-
2
-
-
44949160847
-
Antidiscrimination Laws and the First Amendment,
-
83
-
David E. Bernstein, "Antidiscrimination Laws and the First Amendment," Missouri Law Review 66 (2001): 83, 105 n. 109;
-
(2001)
Missouri Law Review
, vol.66
, Issue.109
, pp. 105
-
-
Bernstein, D.E.1
-
3
-
-
44949234403
-
-
Moose Lodge No. 107 v. Irvis, 407 U.S. 163, 173 (1972).
-
Moose Lodge No. 107 v. Irvis, 407 U.S. 163, 173 (1972).
-
-
-
-
4
-
-
44949203327
-
-
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press
-
Robert A. Horn, Groups and the Constitution (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1956), 7;
-
(1956)
Groups and the Constitution
, pp. 7
-
-
Horn, R.A.1
-
5
-
-
0003228117
-
The Claim to Freedom of Conscience: Freedom of Speech, Freedom of Thought, Freedom of Worship?
-
see also, Ole Peter Grell, Jonathan I. Israel, and Nicholas Tyacke, eds, Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
see also John Dunn, "The Claim to Freedom of Conscience: Freedom of Speech, Freedom of Thought, Freedom of Worship?" in Ole Peter Grell, Jonathan I. Israel, and Nicholas Tyacke, eds., From Persecution to Toleration: The Glorious Revolution and Religion in England (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), 170-93.
-
(1991)
From Persecution to Toleration: The Glorious Revolution and Religion in England
, pp. 170-193
-
-
Dunn, J.1
-
6
-
-
44949172316
-
-
References to Locke's Letter Concerning Toleration are made not in the notes but parenthetically in the text, with the following conventions. LT 32 refers to William Popple's translation of A Letter Concerning Toleration London: Printed for Awnsham Churchill, 1689, page 32. I thank Tom West for pointing out to me several discrepancies between Popple's translation and Locke's original Latin
-
References to Locke's Letter Concerning Toleration are made not in the notes but parenthetically in the text, with the following conventions. "LT 32" refers to William Popple's translation of A Letter Concerning Toleration (London: Printed for Awnsham Churchill, 1689), page 32. I thank Tom West for pointing out to me several discrepancies between Popple's translation and Locke's original Latin.
-
-
-
-
7
-
-
44949110853
-
-
In cases involving those discrepancies, I translate Locke's Latin myself, citing John Locke, Epistola de Tolerantia: A Letter on Toleration, ed. Raymond Klibansky, trans. J. W. Gough (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1968).
-
In cases involving those discrepancies, I translate Locke's Latin myself, citing John Locke, Epistola de Tolerantia: A Letter on Toleration, ed. Raymond Klibansky, trans. J. W. Gough (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1968).
-
-
-
-
8
-
-
44949187221
-
-
References to Locke's other major, mature writings are also made in the text, with the following conventions: TT I.86 refers to John Locke, Two Treatises of Government, student edition, ed. Peter Laslett (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), treatise 1, section 86. ECHU II.21.51 refers to John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. Peter H. Nidditch (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979),
-
References to Locke's other major, mature writings are also made in the text, with the following conventions: "TT I.86" refers to John Locke, Two Treatises of Government, student edition, ed. Peter Laslett (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), treatise 1, section 86. "ECHU II.21.51" refers to John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. Peter H. Nidditch (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979),
-
-
-
-
9
-
-
44949087316
-
-
book 2, chapter 21, paragraph 51. RC 235 refers to John Locke, The Reasonableness of Christianity, ed. George W. Ewing (Washington, DC: Regnery Gateway, 1965), paragraph 235. STCE 70 refers to John Locke, Some Thoughts Concerning Education, in Locke, Some Thoughts Concerning Education and Of the Conduct of the Understanding, ed. Ruth W. Grant and Nathan Tarcov (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co., 1996), paragraph 70. In quoted passages, all italics are in the original unless otherwise noted.
