, moral education would be useless and Aristotle would not have stressed so much the importance of experience in giving content to practical wisdom, contrasting practical insight to scientific or mathematical understanding. See Nichomachean Ethics 6.8.1142a12-21. On the other hand, Martha C. Nussbaum in "The Discernment of Perception: An Aristotelian Conception on Private and Public Rationality," in Aristotle's Ethics: Critical Essays, ed. Nancy Sherman (Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, 1999), 145-81, emphasizes the role of emotion in Aristotelian moral perception. She says: "I believe ... that perception is not merely aided by emotion but it is also in part constituted by appropriate response.... And it isn't just that sometimes we need the emotions to get to the right (intellectual) view of the situation; this is true, but is not the entire story.... The emotions are themselves modes of vision, or recognition. Their responses are part of what knowing, that is truly recognizing or acknowledging, consist in" (170-1).
    • (1998) Adam Smith , vol.30
    • Griswold, C.1
  • 41
    • 6344285172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Charles Griswold, "Nature and Philosophy: Adam Smith on Stoicism, Aesthetic Reconciliation and Imagination," in Adam Smith, ed. Knud Haakonssen (Brookfield: Ashgate, Darthmouth, 1998), 30. Nonetheless, Griswold does not believe that there is a coincidence between Smith and Aristotle in this point, for he seems to fear that this interpretation would lead one to say that Smith's theory is intuitionist. He supports this claim by saying: "It would be tempting to infer (as many have in discussing Aristotle) that 'perception' should be understood as immediate apprehension or intuition, especially in light of Smith's remark that 'it belongs to feeling and sentiment only to judge'.... This would be a mistake, for even quite simple cases of moral perception or feeling involve, for Smith, reflection and interpretation"; Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment, 192. However, I do not know of, and Griswold makes no reference to, any Aristotelian scholar who defends the idea that Aristotle was an intuitionist. Moral perception in Aristotle, just as in Adam Smith, involves at least habitual reflection and interpretation. If this were not the case, moral education would be useless and Aristotle would not have stressed so much the importance of experience in giving content to practical wisdom, contrasting practical insight to scientific or mathematical understanding. See Nichomachean Ethics 6.8.1142a12-21. On the other hand, Martha C. Nussbaum in "The Discernment of Perception: An Aristotelian Conception on Private and Public Rationality," in Aristotle's Ethics: Critical Essays, ed. Nancy Sherman (Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, 1999), 145-81, emphasizes the role of emotion in Aristotelian moral perception. She says: "I believe ... that perception is not merely aided by emotion but it is also in part constituted by appropriate response.... And it isn't just that sometimes we need the emotions to get to the right (intellectual) view of the situation; this is true, but is not the entire story.... The emotions are themselves modes of vision, or recognition. Their responses are part of what knowing, that is truly recognizing or acknowledging, consist in" (170-1).
    • Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment , pp. 192
  • 42
    • 84901538010 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6.8.1142a12-21
    • Charles Griswold, "Nature and Philosophy: Adam Smith on Stoicism, Aesthetic Reconciliation and Imagination," in Adam Smith, ed. Knud Haakonssen (Brookfield: Ashgate, Darthmouth, 1998), 30. Nonetheless, Griswold does not believe that there is a coincidence between Smith and Aristotle in this point, for he seems to fear that this interpretation would lead one to say that Smith's theory is intuitionist. He supports this claim by saying: "It would be tempting to infer (as many have in discussing Aristotle) that 'perception' should be understood as immediate apprehension or intuition, especially in light of Smith's remark that 'it belongs to feeling and sentiment only to judge'.... This would be a mistake, for even quite simple cases of moral perception or feeling involve, for Smith, reflection and interpretation"; Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment, 192. However, I do not know of, and Griswold makes no reference to, any Aristotelian scholar who defends the idea that Aristotle was an intuitionist. Moral perception in Aristotle, just as in Adam Smith, involves at least habitual reflection and interpretation. If this were not the case, moral education would be useless and Aristotle would not have stressed so much the importance of experience in giving content to practical wisdom, contrasting practical insight to scientific or mathematical understanding. See Nichomachean Ethics 6.8.1142a12-21. On the other hand, Martha C. Nussbaum in "The Discernment of Perception: An Aristotelian Conception on Private and Public Rationality," in Aristotle's Ethics: Critical Essays, ed. Nancy Sherman (Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, 1999), 145-81, emphasizes the role of emotion in Aristotelian moral perception. She says: "I believe ... that perception is not merely aided by emotion but it is also in part constituted by appropriate response.... And it isn't just that sometimes we need the emotions to get to the right (intellectual) view of the situation; this is true, but is not the entire story.... The emotions are themselves modes of vision, or recognition. Their responses are part of what knowing, that is truly recognizing or acknowledging, consist in" (170-1).
