메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 26, Issue 1, 2009, Pages 126-147

Up and down with aggregation

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 56749138103     PISSN: 02650525     EISSN: 14716437     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0265052509090062     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (3)

References (70)
  • 1
    • 56749117265 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is not the place to get bogged down in debates about what naturalism is. Although the matter is controversial, I will assume here that natural properties are ones that can be known by empirical means and thus are appropriate subjects for investigation by the natural and social sciences. See G. E. Moore, Principia Ethica, 2d ed, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993, 13;
    • This is not the place to get bogged down in debates about what naturalism is. Although the matter is controversial, I will assume here that natural properties are ones that can be known by empirical means and thus are appropriate subjects for investigation by the natural and social sciences. See G. E. Moore, Principia Ethica, 2d ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 13;
  • 3
    • 0141543798 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. Nicholas Sturgeon, Moore on Ethical Naturalism, Ethics 1.1.3, no. 3 (2003): 528-56, at pp. 534-38.
    • cf. Nicholas Sturgeon, "Moore on Ethical Naturalism," Ethics 1.1.3, no. 3 (2003): 528-56, at pp. 534-38.
  • 4
    • 56749111735 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a related argument that a desire-fulfillment theory of good reasons for action does not have the naturalistic purity some philosophers have supposed it has, see Jean Hampton, The Authority of Reason New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998, esp. chap. 5
    • For a related argument that a desire-fulfillment theory of good reasons for action does not have the naturalistic purity some philosophers have supposed it has, see Jean Hampton, The Authority of Reason (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998), esp. chap. 5.
  • 5
    • 0003214842 scopus 로고
    • Morality and the Theory of Rational Behaviour
    • Amartya Sen and Bernard Williams, eds, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, at pp
    • John Harsanyi, "Morality and the Theory of Rational Behaviour," in Amartya Sen and Bernard Williams, eds., Utilitarianism and Beyond (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), 39-62, at pp. 60-61.
    • (1982) Utilitarianism and Beyond
    • Harsanyi, J.1
  • 6
    • 84879935601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I explain this in my essay Theories of Welfare, Theories of Good Reasons for Action, and Ontological Naturalism, Philosophical Papers 20, no. 1 (1991): 25-36.
    • I explain this in my essay "Theories of Welfare, Theories of Good Reasons for Action, and Ontological Naturalism," Philosophical Papers 20, no. 1 (1991): 25-36.
  • 7
    • 56749119366 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Recent defenses of nonnaturalism include T. M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998), 58-61;
    • Recent defenses of nonnaturalism include T. M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998), 58-61;
  • 8
    • 56749142245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Russ Shafer-Landau, Moral Real-ism (New York: Oxford University Press, 2003);
    • (2003) Moral Real-ism
    • Shafer-Landau, R.1
  • 9
    • 56749115260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Derek Parfit, Climbing the Mountain (Oxford: Clarendon Press, forthcoming).
    • and Derek Parfit, Climbing the Mountain (Oxford: Clarendon Press, forthcoming).
  • 10
    • 0003596242 scopus 로고
    • See, Oxford: Blackwell Publishing
    • See Elizabeth Anscombe, Intention (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 1957), 70;
    • (1957) Intention , pp. 70
    • Anscombe, E.1
  • 11
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 432;
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 432
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 12
    • 0009042525 scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Warren Quinn, Morality and Action (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 236;
    • (1993) Morality and Action , pp. 236
    • Quinn, W.1
  • 14
    • 56749124490 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • and Robert Audi, Ethical Theory and Moral Character (New York: Oxford University Press, 1997), 77, 78.