-
book 2, chapter 21, paragraph 51. "RC 235" refers to John Locke, The Reasonableness of Christianity, ed. George W. Ewing (Washington, DC: Regnery Gateway, 1965), paragraph 235. "STCE 70" refers to John Locke, Some Thoughts Concerning Education, in Locke, Some Thoughts Concerning Education and Of the Conduct of the Understanding, ed. Ruth W. Grant and Nathan Tarcov (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co., 1996), paragraph 70. In quoted passages, all italics are in the original unless otherwise noted.
-
-
-
-
12
-
-
24944486253
-
John Locke and the Case for Toleration
-
Susan Mendus and David Edwards, eds, New York: Oxford University Press, and passim
-
Maurice Cranston, "John Locke and the Case for Toleration," in Susan Mendus and David Edwards, eds., On Toleration (New York: Oxford University Press, 1987), 101-21, 119 and passim.
-
(1987)
On Toleration
, vol.101 -21
, pp. 119
-
-
Cranston, M.1
-
13
-
-
44949128756
-
-
Similarly, while Ingrid Creppell treats Locke's Letter Concerning Toleration as justifying a broader theory of liberalism, she works with Locke's observations on religion and not with his observations on private associations generally.
-
Similarly, while Ingrid Creppell treats Locke's Letter Concerning Toleration as justifying a broader theory of liberalism, she works with Locke's observations on religion and not with his observations on private associations generally.
-
-
-
-
14
-
-
0030531851
-
-
See Ingrid Creppell, Locke on Toleration: The Transformation of Constraint, Political Theory 24, no. 2 (1996): 200, 226, 228-29.
-
See Ingrid Creppell, "Locke on Toleration: The Transformation of Constraint," Political Theory 24, no. 2 (1996): 200, 226, 228-29.
-
-
-
-
15
-
-
44949248910
-
-
See Richard Boyd, The Madisonian Paradox of Freedom of Association elsewhere in this
-
See Richard Boyd, "The Madisonian Paradox of Freedom of Association" (elsewhere in this volume);
-
-
-
-
16
-
-
0003891561
-
-
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
-
and A. John Simmons, On the Edge of Anarchy: Locke, Consent, and the Limits of Society (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993), 135-36.
-
(1993)
On the Edge of Anarchy: Locke, Consent, and the Limits of Society
, pp. 135-136
-
-
John Simmons, A.1
-
17
-
-
84970773446
-
Liberalism and the Art of Separation
-
315
-
Michael Walzer, "Liberalism and the Art of Separation," Political Theory 12, no. 3 (1984): 315, 324;
-
(1984)
Political Theory
, vol.12
, Issue.3
, pp. 324
-
-
Walzer, M.1
-
19
-
-
44949203326
-
-
LT 15. Popple's translation suggests that the right of private society is not only immutable but also fundamental. Locke's Latin has no word corresponding to fundamental.
-
LT 15. Popple's translation suggests that the right of private society is not only "immutable" but also "fundamental." Locke's Latin has no word corresponding to "fundamental."
-
-
-
-
20
-
-
0004273805
-
-
See, for example, New York: Basic Books
-
See, for example, Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 300-302.
-
(1974)
Anarchy, State, and Utopia
, pp. 300-302
-
-
Nozick, R.1
-
21
-
-
84974127275
-
John Locke: Social Contract Versus Political Anthropology
-
See, Winter
-
See Jeremy Waldron, "John Locke: Social Contract Versus Political Anthropology," The Review of Politics 51, no. 1 (Winter 1989): 3-28.
-
(1989)
The Review of Politics
, vol.51
, Issue.1
, pp. 3-28
-
-
Waldron, J.1
-
22
-
-
0000921466
-
Justice as Fairness
-
For more general criticisms of the consent principle, consider
-
For more general criticisms of the consent principle, consider John Rawls, "Justice as Fairness," Philosophical Review 67 (1958): 178.
