메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 83, Issue 6, 2008, Pages 1979-2012

Things better left unwritten?: Constitutional text and the rule of law

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 58649101591     PISSN: 00287881     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (5)

References (246)
  • 1
    • 84868885558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constitution worship is more than an analytical curiosity among academics and a rhetorical tool of politicians. See Max Lerner, Constitution and Court as Symbols, 46 YALE L.J. 1290, 1304 (1937, describing how the process of building the Constitutional legend involved participation of diverse groups and institutions-legal community, immigrant communities, schools, and popular media, In 1997, the National Constitution Center conducted a nationwide telephone survey on constitutional knowledge. National Constitution Center, Startling Lack of Constitutional Knowledge Revealed in First-Ever National Poll, http://72.32.50.200/CitizenAction/ CivicResearchResults/NCCNationalPoll/index.shtml last visited July 20, 2008, Out of one thousand respondents, National Constitution Center, Highlights of Survey, last visited July 20, 2008, ninety-one percent agreed tha
    • Constitution worship is more than an analytical curiosity among academics and a rhetorical tool of politicians. See Max Lerner, Constitution and Court as Symbols, 46 YALE L.J. 1290, 1304 (1937) (describing how "the process of building the Constitutional legend" involved participation of diverse groups and institutions-legal community, immigrant communities, schools, and popular media). In 1997, the National Constitution Center conducted a nationwide telephone survey on constitutional knowledge. National Constitution Center, Startling Lack of Constitutional Knowledge Revealed in First-Ever National Poll, http://72.32.50.200/CitizenAction/ CivicResearchResults/NCCNationalPoll/index.shtml (last visited July 20, 2008). Out of one thousand respondents, National Constitution Center, Highlights of Survey, http://72.32.50.200/CitizenAction/CivicResearchResults/NCCNationalPoll/ HighlightsofthePoll.shtml (last visited July 20, 2008), ninety-one percent agreed that "The US Constitution is important to me," eighty-nine percent agreed that "I am proud of the US Constitution," and seventy-seven percent disagreed that "The Constitution doesn't matter much in my daily life." National Constitution Center, NCC Constitution Poll Statistics, http://72.32.50.200/CitizenAction/CivicResearchResults/ NCCNationalPoll/TheAnswers.shtml (last visited July 20, 2008).
  • 2
    • 58649092990 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lerner, supra note 1, at 1295-96 (The rhetoric of national unity marked the beginning of Constitution worship. The people rejoiced that the disunity of the Confederation had been turned into the unity of the Constitution.).
    • See Lerner, supra note 1, at 1295-96 ("The rhetoric of national unity marked the beginning of Constitution worship. The people rejoiced that the disunity of the Confederation had been turned into the unity of the Constitution.").
  • 3
    • 58649095625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Steven G. Calabresi, The Tradition of the Written Constitution: Text, Precedent, and Burke, 57 ALA. L. REV. 635, 639 (2006) ([I]t is evident from even a cursory awareness of American culture that we have a tradition in the United States of venerating the written Constitution.);
    • See Steven G. Calabresi, The Tradition of the Written Constitution: Text, Precedent, and Burke, 57 ALA. L. REV. 635, 639 (2006) ("[I]t is evident from even a cursory awareness of American culture that we have a tradition in the United States of venerating the written Constitution.");
  • 4
    • 58649097409 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lerner, supra note 1, at 1298-99 (The American was the first written national Constitution. . . . The very definiteness with which the design for a government was set down in words on parchment was enough to command admiration and then reverence.);
    • Lerner, supra note 1, at 1298-99 ("The American was the first written national Constitution. . . . The very definiteness with which the design for a government was set down in words on parchment was enough to command admiration and then reverence.");
  • 5
    • 58649091893 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Michael J. Perry, The Authority of Text, Tradition, and Reason: A Theory of Constitutional 'Interpretation,' 58 S. CAL. L. REV. 551, 557 (1985) (noting [t]he importance attached, not merely in judicial practice but in American political-legal culture generally, to the 'writtenness' of the Constitution: the text is accorded authoritative status).
    • Michael J. Perry, The Authority of Text, Tradition, and Reason: A Theory of Constitutional 'Interpretation,' 58 S. CAL. L. REV. 551, 557 (1985) (noting "[t]he importance attached, not merely in judicial practice but in American political-legal culture generally, to the 'writtenness' of the Constitution: the text is accorded authoritative status").
  • 6
    • 58649087916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lerner, supra note 1, at 1299 (What was wanted was a visible symbol of the things that men hold dear.);
    • See Lerner, supra note 1, at 1299 ("What was wanted was a visible symbol of the things that men hold dear.");
  • 7
    • 58649108877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sanford Levinson, The Constitution in American Civil Religion, 1979 SUP. CT. REV. 123, 123-24 (referring to Constitution as the sacred document of America's civil religion).
    • Sanford Levinson, "The Constitution" in American Civil Religion, 1979 SUP. CT. REV. 123, 123-24 (referring to Constitution as "the sacred document" of America's "civil religion").
  • 9
    • 58649108649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander Hamilton alluded to the written nature of the proposed Constitution in those terms when he was urging his countrymen to ratify it. See THE FEDERALIST NO. 1, at 33 Alexander Hamilton, Clinton Rossiter ed, 1961, arguing that Americans had opportunity to be first nation to establish, good government from reflection and choice, instead of being] forever destined to depend for their political constitutions on accident and force, During the Founding Era, the Supreme Court adopted a similar attitude toward writtenness
    • Alexander Hamilton alluded to the written nature of the proposed Constitution in those terms when he was urging his countrymen to ratify it. See THE FEDERALIST NO. 1, at 33 (Alexander Hamilton) (Clinton Rossiter ed., 1961) (arguing that Americans had opportunity to be first nation to "establish[] good government from reflection and choice, [instead of being] forever destined to depend for their political constitutions on accident and force"). During the Founding Era, the Supreme Court adopted a similar attitude toward writtenness.
  • 10
    • 58649084500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137, 178 (1803) (noting that written constitutions have [been] deemed the greatest improvement on political institutions and have been viewed with so much reverence). Generations of Justices since Marbury have linked writtenness to assorted constitutional functions.
    • See Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137, 178 (1803) (noting that written constitutions "have [been] deemed the greatest improvement on political institutions" and "have been viewed with so much reverence"). Generations of Justices since Marbury have linked writtenness to assorted constitutional functions.
  • 11
    • 58649094322 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g.. United States v. Morrison, 529 U.S. 598, 616 (2000) (limiting government authority); Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 901 (1992) (plurality opinion) (embodying enduring societal values);
    • See, e.g.. United States v. Morrison, 529 U.S. 598, 616 (2000) (limiting government authority); Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 901 (1992) (plurality opinion) (embodying enduring societal values);
  • 12
    • 58649116150 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • United States v. Salerno, 481 U.S. 739, 761 (1987) (Marshall, J., dissenting) (protecting individual rights);
    • United States v. Salerno, 481 U.S. 739, 761 (1987) (Marshall, J., dissenting) (protecting individual rights);
  • 13
    • 58649114854 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Boddie v. Connecticut, 401 U.S. 371, 393 (1971) (Black, J., dissenting) (ensuring certainty and stability of law).
    • Boddie v. Connecticut, 401 U.S. 371, 393 (1971) (Black, J., dissenting) (ensuring certainty and stability of law).
  • 14
    • 58649105904 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But cf. Perez v. Brownell, 356 U.S. 44, 79 (1958) (Douglas, J., dissenting) (accepting writtenness as important positive aspect of Constitution without passing normative judgment).
    • But cf. Perez v. Brownell, 356 U.S. 44, 79 (1958) (Douglas, J., dissenting) (accepting writtenness as important positive aspect of Constitution without passing normative judgment).
  • 15
    • 58649109088 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Barak Cohen, Empowering Constitutionalism with Text from an Israeli Perspective, 18 AM. U. INT'L L. REV. 585, 586 (2003) (cursorily defining a constitution's 'written-ness' as its unique character as a written document);
    • See, e.g., Barak Cohen, Empowering Constitutionalism with Text from an Israeli Perspective, 18 AM. U. INT'L L. REV. 585, 586 (2003) (cursorily defining "a constitution's 'written-ness'" as "its unique character as a written document");
  • 16
    • 58649123011 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Martin Edelman, Written Constitutions, Democracy and Judicial Interpretation: The Hobgoblin of Judicial Activism, 68 ALB. L. REV. 585, 586 & n.4 (2005) (Only five member states of the United Nations [Bhutan, Israel, San Marino, Saudi Arabia, and the United Kingdom] have never promulgated a formal, integrated written constitution.). As I explain in Part I, this approach is too superficial to be considered an adequate definition of writtenness.
    • Martin Edelman, Written Constitutions, Democracy and Judicial Interpretation: The Hobgoblin of Judicial Activism, 68 ALB. L. REV. 585, 586 & n.4 (2005) ("Only five member states of the United Nations [Bhutan, Israel, San Marino, Saudi Arabia, and the United Kingdom] have never promulgated a formal, integrated written constitution."). As I explain in Part I, this approach is too superficial to be considered an adequate definition of writtenness.
  • 17
    • 58649089707 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, Paul Roth asserts that New Zealand lacks a written constitution because it has no law that is entrenched and to which all other statute law is inferior. His failure to justify why entrenchment is characteristic of a written constitution in the first place renders suspect his subsequent arguments on the differences between written and unwritten constitutions. Paul Roth, Captive Audience Speech Under New Zealand Law, 29 COMP. LAB. L. & POL'Y J. 147, 157 & n.28 (2008).
    • For example, Paul Roth asserts that New Zealand lacks a written constitution because it has no law that is entrenched and "to which all other statute law is inferior." His failure to justify why entrenchment is characteristic of a written constitution in the first place renders suspect his subsequent arguments on the differences between written and unwritten constitutions. Paul Roth, Captive Audience Speech Under New Zealand Law, 29 COMP. LAB. L. & POL'Y J. 147, 157 & n.28 (2008).
  • 18
    • 58649092978 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Such arguments have been made by scholars on both sides of the Atlantic. In his recent book on English public law, Adam Tomkins contends that the written/unwritten distinction is purely formalistic and thus irrelevant. See ADAM TOMKINS, PUBLIC LAW 9 (2003) (The distinction between written and unwritten constitutions is one of form, not of substance. ... No substantive consequences flow from the fact that the constitution is unwritten.). Tomkins also argues that the distinction is inaccurate, since all so-called written constitutions contain certain unwritten elements and vice versa.
    • Such arguments have been made by scholars on both sides of the Atlantic. In his recent book on English public law, Adam Tomkins contends that the written/unwritten distinction is purely formalistic and thus irrelevant. See ADAM TOMKINS, PUBLIC LAW 9 (2003) ("The distinction between written and unwritten constitutions is one of form, not of substance. ... No substantive consequences flow from the fact that the constitution is unwritten."). Tomkins also argues that the distinction is inaccurate, since all so-called written constitutions contain certain unwritten elements and vice versa.
  • 20
    • 33845613607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Rivka Weill, Evolution vs. Revolution: Dueling Models of Dualism, 54 AM. J. COMP. L. 429, 462 2006, To remain a living document, every written constitution must evolve over time. Thus, even written constitutions are usually supplemented with unwritten ones, Finally, David Strauss points to the similarities between the actual functioning of the U.S. written constitution and the U.K. unwritten constitution to argue that the distinction does not matter, at least among mature constitutional regimes with strong constitutional traditions
    • See Rivka Weill, Evolution vs. Revolution: Dueling Models of Dualism, 54 AM. J. COMP. L. 429, 462 (2006) ("To remain a living document, every written constitution must evolve over time. Thus, even written constitutions are usually supplemented with unwritten ones."). Finally, David Strauss points to the similarities between the actual functioning of the U.S. written constitution and the U.K. unwritten constitution to argue that the distinction does not matter, at least among mature constitutional regimes with strong constitutional traditions.
  • 21
    • 0347419824 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Common Law Constitutional Interpretation, 63
    • David A. Strauss, Common Law Constitutional Interpretation, 63 U. CHI. L. REV. 877, 924 (1996).
    • (1996) U. CHI. L. REV , vol.877 , pp. 924
    • Strauss, D.A.1
  • 22
    • 58649099508 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I use the term conceptual ideal to refer to a definition of writtenness that addresses the strengths and weaknesses of both positions in the extant literature. See infra Part I.A.
    • I use the term "conceptual ideal" to refer to a definition of writtenness that addresses the strengths and weaknesses of both positions in the extant literature. See infra Part I.A.
  • 23
    • 34548243816 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 53 and accompanying text. Indeed, the three national constitutions today widely recognized as being unwritten all belong to common law countries
    • See infra note 53 and accompanying text. Indeed, the three national constitutions today widely recognized as being unwritten all belong to common law countries.
    • See infra
  • 24
    • 84888467546 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 17
    • See infra note 17.
    • See infra
  • 25
    • 58649109716 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, liberal democracy itself is not an easy term to define. Frank Cunningham, The Socialist Retrieval of Liberal Democracy, 11 INT'L POL. SCI. REV. 99, 100 1990, Still, headway can be made by attending to the values by reference to which actual [liberal-democratic] activities and institutions, are justified. These values include, freedom, equality, and democracy, plus a stance on their relative weights
    • Of course, "liberal democracy" itself is not an easy term to define. Frank Cunningham, The Socialist Retrieval of Liberal Democracy, 11 INT'L POL. SCI. REV. 99, 100 (1990). Still, "headway can be made by attending to the values by reference to which actual [liberal-democratic] activities and institutions ... are justified. These values include ... freedom, equality, and democracy, plus a stance on their relative weights."
  • 26
    • 58649084253 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 27
    • 58649106551 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Eric Barendt distinguishes between liberal constitutions and what he calls nominal constitutions, which are simply maps of political power, describing the powers of particular persons and institutions. ERIC BARENDT, AN INTRODUCTION TO CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 6 (1998).
    • Eric Barendt distinguishes between liberal constitutions and what he calls "nominal constitutions," which are "simply maps of political power, describing the powers of particular persons and institutions." ERIC BARENDT, AN INTRODUCTION TO CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 6 (1998).
  • 28
    • 58649109478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., THE OXFORD ENGLISH DICTIONARY 639 (2d ed. 1989) (defining written as to form (letters, words, etc.) by hand on paper).
    • See, e.g., THE OXFORD ENGLISH DICTIONARY 639 (2d ed. 1989) (defining "written" as "to form (letters, words, etc.) by hand on paper").
  • 29
    • 58649117878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 7 n.4 ([T]he phrases ['written' and 'unwritten constitutions'] are terms of art and are not to be construed literally.).
    • See TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 7 n.4 ("[T]he phrases ['written' and 'unwritten constitutions'] are terms of art and are not to be construed literally.").
  • 30
    • 58649103428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, the issue of determining what law is constitutional is not always clear-cut. See JEREMY WALDRON, LAW AND DISAGREEMENT 256 1999, Often the decisions which determine the shape of a society's constitution are entangled with or woven into the fabric of ordinary political life, Even in the United States where there is a full written constitution and an established tradition of interpreting it, an event which has fundamental significance for the basis on which political life is conducted may not advertise itself as 'constitutional., This Note views constitutional law as constitutive law-that is, legal provisions that create, organize, direct, and limit government power
    • Of course, the issue of determining what law is " constitutional" is not always clear-cut. See JEREMY WALDRON, LAW AND DISAGREEMENT 256 (1999) ("Often the decisions which determine the shape of a society's constitution are entangled with or woven into the fabric of ordinary political life.... Even in the United States where there is a full written constitution and an established tradition of interpreting it, an event which has fundamental significance for the basis on which political life is conducted may not advertise itself as 'constitutional.'"). This Note views constitutional law as constitutive law-that is, legal provisions that create, organize, direct, and limit government power.
  • 31
    • 58649121848 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 275
    • Id. at 275.