    • (1997) Ethical Theory and Moral Character , vol.77 , pp. 78
    • Audi, R.1
  • 15
    • 85011418800 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Games and the Good
    • But what about desires for ends such as hitting small white balls into distant holes, as in golf, or, more generally, desires for sporting achievements that are in some sense the achievement of contrived goals? For a discussion, see
    • But what about desires for ends such as hitting small white balls into distant holes, as in golf, or, more generally, desires for sporting achievements that are in some sense the achievement of contrived goals? For a discussion, see Thomas Hurka, "Games and the Good," Aristotelian Society Supplementary Proceedings 80 (2006): 217-35;
    • (2006) Aristotelian Society Supplementary Proceedings , vol.80 , pp. 217-235
    • Hurka, T.1
  • 17
    • 56749145472 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and my The Meaning of Life: Subjectivism, Objectivism, and Divine Support, in Nafsika Athanassoulis and Samantha Vice, eds., Morality and the Good Life: Essays in Honour of John Cottingliam (London: Palgrave, 2008): 184-200.
    • and my "The Meaning of Life: Subjectivism, Objectivism, and Divine Support," in Nafsika Athanassoulis and Samantha Vice, eds., Morality and the Good Life: Essays in Honour of John Cottingliam (London: Palgrave, 2008): 184-200.
  • 18
    • 0003740191 scopus 로고
    • See, Oxford: Clarendon Press, appendix I;
    • See Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), appendix I;
    • (1984) Reasons and Persons
    • Parfit, D.1
  • 20
    • 0004278015 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Finnis, Fundamentals of Ethics (New York: Oxford University Press, 1983);
    • (1983) Fundamentals of Ethics
    • Finnis1
  • 23
    • 0039680121 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Bernard Gert, Morality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1988), 92-94;
    • (1988) Morality , pp. 92-94
    • Gert, B.1
  • 24
    • 0040609482 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Human Flourishing Versus Desire Satisfaction
    • and Richard Arneson, "Human Flourishing Versus Desire Satisfaction," Social Philosophy and Policy 16, no. 1 (1999): 113-42.
    • (1999) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.16 , Issue.1 , pp. 113-142
    • Arneson, R.1
  • 25
    • 0003956640 scopus 로고
    • For an influential discussion, see, Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • For an influential discussion, see Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), 227.
    • (1986) The Morality of Freedom , pp. 227
    • Raz, J.1
  • 26
    • 33644891572 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Justifiability to Each Person
    • Derek Parfit, "Justifiability to Each Person," Ratio 16, no. 4 (2003): 368-90.
    • (2003) Ratio , vol.16 , Issue.4 , pp. 368-390
    • Parfit, D.1
  • 27
    • 0039093654 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here I am following David McNaughton and Piers Rawling, Agent-Relativity and the Doing-Happening Distinction, Philosophical Studies 63, no. 2 (1991): 167-85.
    • Here I am following David McNaughton and Piers Rawling, "Agent-Relativity and the Doing-Happening Distinction," Philosophical Studies 63, no. 2 (1991): 167-85.
  • 28
    • 0003992022 scopus 로고
    • For influential earlier discussions, see, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • For influential earlier discussions, see Thomas Nagel, The Possibility of Altruism (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1970), 90-96;
    • (1970) The Possibility of Altruism , pp. 90-96
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 29
    • 0004207980 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Nagel, The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), 153;
    • (1986) The View from Nowhere , pp. 153
    • Nagel1
  • 30
    • 56749121472 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Parfit, Reasons and Persons, 143. Michael Ridge puts forward metaphysical objections to this account of agent-relative duties (Ridge, Reasons for Action: Agent-Relative vs. Agent-Neutral, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/reasons-agent/#4). I am not persuaded by these objections.
    • and Parfit, Reasons and Persons, 143. Michael Ridge puts forward metaphysical objections to this account of agent-relative duties (Ridge, "Reasons for Action: Agent-Relative vs. Agent-Neutral," http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/reasons-agent/#4). I am not persuaded by these objections.
  • 31
    • 85052248588 scopus 로고
    • Famine, Affluence, and Morality
    • Peter Singer, "Famine, Affluence, and Morality," Philosophy and Public Affairs 1, no. 1 (1972): 249-73.