-
(1958)
Philosophical Review
, vol.67
, pp. 178
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
23
-
-
84974173064
-
Locke's Political Anthropology and Lockean Individualism
-
February, 42
-
Ruth W. Grant, "Locke's Political Anthropology and Lockean Individualism," Journal of Politics 50, no. 1 (February 1988): 42, 59-60;
-
(1988)
Journal of Politics
, vol.50
, Issue.1
, pp. 59-60
-
-
Grant, R.W.1
-
26
-
-
44949191163
-
-
See also J. W. Gough, John Locke's Political Philosophy, 2d ed. (London: Oxford University Press, 1973), 14 (finding a basic inconsistency between [Locke's] earlier belief in absolute moral principles and his tendency later to think in hedonistic terms);
-
See also J. W. Gough, John Locke's Political Philosophy, 2d ed. (London: Oxford University Press, 1973), 14 (finding a "basic inconsistency between [Locke's] earlier belief in absolute moral principles and his tendency later to think in hedonistic terms");
-
-
-
-
27
-
-
44949256989
-
-
and Raymond Polin, John Locke's Conception of Freedom, in John Locke: Problems and Perspectives, ed. John W. Yolton (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969), 1 (traditional interpreters of John Locke like to pretend that he professed simultaneously a theoretical philosophy of empirical style and a practical philosophy of innatist inspiration).
-
and Raymond Polin, "John Locke's Conception of Freedom," in John Locke: Problems and Perspectives, ed. John W. Yolton (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969), 1 ("traditional interpreters of John Locke like to pretend that he professed simultaneously a theoretical philosophy of empirical style and a practical philosophy of innatist inspiration").
-
-
-
-
28
-
-
44949235890
-
-
Letter from John Locke to Richard King, August 25, 1703, cited in Andrzej Rapaczynski, Nature and Politics: Liberalism in the Philosophies of Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1987), 15 and n. 11.
-
Letter from John Locke to Richard King, August 25, 1703, cited in Andrzej Rapaczynski, Nature and Politics: Liberalism in the Philosophies of Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1987), 15 and n. 11.
-
-
-
-
30
-
-
77954067695
-
John Locke: From Absolutism to Toleration
-
See
-
See Robert P. Kraynak, "John Locke: From Absolutism to Toleration," The American Political Science Review 74, no. 1 (1980): 53-69.
-
(1980)
The American Political Science Review
, vol.74
, Issue.1
, pp. 53-69
-
-
Kraynak, R.P.1
-
31
-
-
44949130471
-
-
By describing Locke as a philosopher, this interpretation comes into some tension with more historically focused interpretations that prefer to read Locke primarily in the context of the problems of England in his day. See
-
By describing Locke as a philosopher, this interpretation comes into some tension with more historically focused interpretations that prefer to read Locke primarily in the context of the problems of England in his day. See Laslett, "Introduction," 76;
-
Introduction
, vol.76
-
-
Laslett1
-
33
-
-
44949124313
-
-
Although Locke's Of the Conduct of the Understanding targets the same audience, on the topics covered here that work is less relevant than and adds little to the Essay. I pass over Locke's subsequent letters on toleration for similar reasons
-
Although Locke's Of the Conduct of the Understanding targets the same audience, on the topics covered here that work is less relevant than and adds little to the Essay. I pass over Locke's subsequent letters on toleration for similar reasons.
-
-
-
-
34
-
-
0004166819
-
-
Chicago: University of Chicago Press
-
Ruth W. Grant, John Locke's Liberalism (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987), 8-9.
-
(1987)
John Locke's Liberalism
, pp. 8-9
-
-
Grant, R.W.1
-
35
-
-
44949260731
-
-
For similar approaches to interpreting Locke, consider Michael P. Zuckert, Launching Liberalism: On Lockean Political Philosophy (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 2002), 3-17;
-
For similar approaches to interpreting Locke, consider Michael P. Zuckert, Launching Liberalism: On Lockean Political Philosophy (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 2002), 3-17;
-
-
-
-
39
-
-
0004152043
-
Persecution and the Art of Writing
-
488
-
and Leo Strauss, "Persecution and the Art of Writing," Social Research 8, no. 1 (1941): 488, 503 n. 21.