  • 32
    • 58649106778 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • While no definitive categorization of constitutions exists, the three countries most widely recognized today as having unwritten constitutions are Israel, New Zealand, and the United Kingdom. E.g, Maria Dakolias, Are We There Yet, Measuring Success of Constitutional Reform, 39 VAND. J. TRANSNAT'L L. 1117, 1118 2006
    • While no definitive categorization of constitutions exists, the three countries most widely recognized today as having unwritten constitutions are Israel, New Zealand, and the United Kingdom. E.g., Maria Dakolias, Are We There Yet?: Measuring Success of Constitutional Reform, 39 VAND. J. TRANSNAT'L L. 1117, 1118 (2006).
  • 33
    • 58649107251 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See RODNEY BRAZIER, CONSTTTUTIONAL PRACTICE: THE FOUNDATIONS OF BRITISH GOVERNMENT 3 (3d ed. 1999) ([T]he whole system of British central government is based on practice, not law[, and] requires a detailed consideration of 'rules' [such as] the powers of the Sovereign, the existence of and relationships between the Prime Minister and the Cabinet... and the appointment and disciplining of the judiciary.);
    • See RODNEY BRAZIER, CONSTTTUTIONAL PRACTICE: THE FOUNDATIONS OF BRITISH GOVERNMENT 3 (3d ed. 1999) ("[T]he whole system of British central government is based on practice, not law[, and] requires a detailed consideration of 'rules' [such as] the powers of the Sovereign, the existence of and relationships between the Prime Minister and the Cabinet... and the appointment and disciplining of the judiciary.");
  • 34
    • 58649087900 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MICHAEL FOLEY, THE POLITICS OF THE BRTTISH CONSTITUTION 1 (1999) (describing conventional view of British constitutionalism as a summation of political experience expressed through forms, processes, traditions and developments, and substantiated by longevity, continuity, assimilation and adaptation);
    • MICHAEL FOLEY, THE POLITICS OF THE BRTTISH CONSTITUTION 1 (1999) (describing conventional view of British constitutionalism as "a summation of political experience expressed through forms, processes, traditions and developments, and substantiated by longevity, continuity, assimilation and adaptation");
  • 35
    • 58649089915 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Anthony Bradley, The Sovereignty of Parliament - Form or Substance?, in THE CHANGING CONSTITUTION 26, 32 (Jeffrey Jowell & Dawn Oliver eds., 5th ed. 2004) (quoting Sir John Salmond's comment that in United Kingdom [t]he constitution as a matter of fact is logically prior to the constitution as a matter of law, meaning that constitutional practice is logically prior to constitutional law). Constitutional practice as constitutional law is reflected in the centrality of constitutional conventions to the U.K. constitution. Broadly speaking, constitutional conventions are nonlegal rules that impose obligations and confer rights upon constitutional actors.
    • Anthony Bradley, The Sovereignty of Parliament - Form or Substance?, in THE CHANGING CONSTITUTION 26, 32 (Jeffrey Jowell & Dawn Oliver eds., 5th ed. 2004) (quoting Sir John Salmond's comment that in United Kingdom "[t]he constitution as a matter of fact is logically prior to the constitution as a matter of law," meaning that "constitutional practice is logically prior to constitutional law"). Constitutional practice as constitutional law is reflected in the centrality of constitutional conventions to the U.K. constitution. Broadly speaking, constitutional conventions are nonlegal rules that impose obligations and confer rights upon constitutional actors.
  • 36
    • 58649107533 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GEOFFREY MARSHALL, CONSTITUTIONAL CONVENTIONS: THE RULES AND FORMS OF POLITICAL ACCOUNTABILITY 7 (1984). They are not judicially enforceable, although courts may take notice of them to help clarify what the existing law is.
    • GEOFFREY MARSHALL, CONSTITUTIONAL CONVENTIONS: THE RULES AND FORMS OF POLITICAL ACCOUNTABILITY 7 (1984). They are not judicially enforceable, although courts may take notice of them to help clarify what the existing law is.
  • 38
    • 58649100344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 6, they are a prime example of how U.K. constitutional law is determined by how political actors conduct themselves in practice.
    • id. at 6, they are a prime example of how U.K. constitutional law is determined by how political actors conduct themselves in practice.
  • 39
    • 58649104317 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, the structure of the U.K. constitution, in terms of the legal relationship between the different branches of government, is secured by the statutory Bill of Rights and Act of Settlement. TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 45. Similarly, New Zealand's constitution includes a Constitution Act that establishes a framework of government and a Bill of Rights Act to guard against the infringement of rights.
    • For example, the structure of the U.K. constitution, in terms of the legal relationship between the different branches of government, is secured by the statutory Bill of Rights and Act of Settlement. TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 45. Similarly, New Zealand's constitution includes a Constitution Act that establishes a framework of government and a Bill of Rights Act to guard against the infringement of rights.
  • 40
    • 58649093641 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Geoffrey Palmer, The New Zealand Constitution and the Power of Courts, 15 TRANSNAT'L L. & CONTEMP. PROBS. 551, 558, 567 (2006).
    • Geoffrey Palmer, The New Zealand Constitution and the Power of Courts, 15 TRANSNAT'L L. & CONTEMP. PROBS. 551, 558, 567 (2006).
  • 41
    • 58649092738 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BLACK'S LAW DICTIONARY 273-74, 275 (8th ed. 2004) (defining codification as [t]he process of compiling, arranging, and systematizing ... a discrete branch of the law, into an ordered code, and defining code as [a] complete system of positive law, carefully arranged and officially promulgated; a systematic collection or revision of laws, rules, or regulations);
    • See BLACK'S LAW DICTIONARY 273-74, 275 (8th ed. 2004) (defining "codification" as "[t]he process of compiling, arranging, and systematizing ... a discrete branch of the law, into an ordered code," and defining "code" as "[a] complete system of positive law, carefully arranged and officially promulgated; a systematic collection or revision of laws, rules, or regulations");
  • 42
    • 58649124414 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Jeremy Waldron, Judicial Power and Popular Sovereignty, in MARBURY VERSUS MADISON: DOCUMENTS AND COMMENTARY 181, 190 (Mark A. Graber & Michael Perhac eds., 2002) (pointing out that importance of writtenness of Constitution for Chief Justice Marshall in Marbury v. Madison was not just a matter of the people having kept a written record of how they proposed to govern themselves, but of their having chosen a mode of exercise of popular sovereignty that is deliberately law-like in form).
    • see also Jeremy Waldron, Judicial Power and Popular Sovereignty, in MARBURY VERSUS MADISON: DOCUMENTS AND COMMENTARY 181, 190 (Mark A. Graber & Michael Perhac eds., 2002) (pointing out that importance of writtenness of Constitution for Chief Justice Marshall in Marbury v. Madison was not "just a matter of the people having kept a written record of how they proposed to govern themselves," but of "their having chosen a mode of exercise of popular sovereignty that is deliberately law-like in form").
  • 43
    • 58649087492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BLACK'S LAW DICTIONARY, supra note 20, at 273-74 (defining code as [a] complete system of positive law (emphasis added)).
    • See BLACK'S LAW DICTIONARY, supra note 20, at 273-74 (defining "code" as "[a] complete system of positive law" (emphasis added)).
  • 44
    • 58649124415 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See McCulloch v. Maryland, 17 U.S. (4 Wheat.) 316, 407 (1819) (A constitution, to contain an accurate detail of all the subdivisions of which its great powers will admit, and of all the means by which they may be carried into execution, would partake of the prolixity of a legal code, and could scarcely be embraced by the human mind.).
    • See McCulloch v. Maryland, 17 U.S. (4 Wheat.) 316, 407 (1819) ("A constitution, to contain an accurate detail of all the subdivisions of which its great powers will admit, and of all the means by which they may be carried into execution, would partake of the prolixity of a legal code, and could scarcely be embraced by the human mind.").
  • 45
    • 58649113528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Ronald Dworkin, Comment, in A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION: FEDERAL COURTS AND THE LAW 115, 126 (Amy Gutmann ed., 1997)
    • But see Ronald Dworkin, Comment, in A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION: FEDERAL COURTS AND THE LAW 115, 126 (Amy Gutmann ed., 1997)
  • 46
    • 58649111845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [hereinafter A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION] (calling U.S. Constitution the most fundamental American statute of them all).
    • [hereinafter A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION] (calling U.S. Constitution "the most fundamental American statute of them all").
  • 47
    • 58649110940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., CASS R. SUNSTEIN, DESIGNING DEMOCRACY: WHAT CONSTITUTIONS DO 6 (2001) ([T]he central goal of a constitution is to create the preconditions for a well-functioning democratic order . . . .).
    • See, e.g., CASS R. SUNSTEIN, DESIGNING DEMOCRACY: WHAT CONSTITUTIONS DO 6 (2001) ("[T]he central goal of a constitution is to create the preconditions for a well-functioning democratic order . . . .").
  • 48
    • 58649098882 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 9 (Constitutional questions, which change over time, are too varied and too unpredictable for any single legal instrument to be capable of answering them all. Even countries with written or codified constitutions need to supplement those codes with unwritten, or more likely uncodified, rules.).
    • See TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 9 ("Constitutional questions, which change over time, are too varied and too unpredictable for any single legal instrument to be capable of answering them all. Even countries with written or codified constitutions need to supplement those codes with unwritten, or more likely uncodified, rules.").
  • 49
    • 58649093424 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See McCulloch, 17 U.S. (4 Wheat.) at 407 (stating that nature of Constitution requires, that only its great outlines should be marked, its important objects designated, and the minor ingredients which compose those objects, be deduced from the nature of the objects themselves). The distinction I see between core and subsidiary constitutional principles draws upon H.L.A. Hart's concept of the rule of recognition: A principle is subsidiary if it relies for its authority upon an antecedent constitutional principle.
    • See McCulloch, 17 U.S. (4 Wheat.) at 407 (stating that nature of Constitution "requires, that only its great outlines should be marked, its important objects designated, and the minor ingredients which compose those objects, be deduced from the nature of the objects themselves"). The distinction I see between core and subsidiary constitutional principles draws upon H.L.A. Hart's concept of the rule of recognition: A principle is subsidiary if it relies for its authority upon an antecedent constitutional principle.
  • 50
    • 58649098433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 102-04 (1975)
    • See H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 102-04 (1975)
  • 51
    • 58649124211 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (arguing that every legal system contains ultimate rule of recognition at its foundation which provides criteria by which validity of other rules of system can be assessed). For example, the Miranda warnings that must be given to a defendant prior to any custodial interrogation are a subsidiary constitutional principle, formulated by the U.S. Supreme Court in Miranda v. Arizona, 384 U.S. 436 (1966), that is drawn from the core constitutional principle prohibiting unreasonable searches and seizures codified in the Fourth Amendment, U.S. CONST, amend. IV.
    • (arguing that every legal system contains ultimate rule of recognition at its foundation which provides criteria by which validity of other rules of system can be assessed). For example, the Miranda warnings that must be given to a defendant prior to any custodial interrogation are a subsidiary constitutional principle, formulated by the U.S. Supreme Court in Miranda v. Arizona, 384 U.S. 436 (1966), that is drawn from the core constitutional principle prohibiting unreasonable searches and seizures codified in the Fourth Amendment, U.S. CONST, amend. IV.
  • 52
    • 58649120948 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A useful analogy would be to the Uniform Commercial Code (U.C.C.) in American law, which was promulgated to provide a stable and predictable [legal] framework for the business community, and which has since been enacted in whole or in part in all fifty states, as well as in the District of Columbia, the Virgin Islands, and Puerto Rico. Gunther A. Weiss, The Enchantment of Codification in the Common-Law World, 25 YALE J. INT'L L. 435, 520-21 (2000). The U.C.C is a collection of common law principles of commercial law, presented in the form of a code, that is accepted as legally binding by the jurisdictions that have adopted it. Whereas scholars debate whether or not the U.C.C. qualifies as a codification,
    • A useful analogy would be to the Uniform Commercial Code (U.C.C.) in American law, which was promulgated to "provide a stable and predictable [legal] framework for the business community," and which has since "been enacted in whole or in part in all fifty states, as well as in the District of Columbia, the Virgin Islands, and Puerto Rico." Gunther A. Weiss, The Enchantment of Codification in the Common-Law World, 25 YALE J. INT'L L. 435, 520-21 (2000). The U.C.C is a collection of common law principles of commercial law, presented in the form of a code, that is accepted as legally binding by the jurisdictions that have adopted it. Whereas scholars debate whether or not the U.C.C. qualifies as a codification,
  • 54
    • 58649104102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The United States appears to be no exception. Scholars have argued that the United States does in fact have an unwritten constitution in the form of unwritten texts (of precedent, social ideals, and the like, that] supplement [or even] supplant the written document as the exclusive object of constitutional interpretation. Michael S. Moore, Do We Have an Unwritten Constitution, 63 S. CAL. L. REV. 107, 115 (1989, emphasis omitted, Tom Grey's seminal piece on the unwritten U.S. Constitution argues that many of our most fundamental contemporary constitutional principles, such as the right to privacy (which includes the right to an abortion) or the prohibition against racial segregation, cannot be justified through a strict textual interpretation of the Constitution
    • The United States appears to be no exception. Scholars have argued that the United States does in fact have an unwritten constitution in the form of "unwritten texts (of precedent, social ideals, and the like) [that] supplement [or even] supplant the written document as the exclusive object of constitutional interpretation." Michael S. Moore, Do We Have an Unwritten Constitution?, 63 S. CAL. L. REV. 107, 115 (1989) (emphasis omitted). Tom Grey's seminal piece on the unwritten U.S. Constitution argues that many of our most fundamental contemporary constitutional principles, such as the right to privacy (which includes the right to an abortion) or the prohibition against racial segregation, cannot be justified through a strict textual interpretation of the Constitution.
  • 55
    • 58649094553 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thomas C. Grey, Do We Have an Unwritten Constitution?, 27 STAN. L. REV. 703, 708-09, 711-13 (1975).
    • Thomas C. Grey, Do We Have an Unwritten Constitution?, 27 STAN. L. REV. 703, 708-09, 711-13 (1975).
  • 56
    • 58649100790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Hudson v. Palmer, 468 U.S. 517, 556 (1984) (Stevens, J., dissenting) (noting that written constitution enshrine[s] as principles of fundamental law beyond the reach of governmental officials or legislative majorities).
    • See, e.g., Hudson v. Palmer, 468 U.S. 517, 556 (1984) (Stevens, J., dissenting) (noting that written constitution "enshrine[s] as principles of fundamental law beyond the reach of governmental officials or legislative majorities").
  • 57
    • 58649108871 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • James Madison highlighted the distinction between the U.S. and U.K. constitutions in this respect: The important distinction so well understood in America between a Constitution established by the people and unalterable by the government, and a law established by the government and alterable by the government, seems to have been little understood and less observed in any other country, Even in Great Britain, where the principles of political and civil liberty have been most discussed, and where we hear most of the rights of the Constitution, it is maintained that the authority of the Parliament is transcendent and uncontrollable as well with regard to the Constitution as the ordinary objects of legislative provision. THE FEDERALIST NO. 53, at 331 James Madison, Clinton Rossiter ed, 1961
    • James Madison highlighted the distinction between the U.S. and U.K. constitutions in this respect: The important distinction so well understood in America between a Constitution established by the people and unalterable by the government, and a law established by the government and alterable by the government, seems to have been little understood and less observed in any other country.... Even in Great Britain, where the principles of political and civil liberty have been most discussed, and where we hear most of the rights of the Constitution, it is maintained that the authority of the Parliament is transcendent and uncontrollable as well with regard to the Constitution as the ordinary objects of legislative provision. THE FEDERALIST NO. 53, at 331 (James Madison) (Clinton Rossiter ed., 1961).
