메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 25, Issue 2, 2008, Pages 201-234

The private society and the liberal public good in John Locke's thought

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 44949150958     PISSN: 02650525     EISSN: 14716437     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0265052508080242     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (2)

References (146)
  • 2
    • 44949160847 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Antidiscrimination Laws and the First Amendment,
    • 83
    • David E. Bernstein, "Antidiscrimination Laws and the First Amendment," Missouri Law Review 66 (2001): 83, 105 n. 109;
    • (2001) Missouri Law Review , vol.66 , Issue.109 , pp. 105
    • Bernstein, D.E.1
  • 3
    • 44949234403 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moose Lodge No. 107 v. Irvis, 407 U.S. 163, 173 (1972).
    • Moose Lodge No. 107 v. Irvis, 407 U.S. 163, 173 (1972).
  • 4
    • 44949203327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press
    • Robert A. Horn, Groups and the Constitution (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1956), 7;
    • (1956) Groups and the Constitution , pp. 7
    • Horn, R.A.1
  • 5
    • 0003228117 scopus 로고
    • The Claim to Freedom of Conscience: Freedom of Speech, Freedom of Thought, Freedom of Worship?
    • see also, Ole Peter Grell, Jonathan I. Israel, and Nicholas Tyacke, eds, Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • see also John Dunn, "The Claim to Freedom of Conscience: Freedom of Speech, Freedom of Thought, Freedom of Worship?" in Ole Peter Grell, Jonathan I. Israel, and Nicholas Tyacke, eds., From Persecution to Toleration: The Glorious Revolution and Religion in England (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), 170-93.
    • (1991) From Persecution to Toleration: The Glorious Revolution and Religion in England , pp. 170-193
    • Dunn, J.1
  • 6
    • 44949172316 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • References to Locke's Letter Concerning Toleration are made not in the notes but parenthetically in the text, with the following conventions. LT 32 refers to William Popple's translation of A Letter Concerning Toleration London: Printed for Awnsham Churchill, 1689, page 32. I thank Tom West for pointing out to me several discrepancies between Popple's translation and Locke's original Latin
    • References to Locke's Letter Concerning Toleration are made not in the notes but parenthetically in the text, with the following conventions. "LT 32" refers to William Popple's translation of A Letter Concerning Toleration (London: Printed for Awnsham Churchill, 1689), page 32. I thank Tom West for pointing out to me several discrepancies between Popple's translation and Locke's original Latin.
  • 7
    • 44949110853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In cases involving those discrepancies, I translate Locke's Latin myself, citing John Locke, Epistola de Tolerantia: A Letter on Toleration, ed. Raymond Klibansky, trans. J. W. Gough (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1968).
    • In cases involving those discrepancies, I translate Locke's Latin myself, citing John Locke, Epistola de Tolerantia: A Letter on Toleration, ed. Raymond Klibansky, trans. J. W. Gough (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1968).
  • 8
    • 44949187221 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • References to Locke's other major, mature writings are also made in the text, with the following conventions: TT I.86 refers to John Locke, Two Treatises of Government, student edition, ed. Peter Laslett (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), treatise 1, section 86. ECHU II.21.51 refers to John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. Peter H. Nidditch (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979),
    • References to Locke's other major, mature writings are also made in the text, with the following conventions: "TT I.86" refers to John Locke, Two Treatises of Government, student edition, ed. Peter Laslett (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), treatise 1, section 86. "ECHU II.21.51" refers to John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. Peter H. Nidditch (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979),
  • 9
    • 44949087316 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • book 2, chapter 21, paragraph 51. RC 235 refers to John Locke, The Reasonableness of Christianity, ed. George W. Ewing (Washington, DC: Regnery Gateway, 1965), paragraph 235. STCE 70 refers to John Locke, Some Thoughts Concerning Education, in Locke, Some Thoughts Concerning Education and Of the Conduct of the Understanding, ed. Ruth W. Grant and Nathan Tarcov (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co., 1996), paragraph 70. In quoted passages, all italics are in the original unless otherwise noted.
