메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 47, Issue 2, 2007, Pages 138-155

Kant and the aesthetics of nature

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 61149226662     PISSN: 00070904     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1093/aesthj/ayl052     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (16)

References (39)
  • 1
    • 36549036980 scopus 로고
    • Frankfurt: Suhrkamp (= Werke, Bd. 13)
    • 'Wir fühlen uns bei der Naturschönheit zu sehr im Unbestimmten, ohne Kriterium zu sein . . .' G. W. F. Hegel, Vorlesungen über die Ästhetik I (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1970) (= Werke, Bd. 13), p. 15 (my translation)
    • (1970) Vorlesungen Über Die Ästhetik I , pp. 15
    • Hegel, G.W.F.1
  • 2
    • 0004175786 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge U.P.
    • See, for instance, R. Wollheim, Art and Its Objects (Cambridge: Cambridge U.P., 1980), pp. 96-98
    • (1980) Art and Its Objects , pp. 96-98
    • Wollheim, R.1
  • 5
    • 34249423074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Freedom and Objectivity in the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature
    • See again Carlson, Aesthetics and the Environment, for a series of influential essays on this question and an overview of the history of the discussion. Also cf. G. Parsons, 'Freedom and Objectivity in the Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature', British Journal of Aesthetics, vol. 46 (2006), pp. 17-37
    • (2006) British Journal of Aesthetics , vol.46 , pp. 17-37
    • Parsons, G.1
  • 7
    • 0004580816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Appreciating Nature on Its Own Terms
    • The phrase is from Y. Saito, 'Appreciating Nature on Its Own Terms', Environmental Ethics, vol. 20 (1998), pp. 135-149
    • (1998) Environmental Ethics , vol.20 , pp. 135-149
    • Saito, Y.1
  • 9
    • 60949729976 scopus 로고
    • Quoted from, Manchester: Manchester U.P, and
    • Quoted from F. W. Leakey, Baudelaire and Nature (Manchester: Manchester U.P., 1969), pp. 113 and 121
    • (1969) Baudelaire and Nature , pp. 113-121
    • Leakey, F.W.1
  • 10
    • 79956599681 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Amherst, MA: Prometheus
    • O. Wilde, Intentions (Amherst, MA: Prometheus 2004), p. 55
    • (2004) Intentions , pp. 55
    • Wilde, O.1
  • 11
    • 79956599791 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The classic source for this approach is Carlson, Aesthetics and the Environment
    • The classic source for this approach is Carlson, Aesthetics and the Environment
  • 12
    • 10644263933 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. P. Guyer and E. Matthews Cambridge: Cambrige U.P.
    • References to the third Critique follow the pagination of vol. 5 of the Akademie edition. The translations, unless noted otherwise, are from I. Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgement, trans. P. Guyer and E. Matthews (Cambridge: Cambrige U.P., 2000)
    • (2000) Critique of the Power of Judgement
    • Kant, I.1
  • 13
    • 79956651969 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'The powers of cognition that are set into ply hy this representation are hereby in a free play, since no determinate concept restricts them to a particular rule of cognition. Thus the state of mind in this representation must be that of a feeling of the free play of the powers of representation in a given representation for a cognition in general' (5: 217; cf. also 5: 287)
    • 'The powers of cognition that are set into ply hy this representation are hereby in a free play, since no determinate concept restricts them to a particular rule of cognition. Thus the state of mind in this representation must be that of a feeling of the free play of the powers of representation in a given representation for a cognition in general' (5: 217; cf. also 5: 287)
  • 14
    • 61149347928 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Role of Symbolic Presentation in Kant's Theory of Taste
    • For a more detailed account, see A. Rueger and S. Evren, 'The Role of Symbolic Presentation in Kant's Theory of Taste', British Journal of Aesthetics, vol. 45 (2005), pp. 229-247
    • (2005) British Journal of Aesthetics , vol.45 , pp. 229-247
    • Rueger, A.1    Evren, S.2
  • 15
    • 0009262872 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford U.P.
    • Virtually alone among commentators of Kant, S. Kemal has also argued that, on Kant's theory, 'natural objects are ascribed aesthetic qualities by analogy with fine art' (Kant and Fine Art: An Essay on Kant and the Philosophy of Fine Art and Culture [Oxford: Oxford U.P., 1986], p. 20) I don't find Kemal's reasons for this claim plausible and my own view does not emphasize fine art in the same way
    • (1986) Kant and Fine Art: An Essay on Kant and the Philosophy of Fine Art and Culture , pp. 20
  • 18
    • 84920729646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford U.P
    • That a judgement of adherent beauty is actually a conjunction of a judgement of free beauty (a pure judgement of taste) and a judgement of perfection is not an uncontroversial view. For supporting arguments see M, Budd, The Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature (Oxford: Oxford U.P., 2002), pp. 36-39
    • (2002) The Aesthetic Appreciation of Nature , pp. 36-39
    • Budd, M.1
  • 19
    • 61249524236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Parerga and Pulchritudo adhaerens: A Reading of the Third Moment of the Analytic of the Beautiful
    • M. Gammon, 'Parerga and Pulchritudo adhaerens: A Reading of the Third Moment of the "Analytic of the Beautiful"', Kant-Studien, vol. 90 (1999), pp. 148-167
    • (1999) Kant-Studien , vol.90 , pp. 148-167
    • Gammon, M.1
  • 20
    • 33748543708 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge U.P, 290-298