  • 58
    • 58649083585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Beyond concerns of finality, it is inherent in the nature of a constitution to provide for its own amendment, at least insofar as the process of amending a society's constitution is regarded as constitutive of that society's political and legal system. See WALDRON, supra note 16, at 260-61 (arguing that constitutional provisions may be viewed as constitutive procedural rules that establish framework within which society acts).
    • Beyond concerns of finality, it is inherent in the nature of a constitution to provide for its own amendment, at least insofar as the process of amending a society's constitution is regarded as constitutive of that society's political and legal system. See WALDRON, supra note 16, at 260-61 (arguing that constitutional provisions may be viewed as constitutive procedural rules that establish framework within which society acts).
  • 59
    • 58649116590 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If this is not the case in a given constitution, the constitution would merely be an initiating statute that is thoroughly 'inside' the ordinary political order, as opposed to a constitution that in some ways [is] supposed to stand 'above' and in some sense even 'outside' the everyday system of ordinary political decisionmaking. Sanford Levinson, The Political Implications of Amending Clauses, 13 CONST. COMMENT. 107, 107-08 (1996).
    • If this is not the case in a given constitution, the constitution would merely be "an initiating statute that is thoroughly 'inside' the ordinary political order," as opposed to a constitution that "in some ways [is] supposed to stand 'above' and in some sense even 'outside' the everyday system of ordinary political decisionmaking." Sanford Levinson, The Political Implications of Amending Clauses, 13 CONST. COMMENT. 107, 107-08 (1996).
  • 60
    • 58649093872 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137, 177 (1803).
    • Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137, 177 (1803).
  • 61
    • 58649113127 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The authority that establishes the constitution of a society can be accepted by that society as supreme on any number of grounds. In the United States, the Constitution was founded upon the theory of popular sovereignty. See id. at 176 That the people have an original right to establish, for their future government, such principles as, in their opinion, shall most conduce to their own happiness, is the basis, on which the whole American fabric has been erected, Thus, the Constitution was only established when it was ratified by the people
    • The authority that establishes the constitution of a society can be accepted by that society as "supreme" on any number of grounds. In the United States, the Constitution was founded upon the theory of popular sovereignty. See id. at 176 ("That the people have an original right to establish, for their future government, such principles as, in their opinion, shall most conduce to their own happiness, is the basis, on which the whole American fabric has been erected."). Thus, the Constitution was only established when it was ratified by the people.
  • 62
    • 58649107995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See THE FEDERALIST NO. 49, at 313-14 (James Madison) (Clinton Rossiter ed., 1961) ([T]he people are the only legitimate fountain of power, and it is from them that the constitutional charter, under which the several branches of government hold their power, is derived . . . .). For Commonwealth countries such as Canada and Australia, the supreme authority was the British Parliament legislating from across the ocean.
    • See THE FEDERALIST NO. 49, at 313-14 (James Madison) (Clinton Rossiter ed., 1961) ("[T]he people are the only legitimate fountain of power, and it is from them that the constitutional charter, under which the several branches of government hold their power, is derived . . . ."). For Commonwealth countries such as Canada and Australia, the supreme authority was the British Parliament legislating from across the ocean.
  • 63
    • 58649087050 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LESLIE ZINES, CONSTITUTIONAL CHANGE IN THE COMMONWEALTH 3 (1991).
    • LESLIE ZINES, CONSTITUTIONAL CHANGE IN THE COMMONWEALTH 3 (1991).
  • 64
    • 58649087287 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, New Zealand considers its unwritten constitution to be composed of legislation, judicial decisions, treaties, royal prerogative powers, and constitutional conventions. Kenneth Keith, On the Constitution of New Zealand: An Introduction to the Foundations of the Current Form of Government, in CABINET MANUAL (Cabinet Office, Dep't of the Prime Minister and Cabinet ed., 2008), available at http://www.dpmc.govt.nz/ cabinet/manual/intro.html.
    • For example, New Zealand considers its unwritten constitution to be composed of legislation, judicial decisions, treaties, royal prerogative powers, and constitutional conventions. Kenneth Keith, On the Constitution of New Zealand: An Introduction to the Foundations of the Current Form of Government, in CABINET MANUAL (Cabinet Office, Dep't of the Prime Minister and Cabinet ed., 2008), available at http://www.dpmc.govt.nz/ cabinet/manual/intro.html.
  • 65
    • 58649086633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Marbury, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) at 176.
    • Marbury, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) at 176.
  • 66
    • 58649090787 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Change would become more viable if the constitutional amendment process were no different from the ordinary legislative process. However, given that a constitution originally derives its legitimacy from the particular process by which it was enacted, it can be argued that any legitimate constitutional change must at the very least keep with the spirit of the enactment process, which presumably involved greater societal consensus than the laws passed regularly by the legislature. Furthermore, the foundational nature of constitutional law itself counsels against subjecting constitutional principles to speedy and/or frequent change. See Mark Tushnet, The Whole Thing, 12 CONST. COMMENT. 223,225 1995, Perhaps some degree of institutional stability is required for a system to warrant the name constitutional, which suggests that it should not be too easy to amend all of a constitution's provisions, or perhaps any of its basic institutional prescr
    • Change would become more viable if the constitutional amendment process were no different from the ordinary legislative process. However, given that a constitution originally derives its legitimacy from the particular process by which it was enacted, it can be argued that any legitimate constitutional change must at the very least keep with the spirit of the enactment process, which presumably involved greater societal consensus than the laws passed regularly by the legislature. Furthermore, the foundational nature of constitutional law itself counsels against subjecting constitutional principles to speedy and/or frequent change. See Mark Tushnet, The Whole Thing, 12 CONST. COMMENT. 223,225 (1995) ("Perhaps some degree of institutional stability is required for a system to warrant the name constitutional, which suggests that it should not be too easy to amend all of a constitution's provisions, or perhaps any of its basic institutional prescriptions.").
  • 67
    • 58649122997 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Marbury, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) at 176 (emphasis added).
    • Marbury, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) at 176 (emphasis added).
  • 68
    • 58649109265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 69
    • 58649102167 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This term, coined by Alexander Bickel, encapsulates the problem posed in a democratic society when unelected judges overturn decisions made by the representative branches of government. ALEXANDER M. BICKEL, THE LEAST DANGEROUS BRANCH: THE SUPREME COURT AT THE BAR OF POLITICS 16-17 (1962);
    • This term - coined by Alexander Bickel - encapsulates the problem posed in a democratic society when unelected judges overturn decisions made by the representative branches of government. ALEXANDER M. BICKEL, THE LEAST DANGEROUS BRANCH: THE SUPREME COURT AT THE BAR OF POLITICS 16-17 (1962);
  • 70
    • 58649094543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see abo Barry Friedman, Dialogue and Judicial Review, 91 MICH. L. REV. 577, 586-90 (1993) (discussing how legal scholarship has defined problem of countermajoritarian difficulty).
    • see abo Barry Friedman, Dialogue and Judicial Review, 91 MICH. L. REV. 577, 586-90 (1993) (discussing how legal scholarship has defined problem of countermajoritarian difficulty).
  • 71
    • 6944253570 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paying the Alligator: Precommitment in Law, Bioethics and Constitutions, 81
    • For an overview of the academic literature on precommitment in constitutional law, see generally
    • For an overview of the academic literature on precommitment in constitutional law, see generally John A. Robertson, "Paying the Alligator": Precommitment in Law, Bioethics and Constitutions, 81 TEX. L. REV. 1729 (2003).
    • (2003) TEX. L. REV , vol.1729
    • Robertson, J.A.1
  • 72
    • 58649084724 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stephen Holmes, Precommitment and the Paradox of Democracy, in CONSTITUTION-ALISM AND DEMOCRACY 195-96 (Jon Elster & Rune Slagstad eds., 1988);
    • Stephen Holmes, Precommitment and the Paradox of Democracy, in CONSTITUTION-ALISM AND DEMOCRACY 195-96 (Jon Elster & Rune Slagstad eds., 1988);
  • 73
    • 58649090149 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also SUNSTEIN, supra note 23, at 241 ([Democratic constitutions [are] 'precommitment strategies[]' in which nations, aware of problems that are likely to arise, take steps to ensure that those problems will not arise or that they will produce minimal damage if they do.).
    • see also SUNSTEIN, supra note 23, at 241 ("[Democratic constitutions [are] 'precommitment strategies[]' in which nations, aware of problems that are likely to arise, take steps to ensure that those problems will not arise or that they will produce minimal damage if they do.").
  • 74
    • 58649116373 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WALDRON, supra note 16, at 260
    • WALDRON, supra note 16, at 260.
  • 75
    • 33846607590 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at, criticizing facile invocation of precommitment argument as support for judicial review
    • But see id. at 262-71 (criticizing facile invocation of precommitment argument as support for judicial review).
    • But see id , pp. 262-271
  • 76
    • 58649117023 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Marbury, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) at 177.
    • Marbury, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) at 177.
  • 77
    • 58649090788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 18 (A constitutional distinction which is of rather more significance than the [written/unwritten] distinction ... is that between political and legal constitutions.).
    • See TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 18 ("A constitutional distinction which is of rather more significance than the [written/unwritten] distinction ... is that between political and legal constitutions.").
  • 78
    • 58649124856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 18-19
    • Id. at 18-19.
  • 79
    • 58649109905 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Marbury, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) at 177 (holding that it is judiciary's responsibility to say what the law is).
    • Marbury, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) at 177 (holding that it is judiciary's responsibility to "say what the law is").
  • 80
    • 58649090993 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part I.B.
    • See supra Part I.B.
  • 81
    • 58649115506 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 901 (1992) (Our Constitution is a covenant running from the first generation of Americans to us and then to future generations.... We accept our responsibility not to retreat from interpreting the full meaning of the covenant....). Such a characterization of the courts was welcomed by James Madison when he introduced the Bill of Rights in Congress.
    • See, e.g., Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 901 (1992) ("Our Constitution is a covenant running from the first generation of Americans to us and then to future generations.... We accept our responsibility not to retreat from interpreting the full meaning of the covenant...."). Such a characterization of the courts was welcomed by James Madison when he introduced the Bill of Rights in Congress.
  • 82
    • 58649084922 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 1 ANNALS OF CONG. 439 (1789) (If [the first ten amendments] are incorporated into the Constitution, independent tribunals of justice will consider themselves in a peculiar manner the guardians of those rights; they will be an impenetrable bulwark against every assumption of power in the Legislative or Executive....);
    • See 1 ANNALS OF CONG. 439 (1789) ("If [the first ten amendments] are incorporated into the Constitution, independent tribunals of justice will consider themselves in a peculiar manner the guardians of those rights; they will be an impenetrable bulwark against every assumption of power in the Legislative or Executive....");
  • 83
    • 58649096467 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Lerner, supra note 1, at 1308 (From Marshall through Taney, and increasingly after the Civil War, the Supreme Court offered to guard exclusively the charter of fundamental liberties.).
    • see also Lerner, supra note 1, at 1308 ("From Marshall through Taney, and increasingly after the Civil War, the Supreme Court offered to guard exclusively the charter of fundamental liberties.").
  • 84
    • 58649102586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lerner, supra note 1, at 1309 ([J]udges have been associated in our minds with the function of protection rather than with the struggle for power. This has been of enormous importance. It has conscripted to the service of the judicial symbol all the accumulated Anglo-Saxon tradition of the 'rule of law.' ).
    • See Lerner, supra note 1, at 1309 ("[J]udges have been associated in our minds with the function of protection rather than with the struggle for power. This has been of enormous importance. It has conscripted to the service of the judicial symbol all the accumulated Anglo-Saxon tradition of the 'rule of law.' ").
  • 85
    • 58649115287 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Bd. of Regents of State Colls, v. Roth, 408 U.S. 564, 579 (1972) ([I]t is a written Constitution that we apply. Our role is confined to interpretation of that Constitution.).
    • See, e.g., Bd. of Regents of State Colls, v. Roth, 408 U.S. 564, 579 (1972) ("[I]t is a written Constitution that we apply. Our role is confined to interpretation of that Constitution.").
  • 86
    • 58649101518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Lerner, supra note 1, at 1293 (Since the Supreme Court is popularly considered as exercising a guardianship over the Constitution, the result has been to invest the judges of the Court with all the panoply of sanctity with which the Constitution has itself been invested.).
    • See, e.g., Lerner, supra note 1, at 1293 ("Since the Supreme Court is popularly considered as exercising a guardianship over the Constitution, the result has been to invest the judges of the Court with all the panoply of sanctity with which the Constitution has itself been invested.").
  • 87
    • 58649109479 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The 2000 U.S. presidential election provides perhaps the most striking example of the fact and implications of constitutional judicial supremacy in America. The race was widely contested and the electoral votes that Florida held tipped the balance. After the Florida Elections Canvassing Commission declared Republican candidate George W. Bush to be the winner by less than one-half of one percent of the votes cast, Democratic candidate Al Gore contested the certification in court. Bush v. Gore, 531 U.S. 98, 101 (2000) (per curiam). Gore requested a manual recount of 9000 votes in Miami-Dade County on which the voting machines had failed to detect a vote for President ( undervotes). Id. at 102. The Supreme Court struck down such manual recounts as unconstitutional,
    • The 2000 U.S. presidential election provides perhaps the most striking example of the fact and implications of constitutional judicial supremacy in America. The race was widely contested and the electoral votes that Florida held tipped the balance. After the Florida Elections Canvassing Commission declared Republican candidate George W. Bush to be the winner by less than one-half of one percent of the votes cast, Democratic candidate Al Gore contested the certification in court. Bush v. Gore, 531 U.S. 98, 101 (2000) (per curiam). Gore requested a manual recount of 9000 votes in Miami-Dade County on which the voting machines had failed to detect a vote for President (" undervotes"). Id. at 102. The Supreme Court struck down such manual recounts as unconstitutional,
  • 89
    • 0036110759 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jeremy Waldron, Is the Rule of Law an Essentially Contested Concept (in Florida)?, 21 LAW & PHIL. 137, 137-38 (2002). There were certainly objections from other quarters, and even outrage.
    • Jeremy Waldron, Is the Rule of Law an Essentially Contested Concept (in Florida)?, 21 LAW & PHIL. 137, 137-38 (2002). There were certainly objections from other quarters, and even outrage.
  • 90
    • 58649114181 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 138 ([M]any others thought that the best they could do for the Rule of Law was to condemn the decision in Bush v. Gore . . . .). Significantly, the word of the Court stood and Bush went on to serve as President for two terms.
    • See id. at 138 ("[M]any others thought that the best they could do for the Rule of Law was to condemn the decision in Bush v. Gore . . . ."). Significantly, the word of the Court stood and Bush went on to serve as President for two terms.
  • 91
    • 58649107534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BARENDT, supra note 13, at 33 (drawing connection between U.K. constitution's being uncodified and its description as common law constitution).
    • See BARENDT, supra note 13, at 33 (drawing connection between U.K. constitution's being uncodified and its description as common law constitution).
  • 92
    • 58649104785 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 103
    • TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 103.
  • 93
    • 58649099726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BARENDT, supra note 13, at 33 (noting that common law constitutional principles may be reformulated by statutes). Any objection that this sounds, in the analogous American legal context, as if political branches are disregarding constitutional rules laid down by the courts fails to recognize that an unwritten constitution b politics, in the sense that the content of the constitution is determined by ongoing political practices and developments.
    • See BARENDT, supra note 13, at 33 (noting that common law constitutional principles may be "reformulated by statutes"). Any objection that this sounds, in the analogous American legal context, as if political branches are disregarding constitutional rules laid down by the courts fails to recognize that an unwritten constitution b politics, in the sense that the content of the constitution is determined by ongoing political practices and developments.
  • 94
    • 58649098434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 18 and accompanying text. Thus, in effect, what the legislature does in such situations is announce a new constitutional rule that is controlling until amended or repealed. Of course, legislative constitutional change may also be stymied by politics, for instance where public disapproval of proposed reforms causes the government to back down
    • See supra note 18 and accompanying text. Thus, in effect, what the legislature does in such situations is announce a new constitutional rule that is controlling until amended or repealed. Of course, legislative constitutional change may also be stymied by politics, for instance where public disapproval of proposed reforms causes the government to back down.