    • Nichomachean Ethics
  • 43
    • 0009261190 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The discernment of perception: An Aristotelian conception on private and public rationality
    • ed. Nancy Sherman (Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield)
    • Charles Griswold, "Nature and Philosophy: Adam Smith on Stoicism, Aesthetic Reconciliation and Imagination," in Adam Smith, ed. Knud Haakonssen (Brookfield: Ashgate, Darthmouth, 1998), 30. Nonetheless, Griswold does not believe that there is a coincidence between Smith and Aristotle in this point, for he seems to fear that this interpretation would lead one to say that Smith's theory is intuitionist. He supports this claim by saying: "It would be tempting to infer (as many have in discussing Aristotle) that 'perception' should be understood as immediate apprehension or intuition, especially in light of Smith's remark that 'it belongs to feeling and sentiment only to judge'.... This would be a mistake, for even quite simple cases of moral perception or feeling involve, for Smith, reflection and interpretation"; Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment, 192. However, I do not know of, and Griswold makes no reference to, any Aristotelian scholar who defends the idea that Aristotle was an intuitionist. Moral perception in Aristotle, just as in Adam Smith, involves at least habitual reflection and interpretation. If this were not the case, moral education would be useless and Aristotle would not have stressed so much the importance of experience in giving content to practical wisdom, contrasting practical insight to scientific or mathematical understanding. See Nichomachean Ethics 6.8.1142a12-21. On the other hand, Martha C. Nussbaum in "The Discernment of Perception: An Aristotelian Conception on Private and Public Rationality," in Aristotle's Ethics: Critical Essays, ed. Nancy Sherman (Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, 1999), 145-81, emphasizes the role of emotion in Aristotelian moral perception. She says: "I believe ... that perception is not merely aided by emotion but it is also in part constituted by appropriate response.... And it isn't just that sometimes we need the emotions to get to the right (intellectual) view of the situation; this is true, but is not the entire story.... The emotions are themselves modes of vision, or recognition. Their responses are part of what knowing, that is truly recognizing or acknowledging, consist in" (170-1).
    • (1999) Aristotle's Ethics: Critical Essays , pp. 145-181
    • Nussbaum, M.C.1
  • 44
    • 6344293492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6.12.1144a29
    • See NE 6.12.1144a29. Once more, this "immediate perception" involves reflection and can only be "immediate" because it is a virtue, an acquired habit.
    • NE
  • 45
    • 6344256171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.3:2
    • See TMS 3.3:2.
    • TMS
  • 46
    • 6344240296 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Vivenza makes a similar point: "Some scholars have seen a connection between Aristotle's phronimos (man of practical wisdom) and the impartial spectator; rightly enough, to my mind, though Smith's concept is much more complex and elaborate, and therefore, in the end, different"; Adam Smith and the Classics, 48. Griswold makes the same analogy, although in a looser way (Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment, 190). However, I do not see the necessity of humanizing the impartial spectator, for it seems to be enough, and even better supported than the connection with the Aristotelian virtue of prudence (it is acquired through exercising and it disposes one to choose the good in every occasion). Still, like Vivenza, I think that the impartial spectator is a much more complex and elaborate concept, hence I do not want to push too far on the similarities with prudence.
    • Adam Smith and the Classics , pp. 48
  • 47
    • 6344285172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Vivenza makes a similar point: "Some scholars have seen a connection between Aristotle's phronimos (man of practical wisdom) and the impartial spectator; rightly enough, to my mind, though Smith's concept is much more complex and elaborate, and therefore, in the end, different"; Adam Smith and the Classics, 48. Griswold makes the same analogy, although in a looser way (Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment, 190). However, I do not see the necessity of humanizing the impartial spectator, for it seems to be enough, and even better supported than the connection with the Aristotelian virtue of prudence (it is acquired through exercising and it disposes one to choose the good in every occasion). Still, like Vivenza, I think that the impartial spectator is a much more complex and elaborate concept, hence I do not want to push too far on the similarities with prudence.
    • Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment , pp. 190
  • 48
    • 6344266788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.1.3:10
    • TMS 1.1.3:10.
    • TMS
  • 49
    • 6344225903 scopus 로고
    • Aporien der praktischen Vernunft
    • Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann
    • See Wolfgang Wieland, "Aporien der praktischen Vernunft," in Wissenschaft und Gegenwart, Geisteswissenschaftliche Reihe (Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann, 1989), 65; and "Praxis und Urteilskraft," Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 28 (1974): 17-42.
    • (1989) Wissenschaft und Gegenwart, Geisteswissenschaftliche Reihe , pp. 65
    • Wieland, W.1
  • 50
    • 6344227811 scopus 로고
    • Praxis und urteilskraft
    • See Wolfgang Wieland, "Aporien der praktischen Vernunft," in Wissenschaft und Gegenwart, Geisteswissenschaftliche Reihe (Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann, 1989), 65; and "Praxis und Urteilskraft," Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 28 (1974): 17-42.
