-
4
-
-
0007313107
-
-
New York: Haven, Reprinted Evanston, IL: Chicago Spectrum Press, 1997, p. 12
-
The Art Circle: A Theory of Art (New York: Haven, 1984). Reprinted (Evanston, IL: Chicago Spectrum Press, 1997), p. 12
-
(1984)
The Art Circle: A Theory of Art
-
-
-
5
-
-
80054512825
-
The germ of institutionalism is introduced in Defining Art
-
The germ of institutionalism is introduced in "Defining Art," American Philosophical Quarterly 5 (1969): 252-258
-
(1969)
American Philosophical Quarterly
, vol.5
, pp. 252-258
-
-
-
6
-
-
1642376646
-
The Institutional Theory of Art
-
For the remark about never having promised to play according to the original rules, see Dickie, "The Institutional Theory of Art" in Theories of Art Today, ed. Noël Carroll (University of Wisconsin Press, 2000), pp. 103-104
-
(2000)
Theories of Art Today
, pp. 103-104
-
-
Dickie1
-
9
-
-
79956597989
-
-
I have altered the order. Dickie's list runs: artist, work of art, public, artworld system, and the artworld. I am indebted to Barbara Scholz's essay, "Rescuing the Institutional Theory of Art: Implicit Definitions and Folk Aesthetics," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 52 (1994): 309-325, for the idea of rearranging the definitions
-
(1994)
The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism
, vol.52
, pp. 309-325
-
-
-
10
-
-
80054546368
-
-
For Dickie's explanation of why he organizes the list as he does, see "The Institutional Theory of Art," pp. 100-101
-
The Institutional Theory of Art
, pp. 100-101
-
-
-
12
-
-
0004046295
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press, sec. 7
-
See J. L. Austin, Sense and Sensibilia (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1962), sec. 7
-
(1962)
Sense and Sensibilia
-
-
Austin, J.L.1
-
13
-
-
85022876184
-
-
Dickie is explicit on this point. He says, for example, "If art is the sort of thing I think it is, the only correct account of it would have to be a circular account." The Art Circle, p. 78
-
The Art Circle
, pp. 78
-
-
-
14
-
-
80054546345
-
-
Dickie defends circularity, uninformativeness, and arbitrariness in The Art Circle, pp. 75-79. The considerations he offers seem to support the plausible view that answers to philosophical questions will be uninformative in a certain sort of way. It is interesting that many of Dickie's arguments in support of a circular account are compelling arguments against more descriptively rich accounts
-
Dickie defends circularity, uninformativeness, and arbitrariness in The Art Circle
, pp. 75-79
-
-
-
15
-
-
79956597989
-
Rescuing the Institutional Theory of Art: Implicit Definitions and Folk Aesthetics
-
I have not been able to find a contemporary philosopher who holds this view. Barbara Scholz's essay, "Rescuing the Institutional Theory of Art: Implicit Definitions and Folk Aesthetics," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 52 (1994): 309-325, looks like an example until one notices that on Scholz's understanding of implicit definition, implicit definitions are not sufficient to mark out what is being defined. In different circumstances, I would argue that R. J. Collingwood is a weak institutionalist in The Principles of Art (1938)
-
(1994)
The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism
, vol.52
, pp. 309-325
-
-
Scholz's essay, B.1
-
17
-
-
60949721567
-
-
Noël Carroll's remark that I quoted in the opening paragraph, that Dickie would be clearer if he gave up talking about defining "art," suggests that Carroll inclines to partial institutionalism. Robert Stecker also seems to endorse partial institutionalism in his essay, "Is It Reasonable to Attempt to Define Art?" in Theories of Art Today, éd. Noël Carroll (University of Wisconsin Press, 2000), pp. 45-64
-
(2000)
Is It Reasonable to Attempt to Define Art? in Theories of Art Today
, pp. 45-64
-
-
Stecker, R.1
-
18
-
-
77049113244
-
The terminology belongs to Jeffery Wieand. See "Can There Be an Institutional Theory of Art?" The
-
The terminology belongs to Jeffery Wieand. See "Can There Be an Institutional Theory of Art?" The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 39 (1981): 409-117
-
(1981)
Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism
, vol.39
, pp. 409-117
-
-
-
20
-
-
84979111229
-
Dickie is thinking of two of Danto's essays in particular
-
Dickie is thinking of two of Danto's essays in particular. "Artworks and Real Things," Theoria 39 (1973): 1-17
-
(1973)
Artworks and Real Things, Theoria
, vol.39
, pp. 1-17
