메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 102, Issue 12, 2005, Pages 624-649

Against fictional realism

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 51749099532     PISSN: 0022362X     EISSN: 19398549     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.5840/jphil2005102129     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (80)

References (73)
  • 6
    • 8344280691 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Quantification and Fictional Discourse
    • Anthony Everett and Thomas Hofweber (Stanford: CSLI), see pp. 243-44
    • and Peter van Inwagen, "Quantification and Fictional Discourse," in Anthony Everett and Thomas Hofweber, eds., Empty Names, Fiction, and the Puzzles of Non-Existence (Stanford: CSLI, 2000), pp. 235-47, see pp. 243-44
    • (2000) Empty Names, Fiction, and the Puzzles of Non-Existence , pp. 235-247
    • Van Inwagen, P.1
  • 7
    • 79956499110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Creatures of Fiction, in his Ontology
    • (New York: Cambridge), on p. 43
    • as well as "Creatures of Fiction," in his Ontology, Identity, and Modality (New York: Cambridge, 2001), pp. 37-56, on p. 43
    • (2001) Identity, and Modality , pp. 37-56
  • 8
    • 70450053026 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Existence and Ontological Commitment
    • (New York: Oxford), see pp. 136-38
    • and "Existence and Ontological Commitment," in Michael Loux and Dean Zimmerman, eds., Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics (New York: Oxford, 2003), pp. 131-57, see pp. 136-38. Strict Quineans will insist that our ontological commitments are revealed, not by the natural language sentences we hold true, but rather by the way we choose to paraphrase these into First Order Logic but I will ignore this complication here.
    • (2003) Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics , pp. 131-157
    • Loux, M.1    Zimmerman, D.2
  • 14
    • 0008392464 scopus 로고
    • The Logical Status of Fictional Discourse
    • (New York: Cambridge)
    • The classic statement of the view that utterances of object-fictional sentences should be understood as pretend assertions can be found in John Searle, "The Logical Status of Fictional Discourse," in his Expression and Meaning (New York: Cambridge, 1979), pp. 58-75;
    • (1979) Expression and Meaning , pp. 58-75
    • Searle, J.1
  • 15
    • 38949173964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fictionalism about Fictional Characters
    • See Stuart Brock, "Fictionalism about Fictional Characters," Noûs, XXXVI, 1 (2002): 1-21;
    • (2002) Noûs , vol.36 , Issue.1 , pp. 1-21
    • Brock, S.1
  • 16
    • 0003476974 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge: Harvard)
    • and Kendall Walton, Mimesis as Make-Believe (Cambridge: Harvard, 1990), pp. 396-405, for discussions of the ontological implications, or lack thereof, of object-fictional sentences.
    • (1990) Mimesis As Make-Believe , pp. 396-405
    • Walton, K.1
  • 17
    • 52649138102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hesperus and Phosphorus: Sense, Pretense, and Reference
    • For examples of the former, see Mark Crimmins, "Hesperus and Phosphorus: Sense, Pretense, and Reference," Philosophical Review, CVII, 1 (1998): 2-18;
    • (1998) Philosophical Review , vol.117 , Issue.1 , pp. 2-18
    • Crimmins, M.1
  • 19
    • 34248749117 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge: Blackwell)
    • For examples of the latter, see Mark Richard, "Commitment," in James Tomberlin, ed., Philosophical Perspectives 12 (Cambridge: Blackwell, 1998), pp. 255-81
    • (1998) Philosophical Perspectives , vol.12 , pp. 255-281
    • Tomberlin, J.1
  • 20
    • 37549035460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Seeking a Centaur, Adoring Adonis: Intensional Transitives and Empty Terms
    • (Maiden, MA: Blackwell)
    • and "Seeking a Centaur, Adoring Adonis: Intensional Transitives and Empty Terms," in Howard Wettstein and Peter French, eds., Figurative Language: Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Volume XV (Maiden, MA: Blackwell, 2001), pp. 103-27.