  • 95
    • 84888467546 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 60
    • See infra note 60.
    • See infra
  • 96
    • 58649121393 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 104
    • TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 104.
  • 97
    • 58649112481 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 21-23
    • Id. at 21-23.
  • 98
    • 58649101963 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 21, 23-24.
    • Id. at 21, 23-24.
  • 99
    • 58649091629 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Dakolias, supra note 17, at 1164 ([The United Kingdom's] entry into the European Union ... required [it] to comply with [European Directives] and harmonize its legislation and required the judiciary to determine compliance of such legislation.);
    • See Dakolias, supra note 17, at 1164 ("[The United Kingdom's] entry into the European Union ... required [it] to comply with [European Directives] and harmonize its legislation and required the judiciary to determine compliance of such legislation.");
  • 100
    • 58649113321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constantine Theophilopoulos, The Influence of American and English Law on the Interpretation of the South African Right to Silence and the Privilege Against Self-incrimination, 19 TEMP. INT'L & COMP. L.J. 387, 396 (2005) (England, with its proud heritage of an unwritten constitution, has introduced the Human Rights Act of 1998, which incorporates the principles of the European Convention into domestic English law.).
    • Constantine Theophilopoulos, The Influence of American and English Law on the Interpretation of the South African Right to Silence and the Privilege Against Self-incrimination, 19 TEMP. INT'L & COMP. L.J. 387, 396 (2005) ("England, with its proud heritage of an unwritten constitution, has introduced the Human Rights Act of 1998, which incorporates the principles of the European Convention into domestic English law.").
  • 101
    • 58649090992 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FOLEY, supra note 18, at 250-51. The U.K. Chief Justice, Lord Woolf, has described the constitutional changes undertaken by the administration under Prime Minister Tony Blair as a torrent, which included the removal of the hereditary peers from the House of Lords, devolution, the incorporation into domestic law of the European Convention on Human Rights and the creation of a unified courts administration. Lord Woolf, The Lord Chief Justice of England & Wales, Squire Centenary Lecture: The Rule of Law and a Change in the Constitution (Mar. 3, 2004), available at http://www.law.cam.ac.uk/docs/view.php?doc=1415 [hereinafter Squire Centenary Lecture]. While there is general popular support for constitutional reform,
    • FOLEY, supra note 18, at 250-51. The U.K. Chief Justice, Lord Woolf, has described the constitutional changes undertaken by the administration under Prime Minister Tony Blair as a "torrent," which included "the removal of the hereditary peers from the House of Lords, devolution, the incorporation into domestic law of the European Convention on Human Rights and the creation of a unified courts administration." Lord Woolf, The Lord Chief Justice of England & Wales, Squire Centenary Lecture: The Rule of Law and a Change in the Constitution (Mar. 3, 2004), available at http://www.law.cam.ac.uk/docs/view.php?doc=1415 [hereinafter Squire Centenary Lecture]. While there is general popular support for constitutional reform,
  • 102
    • 58649108446 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FOLEY, supra note 18, at 256-57, not all of the Blair administration's plans for codification met with approval or acceptance. For example, its attempt in 2003 to unilaterally abolish the longstanding post of Lord Chancellor and create a Supreme Court of the United Kingdom was fiercely criticized on various grounds-the sudden and apparently arbitrary nature of the decision; the failure to consult other branches of government, especially the judiciary; and the disregard for constitutional history and precedent.
    • FOLEY, supra note 18, at 256-57, not all of the Blair administration's plans for codification met with approval or acceptance. For example, its attempt in 2003 to unilaterally abolish the longstanding post of Lord Chancellor and create a Supreme Court of the United Kingdom was fiercely criticized on various grounds-the sudden and apparently arbitrary nature of the decision; the failure to consult other branches of government, especially the judiciary; and the disregard for constitutional history and precedent.
  • 103
    • 85023146121 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lord Woolf, Constitutional Developments in a Common-Law Jurisdiction, 37 ISR. L. REV. 5, 9, 10-11 (2003). Strong opposition from the judiciary and the House of Lords, combined with media scrutiny, forced the government to back down.
    • See Lord Woolf, Constitutional Developments in a Common-Law Jurisdiction, 37 ISR. L. REV. 5, 9, 10-11 (2003). Strong opposition from the judiciary and the House of Lords, combined with media scrutiny, forced the government to back down.
  • 104
    • 58649094306 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. The bill that narrowly passed Parliament in March 2005 reformed the office of Lord Chancellor instead of removing it altogether, made formal guarantees about the rule of law and continued judicial independence, and gave the senior judiciary the right to select its own members to the supreme court.
    • Id. The bill that narrowly passed Parliament in March 2005 reformed the office of Lord Chancellor instead of removing it altogether, made formal guarantees about the rule of law and continued judicial independence, and gave the senior judiciary the right to select its own members to the supreme court.
  • 105
    • 84868870473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Constitutional Reform Act, 2005, c. 4, §§ 14-15, scheds. 3-4 (U.K.) (providing for transfer of functions to and from Lord Chancellor);
    • See Constitutional Reform Act, 2005, c. 4, §§ 14-15, scheds. 3-4 (U.K.) (providing for transfer of functions to and from Lord Chancellor);
  • 106
    • 84868885568 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. §§ 1, 3-4 (guaranteeing rule of law and judicial independence);
    • id. §§ 1, 3-4 (guaranteeing rule of law and judicial independence);
  • 108
    • 58649116137 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In March 2008, Brown announced a draft Constitution Renewal Bill containing proposals to, inter alia, strengthen Parliament and restrict the role of the attorney general. Easy Does It, ECONOMIST, Mar. 29, 2008, at 42 noting Brown's long-standing enthusiasm for reform while suggesting that his proposals appeared timid
    • In March 2008, Brown announced a draft Constitution Renewal Bill containing proposals to, inter alia, strengthen Parliament and restrict the role of the attorney general. Easy Does It, ECONOMIST, Mar. 29, 2008, at 42 (noting Brown's "long-standing enthusiasm" for reform while suggesting that his proposals appeared "timid").
  • 109
    • 0042440459 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Rule of Law as a Concept in Constitutional Discourse, 97
    • analyzing competing ideals of rule of law used in constitutional discourse, See generally
    • See generally Richard H. Fallon, Jr., "The Rule of Law" as a Concept in Constitutional Discourse, 97 COLUM. L. REV. 1 (1997) (analyzing competing ideals of rule of law used in constitutional discourse).
    • (1997) COLUM. L. REV , vol.1
    • Fallon Jr., R.H.1
  • 110
    • 58649097837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See JOSEPH RAZ, THE AUTHORITY OF LAW: ESSAYS ON LAW AND MORALITY 212 (1979) (Taken in its broadest sense [the rule of law] means that people should obey the law and be ruled by it. But in political and legal theory it has come to be read [as saying] that the government shall be ruled by the law and subject to it.).
    • See JOSEPH RAZ, THE AUTHORITY OF LAW: ESSAYS ON LAW AND MORALITY 212 (1979) ("Taken in its broadest sense [the rule of law] means that people should obey the law and be ruled by it. But in political and legal theory it has come to be read [as saying] that the government shall be ruled by the law and subject to it.").
  • 111
    • 58649114412 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 214
    • Id. at 214.
  • 112
    • 58649114602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.;
    • Id.;
  • 113
    • 58649105225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see abo Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620, 633 (1996) (Central... to the idea of the rule of law . . . is the principle that government and each of its parts remain open on impartial terms to all who seek its assistance.).
    • see abo Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620, 633 (1996) ("Central... to the idea of the rule of law . . . is the principle that government and each of its parts remain open on impartial terms to all who seek its assistance.").
  • 114
    • 58649111377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • F.A. Hayek is perhaps the best known proponent of the argument that the rule of law promotes freedom because when we obey laws ... we are not subject to another man's will and are therefore free. F.A. HAYEK, THE CONSTITUTION OF LIBERTY 153 (1960). Joseph Raz clarifies that Hayek uses freedom to mean an effective ability to choose between as many options as possible, as opposed to what Raz calls political freedom.
    • F.A. Hayek is perhaps the best known proponent of the argument that the rule of law promotes freedom because "when we obey laws ... we are not subject to another man's will and are therefore free." F.A. HAYEK, THE CONSTITUTION OF LIBERTY 153 (1960). Joseph Raz clarifies that Hayek uses "freedom" to mean "an effective ability to choose between as many options as possible," as opposed to what Raz calls "political freedom."
  • 115
    • 58649121159 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RAZ, supra note 63, at 220
    • RAZ, supra note 63, at 220.
  • 116
    • 58649120616 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See RAZ, supra note 63, at 221 (arguing that rule of law respects human dignity by treating humans as persons capable of planning and plotting their future).
    • See RAZ, supra note 63, at 221 (arguing that rule of law respects human dignity by "treating humans as persons capable of planning and plotting their future").
  • 117
    • 58649106552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • My list of rule-of-law values, which is adopted from Joseph Raz's discussion in The Authority of Law, id. at 219-22, is not intended to be exhaustive. Raz points out that the values underlying the rule of law are in a sense negative because they all run to countering the evils of law-for example, the very existence of law as an institution creates the danger of infringement upon individual freedom because it allows for the government to regulate what people may or may not do, and so we require the rule of law as a safeguard against such a danger occurring.
    • My list of rule-of-law values, which is adopted from Joseph Raz's discussion in The Authority of Law, id. at 219-22, is not intended to be exhaustive. Raz points out that the values underlying the rule of law are in a
  • 118
    • 58649098435 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • it would theoretically be possible to identify additional rule-of-law values corresponding to various conceivable dangers arising from law itself. However, given space constraints, I focus upon the rule-of-law values responding to those recurring, fundamental concerns that have been expressed regarding the law and its reach
    • Id. at 212. From this perspective, it would theoretically be possible to identify additional rule-of-law values corresponding to various conceivable dangers arising from law itself. However, given space constraints, I focus upon the rule-of-law values responding to those recurring, fundamental concerns that have been expressed regarding the law and its reach.
    • at 212. From this perspective
  • 119
    • 58649091212 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Jeremy Bentham, Principles of the Civil Code, in THE THEORY OF LEGISLATION 88, 109, 111 (C.K. Ogden ed., 1931) (1802) (arguing that principal object of law is the care of security, which gives individuals the power of forming a general plan of conduct for their lives);
    • See, e.g., Jeremy Bentham, Principles of the Civil Code, in THE THEORY OF LEGISLATION 88, 109, 111 (C.K. Ogden ed., 1931) (1802) (arguing that "principal object of law" is "the care of security," which gives individuals "the power of forming a general plan of conduct" for their lives);
  • 120
    • 58649087493 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • William Blackstone, 1 COMMENTARIES *44-45 (noting permanent, uniform, and universal nature of law, which includes requirement that law must be notified to the people who are to obey it).
    • William Blackstone, 1 COMMENTARIES *44-45 (noting "permanent, uniform, and universal" nature of law, which includes requirement that law must "be notified to the people who are to obey it").
  • 121
    • 58649122077 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Goldberg v. Kelly, 397 U.S. 254, 277 (1970) (Black, J., dissenting) (A written constitution, designed to guarantee protection against governmental abuses, including those of judges, must have written standards that mean something definite and have an explicit content.);
    • See, e.g., Goldberg v. Kelly, 397 U.S. 254, 277 (1970) (Black, J., dissenting) ("A written constitution, designed to guarantee protection against governmental abuses, including those of judges, must have written standards that mean something definite and have an explicit content.");
  • 122
    • 58649092291 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Muller v. Oregon, 208 U.S. 412, 420 (1908) ([I]t is the peculiar value of a written constitution that it places in unchanging form limitations upon legislative action, and thus gives a permanence and stability to popular government which otherwise would be lacking.).
    • Muller v. Oregon, 208 U.S. 412, 420 (1908) ("[I]t is the peculiar value of a written constitution that it places in unchanging form limitations upon legislative action, and thus gives a permanence and stability to popular government which otherwise would be lacking.").
  • 123
    • 58649117242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra notes 73-75 and accompanying text for the distinction between principles of legality and substantive rule-of-law values. That Fuller's principles of legality provide a useful framework is not to say that they are definitive of the rule of law; rather, they are but one example of the rule-of-law laundry lists that scholars have come up with.
    • See infra notes 73-75 and accompanying text for the distinction between principles of legality and substantive rule-of-law values. That Fuller's principles of legality provide a useful framework is not to say that they are definitive of the rule of law; rather, they are but one example of the rule-of-law "laundry lists" that scholars have come up with.
  • 124
    • 58649085797 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., RAZ, supra note 63, at 214-18 (combining several of Fuller's principles with, inter alia, guarantee of independent judiciary and observance of principles of natural justice). I rely on Fuller's list for two reasons. First, proponents of the written constitution tend to argue in the same terms that Fuller does.
    • See, e.g., RAZ, supra note 63, at 214-18 (combining several of Fuller's principles with, inter alia, guarantee of independent judiciary and observance of "principles of natural justice"). I rely on Fuller's list for two reasons. First, proponents of the written constitution tend to argue in the same terms that Fuller does.
  • 125
    • 58649102365 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Boddie v. Connecticut, 401 U.S. 371, 393 (1971) (Black, J., dissenting) (arguing that written constitution is important because it provides certainty and security). Second, Fuller's principles are generally accepted as being necessary for the rule of law, even if critics go on to complain that Fuller draws the wrong conclusions from them.
    • See, e.g., Boddie v. Connecticut, 401 U.S. 371, 393 (1971) (Black, J., dissenting) (arguing that written constitution is important because it provides "certainty and security"). Second, Fuller's principles are generally accepted as being necessary for the rule of law, even if critics go on to complain that Fuller draws the wrong conclusions from them.
  • 126
    • 58649116801 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., H.L.A. Hart, Book Review, 78 HARV. L. REV. 1281, 1285-88 (1965)
    • See, e.g., H.L.A. Hart, Book Review, 78 HARV. L. REV. 1281, 1285-88 (1965)
  • 127
    • 58649119495 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (reviewing LON L. FULLER, THE MORALITY OF LAW (1964)) (accepting importance of principles of legality listed by Fuller but criticizing Fuller's classification of such principles as morality).
    • (reviewing LON L. FULLER, THE MORALITY OF LAW (1964)) (accepting importance of principles of legality listed by Fuller but criticizing Fuller's classification of such principles as "morality").
  • 128
    • 58649090570 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LON L. FULLER, THE MORALITY OF LAW 39 (2d ed. 1969). The principle of congruency is a special case that straddles both the formal and the substantive aspects of the rule of law - in effect, it requires that the government follow the rules and that it not behave arbitrarily.
    • LON L. FULLER, THE MORALITY OF LAW 39 (2d ed. 1969). The principle of congruency is a special case that straddles both the formal and the substantive aspects of the rule of law - in effect, it requires that the government follow the rules and that it not behave arbitrarily.
  • 129
    • 58649085158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 130
    • 58649105003 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fuller argued that [t]his body of laws [would be] subject to all the kinds of ship-wreck that can visit any other legal system if it failed to meet the principles of legality. Id. at 115.
    • Fuller argued that "[t]his body of laws [would be] subject to all the kinds of ship-wreck that can visit any other legal system" if it failed to meet the principles of legality. Id. at 115.