    • (1974) Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung , vol.28 , pp. 17-42
  • 51
    • 0007339328 scopus 로고
    • What is moral action?
    • Robert Sokolowski, "What is Moral Action?" New Scholasticism 63 (1989): 26.
    • (1989) New Scholasticism , vol.63 , pp. 26
    • Sokolowski, R.1
  • 52
    • 6344282112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.3.1094b13-14
    • NE 1.3.1094b13-14.
    • NE
  • 53
    • 0004277209 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge & Kegan Paul
    • See Douglas S. Hutchinson, The Virtues in Aristotle (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1986), 4: "So Aristotle has two reasons to believe that ethics is not primarily a matter of enumerating principles of conduct. First the mere acquisition of such principles is ineffective, except under special circumstances, when we already have the virtues, and, second, such principles are necessarily defective in the face of the irregularity and individuality of practical matters, which means that they must be supplemented by a sort of perceptual ability, which comes only with the virtues."
    • (1986) The Virtues in Aristotle , pp. 4
    • Hutchinson, D.S.1
  • 54
  • 55
    • 0036956103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The passions of the wise: Phronesis, rhetoric, and Aristotle's passionate practical deliberation
    • Arash Abizadeh, "The Passions of the Wise: Phronesis, Rhetoric, and Aristotle's Passionate Practical Deliberation," Review of Metaphysics 56 (2002): 287.
    • (2002) Review of Metaphysics , vol.56 , pp. 287
    • Abizadeh, A.1
  • 57
    • 0003437941 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Thomas Nagel, Equality and Partiality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1991), 10.
    • (1991) Equality and Partiality , pp. 10
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 59
    • 84904145133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nagel, Equality, 17. The same idea is developed in "The Fragmentation of Value," in Mortal Questions (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1979), 128-41.
    • Equality , pp. 17
    • Nagel1
  • 60
    • 0001942520 scopus 로고
    • The fragmentation of value
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Nagel, Equality, 17. The same idea is developed in "The Fragmentation of Value," in Mortal Questions (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1979), 128-41.
    • (1979) Mortal Questions , pp. 128-141
  • 61
    • 6344269744 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.3:2
    • TMS 3.3:2.
    • TMS
  • 64
    • 6344269106 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 7.4:3
    • See TMS 7.4:3. For Aristotle's account of this point, see Nussbaum, "The Discernment," 157-8.
    • TMS
  • 65
    • 6344231122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See TMS 7.4:3. For Aristotle's account of this point, see Nussbaum, "The Discernment," 157-8.
    • The Discernment , pp. 157-158
    • Nussbaum1
  • 66
    • 6344269899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6.2.1:22
    • In TMS 6.2.1:22, he asserts: "[There are] differences and distinctions which, though not imperceptible, are, by their nicety and delicacy, often altogether indefinable." Similarly, Nussbaum, 161, says: "In the NE V passage [1137b13-32], and implicitly in the one of Book II [1109b18-23], Aristotle alludes to a second feature of the practical, its indeterminate or indefinite character (to aoriston)."
    • TMS
  • 67
    • 6344282109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 7.3.2:8
    • See TMS 7.3.2:8. For Aristotle's account, see NE 6.8.1142a28.
    • TMS
  • 68
    • 6344241859 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6.8.1142a28
    • See TMS 7.3.2:8. For Aristotle's account, see NE 6.8.1142a28.
    • NE
  • 69
    • 6344275472 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6.2.1:22
    • For instance, in TMS 6.2.1:22 he says: "We shall stand in need of no casuistic rules to direct our conduct. These it is often impossible to accommodate to all the differences and gradations of circumstance, character and situation."
    • TMS
  • 70
    • 6344269595 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.3:3
    • See TMS 3.3:3, where he asserts: "Habit and experience have taught us to do this so easily and readily, that we are scarce sensible that we do it."
    • TMS
  • 73
    • 0002391405 scopus 로고
    • The utilitarianism of Adam Smith's policy advice
    • See, for instance, Thomas Campbell and Ian Ross, "The Utilitarianism of Adam Smith's Policy Advice," Journal of the History of Ideas 42 (1981): 73-92.
    • (1981) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.42 , pp. 73-92
    • Campbell, T.1    Ross, I.2
  • 74
    • 6344279738 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Freiburg: Karl Alber Verlag), chap. 3
    • For the explanation of teleology, I rely on Alejandro Vigo, Zeit und Praxis bei Aristoteles (Freiburg: Karl Alber Verlag, 1996), chap. 3. See also John Cooper, Reason and Human Good in Aristotle (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1975), 15-18 and 93-7. Although Cooper does not use the word "teleology" for this feature, he acknowledges that Aristotle's construction of practical reason is end-oriented.