    • (2001) Figurative Language: Midwest Studies in Philosophy , vol.15 , pp. 103-127
    • Wettstein, H.1    French, P.2
  • 21
    • 49049113231 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Empty Names, Fictional Names, Mythical Names
    • See Braun, "Empty Names, Fictional Names, Mythical Names," Noûs, XXXIX, 4 (2005): 596-631;
    • (2005) Noûs , vol.39 , Issue.4 , pp. 596-631
    • Braun1
  • 22
    • 0011087972 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nonexistence
    • Salmon, "Nonexistence," Noûs, XXXII, 3 (1998): 277-319;
    • (1998) Noûs , vol.32 , Issue.3 , pp. 277-319
    • Salmon1
  • 23
    • 57049083210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fiction and Metaphysics, Fictional Characters and Literary Practices
    • and Thomasson, Fiction and Metaphysics, "Fictional Characters and Literary Practices," British Journal of Aesthetics, XLIII, 2 (2003): 138-57
    • (2003) British Journal of Aesthetics , vol.43 , Issue.2 , pp. 138-157
    • Thomasson1
  • 24
    • 79956502074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Speaking of Fictional Characters
    • and "Speaking of Fictional Characters," Dialectica, LVII, 2 (2003): 205-23.
    • (2003) Dialectica , vol.47 , Issue.2 , pp. 205-223
  • 31
    • 38149129646 scopus 로고
    • A Prolegomenon to a Meinongian Semantics
    • September 19
    • Parsons, "A Prolegomenon to a Meinongian Semantics," this JOURNAL, LXXI, 16 (September 19, 1974): 561-80
    • (1974) JOURNAL , vol.71 , Issue.16 , pp. 561-580
    • Parsons1
  • 32
    • 54749158295 scopus 로고
    • Are There Nonexistent Objects?
    • Nonexistent Objects, and "Are There Nonexistent Objects?" American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, XIX (1982): 365-71;
    • (1982) American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly , vol.19 , pp. 365-371
  • 34
    • 34547713183 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for example, Lamarque, "Objects of Interpretation," Metaphilosophy, XXXI, 1/2 (2000): 96-124 (see in particular p. 120);
    • (2000) Metaphilosophy , vol.31 , Issue.1-2 , pp. 96-124
    • Lamarque, O.1
  • 36
    • 79956846100 scopus 로고
    • Evans's original argument is in his "Can There Be Vague Objects?" Analysis, XXXVIII (1978): 208. There is an enormous body of literature on Evans's argument to which I cannot hope to do justice here, but see Timothy Williamson, "Vagueness in Reality," in Loux and Zimmerman, eds., for an excellent discussion of the relevant issues and references to the relevant literature.
    • (1978) Evans's Original Argument Is in His Can There Be Vague Objects? Analysis , vol.38 , pp. 208
  • 37
    • 79956765786 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fuzzy Logic and Vague Identity
    • (October)
    • For an application of fuzzy logic to Evans's argument, see B. Jack Copeland's excellent "Fuzzy Logic and Vague Identity," this JOURNAL, XCIV, 10 (October 1997): 514-34.
    • (1997) JOURNAL , vol.94 , Issue.10 , pp. 514-534
    • Jack Copeland'S, B.1
  • 38
    • 34250481936 scopus 로고
    • The Logic of Inexact Concepts
    • For classic expositions of fuzzy logic, see Joseph Goguen, "The Logic of Inexact Concepts," Synthese, XIX (1969): 325-73;
    • (1969) Synthese , vol.19 , pp. 325-373
    • Goguen, J.1
  • 40
    • 0010023020 scopus 로고
    • Truth, Belief, and Vagueness
    • and "Truth, Belief, and Vagueness," Journal of Philosophical Logic, V (1976): 47-78;
    • (1976) Journal of Philosophical Logic , pp. 47-78
  • 42
    • 0004115597 scopus 로고
    • (Ithaca, NY: Cornell)
    • Van Inwagen makes a similar point in his Material Beings (Ithaca, NY: Cornell, 1990), p. 240.
