메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 59, Issue 2, 2001, Pages 153-165

Participatory art and appreciative practice

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 61049107433     PISSN: 00218529     EISSN: 15406245     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/0021-8529.00015     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (14)

References (26)
  • 2
    • 0037892517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Disputes About Art
    • How we identify artifacts as works of art is a problem that I cannot address here. I have done so elsewhere. See my "Disputes About Art," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 54 (1996): 153-163. In the present context, all that we need notice is that were someone to claim of the Abbey that it is a work of art, there would be much that would count in favor of the claim, and very little that could count against it: architecture is an art form, and buildings often are regarded as works of art
    • (1996) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.54 , pp. 153-163
  • 3
    • 0012136755 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge and Kegan Paul
    • Arnold Hauser, The Social History of Art, vol. 2 (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1968)
    • (1968) The Social History of Art , vol.2
    • Hauser, A.1
  • 4
    • 79956676742 scopus 로고
    • University of Chicago Press chap. 5, especially pp. 284ff.
    • Arnold Hauser, The Sociology of Art (University of Chicago Press, 1982), chap. 5, especially pp. 284ff
    • (1982) The Sociology of Art
    • Hauser, A.1
  • 6
    • 79953940207 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paintings and Their Places
    • For a range of related observations, see Susan L. Feagin, "Paintings and Their Places," in Art and Its Messages: Meaning, Morality, and Society, ed. Stephen Davies (Pennsylvania State University Press, 1997), pp. 17-25
    • (1997) Art and Its Messages: Meaning, Morality, and Society , pp. 17-25
    • Feagin, S.L.1
  • 8
    • 61049365368 scopus 로고
    • his Robust Relativism
    • It might be argued that in interpreting and so appreciating a work of art, the viewer in some sense completes it. This has often been argued by Joseph Margolis. See his "Robust Relativism," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 35 (1976): 37-46
    • (1976) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.35 , pp. 37-46
    • Margolis, J.1
  • 13
    • 0004341760 scopus 로고
    • I have responded to claims of this sort in, Temple University Press, chap. 5
    • I have responded to claims of this sort in Knowledge, Fiction and Imagination (Temple University Press, 1987), chap. 5
    • (1987) Knowledge, Fiction and Imagination
  • 14
    • 60949316369 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Interpretation and Justification
    • and in "Interpretation and Justification," Metaphilosophy 31 (2000):4-24
    • (2000) Metaphilosophy , vol.31 , pp. 4-24
  • 15
    • 61949399358 scopus 로고
    • Disputes About Art
    • Whether or not it does make sense depends on the adequacy of functional accounts of art. While I cannot argue the case here, see my "Disputes About Art," as well as Robert Stecker, "Historical Functionalism or the Four Factor Theory," The British Journal of Aesthetics 34 (1994): 255-265
    • (1994) The British Journal of Aesthetics , vol.34 , pp. 255-265
  • 16
    • 79953967169 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Los Angeles, November 15 through February 21, 1999
    • Exhibited as part of the Charles Ray Retrospective, Museum of Contemporary Art, Los Angeles, November 15, 1998 through February 21, 1999
    • (1998) Museum of Contemporary Art
    • Retrospective, C.R.1
  • 17
    • 79954152546 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On this, see my "Disputes About Art," pp. 159-162
    • Disputes About Art , pp. 159-162
  • 18
    • 61049450601 scopus 로고
    • Art, Practice, and Narrative
    • See, as well, Noël Carroll, "Art, Practice, and Narrative," Monist 71 (1988): 140-156
    • (1988) Monist , vol.71 , pp. 140-156
    • Carroll, N.1
  • 19
    • 0001995839 scopus 로고
    • Historical Narratives and the Philosophy of Art
    • and "Historical Narratives and the Philosophy of Art," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 51 (1993): 313-326
    • (1993) The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.51 , pp. 313-326
  • 21
    • 79953375522 scopus 로고
    • Defining Art Historically, reprinted in Music
    • Cornell University Press
    • Jerrold Levinson, "Defining Art Historically," reprinted in Music, Art and Metaphysics (Cornell University Press, 1991), pp. 3-25
    • (1991) Art and Metaphysics , pp. 3-25
    • Levinson, J.1
  • 22
    • 84963456789 scopus 로고
    • Messages 'In' and Messages 'Through' Art
    • See my "Messages 'In' and Messages 'Through' Art," The Australasian Journal of Philosophy 73 (1995): 199-203
    • (1995) The Australasian Journal of Philosophy , vol.73 , pp. 199-203
  • 23
    • 0442283328 scopus 로고
    • Temple University Press chap. 10
    • For a defense of the distinction between rational and seductive persuasion, see my The Boundaries of Art (Temple University Press, 1992), chap. 10
    • (1992) The Boundaries of Art
  • 24
    • 0442330350 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Anaesthetics of Emotion
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press especially pp. 251-254
    • For more on the tensions here described between forms of appreciation, see my discussion of the critical paradox in "The Anaesthetics of Emotion" in Emotion and the Arts, ed. M. Hjort and S. Laver (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997), pp. 246-262, especially pp. 251-254
    • (1997) Emotion and the Arts , pp. 246-262
    • Hjort1    S. Laver, M.2
  • 26
    • 79954201216 scopus 로고
    • The Trouble With Truth
    • See, as well, my "The Trouble With Truth," Philosophy and Literature 19 (1995): 350-359
    • (1995) Philosophy and Literature , vol.19 , pp. 350-359


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.