    • (1996) Zeit und Praxis bei Aristoteles
    • Vigo, A.1
  • 75
    • 0003659604 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Harvard University Press
    • For the explanation of teleology, I rely on Alejandro Vigo, Zeit und Praxis bei Aristoteles (Freiburg: Karl Alber Verlag, 1996), chap. 3. See also John Cooper, Reason and Human Good in Aristotle (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1975), 15-18 and 93-7. Although Cooper does not use the word "teleology" for this feature, he acknowledges that Aristotle's construction of practical reason is end-oriented.
    • (1975) Reason and Human Good in Aristotle , pp. 15-18
    • Cooper, J.1
  • 77
    • 6344238466 scopus 로고
    • The metaphysical and psychological basis of Aristotle's ethics
    • ed. Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (Berkeley: University of California Press)
    • See Terence H. Irwin, "The Metaphysical and Psychological Basis of Aristotle's Ethics," in Essays on Aristotle's Ethics, ed. Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980), 46-7.
    • (1980) Essays on Aristotle's Ethics , pp. 46-47
    • Irwin, T.H.1
  • 78
    • 6344227809 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is true even when there is no actual deliberation. About this topic, Cooper says: "In so far as those are one's reasons, it is as if one had deliberated and decided accordingly (even if one did not deliberating at all)"; Reason and Human Good, 9-10.
    • Reason and Human Good , pp. 9-10
  • 79
    • 6344272255 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.8.1099a32-b7
    • See NE 1.8.1099a32-b7.
    • NE
  • 80
    • 6344269003 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.10.1101a67
    • See NE 1.10.1101a67.
    • NE
  • 81
    • 6344273031 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 3
    • See Vigo, Zeit, chap. 3.
    • Zeit
    • Vigo1
  • 82
    • 0001991554 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle on learning to be good
    • See Myles F. Burnyeat, "Aristotle on Learning to be Good," in Essays on Aristotle's Ethics, 83, where he describes the akratic man as he who has a reasoned desire to do one thing yet under the influence of a contrary desire actually does another.
    • Essays on Aristotle's Ethics , pp. 83
    • Burnyeat, M.F.1
  • 83
    • 6344287053 scopus 로고
    • Learning the emotions
    • For this topic, see Harold Baillie, "Learning the Emotions," New Scholasticism 62 (1988): 221; and Nancy Sherman, "The Habituation of Character," in Aristotle's Ethics, 238, who describes emotions in Aristotle as intentional and cognitive.
    • (1988) New Scholasticism , vol.62 , pp. 221
    • Baillie, H.1
  • 84
    • 6344242808 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The habituation of character
    • For this topic, see Harold Baillie, "Learning the Emotions," New Scholasticism 62 (1988): 221; and Nancy Sherman, "The Habituation of Character," in Aristotle's Ethics, 238, who describes emotions in Aristotle as intentional and cognitive.
    • Aristotle's Ethics , pp. 238
    • Sherman, N.1
  • 85
    • 6344269596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sherman, "The Habituation," 235, says: "The desiderative part of the non-rational soul (appetites, emotions and feelings) does not engage in reasoning but can listen to reason, be shaped by it."
    • The Habituation , pp. 235
    • Sherman1
  • 86
    • 6344236722 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2.6.1106b36-1107a3
    • See NE 2.6.1106b36-1107a3.
    • NE
  • 89
    • 6344234743 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.3:14, 21, and 22
    • In making this point I would like to highlight the similarities between Aristotle's and Adam Smith's accounts of moral education, regardless of the formal differences that are due to their styles and level of discussion. See especially TMS 3.3:14, 21, and 22; also TMS 6.3:25; and for Aristotle, see Sherman, "The Habituation," 257.
    • TMS
  • 90
    • 6344270038 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6.3:25
    • In making this point I would like to highlight the similarities between Aristotle's and Adam Smith's accounts of moral education, regardless of the formal differences that are due to their styles and level of discussion. See especially TMS 3.3:14, 21, and 22; also TMS 6.3:25; and for Aristotle, see Sherman, "The Habituation," 257.
    • TMS
  • 91
    • 6344269596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In making this point I would like to highlight the similarities between Aristotle's and Adam Smith's accounts of moral education, regardless of the formal differences that are due to their styles and level of discussion. See especially TMS 3.3:14, 21, and 22; also TMS 6.3:25; and for Aristotle, see Sherman, "The Habituation," 257.
    • The Habituation , pp. 257
    • Sherman1
  • 92
    • 6344272138 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6.8.1141b24-25
    • In NE 6.8.1141b24-25, Aristotle also says: "Political wisdom and practical wisdom are the same state of mind, but to be them is not the same." Cooper explains that in this passage, "Aristotle's point is that political wisdom and practical intellect are the same capacity but, in effect, put to use in different relations"; Reason and Human Good, 34-5.
    • NE
  • 93
    • 6344227809 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In NE 6.8.1141b24-25, Aristotle also says: "Political wisdom and practical wisdom are the same state of mind, but to be them is not the same." Cooper explains that in this passage, "Aristotle's point is that political wisdom and practical intellect are the same capacity but, in effect, put to use in different relations"; Reason and Human Good, 34-5.