  • 131
    • 84868885570 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I use principles of legality as well as the complementary term rule-of-law values as terms of art. Principles of legality are specific formal requirements that laws must meet. Cf. U.S. CONST, art I, § 9, cl. 3 (enshrining principle of prospectivity by forbidding passage of ex post facto laws);
    • I use "principles of legality" as well as the complementary term "rule-of-law values" as terms of art. Principles of legality are specific formal requirements that laws must meet. Cf. U.S. CONST, art I, § 9, cl. 3 (enshrining principle of prospectivity by forbidding passage of ex post facto laws);
  • 132
    • 58649109717 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Grayned v. City of Rockford, 408 U.S. 104, 108 (1972) (recognizing principle of clarity by declaring that it is a basic principle of due process that an enactment is void for vagueness if its prohibitions are not clearly defined). Rule-of-law values refer to broader substantive objectives that a system of laws must accomplish, such as restraining the government from abusing its powers or providing a reliable basis for individual planning, in order for it to conform to the rule of law.
    • Grayned v. City of Rockford, 408 U.S. 104, 108 (1972) (recognizing principle of clarity by declaring that it is a "basic principle of due process that an enactment is void for vagueness if its prohibitions are not clearly defined"). Rule-of-law values refer to broader substantive objectives that a system of laws must accomplish, such as restraining the government from abusing its powers or providing a reliable basis for individual planning, in order for it to conform to the rule of law.
  • 133
    • 58649122998 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This becomes clear when we ask why we object to laws that are unclear or retroactive. It is not for the sake of clarity or prospectivity itself, but because a vague law or a law that applies retroactively violates rule-of-law values. Such a law not only contains the risk of arbitrary government action but also, by rendering it difficult if not impossible for individuals to plan their affairs, curtails personal freedom and disregards human dignity. See Grayned, 408 U.S. at 108-09 (noting that vague laws offend several important values because they fail to give the person of ordinary intelligence a reasonable opportunity to know what is prohibited, so that he may act accordingly and allow for arbitrary and discriminatory application);
    • This becomes clear when we ask why we object to laws that are unclear or retroactive. It is not for the sake of clarity or prospectivity itself, but because a vague law or a law that applies retroactively violates rule-of-law values. Such a law not only contains the risk of arbitrary government action but also, by rendering it difficult if not impossible for individuals to plan their affairs, curtails personal freedom and disregards human dignity. See Grayned, 408 U.S. at 108-09 (noting that vague laws "offend several important values" because they fail to "give the person of ordinary intelligence a reasonable opportunity to know what is prohibited, so that he may act accordingly" and allow for "arbitrary and discriminatory application");
  • 134
    • 58649089484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FULLER, supra note 70, at 59 (arguing that criminal retroactivity is so universally condemned . . . [because] the criminal law is most obviously and directly concerned with shaping and controlling human conduct).
    • FULLER, supra note 70, at 59 (arguing that criminal retroactivity is "so universally condemned . . . [because] the criminal law is most obviously and directly concerned with shaping and controlling human conduct").
  • 135
    • 58649123471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, like much else in the rule-of-law literature, this particular conception of the rule of law is open to challenge. One could take a strict formal approach and argue-as Fuller does-that adherence to the principles of legality is the rule of law. See Lon L. Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Law, A Reply to Professor Hart, 71 HARV. L. REV. 630, 645 1957, arguing that principles of legality constitute morality of order [that] must be respected before enactment can properly be called law, Three points are worth making in response. The first concerns Hart's criticism of Fuller's portrayal of the principles of legality as morality. Viewed in and of themselves, such principles are merely principles of good craftmanship, and] are independent of the law's substantive aims just as the principles of carpentry are independent of whether the carpenter is making hospital beds or torturers' racks
    • Of course, like much else in the rule-of-law literature, this particular conception of the rule of law is open to challenge. One could take a strict formal approach and argue-as Fuller does-that adherence to the principles of legality is the rule of law. See Lon L. Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Law - A Reply to Professor Hart, 71 HARV. L. REV. 630, 645 (1957) (arguing that principles of legality constitute "morality of order [that] must be respected" before enactment can properly be called law). Three points are worth making in response. The first concerns Hart's criticism of Fuller's portrayal of the principles of legality as "morality." Viewed in and of themselves, such principles are merely "principles of good craftmanship[,]... [and] are independent of the law's substantive aims just as the principles of carpentry are independent of whether the carpenter is making hospital beds or torturers' racks."
  • 136
    • 58649115064 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart, supra note 69, at 1284. Second, my characterization of the rule of law may in fact be viewed as being conceptually consistent with Fuller's. Fuller distinguishes between the internal morality of law, constituted by the principles of legality, and the law's external morality, a substantive concept that encompasses rule-of-law values such as those I have identified.
    • Hart, supra note 69, at 1284. Second, my characterization of the rule of law may in fact be viewed as being conceptually consistent with Fuller's. Fuller distinguishes between the "internal" morality of law, constituted by the principles of legality, and the law's "external" morality, a substantive concept that encompasses rule-of-law values such as those I have identified.
  • 137
    • 58649105665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Fuller, supra, at 644 (describing external morality of law as law that corresponds to the demands of justice, or morality, or men's notions of what ought to be). Indeed, his description of the relationship between the internal and external moralities of law as one of reciprocal[] influence, where a deterioration of the one will almost inevitably produce a deterioration in the other, is similar to the connections I have drawn between principles of legality and rule-of-law values.
    • See Fuller, supra, at 644 (describing external morality of law as "law that corresponds to the demands of justice, or morality, or men's notions of what ought to be"). Indeed, his description of the relationship between the internal and external moralities of law as one of "reciprocal[] influence," where "a deterioration of the one will almost inevitably produce a deterioration in the other," is similar to the connections I have drawn between principles of legality and rule-of-law values.
  • 138
    • 58649091876 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 645. If this is the case, the dispute becomes largely semantic, since it is nothing more than a question of which of these concepts one chooses to classify under rule of law, as opposed to some other heading. Finally, accepting that the rule of law is a purely formal concept would still not affect the viability of my arguments, since Parts III.A and III.B.1 make the point that a written constitution does a relatively poor job of meeting the requirements of formal legality as compared to an unwritten constitution. However, I think the argument that writtenness matters-for better or for worse-is strengthened by showing how it influences not only the formal characteristics of a society's constitution but also the political values that the society strives toward. Thus, my analysis draws the link between these two aspects of the rule of law
    • Id. at 645. If this is the case, the dispute becomes largely semantic, since it is nothing more than a question of which of these concepts one chooses to classify under "rule of law," as opposed to some other heading. Finally, accepting that the rule of law is a purely formal concept would still not affect the viability of my arguments, since Parts III.A and III.B.1 make the point that a written constitution does a relatively poor job of meeting the requirements of formal legality as compared to an unwritten constitution. However, I think the argument that writtenness matters-for better or for worse-is strengthened by showing how it influences not only the formal characteristics of a society's constitution but also the political values that the society strives toward. Thus, my analysis draws the link between these two aspects of the rule of law.
  • 139
    • 58649103226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The U.S. Supreme Court, for instance, has explicitly linked the written nature of the U.S. Constitution to the Court's final power of review over constitutional issues. See United States v. Morrison, 529 U.S. 598, 616 & n.7 (2000) (Under our written Constitution ... the limitation of congressional authority is not solely a matter of legislative grace.... No doubt the political branches have a role in interpreting and applying the Constitution, but ever since Marbury, this Court has remained the ultimate expositor of the constitutional text.).
    • The U.S. Supreme Court, for instance, has explicitly linked the written nature of the U.S. Constitution to the Court's final power of review over constitutional issues. See United States v. Morrison, 529 U.S. 598, 616 & n.7 (2000) ("Under our written Constitution ... the limitation of congressional authority is not solely a matter of legislative grace.... No doubt the political branches have a role in interpreting and applying the Constitution, but ever since Marbury, this Court has remained the ultimate expositor of the constitutional text.").
  • 140
    • 58649085161 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is also a threshold argument to be made that writtenness is simply ineffective-that judges are not constrained by the text when they make constitutional decisions. See Strauss, supra note 9, at 883 (Most of the time, in deciding a constitutional issue, the text plays only a nominal role. The issue is decided by reference to 'doctrine'-an elaborate structure of precedents built up over time by the courts-and to considerations of morality and public policy.).
    • There is also a threshold argument to be made that writtenness is simply ineffective-that judges are not constrained by the text when they make constitutional decisions. See Strauss, supra note 9, at 883 ("Most of the time, in deciding a constitutional issue, the text plays only a nominal role. The issue is decided by reference to 'doctrine'-an elaborate structure of precedents built up over time by the courts-and to considerations of morality and public policy.").
  • 141
    • 58649116802 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Burnet v. Coronado Oil & Gas Co., 285 U.S. 393, 406 (1932) (Brandeis, J., dissenting), overruled in part by Helvering v. Bankline Oil Co., 303 U.S. 362, 369 (1938) (Stare decbis is usually the wise policy, because in most matters it is more important that the applicable rule of law be settled than that it be settled right.);
    • See Burnet v. Coronado Oil & Gas Co., 285 U.S. 393, 406 (1932) (Brandeis, J., dissenting), overruled in part by Helvering v. Bankline Oil Co., 303 U.S. 362, 369 (1938) ("Stare decbis is usually the wise policy, because in most matters it is more important that the applicable rule of law be settled than that it be settled right.");
  • 142
    • 58649089918 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nat'l Bank v. Whitney, 103 U.S. 99, 102 (1880) (Judicial decisions affecting the business interests of the country should not be disturbed except for the most cogent reasons, certainly not because of subsequent doubts as to their soundness. The prosperity of a commercial community depends ... upon the stability of the rules by which its transactions are governed.);
    • Nat'l Bank v. Whitney, 103 U.S. 99, 102 (1880) ("Judicial decisions affecting the business interests of the country should not be disturbed except for the most cogent reasons, certainly not because of subsequent doubts as to their soundness. The prosperity of a commercial community depends ... upon the stability of the rules by which its transactions are governed.");
  • 143
    • 58649117879 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see abo HENRY M. HART, JR. & ALBERT M. SACKS, THE LEGAL PROCESS: BASIC PROBLEMS IN THE MAKING AND APPLICATION OF LAW 1-9 (William N. Eskridge, Jr. & Philip P. Frickey eds., 1994) (1958) (discussing importance of institutional settlement in organized society).
    • see abo HENRY M. HART, JR. & ALBERT M. SACKS, THE LEGAL PROCESS: BASIC PROBLEMS IN THE MAKING AND APPLICATION OF LAW 1-9 (William N. Eskridge, Jr. & Philip P. Frickey eds., 1994) (1958) (discussing importance of "institutional settlement" in organized society).
  • 144
    • 84868888623 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Patterson v. McLean Credit Union, 491 U.S. 164, 172 (1989), superseded by statute, Civil Rights Act of 1991, Pub. L. No. 102-166, § 101, 105 Stat. 1071, 1072,
    • See Patterson v. McLean Credit Union, 491 U.S. 164, 172 (1989), superseded by statute, Civil Rights Act of 1991, Pub. L. No. 102-166, § 101, 105 Stat. 1071, 1072,
  • 145
    • 58649110518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • as recognized in Jones v. R.R. Donnelley & Sons Co., 541 U.S. 369, 372-73 (2004)
    • as recognized in Jones v. R.R. Donnelley & Sons Co., 541 U.S. 369, 372-73 (2004)
  • 146
    • 58649096254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ([I]t is indisputable that stare decisis is a basic self-governing principle within the Judicial Branch, which is entrusted with the sensitive and difficult task of fashioning and preserving a jurisprudential system that is not based upon 'an arbitrary discretion.');
    • ("[I]t is indisputable that stare decisis is a basic self-governing principle within the Judicial Branch, which is entrusted with the sensitive and difficult task of fashioning and preserving a jurisprudential system that is not based upon 'an arbitrary discretion.'");
  • 147
    • 58649112700 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Welch v. Tex. Dep't of Highways and Pub. Transp., 483 U.S. 468, 478-79 (1987) (The rule of law depends in large part on adherence to the doctrine of stare decisis.).
    • see also Welch v. Tex. Dep't of Highways and Pub. Transp., 483 U.S. 468, 478-79 (1987) ("The rule of law depends in large part on adherence to the doctrine of stare decisis.").
  • 148
    • 58649106781 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Randall v. Sorrell, 548 U.S. 230, 244 (2006) (Stare decisis thereby avoids the instability and unfairness that accompany disruption of settled legal expectations. For this reason, the rule of law demands that adhering to our prior case law be the norm.);
    • See Randall v. Sorrell, 548 U.S. 230, 244 (2006) ("Stare decisis thereby avoids the instability and unfairness that accompany disruption of settled legal expectations. For this reason, the rule of law demands that adhering to our prior case law be the norm.");
  • 149
    • 58649084923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Vasquez v. Hillery, 474 U.S. 254, 265 (1986) (describing stare decisis as the means by which we ensure that the law will not merely change erratically, but will develop in a principled and intelligible fashion[, because it] permits society to presume that bedrock principles are founded in the law rather than in the proclivities of individuals).
    • Vasquez v. Hillery, 474 U.S. 254, 265 (1986) (describing stare decisis as "the means by which we ensure that the law will not merely change erratically, but will develop in a principled and intelligible fashion[, because it] permits society to presume that bedrock principles are founded in the law rather than in the proclivities of individuals").
  • 150
    • 58649116353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Nat'l Bank, 103 U.S. at 102 (If there should be a change, the legislature can make it with infinitely less derangement of those interests than would follow a new ruling of the court, for statutory regulations would operate only in the future.).
    • See Nat'l Bank, 103 U.S. at 102 ("If there should be a change, the legislature can make it with infinitely less derangement of those interests than would follow a new ruling of the court, for statutory regulations would operate only in the future.").
  • 151
    • 58649118321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Arizona v. Rumsey, 467 U.S. 203, 212 (1984) ([A]ny departure from the doctrine of stare decbb demands special justification.).
    • See Arizona v. Rumsey, 467 U.S. 203, 212 (1984) ("[A]ny departure from the doctrine of stare decbb demands special justification.").
  • 152
    • 58649107997 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is not to deny the possibility of either conflicting precedents or hairsplitting distinctions that in effect amount to contradictions. Of course, stare decisis would still encourage consistency overall: First, it bars openly contradictory opinions from being issued; second, higher courts are able to use stare decisis as a rationale to strike down lower court opinions that incorrectly interpret precedent
    • This is not to deny the possibility of either conflicting precedents or hairsplitting distinctions that in effect amount to contradictions. Of course, stare decisis would still encourage consistency overall: First, it bars openly contradictory opinions from being issued; second, higher courts are able to use stare decisis as a rationale to strike down lower court opinions that incorrectly interpret precedent.
  • 153
    • 58649083802 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Since stare decisis by definition requires a court to adhere to precedent because of its status as precedent, the doctrine sets a standard for change that demands more than mere inaccuracy of decision. For instance, the U.S. Supreme Court has set out four factors for a court to consider in deciding whether or not to overrule a prior decision: whether the rule is intolerable simply in defying practical workability, the nature and extent of any reliance on the rule, any related principles of law [that] have so far developed as to have left the old rule no more than a remnant of abandoned doctrine, and whether changes in facts or perception of facts have robbed the old rule of significant application or justification. Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 854-55 1992, plurality opinion
    • Since stare decisis by definition requires a court to adhere to precedent because of its status as precedent, the doctrine sets a standard for change that demands more than mere inaccuracy of decision. For instance, the U.S. Supreme Court has set out four factors for a court to consider in deciding whether or not to overrule a prior decision: whether the rule is "intolerable simply in defying practical workability," the nature and extent of any reliance on the rule, any "related principles of law [that] have so far developed as to have left the old rule no more than a remnant of abandoned doctrine," and whether changes in facts or perception of facts have "robbed the old rule of significant application or justification." Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 854-55 (1992) (plurality opinion).
  • 154
    • 58649105440 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part I.
    • See supra Part I.
  • 155
    • 0347936425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Frank H. Easterbrook, Alternatives to Originalism?, 19 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 479, 486 (1996) (Judicial review came from a theory of meaning that supposed the possibility of right answers-from an originalist theory rooted in text.).
    • See Frank H. Easterbrook, Alternatives to Originalism?, 19 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 479, 486 (1996) ("Judicial review came from a theory of meaning that supposed the possibility of right answers-from an originalist theory rooted in text.").