    • book 2, chapter 21, paragraph 51. "RC 235" refers to John Locke, The Reasonableness of Christianity, ed. George W. Ewing (Washington, DC: Regnery Gateway, 1965), paragraph 235. "STCE 70" refers to John Locke, Some Thoughts Concerning Education, in Locke, Some Thoughts Concerning Education and Of the Conduct of the Understanding, ed. Ruth W. Grant and Nathan Tarcov (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co., 1996), paragraph 70. In quoted passages, all italics are in the original unless otherwise noted.
  • 12
    • 24944486253 scopus 로고
    • John Locke and the Case for Toleration
    • Susan Mendus and David Edwards, eds, New York: Oxford University Press, and passim
    • Maurice Cranston, "John Locke and the Case for Toleration," in Susan Mendus and David Edwards, eds., On Toleration (New York: Oxford University Press, 1987), 101-21, 119 and passim.
    • (1987) On Toleration , vol.101 -21 , pp. 119
    • Cranston, M.1
  • 13
    • 44949128756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Similarly, while Ingrid Creppell treats Locke's Letter Concerning Toleration as justifying a broader theory of liberalism, she works with Locke's observations on religion and not with his observations on private associations generally.
    • Similarly, while Ingrid Creppell treats Locke's Letter Concerning Toleration as justifying a broader theory of liberalism, she works with Locke's observations on religion and not with his observations on private associations generally.
  • 14
    • 0030531851 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Ingrid Creppell, Locke on Toleration: The Transformation of Constraint, Political Theory 24, no. 2 (1996): 200, 226, 228-29.
    • See Ingrid Creppell, "Locke on Toleration: The Transformation of Constraint," Political Theory 24, no. 2 (1996): 200, 226, 228-29.
  • 15
    • 44949248910 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Richard Boyd, The Madisonian Paradox of Freedom of Association elsewhere in this
    • See Richard Boyd, "The Madisonian Paradox of Freedom of Association" (elsewhere in this volume);
  • 17
    • 84970773446 scopus 로고
    • Liberalism and the Art of Separation
    • 315
    • Michael Walzer, "Liberalism and the Art of Separation," Political Theory 12, no. 3 (1984): 315, 324;
    • (1984) Political Theory , vol.12 , Issue.3 , pp. 324
    • Walzer, M.1
  • 19
    • 44949203326 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • LT 15. Popple's translation suggests that the right of private society is not only immutable but also fundamental. Locke's Latin has no word corresponding to fundamental.
    • LT 15. Popple's translation suggests that the right of private society is not only "immutable" but also "fundamental." Locke's Latin has no word corresponding to "fundamental."
  • 20
    • 0004273805 scopus 로고
    • See, for example, New York: Basic Books
    • See, for example, Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 300-302.
    • (1974) Anarchy, State, and Utopia , pp. 300-302
    • Nozick, R.1
  • 21
    • 84974127275 scopus 로고
    • John Locke: Social Contract Versus Political Anthropology
    • See, Winter
    • See Jeremy Waldron, "John Locke: Social Contract Versus Political Anthropology," The Review of Politics 51, no. 1 (Winter 1989): 3-28.
    • (1989) The Review of Politics , vol.51 , Issue.1 , pp. 3-28
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 22
    • 0000921466 scopus 로고
    • Justice as Fairness
    • For more general criticisms of the consent principle, consider
    • For more general criticisms of the consent principle, consider John Rawls, "Justice as Fairness," Philosophical Review 67 (1958): 178.
    • (1958) Philosophical Review , vol.67 , pp. 178
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 23
    • 84974173064 scopus 로고
    • Locke's Political Anthropology and Lockean Individualism
    • February, 42
    • Ruth W. Grant, "Locke's Political Anthropology and Lockean Individualism," Journal of Politics 50, no. 1 (February 1988): 42, 59-60;
    • (1988) Journal of Politics , vol.50 , Issue.1 , pp. 59-60
    • Grant, R.W.1
  • 26
    • 44949191163 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also J. W. Gough, John Locke's Political Philosophy, 2d ed. (London: Oxford University Press, 1973), 14 (finding a basic inconsistency between [Locke's] earlier belief in absolute moral principles and his tendency later to think in hedonistic terms);
    • See also J. W. Gough, John Locke's Political Philosophy, 2d ed. (London: Oxford University Press, 1973), 14 (finding a "basic inconsistency between [Locke's] earlier belief in absolute moral principles and his tendency later to think in hedonistic terms");
  • 27
    • 44949256989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Raymond Polin, John Locke's Conception of Freedom, in John Locke: Problems and Perspectives, ed. John W. Yolton (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969), 1 (traditional interpreters of John Locke like to pretend that he professed simultaneously a theoretical philosophy of empirical style and a practical philosophy of innatist inspiration).