-
(1941)
Social Research
, vol.8
, Issue.1-21
, pp. 503
-
-
Strauss, L.1
-
43
-
-
44949118296
-
-
On this point, I follow Thomas West, Ruth Grant, A. John Simmons, and Nathan Tarcov more than I do Michael Zuckert. Zuckert grounds Locke's normative claims in self-ownership, which is not necessarily eudaimonistic. See
-
On this point, I follow Thomas West, Ruth Grant, A. John Simmons, and Nathan Tarcov more than I do Michael Zuckert. Zuckert grounds Locke's normative claims in "self-ownership," which is not necessarily eudaimonistic. See Zuckert, Launching Liberalism, 4-5, 193-95;
-
Launching Liberalism
, vol.4-5
, pp. 193-195
-
-
Zuckert1
-
44
-
-
44949227672
-
-
see also Thomas G. West, Nature and Happiness in Locke, The Claremont Review of Books 4, no. 2 (2004) (reviewing Zuckert, Launching Liberalism), available online at http://www.claremont.org/ publications/pubid.659/pub_detail.asp;
-
see also Thomas G. West, "Nature and Happiness in Locke," The Claremont Review of Books 4, no. 2 (2004) (reviewing Zuckert, Launching Liberalism), available online at http://www.claremont.org/ publications/pubid.659/pub_detail.asp;
-
-
-
-
49
-
-
33748451349
-
-
See also Nomi M. Stolzenberg and Gideon Yaffe, Waldron's Locke and Locke's Waldron: A Review of Jeremy Waldron's God, Locke, and Equality, Inquiry 49, no. 2 (2006): 186, 197-202 (criticizing Waldron for reading Locke as a deontologist and not a utilitarian).
-
See also Nomi M. Stolzenberg and Gideon Yaffe, "Waldron's Locke and Locke's Waldron: A Review of Jeremy Waldron's God, Locke, and Equality," Inquiry 49, no. 2 (2006): 186, 197-202 (criticizing Waldron for reading Locke as a deontologist and not a utilitarian).
-
-
-
-
50
-
-
44949174711
-
-
See Alasdair MacIntyre, Hume on the 'Is' and the 'Ought', in MacIntyre, Against the Self-Images of the Age: Essays on Ideology and Philosophy (South Bend, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1978): 109, 124;
-
See Alasdair MacIntyre, "Hume on the 'Is' and the 'Ought'," in MacIntyre, Against the Self-Images of the Age: Essays on Ideology and Philosophy (South Bend, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1978): 109, 124;
-
-
-
-
51
-
-
84974286205
-
-
G. E. Anscombe, Modern Moral Philosophy, Philosophy 33, no. 124 (1958): 1, 2 (general criticisms of Kantian deontology);
-
G. E. Anscombe, "Modern Moral Philosophy," Philosophy 33, no. 124 (1958): 1, 2 (general criticisms of Kantian deontology);
-
-
-
-
54
-
-
0003687723
-
-
Chicago: University of Chicago Press
-
Leo Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953), 202-51;
-
(1953)
Natural Right and History
, pp. 202-251
-
-
Strauss, L.1
-
55
-
-
0038958021
-
John Locke
-
Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, eds, 3d ed, Chicago: University of Chicago Press
-
and Robert A. Goldwin, "John Locke," in Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, eds., History of Political Philosophy, 3d ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987), 476.