    • (1972) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.1 , Issue.1 , pp. 249-273
    • Singer, P.1
  • 39
    • 56749115259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Tim Chappell, ed., Moral Demand-ingness (London: Palgrave, 2008).
    • and Tim Chappell, ed., Moral Demand-ingness (London: Palgrave, 2008).
  • 40
    • 56749111733 scopus 로고
    • Moral Character and the Iteration Problem
    • Here I have been most influenced by
    • Here I have been most influenced by Garrett Cullity, "Moral Character and the Iteration Problem," Utilitas 7, no. 2 (1995): 279-89.
    • (1995) Utilitas , vol.7 , Issue.2 , pp. 279-289
    • Cullity, G.1
  • 41
    • 56749145471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See my Ideal Code, Real World: A Rule-Consequentialist Theory of Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), 147-74;
    • See my Ideal Code, Real World: A Rule-Consequentialist Theory of Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), 147-74;
  • 42
    • 56749167299 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • my Rule-Consequentialism and Internal Consistency: A Reply to Card, Utilitas 19, no. 4 (2007): 514-19;
    • my "Rule-Consequentialism and Internal Consistency: A Reply to Card," Utilitas 19, no. 4 (2007): 514-19;
  • 43
    • 56749129506 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and my The Demandingness Objection, in Chappell, ed., Moral Demandingness.
    • and my "The Demandingness Objection," in Chappell, ed., Moral Demandingness.
  • 44
    • 0004312645 scopus 로고
    • As far as I know, Michael Slote first called attention to this aspect of common-sense morality. See, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, chap. 1;
    • As far as I know, Michael Slote first called attention to this aspect of common-sense morality. See Slote, Common-Sense Morality and Consequentialism (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1985), chap. 1;
    • (1985) Common-Sense Morality and Consequentialism
    • Slote1
  • 45
    • 0003952106 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • and Slote, From Morality to Virtue (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), 13-16.
    • (1992) From Morality to Virtue , pp. 13-16
    • Slote1
  • 46
    • 0141655125 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • More recently, Douglas Portmore has stressed this aspect in Portmore, Position-Relative Consequentialism, Agent-Centered Options, and Supererogation, Ethics 113, no. 2 (2003): 303-32, at pp. 311-14;
    • More recently, Douglas Portmore has stressed this aspect in Portmore, "Position-Relative Consequentialism, Agent-Centered Options, and Supererogation," Ethics 113, no. 2 (2003): 303-32, at pp. 311-14;
  • 47
    • 40849129236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Consequentializing Moral Theories
    • at p
    • Portmore, "Consequentializing Moral Theories," Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 88, no. 1 (2007): 39-73, at p. 58;
    • (2007) Pacific Philosophical Quarterly , vol.88 , Issue.1
    • Portmore1
  • 48
    • 40849119887 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dual-Ranking Act-Consequentialism
    • and Portmore, "Dual-Ranking Act-Consequentialism," Philosophical Studies 138 (2008): 409-27.
    • (2008) Philosophical Studies , vol.138 , pp. 409-427
    • Portmore1
  • 49
    • 56749133600 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I go into more detail about this in my When Is Impartiality Morally Appropriate? in John Cottingham, Brian Feltham, and Philip Stratton-Lake, eds., Partiality and Impartiality: Morality, Special Relationships, and the Wider World (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2009).
    • I go into more detail about this in my "When Is Impartiality Morally Appropriate?" in John Cottingham, Brian Feltham, and Philip Stratton-Lake, eds., Partiality and Impartiality: Morality, Special Relationships, and the Wider World (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2009).
  • 50
    • 56749133599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Famine, Affluence, and Morality; and Kagan
    • See, for example
    • See, for example, Singer, "Famine, Affluence, and Morality"; and Kagan, The Limits of Morality;
    • The Limits of Morality
    • Singer1
  • 51
    • 0004651070 scopus 로고
    • Moral Relativism Defended
    • cf. Gilbert Harman, "Moral Relativism Defended," Philosophical Review 84, no. 1 (1975): 3-22.