    • (1990) Material Beings , pp. 240
    • Inwagen, V.1
  • 43
    • 4444248630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Puzzle of Imaginative Resistance
    • (February)
    • These examples might be multiplied. With sufficient ingenuity we might construct stories where, for example, the law of excluded middle, the reflexivity of identity, the transitivity of identity, and the laws of arithmetic, fail to apply to identity statements involving the denizens of the stories and hence fail to apply to the fictional characters occurring in those stories. Indeed, Tamar Szabo Gendler's The Tower of Goldbach (see her "The Puzzle of Imaginative Resistance," this JOURNAL, XCVII, 2 (February 2000): 55-81) provides a case where, arguably, 7 fictional characters plus 5 fictional characters both does and does not equal 12 fictional characters.
    • (2000) JOURNAL , vol.97 , Issue.2 , pp. 55-81
  • 44
    • 84909389938 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Tower of Goldbach and Other Impossible Tales
    • (New York: Routledge)
    • We might, for example, take my stories to be describing conceptual impossibilities and agree with Kathleen Stock that we cannot imagine conceptual impossibilities; see her "The Tower of Goldbach and Other Impossible Tales," in Matthew Kieran and Dominic Lopes, eds., Imagination, Philosophy, and the Arts (New York: Routledge, 2003), pp. 107-24.
    • (2003) Imagination, Philosophy, and the Arts , pp. 107-124
    • Kieran, M.1    Lopes, D.2
  • 45
    • 22144435701 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Morality, Fiction, and Possibility
    • Of course, Stock's arguments raise the question of what counts as a conceptual impossibility. But, putting this issue to one side, I think there are serious reasons to doubt their cogency. Brian Weatherson, "Morality, Fiction, and Possibility," The Philosopher's Imprint, IV (2004): 1-27 (see especially pp. 10-11) raises some well-taken worries about some of Stock's arguments and I give some further reasons to suppose can imagine the logically incoherent below.
    • (2004) The Philosopher's Imprint , vol.4 , pp. 1-27
    • Weatherson, B.1
  • 46
    • 85039110664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Puzzle of Imaginative Resistance, and on the Relationship between Pretense and Belief
    • See Szabo Gendler's "The Puzzle of Imaginative Resistance," and "On the Relationship between Pretense and Belief," in Kieran and Lopes, pp. 139-40, for a defense of our ability to imagine conceptual impossibilities. Weatherson, "Morality, Fiction, and Possibility," argues that we are able to imagine certain impossibilities although he is more cautious than Gendler about our ability to imagine conceptual impossibilities.
    • Kieran and Lopes , pp. 139-140
    • Gendler'S, S.1
  • 48
    • 0040310755 scopus 로고
    • (New York: Cambridge)
    • This sort of view is defended by, amongst others, Greg Currie in his The Nature of Fiction (New York: Cambridge, 1990)
    • (1990) The Nature of Fiction
    • Currie, G.1
  • 49
    • 0000327154 scopus 로고
    • Imagination and Simulation
    • Martin Davies and Tony Stone, eds. (Cambridge: Blackwell)
    • No doubt there is a lot of work still to be done in unpacking these concepts but I think that we have a solid pre-theoretic grasp upon these notions and there is an increasing body of interesting work in philosophy and psychology on pretense and the imagination. See, for example, Currie, "Imagination and Simulation," in Martin Davies and Tony Stone, eds., Mental Simulation (Cambridge: Blackwell, 1995), pp. 151-69
    • (1995) Mental Simulation , pp. 151-169
    • Currie1
  • 50
    • 0342335438 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Paradox of Caring
    • New York: Oxford
    • "The Paradox of Caring," in Mette Hjort and Sue Laver, eds., Emotion and the Arts (New York: Oxford, 1997), pp. 63-77
    • (1997) Emotion and the Arts , pp. 63-77
    • Hjort, M.1    Laver, S.2
  • 51
    • 0002584962 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pretense, Pretending, and Metarepresenting
    • and "Pretense, Pretending, and Metarepresenting," Mind and Language, XIII, 1 (1998): 35-55;
    • (1998) Mind and Language , vol.13 , Issue.1 , pp. 35-55
  • 54
    • 79956411427 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Imagining and Pretending