    • Reason and Human Good , pp. 34-35
  • 94
    • 0347574050 scopus 로고
    • Two concepts of morality: A distinction of Adam Smith's ethics and its Stoic origin
    • Norbert Waszek, "Two Concepts of Morality: A Distinction of Adam Smith's Ethics and its Stoic Origin," Journal of the History of Ideas 45 (1984): 591-606.
    • (1984) Journal of the History of Ideas , vol.45 , pp. 591-606
    • Waszek, N.1
  • 95
    • 6344221247 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For instance, Charles Griswold, James Otteson, and Vivienne Brown.
  • 96
    • 6344225900 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.1.5:6
    • TMS 1.1.5:6.
    • TMS
  • 97
    • 6344251555 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.1.5:9
    • TMS 1.1.5:9. See also TMS 6.3:19.
    • TMS
  • 98
    • 6344250383 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6.3:19
    • TMS 1.1.5:9. See also TMS 6.3:19.
    • TMS
  • 99
    • 6344225899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.1.1:5
    • TMS 1.1.1:5.
    • TMS
  • 101
    • 6344284045 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Darwall, "Sympathetic, 144. See TMS 1.1.1:10: "Sympathy, therefore, does not arise so much from the view of the passion, as from that of the situation which excites it."
    • Sympathetic , pp. 144
    • Darwall1
  • 102
    • 6344250382 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.1.1:10
    • Darwall, "Sympathetic, 144. See TMS 1.1.1:10: "Sympathy, therefore, does not arise so much from the view of the passion, as from that of the situation which excites it."
    • TMS
  • 103
    • 6344288622 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.3.1:9
    • See TMS 1.3.1:9, where in a footnote, replying to his friend David Hume, Smith indicates this same distinction.
    • TMS
  • 108
    • 6344282111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.3:1
    • See TMS 3.3:1.
    • TMS
  • 109
    • 6344225576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.3.2:1
    • TMS 1.3.2:1. See also Adam Smith, An Inquiry concerning the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, ed. Roy H. Campbell, Andrew S. Skinner, and William B. Todd (Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1981), 2.3:28 and 3.3:12.
    • TMS
  • 110
    • 0003411497 scopus 로고
    • ed. Roy H. Campbell, Andrew S. Skinner, and William B. Todd (Indianapolis: Liberty Press), 2.3:28 and 3.3:12
    • TMS 1.3.2:1. See also Adam Smith, An Inquiry concerning the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, ed. Roy H. Campbell, Andrew S. Skinner, and William B. Todd (Indianapolis: Liberty Press, 1981), 2.3:28 and 3.3:12.
    • (1981) An Inquiry Concerning the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations
    • Smith, A.1
  • 111
    • 6344250384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • However infrequent this interpretation may be, it is perfectly consistent with the text. Every time Smith uses the expression "to better our condition," he specifies that "for the bulk of mankind" it is "to improve wealth and honors." On the other hand, when he talks about the wise and virtuous, he clearly states that their motivation is the praiseworthy rather than simple praise.
  • 112
    • 6344261390 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.3:14
    • TMS 3.3:14.
    • TMS
  • 113
    • 6344258055 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 4.1448b5-23
    • See Poetics 4.1448b5-23; Rhetoric 1.11.1371b5-10, and Sherman's explanation in "The Habituation," 240-1. Griswold has also identified several similarities on this subject (see Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment, 210).
    • Poetics
  • 114
    • 84872421184 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.11.1371b5-10
    • See Poetics 4.1448b5-23; Rhetoric 1.11.1371b5-10, and Sherman's explanation in "The Habituation," 240-1. Griswold has also identified several similarities on this subject (see Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment, 210).
    • Rhetoric
  • 115
    • 6344261392 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Poetics 4.1448b5-23; Rhetoric 1.11.1371b5-10, and Sherman's explanation in "The Habituation," 240-1. Griswold has also identified several similarities on this subject (see Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment, 210).
    • The Habituation , pp. 240-241
  • 116
    • 6344285172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Poetics 4.1448b5-23; Rhetoric 1.11.1371b5-10, and Sherman's explanation in "The Habituation," 240-1. Griswold has also identified several similarities on this subject (see Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment, 210).
    • Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment , pp. 210
  • 117
    • 6344263331 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.3:21
    • TMS 3.3:21.
    • TMS
  • 118
    • 6344261391 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.3:22
    • TMS 3.3:22.
    • TMS
  • 119
    • 6344269596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare Sherman, "The Habituation," 238-9: "According to Aristotle, right education is to teach children to find pleasure and pain as it is appropriate (1104b11-13)"; and, "Cultivating the dispositional capacities to feel fear, anger, goodwill, compassion or pity appropriately will be bound up with learning how to discern the circumstances that warrant these responses."
    • The Habituation , pp. 238-239
    • Sherman1
  • 120
    • 6344279740 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6.concl.:3
    • TMS 6.concl.:3.
