메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 30, Issue 1, 2006, Pages 1-15

Dynamics of Sociality

(1)  Bratman, Michael E a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 56749143276     PISSN: 03636550     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1475-4975.2006.00125.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (44)

References (32)
  • 1
    • 0010475612 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See essays 5-8 in my Faces of Intention (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999)
    • (1999) Faces of Intention
  • 3
    • 85012262572 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Law. Plans, and Practical Reason
    • In appealing to a "public context" rather than explicitly to common knowledge I have learned from Scott Shapiro, "Law. Plans, and Practical Reason," Legal Theory 8 (2002): 387-441, at 412.
    • (2002) Legal Theory , vol.8 , pp. 387-441
    • Shapiro, S.1
  • 4
    • 85022384870 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Finally, concerning interdependence, see "I Intend that We J," 153 57.
    • I Intend that We J
  • 5
    • 0003975273 scopus 로고
    • See my Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987; reissued by CSLI Publications, 1999) and Faces of Intention.
    • (1987) Plans, and Practical Reason
  • 7
    • 84928054203 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Collective Persons and Powers
    • description of my view as a mutual-awareness analysis is inaccurate. See his at 456
    • In this respect Philip Pettit's description of my view as a "mutual-awareness" analysis is inaccurate. See his "Collective Persons and Powers." Legal Theory 8 (2002): 443-70, at 456.
    • (2002) Legal Theory , vol.8 , pp. 443-70
    • Pettit's, P.1
  • 8
    • 77950030362 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Practical Intersubjectivity
    • discussion of what he calls the bridge intention proposal (though Roth thinks this proposal does not fully account for what he calls practical intersubjectivity, See his ed. Frederick F. Schmitt Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield
    • Some of the implications of these interintention interconnections are nicely brought out in Abraham Sesshu Roth's discussion of what he calls the "bridge intention proposal" (though Roth thinks this proposal does not fully account for what he calls "practical intersubjectivity"). See his "Practical Intersubjectivity," in Socializing Metaphysics, ed. Frederick F. Schmitt (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield. 2003). 65-91.
    • (2003) Socializing Metaphysics , pp. 65-91
    • Sesshu Roth's, A.1
  • 9
    • 60949382392 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For this account of shared valuing see my "Shared Valuing and Frameworks for Practical Reasoning." My formulation here makes explicit what was only implicit in that earlier work, that we do indeed intend to engage in and be guided by relevant shared deliberation.Thanks to Scott Shapiro for helping me see the need for making this explicit.
    • Shared Valuing and Frameworks for Practical Reasoning
  • 10
    • 33644689578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Desired Desires
    • reprinted in his Oxford: Oxford University Press at 129-30
    • Gilbert Harman, "Desired Desires," reprinted in his Explaining Value and Other Essays in Moral Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), 117-36, at 129-30.
    • (2000) Explaining Value and Other Essays in Moral Philosophy , pp. 117-36
    • Harman, G.1
  • 11
    • 79954055763 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Three Theories of Self-Governance
    • 46
    • See my "Three Theories of Self-Governance," Philosophical Topics 32 (2004): 21 46, and reprinted in my Structures of Agency.
    • (2004) Philosophical Topics , vol.32 , pp. 21
  • 13
    • 26444444344 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Autonomy and Hierarchy
    • and my "Autonomy and Hierarchy," Social Philosophy & Policy 20 (2003): 156-76. Both are reprinted in my Structures of Agency.
    • (2003) Social Philosophy & Policy , vol.20 , pp. 156-76
  • 14
    • 33749445704 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Practical Reasoning and Acceptance in a Context
    • as reprinted in
    • Here I am drawing on ideas in my "Practical Reasoning and Acceptance in a Context," as reprinted in Faces of Intention.
    • Faces of Intention
  • 15
    • 79960026690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Collective Agents and Cognitive Attitudes
    • For a useful discussion of related ideas see Anthonie Meijers, "Collective Agents and Cognitive Attitudes," Protosociology 16 (2002): 70-86.
    • (2002) Protosociology , vol.16 , pp. 70-86
    • Meijers, A.1
  • 16
    • 84937383867 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Belief and Acceptance as Features of Groups
    • Meijers, however, argues that all cases of "collective belief" that are not merely a summative matter are ones of context-relative collective acceptance. (For an alternative view see Margaret Gilbert, "Belief and Acceptance as Features of Groups," Protosociology 16 [2002]: 35-69.) I do not take a position on this issue here. All that I claim is that there is a phenomenon of shared valuing and that it is context-relative and has the features I have highlighted.
    • (2002) Protosociology , vol.16 , pp. 35-69
    • Gilbert, M.1
  • 17
    • 22744437696 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Contract and Collaboration
    • at 1456
    • Example courtesy of Daniel Markovits, "Contract and Collaboration," The Yale Law Journal 113 (2004): 1417-1518, at 1456.
    • (2004) The Yale Law Journal , vol.113 , pp. 1417-1518
    • Markovits, D.1
  • 19
    • 84859396722 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Temptation Revisited
    • in my
    • This is a theme in many of my discussions of these matters. For a recent discussion see my "Temptation Revisited," in my Structures of Agency.
    • Structures of Agency
  • 20
    • 79953941259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Anchors for Deliberation