  • 156
    • 58649092086 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Patterson v. McLean Credit Union, 491 U.S. 164, 172-73 (1989) (Considerations of stare decisis have special force in the area of statutory interpretation, for here, unlike in the context of constitutional interpretation, the legislative power is implicated, and Congress remains free to alter what we have done.);
    • See Patterson v. McLean Credit Union, 491 U.S. 164, 172-73 (1989) ("Considerations of stare decisis have special force in the area of statutory interpretation, for here, unlike in the context of constitutional interpretation, the legislative power is implicated, and Congress remains free to alter what we have done.");
  • 157
    • 58649083584 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Burnet v. Coronado Oil & Gas Co., 285 U.S. 393, 406-07 (1932)
    • Burnet v. Coronado Oil & Gas Co., 285 U.S. 393, 406-07 (1932)
  • 158
    • 58649097600 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Brandeis, J., dissenting) (Stare decisis is usually the wise policy ... even where the error is a matter of serious concern, provided correction can be had by legislation. But in cases involving the Federal Constitution, where correction through legislative action is practically impossible, this Court has often overruled its earlier decisions.).
    • (Brandeis, J., dissenting) ("Stare decisis is usually the wise policy ... even where the error is a matter of serious concern, provided correction can be had by legislation. But in cases involving the Federal Constitution, where correction through legislative action is practically impossible, this Court has often overruled its earlier decisions.").
  • 159
    • 58649114603 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, the U.S. Supreme Court has consistently recognized that the doctrine of stare decisis holds less weight in constitutional cases. See, e.g., Casey, 505 U.S. at 854 ([I]t is common wisdom that the rule of stare decisis is not an 'inexorable command,' and certainly it is not such in every constitutional case . . . .);
    • Indeed, the U.S. Supreme Court has consistently recognized that the doctrine of stare decisis holds less weight in constitutional cases. See, e.g., Casey, 505 U.S. at 854 ("[I]t is common wisdom that the rule of stare decisis is not an 'inexorable command,' and certainly it is not such in every constitutional case . . . .");
  • 160
    • 58649093861 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Glidden Co. v. Zdanok, 370 U.S. 530, 543 (1962) ([T]his Court's considered practice [is] not to apply stare decisis as rigidly in constitutional as in nonconstitutional cases.).
    • Glidden Co. v. Zdanok, 370 U.S. 530, 543 (1962) ("[T]his Court's considered practice [is] not to apply stare decisis as rigidly in constitutional as in nonconstitutional cases.").
  • 161
    • 58649109480 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Dickerson v. United States, 530 U.S. 428, 461 (2000) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (objecting to Court writ[ing] a prophylactic, extraconstitutional Constitution, binding on Congress and the States).
    • See Dickerson v. United States, 530 U.S. 428, 461 (2000) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (objecting to Court "writ[ing] a prophylactic, extraconstitutional Constitution, binding on Congress and the States").
  • 162
    • 58649112068 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Applying a functional approach, one might deny altogether the utility of pure legal concepts such as due process or equal protection, and argue that explaining legal decisions in legal terms merely masks the actual motivations of courts in reaching their decisions. Felix S. Cohen, Transcendental Nonsense and the Functional Approach, 35 COLUM. L. REV. 809, 812-14 (1935).
    • Applying a functional approach, one might deny altogether the utility of pure legal concepts such as "due process" or "equal protection," and argue that explaining legal decisions in legal terms merely masks the actual motivations of courts in reaching their decisions. Felix S. Cohen, Transcendental Nonsense and the Functional Approach, 35 COLUM. L. REV. 809, 812-14 (1935).
  • 163
    • 58649084254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Justice Hugo Black authored many a dissent accusing the Supreme Court of doing just that. See, e.g., Rogers v. Bellei, 401 U.S. 815, 837 (1971) (Black, J., dissenting) (The Court today holds that Congress can . . . rob a citizen of his [Fourteenth Amendment] citizenship just so long as [a majority] can satisfy [itself] that the congressional action was not 'unreasonable [or] arbitrary,' 'misplaced or arbitrary,' or 'irrational or arbitrary or unfair,' .... [N]ot one of these 'tests' appears in the Constitution. (internal citations omitted));
    • Justice Hugo Black authored many a dissent accusing the Supreme Court of doing just that. See, e.g., Rogers v. Bellei, 401 U.S. 815, 837 (1971) (Black, J., dissenting) ("The Court today holds that Congress can . . . rob a citizen of his [Fourteenth Amendment] citizenship just so long as [a majority] can satisfy [itself] that the congressional action was not 'unreasonable [or] arbitrary,' 'misplaced or arbitrary,' or 'irrational or arbitrary or unfair,' .... [N]ot one of these 'tests' appears in the Constitution." (internal citations omitted));
  • 164
    • 58649119730 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Baldwin v. New York, 399 U.S. 66, 75 (1970) (Black, J., dissenting) ([The Framers] decided that the value of a jury trial far outweighed its costs for 'all crimes' and '(i)n all criminal prosecutions.'... I cannot agree that this Court can ... substitute its own judgment [that jury trial right is limited to serious crimes] for that embodied in the Constitution.). Black's argument in such opinions was that the Court acted arbitrarily in spite of the written Constitution; in contrast, I argue that the very presence of a constitutional text was what enabled the Court's behavior, because it necessarily created a need for judicial interpretation while rendering such interpretation unreviewable.
    • Baldwin v. New York, 399 U.S. 66, 75 (1970) (Black, J., dissenting) ("[The Framers] decided that the value of a jury trial far outweighed its costs for 'all crimes' and '(i)n all criminal prosecutions.'... I cannot agree that this Court can ... substitute its own judgment [that jury trial right is limited to "serious" crimes] for that embodied in the Constitution."). Black's argument in such opinions was that the Court acted arbitrarily in spite of the written Constitution; in contrast, I argue that the very presence of a constitutional text was what enabled the Court's behavior, because it necessarily created a need for judicial interpretation while rendering such interpretation unreviewable.
  • 165
    • 58649097151 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Cohen, supra note 90, at 840 (It is the great disservice of the classical conception of law that it hides from judicial eyes the ethical character of every judicial question, and thus serves to perpetuate class prejudices and uncritical moral assumptions which could not survive the sunlight of free ethical controversy.).
    • See Cohen, supra note 90, at 840 ("It is the great disservice of the classical conception of law that it hides from judicial eyes the ethical character of every judicial question, and thus serves to perpetuate class prejudices and uncritical moral assumptions which could not survive the sunlight of free ethical controversy.").
  • 166
    • 58649122078 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See RICHARD A. POSNER, THE PROBLEMATICS OF MORAL AND LEGAL THEORY 264 (1999) (The positivist judge is apt not to question his premises ... [nor] to recognize that he may be wrong and to seek through investigation to determine whether he is wrong.).
    • See RICHARD A. POSNER, THE PROBLEMATICS OF MORAL AND LEGAL THEORY 264 (1999) ("The positivist judge is apt not to question his premises ... [nor] to recognize that he may be wrong and to seek through investigation to determine whether he is wrong.").
  • 167
    • 58649084031 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This appears to be Justice Antonin Scalia's outraged appraisal of recent Fourteenth Amendment decisions by the Supreme Court. See Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 602 (2003, Scalia, J, dissenting, Today's opinion is the product of a Court, which is the product of a law-profession culture, that has largely signed on to the so-called homosexual agenda, );
    • This appears to be Justice Antonin Scalia's outraged appraisal of recent Fourteenth Amendment decisions by the Supreme Court. See Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 602 (2003) (Scalia, J., dissenting) ("Today's opinion is the product of a Court, which is the product of a law-profession culture, that has largely signed on to the so-called homosexual agenda....");
  • 168
    • 58649124857 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620, 653 (1996) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (Today's opinion has no foundation in American constitutional law, and barely pretends to. . . . Striking [down Colorado's Amendment 2, which prohibited any governmental action designed to protect gays and lesbians as a class,] is an act, not of judicial judgment, but of political will.). Like Justice Black, however, Scalia fails to appreciate that it is the Court's reliance on a written constitutional text that empowers it to issue with finality the kinds of decisions that Scalia finds so deplorable.
    • Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620, 653 (1996) (Scalia, J., dissenting) ("Today's opinion has no foundation in American constitutional law, and barely pretends to. . . . Striking [down Colorado's Amendment 2, which prohibited any governmental action designed to protect gays and lesbians as a class,] is an act, not of judicial judgment, but of political will."). Like Justice Black, however, Scalia fails to appreciate that it is the Court's reliance on a written constitutional text that empowers it to issue with finality the kinds of decisions that Scalia finds so deplorable.
  • 169
    • 58649083120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is not to imply that a written constitution contains no uncodified rules, as I have acknowledged, every real-world constitution relies upon uncodified rules to a certain extent. See supra note 27 and accompanying text. However, such rules are of greater import in an unwritten constitution, where they are not treated as merely supple-menting] the codified constitutional text
    • This is not to imply that a written constitution contains no uncodified rules - as I have acknowledged, every real-world constitution relies upon uncodified rules to a certain extent. See supra note 27 and accompanying text. However, such rules are of greater import in an unwritten constitution, where they are not treated as merely "supple-menting]" the codified constitutional text.
  • 170
    • 58649083343 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 9 (Even countries with written or codified constitutions need to supplement those codes with unwritten, or more likely uncodified, rules.).
    • Cf. TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 9 ("Even countries with written or codified constitutions need to supplement those codes with unwritten, or more likely uncodified, rules.").
  • 171
    • 58649124623 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See FOLEY, supra note 18, at 2 ([T]he [British] constitution is vulnerable to the charge of being driven by the exigencies and practicalities of contemporary politics.... [It] can be seen as being reducible to the needs of prevailing political forces.).
    • See FOLEY, supra note 18, at 2 ("[T]he [British] constitution is vulnerable to the charge of being driven by the exigencies and practicalities of contemporary politics.... [It] can be seen as being reducible to the needs of prevailing political forces.").
  • 172
    • 58649083801 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Carolene Products's famous Footnote Four has come to be understood, the Fourteenth Amendment is designed to protect discrete and insular minorities from government action motivated by majority prejudice, which tends seriously to curtail the operation of those political processes ordinarily to be relied upon to protect minorities. United States v. Carolene Prods., 304 U.S. 144, 152 n.4 (1938);
    • As Carolene Products's famous Footnote Four has come to be understood, the Fourteenth Amendment is designed to protect "discrete and insular minorities" from government action motivated by majority prejudice, "which tends seriously to curtail the operation of those political processes ordinarily to be relied upon to protect minorities." United States v. Carolene Prods., 304 U.S. 144, 152 n.4 (1938);
  • 173
    • 34249951655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see abo Bruce Ackerman, The Living Constitution, 120 HARV. L. REV. 1737, 1800 (2007) (A century ago, [commentators] looked abroad to compare the triumph of organic development in Britain with the tragic failure of Reconstruction in America. But today, the whole world seems to be designing constitutional machines to check and balance power in the name of human rights.). Of course, this conception of the Fourteenth Amendment is a judicial gloss on the bare words of the constitutional provision and is subject to the criticism of judicial insulation made in Part III.B.2.
    • see abo Bruce Ackerman, The Living Constitution, 120 HARV. L. REV. 1737, 1800 (2007) ("A century ago, [commentators] looked abroad to compare the triumph of organic development in Britain with the tragic failure of Reconstruction in America. But today, the whole world seems to be designing constitutional machines to check and balance power in the name of human rights."). Of course, this conception of the Fourteenth Amendment is a judicial gloss on the bare words of the constitutional provision and is subject to the criticism of judicial insulation made in Part III.B.2.
  • 174
    • 58649108412 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lord Lester of Herne Hill, QC & Lydia Clapinska, Human Rights and the British Constitution, in THE CHANGING CONSTITUTION, supra note 18, at 62, 86 ([U]nless and until we have a modern British Bill of Rights . . . the [European Convention on Human Rights] provides the best available text to accustom our lawmakers, our judges, and our administrators to the constitutional landscape.).
    • See Lord Lester of Herne Hill, QC & Lydia Clapinska, Human Rights and the British Constitution, in THE CHANGING CONSTITUTION, supra note 18, at 62, 86 ("[U]nless and until we have a modern British Bill of Rights . . . the [European Convention on Human Rights] provides the best available text to accustom our lawmakers, our judges, and our administrators to the constitutional landscape.").
  • 175
    • 58649097152 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see WALDRON, supra note 16, at 213 ([I]f people disagree about basic rights . . . while nevertheless needing ... a common framework, an adequate theory of authority in this area can neither include nor be qualified by any simple conception of rights as 'trumps' over majoritarian forms of decisionmaking.).
    • But see WALDRON, supra note 16, at 213 ("[I]f people disagree about basic rights . . . while nevertheless needing ... a common framework, an adequate theory of authority in this area can neither include nor be qualified by any simple conception of rights as 'trumps' over majoritarian forms of decisionmaking.").
  • 176
    • 58649095615 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See FOLEY, supra note 18, at 2 ([I]t is alleged that. . . [w]hat restraint exists [in the British constitution] comes more from the mutual convenience, collective interest or political prudence of the political participants-rather than from the effect of any autonomous and authoritative dimension of constitutional principle.);
    • See FOLEY, supra note 18, at 2 ("[I]t is alleged that. . . [w]hat restraint exists [in the British constitution] comes more from the mutual convenience, collective interest or political prudence of the political participants-rather than from the effect of any autonomous and authoritative dimension of constitutional principle.");
  • 177
    • 58649087902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 24 (suggesting that United Kingdom's political constitution has come to be widely seen as having broken down [because] Ministers, it is felt, are rarely held to account by Parliament).
    • cf. TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 24 (suggesting that United Kingdom's "political constitution has come to be widely seen as having broken down [because] Ministers, it is felt, are rarely held to account by Parliament").
  • 178
    • 58649107998 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Adam Tomkins has pointed to this contradiction in support of his arguments that the written/unwritten distinction is of little consequence. See TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 9-14 (arguing that unwritten constitutions are no more flexible than written constitutions because conventions are traditions - a force for conservatism, for doing the same thing as was done in the past, not a force for change). My response to Tomkins's point is two-fold: First, I argue that such a contradiction is merely apparent, not real, because conventions are in fact continually responding to social change at a highly gradual and informal level; second, I show how other elements of the unwritten constitution lend themselves to greater flexibility than is found in a written constitution.
    • Adam Tomkins has pointed to this contradiction in support of his arguments that the written/unwritten distinction is of little consequence. See TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 9-14 (arguing that unwritten constitutions are no more flexible than written constitutions because conventions are traditions - "a force for conservatism, for doing the same thing as was done in the past, not a force for change"). My response to Tomkins's point is two-fold: First, I argue that such a contradiction is merely apparent, not real, because conventions are in fact continually responding to social change at a highly gradual and informal level; second, I show how other elements of the unwritten constitution lend themselves to greater flexibility than is found in a written constitution.
  • 179
    • 84888467546 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • notes 107-13 and accompanying text
    • See infra notes 107-13 and accompanying text.
    • See infra
  • 180
    • 58649117470 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See FOLEY, supra note 18, at 3 ([The British constitution's] defining condition and chief virtue is one of evolutionary change.).
    • See FOLEY, supra note 18, at 3 ("[The British constitution's] defining condition and chief virtue is one of evolutionary change.").
  • 181
    • 33646364568 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Freedom of Information and Openness: Fundamental Human Rights?, 58
    • We refer to the rules of our constitutional traditions to guide us in the development of [the United Kingdom's] unwritten constitution, See
    • See Patrick Birkinshaw, Freedom of Information and Openness: Fundamental Human Rights?, 58 ADMIN. L. REV. 177, 203 (2006) ("We refer to the rules of our constitutional traditions to guide us in the development of [the United Kingdom's] unwritten constitution.").