    • TMS
  • 121
    • 6344266786 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6.concl.:4
    • TMS 6.concl.:4.
    • TMS
  • 122
    • 6344229136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.2:2
    • TMS 3.2:2.
    • TMS
  • 123
    • 6344261389 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.2:8
    • TMS 3.2:8.
    • TMS
  • 125
    • 6344248485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.1:3
    • TMS 3.1:3.
    • TMS
  • 126
    • 6344251558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See TMS 3.
    • TMS , pp. 3
  • 127
  • 129
    • 0004211602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Nagel's sense, again. See section 2. See also Griswold, Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment, 68, where he compares the impartial spectator's perspective to drama critics' objectivity, which "is achieved through relative, though not complete, detachment."
    • Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment , pp. 68
    • Griswold1
  • 131
    • 6344233026 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2.2.2:1
    • See, for instance, TMS 2.2.2:1.
    • TMS
  • 132
    • 6344277848 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2.2.2.1
    • TMS 2.2.2:1.
    • TMS
  • 133
    • 6344234744 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.3:2
    • TMS 3.3:2.
    • TMS
  • 135
    • 6344222745 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Naturally, in these cases the impartial spectator is no longer "impartial," hence it might be more precise to say that the impartial spectator does not really err but simply disappears. However, psychologically, we may be unable to notice his absence, and rather convince ourselves that those judgments are his impartial judgments instead of what we want to hear.
  • 136
    • 6344251558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 2
    • See TMS 3, chap. 2.
    • TMS , pp. 3
  • 137
    • 6344290990 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.2:1
    • TMS 3.2:1.
    • TMS
  • 138
    • 6344288623 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6.3:25
    • See TMS 6.3:25.
    • TMS
  • 139
    • 6344225901 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.2:16
    • TMS 3.2:16.
    • TMS
  • 140
    • 6344264918 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.2:8
    • TMS 3.2:8.
    • TMS
  • 141
    • 60949527782 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Knud Haakonssen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • See Adam Smith, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, ed. Knud Haakonssen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), xxii. In his introduction, Haakonssen says, "It is clear that Smith gets to greater clarity, especially in the last edition, about our tendency to transpose the impartial social spectator to become an idealized judge."
    • (2002) The Theory of Moral Sentiments
    • Smith, A.1
  • 142
    • 6344279739 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sympathetic exchange: Adam Smith and punishment
    • See Eric Miller, "Sympathetic Exchange: Adam Smith and Punishment," Ratio Juris 9, no. 2 (1996): 194.
    • (1996) Ratio Juris , vol.9 , Issue.2 , pp. 194
    • Miller, E.1
  • 144
    • 0141487932 scopus 로고
    • ed. Laurence Becker and Charlotte Becker (Garland: Hamden)
    • See The Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Laurence Becker and Charlotte Becker (Garland: Hamden, 1992), corresponding to the definition of " Impartiality" by Bernard Gert, 599-600.
    • (1992) The Encyclopedia of Ethics
  • 145
    • 6344290991 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • by Bernard Gert
    • See The Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Laurence Becker and Charlotte Becker (Garland: Hamden, 1992), corresponding to the definition of " Impartiality" by Bernard Gert, 599-600.
    • Impartiality , pp. 599-600
  • 146
    • 6344233025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.4:6
    • See TMS 3.4:6.
    • TMS
  • 149
    • 6344252458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See section 2
    • See section 2.
  • 150
    • 6344254233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6.3:19
    • TMS 6.3:19.
    • TMS
  • 151
    • 6344236723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6.3:25 (my emphasis)
    • TMS 6.3:25 (my emphasis).
    • TMS
  • 152
    • 6344240295 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid. (my emphasis)
    • Ibid. (my emphasis).
  • 153
    • 6344285169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.3:28
    • See TMS 3.3:28.
    • TMS
  • 154
    • 6344250385 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6.3:1
    • See TMS 6.3:1.
    • TMS
  • 155
    • 6344229139 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.5:1
    • In TMS 3.5:1, referring to the virtuous man, he says: "None but those of the happiest mould are capable of suiting, with exact justness, their sentiments and behaviour to the smallest difference of situation." However, Smith does not believe that virtues warrant happiness, for in "paroxysms of distress" his "own natural feelings" press hard upon him, and he requires a great effort to preserve his equanimity. Despite Nature's recompensing him with the pleasure of complete self-approbation, "he still suffers; and the recompense she bestows, though very considerable, is not sufficient completely to compensate the sufferings which those (inalterable) laws (of Nature) inflict" (TMS 3.3-28). This is an important difference with the Stoic sage, and a similarity with Aristotle's phronimos. See also TMS 3.2:3, 1.3.2:5, and 6.concl.:6.