    • and Raymond Polin, "John Locke's Conception of Freedom," in John Locke: Problems and Perspectives, ed. John W. Yolton (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969), 1 ("traditional interpreters of John Locke like to pretend that he professed simultaneously a theoretical philosophy of empirical style and a practical philosophy of innatist inspiration").
  • 28
    • 44949235890 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Letter from John Locke to Richard King, August 25, 1703, cited in Andrzej Rapaczynski, Nature and Politics: Liberalism in the Philosophies of Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1987), 15 and n. 11.
    • Letter from John Locke to Richard King, August 25, 1703, cited in Andrzej Rapaczynski, Nature and Politics: Liberalism in the Philosophies of Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1987), 15 and n. 11.
  • 30
    • 77954067695 scopus 로고
    • John Locke: From Absolutism to Toleration
    • See
    • See Robert P. Kraynak, "John Locke: From Absolutism to Toleration," The American Political Science Review 74, no. 1 (1980): 53-69.
    • (1980) The American Political Science Review , vol.74 , Issue.1 , pp. 53-69
    • Kraynak, R.P.1
  • 31
    • 44949130471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • By describing Locke as a philosopher, this interpretation comes into some tension with more historically focused interpretations that prefer to read Locke primarily in the context of the problems of England in his day. See
    • By describing Locke as a philosopher, this interpretation comes into some tension with more historically focused interpretations that prefer to read Locke primarily in the context of the problems of England in his day. See Laslett, "Introduction," 76;
    • Introduction , vol.76
    • Laslett1
  • 33
    • 44949124313 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although Locke's Of the Conduct of the Understanding targets the same audience, on the topics covered here that work is less relevant than and adds little to the Essay. I pass over Locke's subsequent letters on toleration for similar reasons
    • Although Locke's Of the Conduct of the Understanding targets the same audience, on the topics covered here that work is less relevant than and adds little to the Essay. I pass over Locke's subsequent letters on toleration for similar reasons.
  • 34
    • 0004166819 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Ruth W. Grant, John Locke's Liberalism (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987), 8-9.
    • (1987) John Locke's Liberalism , pp. 8-9
    • Grant, R.W.1
  • 35
    • 44949260731 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For similar approaches to interpreting Locke, consider Michael P. Zuckert, Launching Liberalism: On Lockean Political Philosophy (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 2002), 3-17;
    • For similar approaches to interpreting Locke, consider Michael P. Zuckert, Launching Liberalism: On Lockean Political Philosophy (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 2002), 3-17;
  • 39
    • 0004152043 scopus 로고
    • Persecution and the Art of Writing
    • 488
    • and Leo Strauss, "Persecution and the Art of Writing," Social Research 8, no. 1 (1941): 488, 503 n. 21.
    • (1941) Social Research , vol.8 , Issue.1-21 , pp. 503
    • Strauss, L.1
  • 43
    • 44949118296 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On this point, I follow Thomas West, Ruth Grant, A. John Simmons, and Nathan Tarcov more than I do Michael Zuckert. Zuckert grounds Locke's normative claims in self-ownership, which is not necessarily eudaimonistic. See
    • On this point, I follow Thomas West, Ruth Grant, A. John Simmons, and Nathan Tarcov more than I do Michael Zuckert. Zuckert grounds Locke's normative claims in "self-ownership," which is not necessarily eudaimonistic. See Zuckert, Launching Liberalism, 4-5, 193-95;
    • Launching Liberalism , vol.4-5 , pp. 193-195
    • Zuckert1
  • 44
    • 44949227672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Thomas G. West, Nature and Happiness in Locke, The Claremont Review of Books 4, no. 2 (2004) (reviewing Zuckert, Launching Liberalism), available online at http://www.claremont.org/ publications/pubid.659/pub_detail.asp;
    • see also Thomas G. West, "Nature and Happiness in Locke," The Claremont Review of Books 4, no. 2 (2004) (reviewing Zuckert, Launching Liberalism), available online at http://www.claremont.org/ publications/pubid.659/pub_detail.asp;
  • 49
    • 33748451349 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Nomi M. Stolzenberg and Gideon Yaffe, Waldron's Locke and Locke's Waldron: A Review of Jeremy Waldron's God, Locke, and Equality, Inquiry 49, no. 2 (2006): 186, 197-202 (criticizing Waldron for reading Locke as a deontologist and not a utilitarian).