-
(1987)
History of Political Philosophy
, pp. 476
-
-
Goldwin, R.A.1
-
62
-
-
44949254718
-
-
Aristotle, Politics, 1255a3-a20;
-
Aristotle, Politics, 1255a3-a20;
-
-
-
-
66
-
-
44949226740
-
-
The following discussion relies substantially on insights from Zuckert, Launching Liberalism, 146-68;
-
The following discussion relies substantially on insights from Zuckert, Launching Liberalism, 146-68;
-
-
-
-
69
-
-
0001775066
-
Locke: Toleration and the Rationality of Persecution
-
ed, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 61
-
Jeremy Waldron, "Locke: Toleration and the Rationality of Persecution," in Susan Mendus, ed., Justifying Toleration: Conceptual and Historical Perspectives (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 61, 64-67, 80-82.
-
(1988)
Justifying Toleration: Conceptual and Historical Perspectives
-
-
Waldron, J.1
-
75
-
-
84971947053
-
Locke and Feminism on Private and Public Realms of Activities
-
Spring, 251
-
Mary B. Walsh, "Locke and Feminism on Private and Public Realms of Activities," Review of Politics 57, no. 2 (Spring 1995): 251, 261-62;
-
(1995)
Review of Politics
, vol.57
, Issue.2
, pp. 261-262
-
-
Walsh, M.B.1
-
77
-
-
44949160846
-
-
See Aristotle, Politics, 1252b27-1253a38;
-
See Aristotle, Politics, 1252b27-1253a38;
-
-
-
-
78
-
-
44949142764
-
-
Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1155a22-28, 1167a26-30;
-
Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1155a22-28, 1167a26-30;
-
-
-
-
79
-
-
0004048289
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 23-32;
-
(1971)
A Theory of Justice
, pp. 23-32
-
-
Rawls, J.1
-
81
-
-
44949251537
-
-
2d ed, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Michael J. Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice, 2d ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 9-14, 60-67;
-
(1992)
Liberalism and the Limits of Justice
, vol.9-14
, pp. 60-67
-
-
Sandel, M.J.1
-
83
-
-
44949128755
-
-
From this paragraph until the end of this section, my argument has been informed substantially by
-
From this paragraph until the end of this section, my argument has been informed substantially by Myers, Our Only Star and Compass, 123-29, 196-97.
-
Our Only Star and Compass
, vol.123 -29
, pp. 196-197
-
-
Myers1
-
84
-
-
44949229000
-
-
See Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1155a20-b1.
-
See Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1155a20-b1.
-
-
-
-
86
-
-
44949180537
-
-
See
-
See TT I.58-59;
-
, vol.58-59
-
-
TT, I.1
-
89
-
-
44949120180
-
noninjurious
-
is a term of art meant to exclude acts that threaten harms the public may properly protect against, to be sketched in Section VI
-
Here, "noninjurious" is a term of art meant to exclude acts that threaten harms the public may properly protect against, to be sketched in Section VI.
-
-
-
Here1
-
90
-
-
44949222320
-
-
See David McGowan, Making Sense of Dale, Constitutional Commentary 18 (2001): 121, 125, 157 (discussing Boy Scouts of America v. Dale, 530 U.S. 640, 648-53 [2000]).
-
See David McGowan, "Making Sense of Dale," Constitutional Commentary 18 (2001): 121, 125, 157 (discussing Boy Scouts of America v. Dale, 530 U.S. 640, 648-53 [2000]).
-
-
-
-
91
-
-
44949250606
-
-
See Dale, 530 U.S. at 649-50;
-
See Dale, 530 U.S. at 649-50;
-
-
-
-
92
-
-
44949192610
-
-
Roberts v. United States Jaycees, 468 U.S. 609, 617-23 (1984);
-
Roberts v. United States Jaycees, 468 U.S. 609, 617-23 (1984);
-
-
-
-
93
-
-
44949092139
-
-
and ibid. at 634-646 (O'Connor, J., concurring in the judgment). Here and henceforth, I use judicial opinions as expressions of conventional political wisdom, to show how contemporary political opinions contrast with Locke's. I do not cover the many legal issues that would need to be addressed before determining whether each of these cases was correctly decided as a matter of constitutional law.