    • TMS
  • 156
    • 6344256169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.3-28
    • In TMS 3.5:1, referring to the virtuous man, he says: "None but those of the happiest mould are capable of suiting, with exact justness, their sentiments and behaviour to the smallest difference of situation." However, Smith does not believe that virtues warrant happiness, for in "paroxysms of distress" his "own natural feelings" press hard upon him, and he requires a great effort to preserve his equanimity. Despite Nature's recompensing him with the pleasure of complete self-approbation, "he still suffers; and the recompense she bestows, though very considerable, is not sufficient completely to compensate the sufferings which those (inalterable) laws (of Nature) inflict" (TMS 3.3-28). This is an important difference with the Stoic sage, and a similarity with Aristotle's phronimos. See also TMS 3.2:3, 1.3.2:5, and 6.concl.:6.
    • TMS
  • 157
    • 6344229137 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.2:3, 1.3.2:5, and 6.concl.:6
    • In TMS 3.5:1, referring to the virtuous man, he says: "None but those of the happiest mould are capable of suiting, with exact justness, their sentiments and behaviour to the smallest difference of situation." However, Smith does not believe that virtues warrant happiness, for in "paroxysms of distress" his "own natural feelings" press hard upon him, and he requires a great effort to preserve his equanimity. Despite Nature's recompensing him with the pleasure of complete self-approbation, "he still suffers; and the recompense she bestows, though very considerable, is not sufficient completely to compensate the sufferings which those (inalterable) laws (of Nature) inflict" (TMS 3.3-28). This is an important difference with the Stoic sage, and a similarity with Aristotle's phronimos. See also TMS 3.2:3, 1.3.2:5, and 6.concl.:6.
    • TMS
  • 158
    • 6344252456 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6.1:14
    • TMS 6.1:14.
    • TMS
  • 159
    • 6344238468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • section 1 (my emphasis)
    • TMS 6, section 1 (my emphasis).
    • TMS , pp. 6
  • 160
    • 6344277851 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.3.3:2
    • TMS 1.3.3:2.
    • TMS
  • 161
    • 6344229141 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.3.3:1
    • See TMS 1.3.3:1.
    • TMS
  • 162
    • 6344227810 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.3.3:2
    • See TMS 1.3.3:2.
    • TMS
  • 163
    • 6344247416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Taking this expression in the broad sense just explained.
  • 164
    • 6344231126 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3.3:30
    • See TMS 3.3:30: "Happiness consists in tranquility and enjoyment."
    • TMS
  • 165
    • 6344245598 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 4.1:8
    • TMS 4.1:8.
    • TMS
  • 166
    • 6344245599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 4.1:9
    • TMS 4.1:9.
    • TMS
  • 167
    • 6344247414 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6.2.1:20
    • TMS 6.2.1:20.
    • TMS
  • 168
    • 6344250386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6.2.1:46
    • See TMS 6.2.1:46.
    • TMS
  • 169
    • 6344229140 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6.2.2:15-18
    • See TMS 6.2.2:15-18. Vivienne Brown opposes this thesis, stressing the "apolitical" character of Smith's "man of public spirit" (Adam Smith's Discourse, 138). I admit that Smith's notion of "state" is substantially different from and may even be opposed to Aristotle's polis. Nonetheless, from this evidence I rather infer that their respective ideas of the political sphere are different, and hence the concepts of "public spirit" and great statesman or legislator, within Smith's political theory, should not be measured, at least materially, by Aristotelian standards.
    • TMS
  • 170
    • 6344245600 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See TMS 6.2.2:15-18. Vivienne Brown opposes this thesis, stressing the "apolitical" character of Smith's "man of public spirit" (Adam Smith's Discourse, 138). I admit that Smith's notion of "state" is substantially different from and may even be opposed to Aristotle's polis. Nonetheless, from this evidence I rather infer that their respective ideas of the political sphere are different, and hence the concepts of "public spirit" and great statesman or legislator, within Smith's political theory, should not be measured, at least materially, by Aristotelian standards.
    • Adam Smith's Discourse , pp. 138
  • 171
    • 6344277849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.3.3 and 6.3:28
    • See TMS 1.3.3 and 6.3:28.
    • TMS
  • 172
    • 6344285170 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1.3.3:8
    • See TMS 1.3.3:8.
    • TMS
  • 173
    • 0041729825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Adam Smith on friendship and love
    • Charles Griswold and Douglas Den Uyl, "Adam Smith on Friendship and Love," Review of Metaphysics 49 (1996): 616. See also Griswold, Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment, 316.
    • (1996) Review of Metaphysics , vol.49 , pp. 616
    • Griswold, C.1    Uyl, D.D.2
  • 176
    • 6344231123 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6.3:18
    • See TMS 6.3:18.
    • TMS
  • 177
    • 6344225902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What might properly be called natural jurisprudence?
    • ed. Knud Haakonssen
    • See Knud Haakonssen, "What Might Properly Be Called Natural Jurisprudence?" in Adam Smith, ed. Knud Haakonssen, 206.