    • and H. Allison, Kant's Theory of Taste (Cambridge: Cambridge U.P., 2001), pp. 138-142, 290-298
    • (2001) Kant's Theory of Taste , pp. 138-142
    • Allison, H.1
  • 21
  • 22
    • 79956651843 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Free and Adherent Beauty: A Modest Proposal
    • Cambridge: Cambridge U.P
    • and 'Free and Adherent Beauty: A Modest Proposal', in Guyer, Values of Beauty (Cambridge: Cambridge U.P., 2005), pp. 129-140
    • (2005) Guyer, Values of Beauty , pp. 129-140
  • 23
    • 61249153404 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beautiful Surfaces: Kant on Free and Adherent Beauty in Nature and Art
    • forthcoming
    • See the references in footnote 17 as well as A. Rueger, 'Beautiful Surfaces: Kant on Free and Adherent Beauty in Nature and Art', British Journal for the History of Philosophy (forthcoming)
    • British Journal for the History of Philosophy
    • Rueger, A.1
  • 24
    • 79956636954 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beauty and Utility in Eighteenth-Century Aesthetics
    • Guyer
    • P. Guyer, 'Beauty and Utility in Eighteenth-Century Aesthetics', in Guyer, Values of Beauty, pp. 126-127
    • Values of Beauty , pp. 126-127
    • Guyer, P.1
  • 26
    • 79956599674 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Guyer and Matthews translation modified
    • Guyer and Matthews translation modified
  • 27
    • 61149605860 scopus 로고
    • Die Schönheit der Kristalle und das Spiel der Erkenntniskräfte
    • and Rueger, Beautiful Surfaces
    • Cf. R. Brandt, 'Die Schönheit der Kristalle und das Spiel der Erkenntniskräfte', Kant-Forschungen, vol. 5 (1994), pp. 19-57, and Rueger, 'Beautiful Surfaces'
    • (1994) Kant-Forschungen , vol.5 , pp. 19-57
    • Brandt, R.1
  • 28
    • 79956651813 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is how Kant introduces the distinction between aesthetic and ideological judgements: purposiveness, he says, can be represented either in aesthetic judgements 'on a merely subjective ground' or in teleological judgements 'as an objective ground, as a correspondence of its form with the possibility of the thing itself, in accordance with a concept of it which precedes and contains the ground of this form, 5: 192, In teleological judgements, nature is no longer judged as it appears as art, but to the extent that it really is art albeit superhuman, 5: 311
    • This is how Kant introduces the distinction between aesthetic and ideological judgements: purposiveness, he says, can be represented either in aesthetic judgements 'on a merely subjective ground' or in teleological judgements 'as an objective ground, as a correspondence of its form with the possibility of the thing itself, in accordance with a concept of it which precedes and contains the ground of this form' (5: 192). In teleological judgements, 'nature is no longer judged as it appears as art, but to the extent that it really is art (albeit superhuman) . . .' (5: 311)
  • 29
    • 34250825059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Formal Natural Beauty
    • on p. 213
    • Cf. The completely different, even contrary evaluation of the case of organisms and their surface features in Hegel's aesthetics: Vorlesungen über die Ästhetik I, pp. 193-194 ('The deficiency of natural beauty'). The fact that organisms (qua organisms) have no special significance in Kant's theory while they occupy centre place in Hegel's has not been sufficientlynoted and discussed. Kant's view is also diametrically opposed to the way Nick Zangwill has recently tried to reconstruct the distinction of free and adherent beauty in his project of articulating a 'moderate formalism' in aesthetics. See Zangwill, 'Formal Natural Beauty', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. 101 (2001), pp. 209-224, on p. 213 n.n: 'The beauty of a part of a creature is plausibly a beauty which is relative to its function. One may have to know what the part does-that is, we may have to know its function with respect to the whole organism-in order to see ... its dependent, non-formal beauty. The part is beautiful as a thing with its function. But whole organisms ... in my view, often have a free, formal beauty.'
    • (2001) Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society , vol.101 , pp. 209-224
    • Zangwill1
  • 35
    • 79956651696 scopus 로고
    • Pfullingen: Neske
    • Cf. M. Heidegger, Nietzsche, vol. I (Pfullingen: Neske 1961), p. 130
    • (1961) Nietzsche , vol.1 , pp. 130
    • Heidegger, M.1
  • 38
    • 79956636747 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • With respect to the intellectual interest in beautiful nature Kant does impose cognitive conditions: we have to be aware that it is nature we are judging 5:302-303, But this cognitive constraint does not extend to the pure judgement of taste itself, The thought that nature has produced that beauty must accompany the intuition and reflection, and on this alone is grounded the immediate interest that one takes in it. Otherwise there remains, a mere judgement of taste without any interest, 5: 299
    • With respect to the intellectual interest in beautiful nature Kant does impose cognitive conditions: we have to be aware that it is nature we are judging (see 5:302-303). But this cognitive constraint does not extend to the pure judgement of taste itself. 'The thought that nature has produced that beauty must accompany the intuition and reflection, and on this alone is grounded the immediate interest that one takes in it. Otherwise there remains ... a mere judgement of taste without any interest . . .' (5: 299)
  • 39
    • 79956636745 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This paper is dedicated to my friend Béla Szabados. Thanks to Glenn Parsons for comments on an earlier version
    • This paper is dedicated to my friend Béla Szabados. Thanks to Glenn Parsons for comments on an earlier version


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.