-
and ibid. at 634-646 (O'Connor, J., concurring in the judgment). Here and henceforth, I use judicial opinions as expressions of conventional political wisdom, to show how contemporary political opinions contrast with Locke's. I do not cover the many legal issues that would need to be addressed before determining whether each of these cases was correctly decided as a matter of constitutional law.
-
-
-
-
94
-
-
44949088287
-
-
See Dale, 530 U.S. at 648;
-
See Dale, 530 U.S. at 648;
-
-
-
-
95
-
-
44949125260
-
-
Roberts, 468 U.S. at 623.
-
Roberts, 468 U.S. at 623.
-
-
-
-
97
-
-
44949198982
-
-
I thank Eric Miller and Andy Koppelman for encouraging me to make this point explicit
-
I thank Eric Miller and Andy Koppelman for encouraging me to make this point explicit.
-
-
-
-
99
-
-
44949144705
-
-
For Popple's translation, see LT 40-41.
-
For Popple's translation, see LT 40-41.
-
-
-
-
100
-
-
44949115782
-
-
See TT I.59;
-
See TT I.59;
-
-
-
-
101
-
-
44949198981
-
-
Davis v. Beason, 133 U.S. 33, 342-43 (1890);
-
Davis v. Beason, 133 U.S. 33, 342-43 (1890);
-
-
-
-
102
-
-
44949188166
-
-
Reynolds v. United States, 98 U.S. 145, 164-64 (1879);
-
Reynolds v. United States, 98 U.S. 145, 164-64 (1879);
-
-
-
-
104
-
-
44949105246
-
-
McCreary County v. American Civil Liberties Union, 545 U.S. 844, 860 (2005) (quoting Epperson v. Arkansas, 393 U.S. 97, 104 [1968]).
-
McCreary County v. American Civil Liberties Union, 545 U.S. 844, 860 (2005) (quoting Epperson v. Arkansas, 393 U.S. 97, 104 [1968]).
-
-
-
-
106
-
-
44949120179
-
-
compare Zuckert, Launching Liberalism (suggesting that Locke's rationalism and skepticism undermine general public respect for Christianity and encourage deism and agnosticism) with Myers, Our Only Star and Compass, 46-50 (reading Locke as concluding that human faculties point toward the existence of God, even as Locke rests the grounds of human obligation on rationally knowable foundations).
-
compare Zuckert, Launching Liberalism (suggesting that Locke's rationalism and skepticism undermine general public respect for Christianity and encourage deism and agnosticism) with Myers, Our Only Star and Compass, 46-50 (reading Locke as concluding that human faculties point toward the existence of God, even as Locke rests the grounds of human obligation on rationally knowable foundations).
-
-
-
-
107
-
-
44949091174
-
-
For examples of American cases upholding anti-blasphemy laws in the face of constitutional challenges on similar grounds, consider Updegraph v. Commonwealth, 11 Serg. & Rawle 394 (Pa. 1824);
-
For examples of American cases upholding anti-blasphemy laws in the face of constitutional challenges on similar grounds, consider Updegraph v. Commonwealth, 11 Serg. & Rawle 394 (Pa. 1824);
-
-
-
-
108
-
-
44949157072
-
-
and People v. Ruggles, 8 Johns. R. 290 (N.Y. 1811).
-
and People v. Ruggles, 8 Johns. R. 290 (N.Y. 1811).
-
-
-
-
109
-
-
44949162667
-
-
See ECHU I.3.6; RC 243;
-
See ECHU I.3.6; RC 243;
-
-
-
-
111
-
-
44949228999
-
-
Here Locke contradicts the position he took in his 1667 Essay on Toleration, in John Locke, Political Essays, ed. Mark Goldie (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 134-59.
-
Here Locke contradicts the position he took in his 1667 "Essay on Toleration," in John Locke, Political Essays, ed. Mark Goldie (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 134-59.