    • Adam Smith , pp. 206
    • Haakonssen, K.1
  • 179
    • 6344277850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith on virtues: Vir virtutis discourse and civic humanism
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Leonidas Montes, "Smith on Virtues: Vir Virtutis Discourse and Civic Humanism," in Adam Smith in Context (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), 94.
    • (2003) Adam Smith in Context , pp. 94
    • Montes, L.1
  • 180
    • 0004211602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Griswold, Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment, 138, and Nussbaum, "The Discernment," 170, respectively. Nussbaum asserts: "Aristotle does not make a sharp split between the cognitive and the emotive."
    • Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment , pp. 138
    • Griswold1
  • 181
    • 6344231122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • respectively
    • See Griswold, Adam Smith and the Virtues of Enlightenment, 138, and Nussbaum, "The Discernment," 170, respectively. Nussbaum asserts: "Aristotle does not make a sharp split between the cognitive and the emotive."
    • The Discernment , pp. 170
    • Nussbaum1
  • 183
    • 6344233027 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 6.3:14
    • See TMS 6.3:14. On the other hand, according to Nussbaum, moral perception in Aristotle is "some sort of complex responsiveness to the salient features of one's concrete situation" ("The Discernment," 146).
    • TMS
  • 184
    • 6344227812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See TMS 6.3:14. On the other hand, according to Nussbaum, moral perception in Aristotle is "some sort of complex responsiveness to the salient features of one's concrete situation" ("The Discernment," 146).
    • The Discernment , pp. 146
  • 185
    • 6344231124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 7.2.3:21
    • See TMS 7.2.3:21. Recall exactly the same idea for Aristotle's phronimos, in NE 2.6.1113a32-3.
    • TMS
  • 186
    • 6344285171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2.6.1113a32-3
    • See TMS 7.2.3:21. Recall exactly the same idea for Aristotle's phronimos, in NE 2.6.1113a32-3.
    • NE
  • 187
    • 6344277852 scopus 로고
    • La ética de Adam Smith: Hacia un utilitarismo de la simpatía
    • See José Luis Tasset, "La Ética de Adam Smith: Hacia un Utilitarismo de la Simpatía," Themata 6 (1989): 205.
    • (1989) Themata , vol.6 , pp. 205
    • Tasset, J.L.1
  • 190
    • 6344251556 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 7.2:14
    • Smith himself points out some of these coincidences. For example, while expounding the nature of virtue in different moral systems, he praises Aristotle's "opinion that no conviction of understanding was capable of getting the better of inveterate habits, and that good morals arose not from knowledge but from action" (TMS 7.2:14), in contrast to Plato's and the Stoics' intellectualism. He also admits that his account of virtue corresponds very much to Aristotle's (TMS 7.2:12), for whom it "consists of the habit of mediocrity according to right reason" (TMS 7.2.1:12). Another important similarity is that moral judgment is only possible in particular instances.
    • TMS
  • 191
    • 6344284046 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 7.2:12
    • Smith himself points out some of these coincidences. For example, while expounding the nature of virtue in different moral systems, he praises Aristotle's "opinion that no conviction of understanding was capable of getting the better of inveterate habits, and that good morals arose not from knowledge but from action" (TMS 7.2:14), in contrast to Plato's and the Stoics' intellectualism. He also admits that his account of virtue corresponds very much to Aristotle's (TMS 7.2:12), for whom it "consists of the habit of mediocrity according to right reason" (TMS 7.2.1:12). Another important similarity is that moral judgment is only possible in particular instances.
    • TMS
  • 192
    • 6344251557 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith himself points out some of these coincidences. For example, while expounding the nature of virtue in different moral systems, he praises Aristotle's "opinion that no conviction of understanding was capable of getting the better of inveterate habits, and that good morals arose not from knowledge but from action" (TMS 7.2:14), in contrast to Plato's and the Stoics' intellectualism. He also admits that his account of virtue corresponds very much to Aristotle's (TMS 7.2:12), for whom it "consists of the habit of mediocrity according to right reason" (TMS 7.2.1:12). Another important similarity is that moral judgment is only possible in particular instances.
    • TMS 7.2.1:12
  • 193
    • 6344245600 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Regarding the Stoics' influence, which along with Hume's is the most explicit and obvious, Vivienne Brown affirms that there is "simultaneous dependence on, yet ultimate rejection of, the Stoic philosophy in TMS" (Adam Smith's Discourse, 5). Griswold and Vivenza share this diagnosis.
    • Adam Smith's Discourse , pp. 5
  • 195
    • 6344248484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I particularly refer to universality and impartiality. For his possible influence on Kant and the deontological elements present in TMS, see Fleischacker, A Third Concept.
    • A Third Concept
    • Fleischacker1
  • 196
    • 6344245601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am much indebted to the Research Department of Pontificia Universidad Católica de Chile, DIPUC, for their financial support, and to Leonidas Montes and Alejandro Vigo for their helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.