    • (1975) Philosophical Review , vol.84 , Issue.1 , pp. 3-22
    • cf1    Harman, G.2
  • 52
    • 0004231635 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, x
    • Bernard Williams, Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), x.
    • (1981) Moral Luck
    • Williams, B.1
  • 53
    • 84974307761 scopus 로고
    • Common Sense and First Principles in Sidgwick's Metltods
    • See
    • See David O. Brink, "Common Sense and First Principles in Sidgwick's Metltods," Social Philosophy and Policy 11, no. 1 (1994): 179-201.
    • (1994) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.11 , Issue.1 , pp. 179-201
    • Brink, D.O.1
  • 54
    • 33748540844 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Intuitionism, Pluralism, and the Foundations of Ethics
    • The theme is prominent in Robert Audi's moral philosophy. See, for example, Walter Sinnott-Armstrong and Mark Timmons, eds, New York: Oxford University Press, 1.996
    • The theme is prominent in Robert Audi's moral philosophy. See, for example, Audi, "Intuitionism, Pluralism, and the Foundations of Ethics," in Walter Sinnott-Armstrong and Mark Timmons, eds., Moral Knowledge? (New York: Oxford University Press, 1.996), 101-36;
    • Moral Knowledge , pp. 101-136
    • Audi1
  • 56
    • 56749099857 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is a point I take up at the end of my Intuitions and Moral Theorizing, in Philip Stratton-Lake, ed., Ethical Intuitionism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002), 161-83.
    • It is a point I take up at the end of my "Intuitions and Moral Theorizing," in Philip Stratton-Lake, ed., Ethical Intuitionism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002), 161-83.
  • 57
    • 0040349812 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An influential discussion of weighted prioritarianism can be found in Derek Parfit, Equality and Priority, Ratio 10, no. 4 (1997, 202-21. For a ground-breaking discussion of the aggregative aspect of most versions of weighted prioritarianism, see Marc Fleurbaey, Bertil Tungodden, and Peter Vallentyne, On the Possibility of Nonaggregative Priority for the Worst Off elsewhere in this
    • An influential discussion of weighted prioritarianism can be found in Derek Parfit, "Equality and Priority," Ratio 10, no. 4 (1997): 202-21. For a ground-breaking discussion of the aggregative aspect of most versions of weighted prioritarianism, see Marc Fleurbaey, Bertil Tungodden, and Peter Vallentyne, "On the Possibility of Nonaggregative Priority for the Worst Off" (elsewhere in this volume).
  • 58
    • 56749115256 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The concept of noninstrumental benefit and the concept of noninstrumental harm seem to me as basic as any in practical reasoning. For a different view, see Talbot Brewer, Is Welfare an Independent Good, elsewhere in this Stephen Darwall takes the concept of someone's welfare to be explained as what anyone who cares about her would rationally want for her for her own sake. See his Welfare and Rational Care Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2002, In contrast, I take the concept of rationally caring about someone for her sake to be explained in terms of caring about her welfare
    • The concept of noninstrumental benefit and the concept of noninstrumental harm seem to me as basic as any in practical reasoning. For a different view, see Talbot Brewer, "Is Welfare an Independent Good?" (elsewhere in this volume). Stephen Darwall takes the concept of someone's welfare to be explained as what anyone who cares about her would rationally want for her for her own sake. See his Welfare and Rational Care (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2002). In contrast, I take the concept of rationally caring about someone for her sake to be explained in terms of caring about her welfare.
  • 59
    • 0003437941 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press, I am grateful to Michael Otsuka for discussion about these matters
    • Cf. Thomas Nagel, Equality and Partiality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1991), 65-70. I am grateful to Michael Otsuka for discussion about these matters.
    • (1991) Equality and Partiality , pp. 65-70
    • Thomas Nagel, C.1
  • 63
    • 0004261059 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Ross, Foundations of Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1939).