-
-
-
-
112
-
-
44949127833
-
-
In the text, I also contradict and correct an error I made in Eric R. Claeys, Justice Scalia and the Religion Clauses: A Comment on Professor Epps, Washington University Journal of Law and Policy 21 2006, 349-58, 355 and n. 28
-
In the text, I also contradict and correct an error I made in Eric R. Claeys, "Justice Scalia and the Religion Clauses: A Comment on Professor Epps," Washington University Journal of Law and Policy 21 (2006): 349-58, 355 and n. 28.
-
-
-
-
115
-
-
44949259877
-
Democratic-Republican Societies, Subversion, and the Limits of Legitimate Political Dissent in the Early Republic
-
Robert M. Chesney, "Democratic-Republican Societies, Subversion, and the Limits of Legitimate Political Dissent in the Early Republic," North Carolina Law Review, 82 (2004): 1525.
-
(2004)
North Carolina Law Review
, vol.82
, pp. 1525
-
-
Chesney, R.M.1
-
116
-
-
44949203322
-
-
See 18 U.S.C. sec. 2385 (West 2007);
-
See 18 U.S.C. sec. 2385 (West 2007);
-
-
-
-
118
-
-
84888491658
-
-
sec. 2339B(a)(1) and (g)6, West 2007
-
18 U.S.C. sec. 2339B(a)(1) and (g)(6) (West 2007);
-
18 U.S.C
-
-
-
119
-
-
1342310968
-
Civil Liberties and the Terrorism Prevention Paradigm: The Guilt by Association Critique
-
1408
-
and Robert M. Chesney, "Civil Liberties and the Terrorism Prevention Paradigm: The Guilt by Association Critique," Michigan Law Review 101, no. 6 (2003): 1408, 1432-52.
-
(2003)
Michigan Law Review
, vol.101
, Issue.6
, pp. 1432-1452
-
-
Chesney, R.M.1
-
120
-
-
40749084517
-
-
See, 389 U.S
-
See United States v. Robel, 389 U.S. 258 (1967);
-
(1967)
United States v. Robel
, pp. 258
-
-
-
121
-
-
44949148881
-
-
Keyishian v. Board of Regents, 385 U.S. 589 (1967);
-
Keyishian v. Board of Regents, 385 U.S. 589 (1967);
-
-
-
-
122
-
-
44949179137
-
-
Elfbrandt v. Russell, 384 U.S. 11 (1966);
-
Elfbrandt v. Russell, 384 U.S. 11 (1966);
-
-
-
-
126
-
-
44949089285
-
-
Keyishian v. Board of Regents, 385 U.S. 589, 605-6 (1967);
-
Keyishian v. Board of Regents, 385 U.S. 589, 605-6 (1967);
-
-
-
-
127
-
-
44949179136
-
-
Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616, 630 (1919) (Holmes, J., dissenting);
-
Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616, 630 (1919) (Holmes, J., dissenting);
-
-
-
-
128
-
-
33749842190
-
Illiberalism All the Way Down: Illiberal Groups and Two Conceptions of Liberalism
-
Larry Alexander, "Illiberalism All the Way Down: Illiberal Groups and Two Conceptions of Liberalism," Journal of Contemporary Legal Issues 12 (2002): 625-30.
-
(2002)
Journal of Contemporary Legal Issues
, vol.12
, pp. 625-630
-
-
Alexander, L.1
-
130
-
-
44949149861
-
-
Harry V. Jaffa, On the Nature of Civil and Religious Liberty, in Jaffa, Equality and Liberty: Theory and Practice in American Politics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965), 169-89;
-
Harry V. Jaffa, "On the Nature of Civil and Religious Liberty," in Jaffa, Equality and Liberty: Theory and Practice in American Politics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965), 169-89;
-
-
-
-
131
-
-
44949129492
-
-
and John Marshall, Report of the Minority on the Virginia Resolutions, reprinted in The Founders' Constitution, ed. Philip B. Kurland and Ralph Lerner (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987), 5: 136-39.