    • See also Nomi M. Stolzenberg and Gideon Yaffe, "Waldron's Locke and Locke's Waldron: A Review of Jeremy Waldron's God, Locke, and Equality," Inquiry 49, no. 2 (2006): 186, 197-202 (criticizing Waldron for reading Locke as a deontologist and not a utilitarian).
  • 50
    • 44949174711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Alasdair MacIntyre, Hume on the 'Is' and the 'Ought', in MacIntyre, Against the Self-Images of the Age: Essays on Ideology and Philosophy (South Bend, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1978): 109, 124;
    • See Alasdair MacIntyre, "Hume on the 'Is' and the 'Ought'," in MacIntyre, Against the Self-Images of the Age: Essays on Ideology and Philosophy (South Bend, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1978): 109, 124;
  • 51
    • 84974286205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • G. E. Anscombe, Modern Moral Philosophy, Philosophy 33, no. 124 (1958): 1, 2 (general criticisms of Kantian deontology);
    • G. E. Anscombe, "Modern Moral Philosophy," Philosophy 33, no. 124 (1958): 1, 2 (general criticisms of Kantian deontology);
  • 54
    • 0003687723 scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Leo Strauss, Natural Right and History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953), 202-51;
    • (1953) Natural Right and History , pp. 202-251
    • Strauss, L.1
  • 55
    • 0038958021 scopus 로고
    • John Locke
    • Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, eds, 3d ed, Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • and Robert A. Goldwin, "John Locke," in Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, eds., History of Political Philosophy, 3d ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987), 476.
    • (1987) History of Political Philosophy , pp. 476
    • Goldwin, R.A.1
  • 62
    • 44949254718 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, Politics, 1255a3-a20;
    • Aristotle, Politics, 1255a3-a20;
  • 66
    • 44949226740 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The following discussion relies substantially on insights from Zuckert, Launching Liberalism, 146-68;
    • The following discussion relies substantially on insights from Zuckert, Launching Liberalism, 146-68;
  • 69
    • 0001775066 scopus 로고
    • Locke: Toleration and the Rationality of Persecution
    • ed, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 61
    • Jeremy Waldron, "Locke: Toleration and the Rationality of Persecution," in Susan Mendus, ed., Justifying Toleration: Conceptual and Historical Perspectives (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 61, 64-67, 80-82.
    • (1988) Justifying Toleration: Conceptual and Historical Perspectives
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 75
    • 84971947053 scopus 로고
    • Locke and Feminism on Private and Public Realms of Activities
    • Spring, 251
    • Mary B. Walsh, "Locke and Feminism on Private and Public Realms of Activities," Review of Politics 57, no. 2 (Spring 1995): 251, 261-62;
    • (1995) Review of Politics , vol.57 , Issue.2 , pp. 261-262
    • Walsh, M.B.1
  • 77
    • 44949160846 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Aristotle, Politics, 1252b27-1253a38;
    • See Aristotle, Politics, 1252b27-1253a38;
  • 78
    • 44949142764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1155a22-28, 1167a26-30;
    • Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1155a22-28, 1167a26-30;
  • 79
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), 23-32;
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 23-32
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 81
    • 44949251537 scopus 로고
    • 2d ed, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Michael J. Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice, 2d ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 9-14, 60-67;
    • (1992) Liberalism and the Limits of Justice , vol.9-14 , pp. 60-67
    • Sandel, M.J.1
  • 83
    • 44949128755 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • From this paragraph until the end of this section, my argument has been informed substantially by
    • From this paragraph until the end of this section, my argument has been informed substantially by Myers, Our Only Star and Compass, 123-29, 196-97.