    • (2006) ADMIN. L. REV , vol.177 , pp. 203
    • Birkinshaw, P.1
  • 182
    • 58649093202 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See THE BRITISH POLITICAL PROCESS: AN INTRODUCTION 47 (Tony Wright ed., 2000)
    • See THE BRITISH POLITICAL PROCESS: AN INTRODUCTION 47 (Tony Wright ed., 2000)
  • 183
    • 58649099086 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • [hereinafter THE BRITISH POLITICAL PROCESS] (The 'unwritten' nature of the UK constitution, where there are no constitutional 'higher laws' and no universally agreed set of constitutional enactments, inevitably provides significant scope for the operation of conventions.). According to the paradigm of the written constitution that I have laid out,
    • [hereinafter THE BRITISH POLITICAL PROCESS] ("The 'unwritten' nature of the UK constitution, where there are no constitutional 'higher laws' and no universally agreed set of constitutional enactments, inevitably provides significant scope for the operation of conventions."). According to the paradigm of the written constitution that I have laid out,
  • 184
    • 58649085159 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see supra Part I.A, there would be little to no room for conventional constitutional law, since only those principles codified and integrated into the constitution would be treated as constitutionally binding.
    • see supra Part I.A, there would be little to no room for conventional constitutional law, since only those principles codified and integrated into the constitution would be treated as constitutionally binding.
  • 185
    • 58649096253 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 18 for a discussion of the role of constitutional conventions in the U.K. constitution.
    • See supra note 18 for a discussion of the role of constitutional conventions in the U.K. constitution.
  • 186
    • 58649097838 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra Part III.B.1 for the argument that the presence of an authoritative constitutional text weakens judicial commitment to stare decisis.
    • See supra Part III.B.1 for the argument that the presence of an authoritative constitutional text weakens judicial commitment to stare decisis.
  • 187
    • 58649087494 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • F.A. HAYEK, LAW, LEGISLATION AND LIBERTY: RULES AND ORDER 86 (1983).
    • F.A. HAYEK, LAW, LEGISLATION AND LIBERTY: RULES AND ORDER 86 (1983).
  • 188
    • 58649085382 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 87 (What must guide [the judge's] decision is ... solely what is demanded by general principles on which the going order of society is based.);
    • See id. at 87 ("What must guide [the judge's] decision is ... solely what is demanded by general principles on which the going order of society is based.");
  • 189
    • 58649090346 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • THE BRITISH POLITICAL PROCESS, supra note 103, at 47 ([Conventions] describe, at any point in time, the practical workings of the political and governmental system, and the actual, rather than the theoretical, distribution of power among the various organs of the state.).
    • THE BRITISH POLITICAL PROCESS, supra note 103, at 47 ("[Conventions] describe, at any point in time, the practical workings of the political and governmental system, and the actual, rather than the theoretical, distribution of power among the various organs of the state.").
  • 190
    • 58649093643 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MARSHALL, supra note 18, at 217
    • MARSHALL, supra note 18, at 217.
  • 191
    • 58649084032 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Squire Centenary Lecture, supra note 60 (A virtue of ... our [U.K.] constitution [is that it] has always been capable of evolving as the needs of society change. The evolution can be incremental in a way which would be difficult if we had a written constitution.).
    • See Squire Centenary Lecture, supra note 60 ("A virtue of ... our [U.K.] constitution [is that it] has always been capable of evolving as the needs of society change. The evolution can be incremental in a way which would be difficult if we had a written constitution.").
  • 192
    • 58649093642 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See WALDRON, supra note 16, at 220 ([L]egislative text[, unlike constitutional text,] can readily be amended to meet our evolving sense of how best to get at the important issues at stake.).
    • See WALDRON, supra note 16, at 220 ("[L]egislative text[, unlike constitutional text,] can readily be amended to meet our evolving sense of how best to get at the important issues at stake.").
  • 193
    • 58649101964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MARSHALL, supra note 18, at 13 (noting that Britain's Parliament Act of 1911 formalized relations between the two Houses of Parliament that had formerly been matters of convention).
    • See MARSHALL, supra note 18, at 13 (noting that Britain's Parliament Act of 1911 "formalized relations between the two Houses of Parliament that had formerly been matters of convention").
  • 194
    • 58649119731 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 185-87 (discussing U.K. cases which recognize [constitutional rights . . . that executive action may not interfere with, even where that executive action b apparently authorized by statute, unless the statute expressly states other-wise (emphasis added)).
    • See TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 185-87 (discussing U.K. cases which recognize "[constitutional rights . . . that executive action may not interfere with, even where that executive action b apparently authorized by statute, unless the statute expressly states other-wise" (emphasis added)).
  • 195
    • 58649098064 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See THE BRITISH POLITICAL PROCESS, supra note 103, at 47 (Conventions... relate the formal theory of the constitution to the practical realities of the day, perhaps by modifying the strict law, or by expanding it.).
    • See THE BRITISH POLITICAL PROCESS, supra note 103, at 47 ("Conventions... relate the formal theory of the constitution to the practical realities of the day, perhaps by modifying the strict law, or by expanding it.").
  • 196
    • 58649122577 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These are the principles most often raised in arguments connecting writtenness with the rule of law. See supra note 68 and accompanying text. In contrast, the remaining principles are not based on form and thus have relatively little to do with the presence or absence of a written constitution-whether constitutional rules are framed in general terms, apply prospectively, are non-contradictory, and are within the abilities of their addressees to follow are determined by the content of those rules. This is not to say that writtenness has no repercussions whatsoever upon the content of constitutional rules, and this Note does reference principles other than those of publicity, clarity, and constancy; however, due to space constraints, my focus lies on a more narrow set of values. Finally, for reasons explained in note 70
    • These are the principles most often raised in arguments connecting writtenness with the rule of law. See supra note 68 and accompanying text. In contrast, the remaining principles are not based on form and thus have relatively little to do with the presence or absence of a written constitution-whether constitutional rules are framed in general terms, apply prospectively, are non-contradictory, and are within the abilities of their addressees to follow are determined by the content of those rules. This is not to say that writtenness has no repercussions whatsoever upon the content of constitutional rules, and this Note does reference principles other than those of publicity, clarity, and constancy; however, due to space constraints, my focus lies on a more narrow set of values. Finally, for reasons explained in note 70,
  • 197
    • 58649108186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra, the requirement of congruency is not a part of this inquiry.
    • supra, the requirement of congruency is not a part of this inquiry.
  • 198
    • 58649123237 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See note 70, at, 82 providing examples of how different principles are linked
    • See FULLER, supra note 70, at 80, 82 (providing examples of how different principles are linked).
    • supra , pp. 80
    • FULLER1
  • 199
    • 58649092290 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 51 ([I]f the laws are not made readily available, there is no check against a disregard of them by those charged with their application and enforcement.).
    • See id. at 51 ("[I]f the laws are not made readily available, there is no check against a disregard of them by those charged with their application and enforcement.").
  • 200
    • 58649106779 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lon Fuller takes this point one step further to suggest that, even if the government were not answerable to the people, it would still act more responsibly if it had to justify its actions with reference to known constitutional standards. See id. at 159 (Even if a man is answerable only to his own conscience, he will answer more responsibly if he is compelled to articulate the principles on which he acts.).
    • Lon Fuller takes this point one step further to suggest that, even if the government were not answerable to the people, it would still act more responsibly if it had to justify its actions with reference to known constitutional standards. See id. at 159 ("Even if a man is answerable only to his own conscience, he will answer more responsibly if he is compelled to articulate the principles on which he acts.").
  • 201
    • 58649118092 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 50
    • Id. at 50.
  • 202
    • 58649119497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 203
    • 58649120179 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See HAYEK, supra note 106, at 87 (The task of the [common law] judge [is to tell parties in dispute] what ought to have guided their expectations, not because anyone had told them before that this was the rule, but because this was the established custom which they ought to have known.).
    • See HAYEK, supra note 106, at 87 ("The task of the [common law] judge [is to tell parties in dispute] what ought to have guided their expectations, not because anyone had told them before that this was the rule, but because this was the established custom which they ought to have known.").
  • 204
    • 58649106107 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See THE BRITISH POLITICAL PROCESS, supra note 103, at 34 (The monarchy, Parliament, the courts, ministers and Prime Minister and the rest were not originally established by statute or other formal device, but have developed by custom, practice and convention, and then by recognition in common and statute law.);
    • See THE BRITISH POLITICAL PROCESS, supra note 103, at 34 ("The monarchy, Parliament, the courts, ministers and Prime Minister and the rest were not originally established by statute or other formal device, but have developed by custom, practice and convention, and then by recognition in common and statute law.");
  • 205
    • 33846582209 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • notes 107-13 and accompanying text describing evolutionary nature of constitutional rules in unwritten constitution
    • See also supra notes 107-13 and accompanying text (describing evolutionary nature of constitutional rules in unwritten constitution).
    • See also supra
  • 206
    • 58649094309 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 103-04 (The doctrine of legislative supremacy is a doctrine of the common law. . . . Parliament's victory in the Civil War, reaffirmed forty years later in the Bill of Rights .. . meant that it had conclusively asserted itself, and had thereby acquired for itself greater power and authority than it had . . . enjoy[ed] beforehand ....);
    • See TOMKINS, supra note 9, at 103-04 ("The doctrine of legislative supremacy is a doctrine of the common law. . . . Parliament's victory in the Civil War, reaffirmed forty years later in the Bill of Rights .. . meant that it had conclusively asserted itself, and had thereby acquired for itself greater power and authority than it had . . . enjoy[ed] beforehand ....");
  • 207
    • 58649119732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Peter L. Fitzgerald, Constitutional Crisis over the Proposed Supreme Court for the United Kingdom, 18 TEMP. INT'L & COMP. L.J. 233, 254 (2004) (Judicial deference ... [to Parliament] is the product of case law, history, and the judiciary's own conception of the proper role of the courts.).
    • Peter L. Fitzgerald, Constitutional Crisis over the Proposed Supreme Court for the United Kingdom, 18 TEMP. INT'L & COMP. L.J. 233, 254 (2004) ("Judicial deference ... [to Parliament] is the product of case law, history, and the judiciary's own conception of the proper role of the courts.").
  • 208
    • 0032385485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The History of the Countermajoritarian Difficulty (pt. 1): The Road to Judicial Supremacy, 73
    • describing the Supreme Court's authority to determine constitutional meaning for the entire country as [a] gradual evolution, See
    • See Barry Friedman, The History of the Countermajoritarian Difficulty (pt. 1): The Road to Judicial Supremacy, 73 N.Y.U. L. REV. 333, 342 (1998) (describing "the Supreme Court's authority to determine constitutional meaning for the entire country" as "[a] gradual evolution").
    • (1998) N.Y.U. L. REV , vol.333 , pp. 342
    • Friedman, B.1
  • 209
    • 58649119971 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As explained in Parts II and III.B, supra, however, the evolution of judicial review in the U.S. was made possible in the first place by the written nature of the country's constitution.
    • As explained in Parts II and III.B, supra, however, the evolution of judicial review in the U.S. was made possible in the first place by the written nature of the country's constitution.
  • 210
    • 58649089917 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Mackey v. United States, 401 U.S. 667, 678-79 (1971) (Harlan, J., concurring and dissenting) (We [the Supreme Court] announce new constitutional rules... only as a [corollary] of our dual duty to decide those cases over which we have jurisdiction and to apply the Federal Constitution as one source of the matrix of governing legal rules.).
    • See, e.g., Mackey v. United States, 401 U.S. 667, 678-79 (1971) (Harlan, J., concurring and dissenting) ("We [the Supreme Court] announce new constitutional rules... only as a [corollary] of our dual duty to decide those cases over which we have jurisdiction and to apply the Federal Constitution as one source of the matrix of governing legal rules.").
  • 211
    • 58649115063 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This has been one criticism of the doctrine of substantive due process, where substantive limits upon government action are defended by reference to the Due Process Clauses in the U.S. Constitution, which by their own terms refer only to procedural limitations. U.S. CONST, amends. V, XIV;
    • This has been one criticism of the doctrine of substantive due process, where substantive limits upon government action are defended by reference to the Due Process Clauses in the U.S. Constitution, which by their own terms refer only to procedural limitations. U.S. CONST, amends. V, XIV;
  • 212
    • 0042493053 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Kevin Christopher Newsom, Setting Incorporationbm Straight: A Reinterpretation of the Slaughter-House Cases, 109 YALE L.J. 643, 736 (2000) (The [Supreme] Court's present policy of relying exclusively on the Due Process Clause to protect substantive Bill of Rights freedoms confounds the ordinary meaning of the term 'due process.' Indeed, through the years, various [Justices] have explicitly acknowledged the textual difficulties inherent in substantive due process ....);
    • see also Kevin Christopher Newsom, Setting Incorporationbm Straight: A Reinterpretation of the Slaughter-House Cases, 109 YALE L.J. 643, 736 (2000) ("The [Supreme] Court's present policy of relying exclusively on the Due Process Clause to protect substantive Bill of Rights freedoms confounds the ordinary meaning of the term 'due process.' Indeed, through the years, various [Justices] have explicitly acknowledged the textual difficulties inherent in substantive due process ....);
  • 214
    • 58649090347 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Seminole Tribe of FIa. v. Florida, 517 U.S. 44, 160 (1996) (Souter, J., dissenting) Whereas a constitution [was] seen in the colonial period as a body of vague and unidentifiable precedents and principles of common law origin . . . after independence it [was seen] as a written charter by which the people delegated powers to various institutions of government and imposed limitations on . . . those powers....
    • See Seminole Tribe of FIa. v. Florida, 517 U.S. 44, 160 (1996) (Souter, J., dissenting) ("Whereas a constitution [was] seen in the colonial period as a body of vague and unidentifiable precedents and principles of common law origin . . . after independence it [was seen] as a written charter by which the people delegated powers to various institutions of government and imposed limitations on . . . those powers...."
  • 215
    • 58649095409 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (quoting WILLIAM E. NELSON, AMERICANIZATION OF THE COMMON LAW 90 (1975)).
    • (quoting WILLIAM E. NELSON, AMERICANIZATION OF THE COMMON LAW 90 (1975)).
  • 216
    • 58649094307 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Bd. of Regents of State Colls, v. Roth, 408 U.S. 564, 579 (1972) ([I]t is a written Constitution that we apply. Our role is confined to interpretation of that Constitution.);
    • See Bd. of Regents of State Colls, v. Roth, 408 U.S. 564, 579 (1972) ("[I]t is a written Constitution that we apply. Our role is confined to interpretation of that Constitution.");
  • 217
    • 58649093860 scopus 로고
    • Judges, Critics, and the Realist Tradition, 82
    • J]udicial responsibility begins and ends with determining the present scope and meaning of a decision that the nation, at an earlier time, articulated and enacted into constitutional text
    • Hans A. Linde, Judges, Critics, and the Realist Tradition, 82 YALE L.J. 227, 254 (1972) ("[J]udicial responsibility begins and ends with determining the present scope and meaning of a decision that the nation, at an earlier time, articulated and enacted into constitutional text. . . .").
    • (1972) YALE L.J , vol.227 , pp. 254
    • Linde, H.A.1
  • 218
    • 84963456897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note 53 and accompanying text
    • See supra note 53 and accompanying text.
    • See supra
  • 219
    • 58649107249 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed, on a conceptual level, it is debatable whether clarity of rules is ever possible. See Margaret Jane Radin, Reconsidering the Rule of Law, 69 B.U. L. REV. 781, 800 (1989) (using Wittgensteinian concepts of inherent ambiguity of language to argue that we only know there are rules when disputes don't break out (internal quotation marks omitted)).
    • Indeed, on a conceptual level, it is debatable whether clarity of rules is ever possible. See Margaret Jane Radin, Reconsidering the Rule of Law, 69 B.U. L. REV. 781, 800 (1989) (using Wittgensteinian concepts of inherent ambiguity of language to argue that we only know there are rules when "disputes don't break out" (internal quotation marks omitted)).