    • (1939) Foundations of Ethics
    • Ross1
  • 64
    • 56749111734 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Thomas Nagel, Fragmentation of Value, in Nagel, Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), 128-41.
    • See also Thomas Nagel, "Fragmentation of Value," in Nagel, Mortal Questions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), 128-41.
  • 65
    • 56749094573 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Many recent ideas about combining act-consequentialism with agent-relative restrictions and rights were inspired by Amartya Sen, Rights and Agency, Philosophy and Public Affairs 11, no. 1 1982, 3-39;
    • Many recent ideas about combining act-consequentialism with agent-relative restrictions and rights were inspired by Amartya Sen, "Rights and Agency," Philosophy and Public Affairs 11, no. 1 (1982): 3-39;
  • 66
    • 0039088201 scopus 로고
    • Evaluator Relativity and Consequential Evaluation
    • Sen, "Evaluator Relativity and Consequential Evaluation," Philosophy and Public Affairs 12, no. 2 (1983): 113-32;
    • (1983) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.12 , Issue.2 , pp. 113-132
    • Sen1
  • 67
    • 0039452779 scopus 로고
    • Positional Objectivity
    • For more recent material, see Portmore's essays cited in note 14, though I stress that the views about goodness I attribute to agent-relative act-consequentialism are ones that Portmore's more recent essays have replaced with claims about what the agent has reason to prefer
    • and Sen, "Positional Objectivity," Philosophy and Public Affairs 22, no. 2 (1993): 126-45. For more recent material, see Portmore's essays cited in note 14, though I stress that the views about goodness I attribute to agent-relative act-consequentialism are ones that Portmore's more recent essays have replaced with claims about what the agent has reason to prefer.
    • (1993) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.22 , Issue.2 , pp. 126-145
    • Sen1
  • 68
    • 56749115258 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As Frances Kamm has said to me in discussion, there may be better objections to agent-relative act-consequentialism than mine. I accept that observation, but at least these objections are mine
    • As Frances Kamm has said to me in discussion, there may be better objections to agent-relative act-consequentialism than mine. I accept that observation, but at least these objections are mine.
  • 69
    • 84985409640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A common conception of the distinction between consequentialism and deontology is as follows. Consequentialism starts with a fairly minimal conception of the good (e.g, as welfare) and then derives the value of restrictions, rights, special obligations, permissions, and desert as instruments in the promotion of welfare; deontology gives restrictions, rights, special obligations, permissions, and desert a more foundational, less instrumental role. This common conception of the consequentialism/deontology distinction is threatened by any consequentialist theory that postulates, rather than derives, the value of restrictions, rights, special obligations, permissions, or desert. But my objection to agent-relative act-consequentialism is not that it plays havoc with the common conception of the consequentialism/deontology distinction. For an attack on the consequentialism/deontology distinction, see Adrian S. Piper, A Distinction without a Difference, Midwest Studies in Phil
    • A common conception of the distinction between consequentialism and deontology is as follows. Consequentialism starts with a fairly minimal conception of the good (e.g., as welfare) and then derives the value of restrictions, rights, special obligations, permissions, and desert as instruments in the promotion of welfare; deontology gives restrictions, rights, special obligations, permissions, and desert a more foundational, less instrumental role. This common conception of the consequentialism/deontology distinction is threatened by any consequentialist theory that postulates, rather than derives, the value of restrictions, rights, special obligations, permissions, or desert. But my objection to agent-relative act-consequentialism is not that it plays havoc with the common conception of the consequentialism/deontology distinction. For an attack on the consequentialism/deontology distinction, see Adrian S. Piper, "A Distinction without a Difference," Midwest Studies in Philosophy VII (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1982), 403-35.
  • 70
    • 56749171923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See chapters 6 and 8 of my Ideal Code, Real World.
    • See chapters 6 and 8 of my Ideal Code, Real World.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.