    • Our Only Star and Compass , vol.123 -29 , pp. 196-197
    • Myers1
  • 84
    • 44949229000 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1155a20-b1.
    • See Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1155a20-b1.
  • 86
    • 44949180537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See
    • See TT I.58-59;
    • , vol.58-59
    • TT, I.1
  • 89
    • 44949120180 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • noninjurious
    • is a term of art meant to exclude acts that threaten harms the public may properly protect against, to be sketched in Section VI
    • Here, "noninjurious" is a term of art meant to exclude acts that threaten harms the public may properly protect against, to be sketched in Section VI.
    • Here1
  • 90
    • 44949222320 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See David McGowan, Making Sense of Dale, Constitutional Commentary 18 (2001): 121, 125, 157 (discussing Boy Scouts of America v. Dale, 530 U.S. 640, 648-53 [2000]).
    • See David McGowan, "Making Sense of Dale," Constitutional Commentary 18 (2001): 121, 125, 157 (discussing Boy Scouts of America v. Dale, 530 U.S. 640, 648-53 [2000]).
  • 91
    • 44949250606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Dale, 530 U.S. at 649-50;
    • See Dale, 530 U.S. at 649-50;
  • 92
    • 44949192610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Roberts v. United States Jaycees, 468 U.S. 609, 617-23 (1984);
    • Roberts v. United States Jaycees, 468 U.S. 609, 617-23 (1984);
  • 93
    • 44949092139 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and ibid. at 634-646 (O'Connor, J., concurring in the judgment). Here and henceforth, I use judicial opinions as expressions of conventional political wisdom, to show how contemporary political opinions contrast with Locke's. I do not cover the many legal issues that would need to be addressed before determining whether each of these cases was correctly decided as a matter of constitutional law.
    • and ibid. at 634-646 (O'Connor, J., concurring in the judgment). Here and henceforth, I use judicial opinions as expressions of conventional political wisdom, to show how contemporary political opinions contrast with Locke's. I do not cover the many legal issues that would need to be addressed before determining whether each of these cases was correctly decided as a matter of constitutional law.
  • 94
    • 44949088287 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Dale, 530 U.S. at 648;
    • See Dale, 530 U.S. at 648;
  • 95
    • 44949125260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Roberts, 468 U.S. at 623.
    • Roberts, 468 U.S. at 623.
  • 97
    • 44949198982 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I thank Eric Miller and Andy Koppelman for encouraging me to make this point explicit
    • I thank Eric Miller and Andy Koppelman for encouraging me to make this point explicit.
  • 99
    • 44949144705 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For Popple's translation, see LT 40-41.
    • For Popple's translation, see LT 40-41.
  • 100
    • 44949115782 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See TT I.59;
    • See TT I.59;
  • 101
    • 44949198981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Davis v. Beason, 133 U.S. 33, 342-43 (1890);
    • Davis v. Beason, 133 U.S. 33, 342-43 (1890);
  • 102
    • 44949188166 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reynolds v. United States, 98 U.S. 145, 164-64 (1879);
    • Reynolds v. United States, 98 U.S. 145, 164-64 (1879);
  • 104
    • 44949105246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McCreary County v. American Civil Liberties Union, 545 U.S. 844, 860 (2005) (quoting Epperson v. Arkansas, 393 U.S. 97, 104 [1968]).
    • McCreary County v. American Civil Liberties Union, 545 U.S. 844, 860 (2005) (quoting Epperson v. Arkansas, 393 U.S. 97, 104 [1968]).
  • 106
    • 44949120179 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • compare Zuckert, Launching Liberalism (suggesting that Locke's rationalism and skepticism undermine general public respect for Christianity and encourage deism and agnosticism) with Myers, Our Only Star and Compass, 46-50 (reading Locke as concluding that human faculties point toward the existence of God, even as Locke rests the grounds of human obligation on rationally knowable foundations).