  • 220
    • 58649099511 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Such principles are often referred to as 'essentially' contested concepts- that is, concepts that are intrinsically and desirably contestable. Jeremy Waldron, Vagueness in Law and Language: Some Philosophical Issues, 82 CAL. L. REV. 509, 529-31 (1994).
    • Such principles are often referred to as " 'essentially' contested concepts"- that is, concepts that are intrinsically and desirably contestable. Jeremy Waldron, Vagueness in Law and Language: Some Philosophical Issues, 82 CAL. L. REV. 509, 529-31 (1994).
  • 221
    • 58649087051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See HAYEK, supra note 106, at 118-20 (portraying role of judge as maintaining and improving a going order of action by articulating rules based upon society's general sense of justice).
    • See HAYEK, supra note 106, at 118-20 (portraying role of judge as "maintaining and improving a going order of action" by articulating rules based upon society's "general sense of justice").
  • 222
    • 58649124624 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 116 ([J]udicial decisions may in fact be more predictable if the judge is also bound by generally held views of what is just, even when they are not supported by the letter of the law, than when he is restricted to deriving his decisions only from . . . the written law.).
    • See id. at 116 ("[J]udicial decisions may in fact be more predictable if the judge is also bound by generally held views of what is just, even when they are not supported by the letter of the law, than when he is restricted to deriving his decisions only from . . . the written law.").
  • 223
    • 58649124858 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See WALDRON, supra note 16, at 220 (One lesson of American constitutional experience is that the words of each provision in the Bill of Rights tend to take on a life of their own, becoming the obsessive catchphrase for expressing everything one might want to say about the right in question.).
    • See WALDRON, supra note 16, at 220 ("One lesson of American constitutional experience is that the words of each provision in the Bill of Rights tend to take on a life of their own, becoming the obsessive catchphrase for expressing everything one might want to say about the right in question.").
  • 224
    • 58649102799 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The classic counterargument to this is that it is precisely the judiciary's role to protect constitutional rights from being trampled upon by political majorities. See, e.g., Rosemary Barkett, Judicial Discretion and Judicious Deliberation, 59 FLA. L. REV. 905, 910 (2007) (describing role of judiciary as enforc[ing] the rights of a minority against a majoritarian vote of a legislature that may have forgotten (or chosen to ignore) the dictates of our Constitution). However, this fails to address the questions of how or why the judiciary should determine in the final instance the content of those rights, as opposed to merely upholding them.
    • The classic counterargument to this is that it is precisely the judiciary's role to protect constitutional rights from being trampled upon by political majorities. See, e.g., Rosemary Barkett, Judicial Discretion and Judicious Deliberation, 59 FLA. L. REV. 905, 910 (2007) (describing role of judiciary as "enforc[ing] the rights of a minority against a majoritarian vote of a legislature that may have forgotten (or chosen to ignore) the dictates of our Constitution"). However, this fails to address the questions of how or why the judiciary should determine in the final instance the content of those rights, as opposed to merely upholding them.
  • 225
    • 58649089916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A.V. Dicey believed that fundamental rights were part of the U.K. constitution because they were secured by judicial decisions-in other words, that constitutional principles were inductions or generalisations based upon particular decisions pronounced by the Courts as to the rights of given individuals.
    • A.V. Dicey believed that fundamental rights were part of the U.K. constitution because they were secured by judicial decisions-in other words, that constitutional principles were "inductions or generalisations based upon particular decisions pronounced by the Courts as to the rights of given individuals."
  • 226
    • 58649087901 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A.V. DICEY, INTRODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF THE LAW OF THE CONSTITUTION 193 (8th ed. 1915) (1885).
    • A.V. DICEY, INTRODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF THE LAW OF THE CONSTITUTION 193 (8th ed. 1915) (1885).
  • 227
    • 58649094308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WALDRON, supra note 16, at 220
    • WALDRON, supra note 16, at 220.
  • 228
    • 58649124416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jeremy Waldron contrasts the uniquely determinate phraseology of a codified Bill of Rights with legislative text, which can readily be amended to meet our evolving sense of how best to get at the important issues at stake. Id, T]his process of evolving phraseology is even easier if we are talking about legal recognition in the form of common law principles and precedents, and easier still if rights take the form of 'conventional' understandings subscribed to in the political community at large
    • Jeremy Waldron contrasts the uniquely determinate phraseology of a codified Bill of Rights with legislative text, which "can readily be amended to meet our evolving sense of how best to get at the important issues at stake." Id. "[T]his process of evolving phraseology is even easier if we are talking about legal recognition in the form of common law principles and precedents, and easier still if rights take the form of 'conventional' understandings subscribed to in the political community at large . . . ."
  • 229
    • 58649106998 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 221
    • Id. at 221.
  • 230
    • 58649083119 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See THE FEDERALIST NO. 43, at 246 (James Madison) (Clinton Rossiter ed., 1999) (That useful alterations [to the Constitution] will be suggested by experience could not but be foreseen.... [Article Vs amendment process] guards equally against that extreme facility, which would render the Constitution too mutable; and that extreme difficulty, which might perpetuate its discovered faults.).
    • See THE FEDERALIST NO. 43, at 246 (James Madison) (Clinton Rossiter ed., 1999) ("That useful alterations [to the Constitution] will be suggested by experience could not but be foreseen.... [Article Vs amendment process] guards equally against that extreme facility, which would render the Constitution too mutable; and that extreme difficulty, which might perpetuate its discovered faults.").
  • 231
    • 0042244186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The American constitutional amendment process appears designed to ensure that societal consensus is reached before any codified constitutional change can occur. See John Ferejohn & Lawrence Sager, Commitment and Constitutionalism, 81 TEX. L. REV. 1929, 1958 2003, arguing that Article V, implements' a certain model of constitutional deliberation that involves a high level of public mobilization and engagement supported by a sense of urgency and, seriousness of purpose as well as a generality of perspective, It could be argued that the existence of the twenty-seven amendments shows how constitutional codification can indeed occur repeatedly over time. This argument, however, can just as easily be turned on its head-the fact that only twenty-seven amendments have been ratified since 1787 is a testament to the extraordinary difficulty of amending the Constitution
    • The American constitutional amendment process appears designed to ensure that societal consensus is reached before any codified constitutional change can occur. See John Ferejohn & Lawrence Sager, Commitment and Constitutionalism, 81 TEX. L. REV. 1929, 1958 (2003) (arguing that Article V " 'implements' a certain model of constitutional deliberation" that involves "a high level of public mobilization and engagement supported by a sense of urgency and ... seriousness of purpose" as well as "a generality of perspective"). It could be argued that the existence of the twenty-seven amendments shows how constitutional codification can indeed occur repeatedly over time. This argument, however, can just as easily be turned on its head-the fact that only twenty-seven amendments have been ratified since 1787 is a testament to the extraordinary difficulty of amending the Constitution.
  • 232
    • 58649119496 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 1954 (noting standard critique that Article V sets the bar too high: Its provisions were intended to make the Constitution obdurate to change, and in practice it has been extravagantly so); Sanford Levinson, The Political Implications of Amending Clauses, 13 CONST. COMMENT. 107, 117 (1996) (noting failure of proposed Equal Rights Amendment in spite of the fact that over 60% of the states, containing an ample majority of the population, had given it their assent).
    • See id. at 1954 (noting "standard critique" that "Article V sets the bar too high: Its provisions were intended to make the Constitution obdurate to change, and in practice it has been extravagantly so"); Sanford Levinson, The Political Implications of Amending Clauses, 13 CONST. COMMENT. 107, 117 (1996) (noting failure of proposed Equal Rights Amendment "in spite of the fact that over 60% of the states, containing an ample majority of the population, had given it their assent").
  • 233
    • 58649114413 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, the German constitution contains a few provisions which are wholly unamendable. BARENDT, supra note 13, at 8.
    • For example, the German constitution contains a few provisions which are "wholly unamendable." BARENDT, supra note 13, at 8.
  • 234
    • 34250622168 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • notes 79-84 and accompanying text for a discussion of stare decisis and its significance for the rule of law
    • See supra notes 79-84 and accompanying text for a discussion of stare decisis and its significance for the rule of law.
    • See supra
  • 235
    • 39649113557 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See David Gringer, Note, Why the National Popular Vote Plan b the Wrong Way to Abolbh the Electoral College, 108 COLUM. L. REV. 182, 186-87 & n.30 (2008) (suggesting that repeated failures to reform electoral college despite strong public support for eliminating [it] for at least the last fifty years might be due at least partly to fact that electoral college is biased toward smaller states).
    • See David Gringer, Note, Why the National Popular Vote Plan b the Wrong Way to Abolbh the Electoral College, 108 COLUM. L. REV. 182, 186-87 & n.30 (2008) (suggesting that repeated failures to reform electoral college despite "strong public support for eliminating [it] for at least the last fifty years" might be due at least partly to fact that electoral college is biased toward smaller states).
  • 236
    • 58649099933 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra note 139 and accompanying text (noting difficulty of amending U.S. Constitution through Article V process).
    • See supra note 139 and accompanying text (noting difficulty of amending U.S. Constitution through Article V process).
  • 237
    • 58649122999 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Rochin v. California, 342 U.S. 165, 170 (1952) ([T]he gloss of some of the verbal symbols of the Constitution does not give them a fixed technical content. It exacts a continuing process of application.).
    • See, e.g., Rochin v. California, 342 U.S. 165, 170 (1952) ("[T]he gloss of some of the verbal symbols of the Constitution does not give them a fixed technical content. It exacts a continuing process of application.").
  • 238
    • 58649098436 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See generally BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE 2: TRANSFORMATIONS (1998) (laying out theory of constitutional dualism, which distinguishes between ordinary lawmaking and moments of heightened democratic mobilization).
    • See generally BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE 2: TRANSFORMATIONS (1998) (laying out theory of constitutional dualism, which distinguishes between ordinary lawmaking and moments of heightened democratic mobilization).
  • 239
    • 77951825411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • America's Statutory "Constitution, " 41
    • William N. Eskridge, Jr., America's Statutory "Constitution, " 41 U.C. DAVIS L. REV. 1, 6 (2007).
    • (2007) U.C. DAVIS L. REV , vol.1 , pp. 6
    • Eskridge Jr., W.N.1
  • 240
    • 58649098643 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Antonin Scalia, Common-Law Courts in a Civil-Law System: The Role of United States Federal Courts in Interpreting the Constitution and Laws, in A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION, supra note 22, at 3, 38 (describing Great Divide in constitutional interpretation between original meaning and current meaning and criticizing Living Constitution as the common law returned, but infinitely more powerful... for now it trumps even the statutes of democratic legislatures);
    • See Antonin Scalia, Common-Law Courts in a Civil-Law System: The Role of United States Federal Courts in Interpreting the Constitution and Laws, in A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION, supra note 22, at 3, 38 (describing "Great Divide" in constitutional interpretation between original meaning and current meaning and criticizing "Living Constitution" as "the common law returned, but infinitely more powerful... for now it trumps even the statutes of democratic legislatures");
  • 241
    • 58649121394 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also William H. Rehnquist, The Notion of a Living Constitution, 29 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 401, 403 (2006) (rejecting idea underlying living Constitution that nonelected members of the federal judiciary who are responsible to no constituency whatever have authority to address themselves to a social problem simply because other branches of government have failed or refused to do so).
    • see also William H. Rehnquist, The Notion of a Living Constitution, 29 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 401, 403 (2006) (rejecting idea underlying "living Constitution" that "nonelected members of the federal judiciary" who are "responsible to no constituency whatever" have authority to "address themselves to a social problem simply because other branches of government have failed or refused to do so").
  • 242
    • 37449001451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Ernest A. Young, The Constitution Outside the Constitution, 111 YALE L.J. 408, 413-14, 455 (2007) (noting that theories of extracanonical mechanisms of constitutional change are on a collision course with Article V and run into problems of identify[ing] both which norms have achieved [constitutional] status and what their precise content is). These problems would in turn negatively affect other principles of legality such as clarity and practicability.
    • See Ernest A. Young, The Constitution Outside the Constitution, 111 YALE L.J. 408, 413-14, 455 (2007) (noting that theories of "extracanonical mechanisms of constitutional change" are "on a collision course with Article V" and run into problems of "identify[ing] both which norms have achieved [constitutional] status and what their precise content is"). These problems would in turn negatively affect other principles of legality such as clarity and practicability.
  • 243
    • 58649121849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, part of the outrage over the Blair administration's proposals for judicial reform in 2003, see supra note 60, stemmed from the methods employed by the government to enact the changes it wanted-the sudden and unexpected announcement, and the attempt to pass off far-reaching reforms as part of a routine Cabinet reshuffle that could be unilaterally accomplished-which were felt to undermine constitutional principles such as judicial independence and the separation of powers. See Woolf, supra note 60, at 9 (stating that way in which government announced its plans for judicial reform caused author to have concerns about independence of U.K. judiciary);
    • For example, part of the outrage over the Blair administration's proposals for judicial reform in 2003, see supra note 60, stemmed from the methods employed by the government to enact the changes it wanted-the sudden and unexpected announcement, and the attempt to pass off far-reaching reforms as part of a routine Cabinet reshuffle that could be unilaterally accomplished-which were felt to undermine constitutional principles such as judicial independence and the separation of powers. See Woolf, supra note 60, at 9 (stating that way in which government announced its plans for judicial reform caused author to have concerns about independence of U.K. judiciary);
  • 244
    • 58649092977 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • d'Etat
    • labeling Blair's announcements a coup d'etat by stealth and objecting that his reforms were a shockingly casual way to interfere with the peculiarly informal separation of powers that is one of the glories of British governance, June 13, at
    • Blair's Coup d'Etat, DAILY TELEGRAPH, June 13, 2003, at 27 (labeling Blair's announcements "a coup d'etat by stealth" and objecting that his reforms were "a shockingly casual way to interfere with the peculiarly informal separation of powers that is one of the glories of British governance").
    • (2003) DAILY TELEGRAPH , pp. 27
    • Coup, B.1
  • 245
    • 58649107773 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The National Constitution Center conducted a telephone poll of one thousand U.S. citizens across the country. National Constitution Center, Highlights of Survey, http://72.32.50.200/CitizenAction/CivicResearchResults/ NCCNationalPoll/HighlightsofthePoll.shtml (last visited July 20, 2008).
    • The National Constitution Center conducted a telephone poll of one thousand U.S. citizens across the country. National Constitution Center, Highlights of Survey, http://72.32.50.200/CitizenAction/CivicResearchResults/ NCCNationalPoll/HighlightsofthePoll.shtml (last visited July 20, 2008).
  • 246
    • 58649096684 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For instance, only nineteen percent of respondents knew that there are twenty-seven amendments to the Constitution. National Constitution Center, NCC Constitution Poll Statistics, http://72.32.50.200/CitizenAction/ CivicResearchResults/NCCNationalPoll/TheAnswers-shtml (last visited July 20, 2008). Eighty-four percent thought that the Constitution states that all men are created equal. National Constitution Center, Startling Lack of Constitutional Knowledge Revealed in First-Ever National Poll, http://72.32.50.200/ CitizenAction/CivicResearchResults/NCCNationalPoll/index.shtml (last visited July 20, 2008).
    • For instance, only nineteen percent of respondents knew that there are twenty-seven amendments to the Constitution. National Constitution Center, NCC Constitution Poll Statistics, http://72.32.50.200/CitizenAction/ CivicResearchResults/NCCNationalPoll/TheAnswers-shtml (last visited July 20, 2008). Eighty-four percent thought that the Constitution states that all men are created equal. National Constitution Center, Startling Lack of Constitutional Knowledge Revealed in First-Ever National Poll, http://72.32.50.200/ CitizenAction/CivicResearchResults/NCCNationalPoll/index.shtml (last visited July 20, 2008).


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.