-
and John Marshall, "Report of the Minority on the Virginia Resolutions," reprinted in The Founders' Constitution, ed. Philip B. Kurland and Ralph Lerner (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987), 5: 136-39.
-
-
-
-
132
-
-
44949162666
-
-
For examples of national anti-sedition policies that worked relatively effectively, consider Karl Loewenstein, Legislative Control of Political Extremism in European Democracies, I and II, Columbia Law Review 38, no. 5 1938, 591-622 and 725-74
-
For examples of national anti-sedition policies that worked relatively effectively, consider Karl Loewenstein, "Legislative Control of Political Extremism in European Democracies, I and II," Columbia Law Review 38, no. 5 (1938): 591-622 and 725-74.
-
-
-
-
133
-
-
44949093370
-
-
Loewenstein suggests that many European democracies during the interwar period effectively suppressed fascist and socialist parties until they were conquered by Nazi Germany and the Axis. If Loewenstein is correct, these countries' internal policies toward seditionists were effective regardless of whether the countries could be overwhelmed by superior external force
-
Loewenstein suggests that many European democracies during the interwar period effectively suppressed fascist and socialist parties until they were conquered by Nazi Germany and the Axis. If Loewenstein is correct, these countries' internal policies toward seditionists were effective regardless of whether the countries could be overwhelmed by superior external force.
-
-
-
-
134
-
-
44949104024
-
-
Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books
-
John Dewey, Liberalism and Social Action (Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books, 1999), 27, 35.
-
(1999)
Liberalism and Social Action
, vol.27
, pp. 35
-
-
Dewey, J.1
-
138
-
-
44949130594
-
-
see Koppelman, Antidiscrimination Law and Social Equality, 181-90, citing Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), 55.
-
see Koppelman, Antidiscrimination Law and Social Equality, 181-90, citing Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), 55.
-
-
-
-
139
-
-
34250320560
-
E Pluribus Unum: Diversity and Community in the Twenty-First Century
-
See, 137
-
See Robert D. Putnam, "E Pluribus Unum: Diversity and Community in the Twenty-First Century," Scandinavian Political Studies 30, no. 2 (2007): 137, 146-59.
-
(2007)
Scandinavian Political Studies
, vol.30
, Issue.2
, pp. 146-159
-
-
Putnam, R.D.1
-
141
-
-
44949149003
-
-
and Ronald Dworkin, Reverse Discrimination, in Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1978), 227-28.
-
and Ronald Dworkin, "Reverse Discrimination," in Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1978), 227-28.
-
-
-
-
143
-
-
0039579571
-
Reality
-
169
-
Drew S. Days, III, "Reality," San Diego Law Review 31, no. 1 (1994): 169, 170-80;
-
(1994)
San Diego Law Review
, vol.31
, Issue.1
, pp. 170-180
-
-
Days III, D.S.1
-
144
-
-
44949133921
-
Epstein on His Own Grounds
-
241
-
Richard McAdams, "Epstein on His Own Grounds," San Diego Law Review 31, no. 1 (1994): 241, 249-64;
-
(1994)
San Diego Law Review
, vol.31
, Issue.1
, pp. 249-264
-
-
McAdams, R.1
-
145
-
-
84933490859
-
Contractual Liberties in Discriminatory Markets
-
1219
-
Samuel Issacharoff, "Contractual Liberties in Discriminatory Markets," Texas Law Review 70, no. 5 (1992): 1219, 1225-34;
-
(1992)
Texas Law Review
, vol.70
, Issue.5
, pp. 1225-1234
-
-
Issacharoff, S.1
-
146
-
-
10944241068
-
Free to Search
-
2080
-
and J. Hoult Verkerke, "Free to Search," Harvard Law Review 105, no. 8 (1992): 2080, 2088-96.
-
(1992)
Harvard Law Review
, vol.105
, Issue.8
, pp. 2088-2096
-
-
Hoult Verkerke, J.1
|