    • compare Zuckert, Launching Liberalism (suggesting that Locke's rationalism and skepticism undermine general public respect for Christianity and encourage deism and agnosticism) with Myers, Our Only Star and Compass, 46-50 (reading Locke as concluding that human faculties point toward the existence of God, even as Locke rests the grounds of human obligation on rationally knowable foundations).
  • 107
    • 44949091174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For examples of American cases upholding anti-blasphemy laws in the face of constitutional challenges on similar grounds, consider Updegraph v. Commonwealth, 11 Serg. & Rawle 394 (Pa. 1824);
    • For examples of American cases upholding anti-blasphemy laws in the face of constitutional challenges on similar grounds, consider Updegraph v. Commonwealth, 11 Serg. & Rawle 394 (Pa. 1824);
  • 108
    • 44949157072 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and People v. Ruggles, 8 Johns. R. 290 (N.Y. 1811).
    • and People v. Ruggles, 8 Johns. R. 290 (N.Y. 1811).
  • 109
    • 44949162667 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ECHU I.3.6; RC 243;
    • See ECHU I.3.6; RC 243;
  • 111
    • 44949228999 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here Locke contradicts the position he took in his 1667 Essay on Toleration, in John Locke, Political Essays, ed. Mark Goldie (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 134-59.
    • Here Locke contradicts the position he took in his 1667 "Essay on Toleration," in John Locke, Political Essays, ed. Mark Goldie (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 134-59.
  • 112
    • 44949127833 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the text, I also contradict and correct an error I made in Eric R. Claeys, Justice Scalia and the Religion Clauses: A Comment on Professor Epps, Washington University Journal of Law and Policy 21 2006, 349-58, 355 and n. 28
    • In the text, I also contradict and correct an error I made in Eric R. Claeys, "Justice Scalia and the Religion Clauses: A Comment on Professor Epps," Washington University Journal of Law and Policy 21 (2006): 349-58, 355 and n. 28.
  • 115
    • 44949259877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Democratic-Republican Societies, Subversion, and the Limits of Legitimate Political Dissent in the Early Republic
    • Robert M. Chesney, "Democratic-Republican Societies, Subversion, and the Limits of Legitimate Political Dissent in the Early Republic," North Carolina Law Review, 82 (2004): 1525.
    • (2004) North Carolina Law Review , vol.82 , pp. 1525
    • Chesney, R.M.1
  • 116
    • 44949203322 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 18 U.S.C. sec. 2385 (West 2007);
    • See 18 U.S.C. sec. 2385 (West 2007);
  • 118
    • 84888491658 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • sec. 2339B(a)(1) and (g)6, West 2007
    • 18 U.S.C. sec. 2339B(a)(1) and (g)(6) (West 2007);
    • 18 U.S.C
  • 119
    • 1342310968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Civil Liberties and the Terrorism Prevention Paradigm: The Guilt by Association Critique
    • 1408
    • and Robert M. Chesney, "Civil Liberties and the Terrorism Prevention Paradigm: The Guilt by Association Critique," Michigan Law Review 101, no. 6 (2003): 1408, 1432-52.
    • (2003) Michigan Law Review , vol.101 , Issue.6 , pp. 1432-1452
    • Chesney, R.M.1
  • 120
    • 40749084517 scopus 로고
    • See, 389 U.S
    • See United States v. Robel, 389 U.S. 258 (1967);
    • (1967) United States v. Robel , pp. 258
  • 121
    • 44949148881 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Keyishian v. Board of Regents, 385 U.S. 589 (1967);
    • Keyishian v. Board of Regents, 385 U.S. 589 (1967);
  • 122
    • 44949179137 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Elfbrandt v. Russell, 384 U.S. 11 (1966);
    • Elfbrandt v. Russell, 384 U.S. 11 (1966);
  • 126
    • 44949089285 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Keyishian v. Board of Regents, 385 U.S. 589, 605-6 (1967);
    • Keyishian v. Board of Regents, 385 U.S. 589, 605-6 (1967);
  • 127
    • 44949179136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616, 630 (1919) (Holmes, J., dissenting);
    • Abrams v. United States, 250 U.S. 616, 630 (1919) (Holmes, J., dissenting);
  • 128
    • 33749842190 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Illiberalism All the Way Down: Illiberal Groups and Two Conceptions of Liberalism
    • Larry Alexander, "Illiberalism All the Way Down: Illiberal Groups and Two Conceptions of Liberalism," Journal of Contemporary Legal Issues 12 (2002): 625-30.