    • Davies and Stone (Malden, MA: Blackwell)
    • Paul Harris, "Imagining and Pretending," in Davies and Stone, eds., and The Work of the Imagination (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2000);
    • (2000) The Work of the Imagination
    • Harris, P.1
  • 55
    • 0342853829 scopus 로고
    • Pretense and Representation
    • Alan Leslie, "Pretense and Representation," Psychological Review, XCIV (1987): 412-26;
    • (1987) Psychological Review , vol.94 , pp. 412-426
    • Leslie, A.1
  • 56
    • 85121324142 scopus 로고
    • Making Sense of Pretence
    • Charlie Lewis and Peter Mitchell, eds, Hillside, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum
    • Angeline Lillard, "Making Sense of Pretence," in Charlie Lewis and Peter Mitchell, eds., Children's Early Understanding of Mind: Origins and Development (Hillside, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum, 1994), pp. 211-34
    • (1994) Children's Early Understanding of Mind: Origins and Development , pp. 211-234
    • Lillard, A.1
  • 57
    • 0345758543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pretending, Understanding Pretense, and Understanding Minds
    • Westport, CT: Ablex
    • "Pretending, Understanding Pretense, and Understanding Minds," in Stuart Reifel, ed., Theory in Context and Out (Westport, CT: Ablex, 2001), pp. 233-54
    • (2001) Theory in Context and Out , pp. 233-254
    • Reifel, S.1
  • 58
    • 21244497724 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Just Through the Looking Glass: Children's Understanding of Pretense
    • (New York: Cambridge)
    • and "Just Through the Looking Glass: Children's Understanding of Pretense," in Robert Mitchell, ed., Pretending and Imagination in Animals and Children (New York: Cambridge, 2002), pp. 102-14;
    • (2002) Pretending and Imagination in Animals and Children , pp. 102-114
    • Mitchell, R.1
  • 60
    • 33747732649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Imagination and the Puzzles of Iteration
    • Shaun Nichols, "Imagination and the Puzzles of Iteration," Analysis, LXIII (2003): 182-87
    • (2003) Analysis , vol.63 , pp. 182-187
    • Nichols, S.1
  • 61
    • 33747716303 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Imagining and Believing: The Promise of a Single Code
    • "Imagining and Believing: The Promise of a Single Code," Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, LXII (2004): 129-39
    • (2004) Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism , vol.62 , pp. 129-139
  • 62
    • 85039118573 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Just the Imagination: Why Imagining Doesn't Behave Like Believing
    • "Just the Imagination: Why Imagining Doesn't Behave Like Believing," forthcoming in Mind and Language;
    • Mind and Language
  • 65
    • 84985788212 scopus 로고
    • Metaphor and Prop Oriented Make-Believe
    • and Walton, Mimesis as Make-Believe, "Metaphor and Prop Oriented Make-Believe," The European Journal of Philosophy, I, 1 (1993): 39-57
    • (1993) The European Journal of Philosophy , vol.1 , Issue.1 , pp. 39-57
  • 67
    • 0004045957 scopus 로고
    • (New York: Oxford)
    • In addition to the principles noted above, our pretense will almost certainly also be governed by some restricted version of the Incorporation Principle and the Recursive Principle discussed by Evans, The Varieties of Reference (New York: Oxford, 1982), pp. 354-55. Note however that Evans's Incorporation Principle and his Recursive Principle are in general unlikely to hold without restriction for the sorts of reasons discussed by Walton and due to the sorts of cases of disparity discussed by Szabo Gendler in her "On the Relationship between Pretense and Belief."
    • (1982) The Varieties of Reference , pp. 354-355
    • Evans1
  • 69
    • 0000605706 scopus 로고
    • On Denoting
    • especially p. 438
    • See Russell, "On Denoting," Mind, XIV, 56 (1905): 479-93, especially p. 438.
    • (1905) Mind , vol.14 , Issue.56 , pp. 479-493
    • Russell1
  • 73
    • 79956441450 scopus 로고
    • Russell's Critique of Meinong's Theory of Objects
    • See also Nicholas Griffin, "Russell's Critique of Meinong's Theory of Objects," Grazer Philosophische Studien, XXV/XXVI (1985/1986): 375-401.
    • (1985) Grazer Philosophische Studien , vol.15-16 , pp. 375-401
    • Griffin, N.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.