    • (Aldershot, UK: Ashgate, forthcoming).
    • Concerning this last point see my "Anchors for Deliberation." in Christoph Lumer and Sandro Nannini, eds. Intentionality, Deliberation and Autonomy (Aldershot, UK: Ashgate, forthcoming).
    • Intentionality, Deliberation and Autonomy
    • Lumer, C.1    Nannini, S.2
  • 22
    • 80054651389 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Shared Agency and Contralateral Commitments
    • For a somewhat related view see Abraham Sesshu Roth, "Shared Agency and Contralateral Commitments," Philosophical Review (forthcoming).
    • Philosophical Review (forthcoming)
    • Roth, A.S.1
  • 23
    • 47949117856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Shared Values, Social Unity, and Liberty
    • Gilbert discusses "shared values" in her, 49
    • Gilbert discusses "shared values" in her "Shared Values, Social Unity, and Liberty," Public Affairs Quarterly 19 (2005): 25 49.
    • (2005) Public Affairs Quarterly , vol.19 , pp. 25
  • 24
    • 84977363125 scopus 로고
    • Walking Together: A Paradigmatic Social Phenomenon
    • For Gilbert's different approach to walking together see her "Walking Together: A Paradigmatic Social Phenomenon," Midwest Studies 15 (1990): 1-14. Facundo Alonso also discusses a similar example in unpublished work.
    • (1990) Midwest Studies , vol.15 , pp. 1-14
  • 25
    • 0003867020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press chap. 7
    • My talk of "significant loss" comes from T. M. Scanlon's formulation of his Principles M, D, and L. My point here is that these principles and their ilk need not be engaged by low-level, relatively nonconsequential shared agency. See Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998), chap. 7.
    • (1998) What We Owe to Each Other
    • Scanlon1
  • 26
    • 0004213898 scopus 로고
    • as reprinted in his Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • I borrow talk of "hard" cases from Ronald Dworkin. See his "Hard Cases," as reprinted in his Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1977), 81-130.
    • (1977) Taking Rights Seriously , pp. 81-130
    • Dworkin, R.1    Cases, H.2
  • 27
    • 42949148252 scopus 로고
    • Incompletely Theorized Agreements
    • Cass Sunstein, "Incompletely Theorized Agreements," Harvard Law Review 108 (1994 95): 1733-72.
    • (1994) Harvard Law Review , vol.108 , pp. 1733-1772
    • Sunstein, C.1
  • 28
    • 0003867020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 7
    • Recent contributions to a vigorous debate about these matters include: Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other, chap. 7.
    • What We Owe to Each Other
    • Scanlon1
  • 30
    • 32944474838 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Understanding and Sharing Intentions: The Origins of Cultural Cognition
    • For a fascinating discussion of forms of shared intention in children, and of implications for broad issues about human cognition, see Michael Tomasello, Malinda Carpenter, Joseph Call, Tanya Behne, and Henrike Moll, "Understanding and Sharing Intentions: The Origins of Cultural Cognition," Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28 (2005): 675-735.
    • (2005) Behavioral and Brain Sciences , vol.28 , pp. 675-735
    • Tomasello, M.1    Carpenter, M.2    Call, J.3    Behne, T.4    Moll, H.5
  • 31
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press esp.
    • Blain Neufeld has raised the question of whether John Rawls's discussion of the transition from a political framework seen by the participants as a mere "modus vivendi" to a "constitutional consensus," and from there to an "overlapping consensus." provides an example of the spillover effect (or perhaps, more broadly, an example of the overall social dynamics sketched here). (See John Rawls, Political Liberalism [New York: Columbia University Press, 1993], esp. 158 68.) The issue is complex; but let me make two brief points. First, I have been assuming that the participants of an initial shared activity, such as painting together, will frequently value shared governance; and I have appealed to this as a potential source of rational pressure in the direction of increased stability and depth, where this may include the spillover effect. In contrast (as Rawls makes clear in his remarks at p. 147) we cannot make an analogous assumption concerning the parties in a political framework seen by them as a mere "modus vivendi." Nevertheless, and this is my second point, it is important that Rawls's primary concern in his discussion is to respond to the worry that the idea of an overlapping consensus is Utopian, and to do this by tracing a plausible social route to such a consensus. To the extent that Rawls's story of this social route is, despite the difference just noted, a special case of a social dynamics common to human sharing, Rawls's response to worries about utopianism would be strengthened.
    • (1993) Political Liberalism
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 32
    • 79954226719 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I'd like to reflect briefly on some similarities and differences between the ideas I have been sketching and some central ideas in Pettit's essay, "Collective Persons and Powers." (Pettit discusses these matters in a series of recent publications, but for present purposes I will focus solely on this paper.) There is, first, an important commonality, since we both see the basic structure of shared intention (as he calls it, "shared purpose"-p. 457) as one that can be strengthened in important ways. Pettit is willing to accept something like my account of this basic structure (see p. 457), though, as I noted earlier, I do not think his characterization of my model as a "mutual awareness" account is fully apt. However, whereas I focus on increases in stability and depth of shared intentions and shared valuings, Pettit focuses on an overall "rational unity required of an intentional subject" (457).
    • Collective Persons and Powers , pp. 457


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.