-
-
-
21
-
-
80054543382
-
-
ed. George Dickie and Richard J. Sclafani New York: St. Martins
-
Reprinted in Aesthetics: A Critical Anthology, ed. George Dickie and Richard J. Sclafani (New York: St. Martins, 1989), pp. 551-562
-
(1989)
Aesthetics: A Critical Anthology
, pp. 551-562
-
-
-
23
-
-
63149085041
-
The British Journal of Aesthetics
-
But see also "Art and Value," The British Journal of Aesthetics 40 (2000): 228-241, where Dickie concedes the point that this consideration is less than entirely compelling
-
(2000)
, vol.40
, pp. 228-241
-
-
Value1
-
24
-
-
80054583463
-
-
There is an interesting passage near the end of "Art and Value," in which Dickie acknowledges that in regular critical discourse about paintings, pieces of theater, and so on, nobody calls these items "art" except as extremely high praise. What is interesting is that he seems to see this as evidence for a classificatory sense of "art." See p. 236
-
this as evidence for a classificatory sense of art
, pp. 236
-
-
-
25
-
-
84960599280
-
Good and Evil
-
Peter Geach, "Good and Evil," Analysis 17 (1956): 103-112
-
(1956)
Analysis
, vol.17
, pp. 103-112
-
-
Geach, P.1
-
26
-
-
0001804148
-
-
ed. Philippa Foot Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Reprinted in Theories of Ethics, ed. Philippa Foot (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1967), pp. 64-73
-
(1967)
Theories of Ethics
, pp. 64-73
-
-
-
28
-
-
34347305616
-
Why 'Art' Doesn't Have Two Senses
-
For example, by M. W. Rowe, "Why 'Art' Doesn't Have Two Senses," The British Journal of Aesthetics 31 (1991): 214-221
-
(1991)
The British Journal of Aesthetics
, vol.31
, pp. 214-221
-
-
Rowe, M.W.1
-
29
-
-
61049204407
-
On Functional Definitions of Art: A Response to Rowe
-
See also Graham Oppy, "On Functional Definitions of Art: A Response to Rowe," The British Journal of Aesthetics 33 (1993): 67-71, for criticism of Rowe's tripartite division of nouns and subsequent argument by elimination
-
(1993)
The British Journal of Aesthetics
, vol.33
, pp. 67-71
-
-
Oppy, G.1
-
30
-
-
60949892256
-
Art' as a Cluster Concept
-
ed. Noël Carroll University of Wisconsin Press
-
Berys Gaut, "'Art' as a Cluster Concept," in Theories of Art Today, ed. Noël Carroll (University of Wisconsin Press, 2000), pp. 38-39
-
(2000)
Theories of Art Today
, pp. 38-39
-
-
Gaut, B.1
-
31
-
-
0007319947
-
The End of an Institutional Theory of Art
-
Dickie wonders whether the derivative "sense" is a genuine sense of "art" or is in fact metaphorical. Either way, the possibility that the classificatory sense straightforwardly and literally applies to cars and pieces of furniture is never considered. I am ignoring Dickie's remarks concerning an "evaluative" sense of "art" that is some sort of generic praise word applying as centrally to the Grand Canyon and sunsets as to The Polish Rider and Hamlet. As others have noticed, nothing in institutionalism implies that there must be any such sense of "art." See Robert Stecker, "The End of an Institutional Theory of Art," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 26 (1986): 124-132
-
(1986)
The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism
, vol.26
, pp. 124-132
-
-
Stecker, R.1
-
32
-
-
60949721567
-
Is It Reasonable to Attempt to Define Art?
-
Thus, I would object to Robert Stecker's assumption that a definition of "art" is always aimed to explain how people actually use the term. For Stecker's view, see "Is It Reasonable to Attempt to Define Art?" in Theories of Art Today, ed. Noël Carroll (University of Wisconsin Press, 2000), pp. 45-64
-
(2000)
Theories of Art Today
, pp. 45-64
-
-
Carroll, N.1
-
33
-
-
77958404020
-
A Modest Proposal for Defining a Work of Art
-
and the very similar set of suggestions in Richard Kamber, "A Modest Proposal for Defining a Work of Art," The British Journal of Aesthetics 33 (1993): 313-320
-
(1993)
The British Journal of Aesthetics
, vol.33
, pp. 313-320
-
-
Kamber, R.1
-
35
-
-
84923278341
-
Reflections on One Idea of Collingwood's Aesthetics
-
See also "Reflections on One Idea of Collingwood's Aesthetics," Monist 72 (1982): 581-583
-
(1982)
Monist
, vol.72
, pp. 581-583
-
-
-
36
-
-
0037892517
-
makes some similar suggestions in Disputes about Art
-
David Novitz makes some similar suggestions in "Disputes about Art," The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 54 (1996): 153-164
-
(1996)
The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism
, vol.54
, pp. 153-164
-
-
Novitz, D.1
|