    • (2002) Journal of Contemporary Legal Issues , vol.12 , pp. 625-630
    • Alexander, L.1
  • 130
    • 44949149861 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Harry V. Jaffa, On the Nature of Civil and Religious Liberty, in Jaffa, Equality and Liberty: Theory and Practice in American Politics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965), 169-89;
    • Harry V. Jaffa, "On the Nature of Civil and Religious Liberty," in Jaffa, Equality and Liberty: Theory and Practice in American Politics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965), 169-89;
  • 131
    • 44949129492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and John Marshall, Report of the Minority on the Virginia Resolutions, reprinted in The Founders' Constitution, ed. Philip B. Kurland and Ralph Lerner (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987), 5: 136-39.
    • and John Marshall, "Report of the Minority on the Virginia Resolutions," reprinted in The Founders' Constitution, ed. Philip B. Kurland and Ralph Lerner (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987), 5: 136-39.
  • 132
    • 44949162666 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For examples of national anti-sedition policies that worked relatively effectively, consider Karl Loewenstein, Legislative Control of Political Extremism in European Democracies, I and II, Columbia Law Review 38, no. 5 1938, 591-622 and 725-74
    • For examples of national anti-sedition policies that worked relatively effectively, consider Karl Loewenstein, "Legislative Control of Political Extremism in European Democracies, I and II," Columbia Law Review 38, no. 5 (1938): 591-622 and 725-74.
  • 133
    • 44949093370 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Loewenstein suggests that many European democracies during the interwar period effectively suppressed fascist and socialist parties until they were conquered by Nazi Germany and the Axis. If Loewenstein is correct, these countries' internal policies toward seditionists were effective regardless of whether the countries could be overwhelmed by superior external force
    • Loewenstein suggests that many European democracies during the interwar period effectively suppressed fascist and socialist parties until they were conquered by Nazi Germany and the Axis. If Loewenstein is correct, these countries' internal policies toward seditionists were effective regardless of whether the countries could be overwhelmed by superior external force.
  • 134
    • 44949104024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books
    • John Dewey, Liberalism and Social Action (Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books, 1999), 27, 35.
    • (1999) Liberalism and Social Action , vol.27 , pp. 35
    • Dewey, J.1
  • 138
    • 44949130594 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Koppelman, Antidiscrimination Law and Social Equality, 181-90, citing Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), 55.
    • see Koppelman, Antidiscrimination Law and Social Equality, 181-90, citing Stephen Macedo, Liberal Virtues: Citizenship, Virtue, and Community in Liberal Constitutionalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990), 55.
  • 139
    • 34250320560 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E Pluribus Unum: Diversity and Community in the Twenty-First Century
    • See, 137
    • See Robert D. Putnam, "E Pluribus Unum: Diversity and Community in the Twenty-First Century," Scandinavian Political Studies 30, no. 2 (2007): 137, 146-59.
    • (2007) Scandinavian Political Studies , vol.30 , Issue.2 , pp. 146-159
    • Putnam, R.D.1
  • 141
    • 44949149003 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Ronald Dworkin, Reverse Discrimination, in Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1978), 227-28.
    • and Ronald Dworkin, "Reverse Discrimination," in Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1978), 227-28.
  • 143
    • 0039579571 scopus 로고
    • Reality
    • 169
    • Drew S. Days, III, "Reality," San Diego Law Review 31, no. 1 (1994): 169, 170-80;
    • (1994) San Diego Law Review , vol.31 , Issue.1 , pp. 170-180
    • Days III, D.S.1
  • 144
    • 44949133921 scopus 로고
    • Epstein on His Own Grounds
    • 241
    • Richard McAdams, "Epstein on His Own Grounds," San Diego Law Review 31, no. 1 (1994): 241, 249-64;
    • (1994) San Diego Law Review , vol.31 , Issue.1 , pp. 249-264
    • McAdams, R.1
  • 145
    • 84933490859 scopus 로고
    • Contractual Liberties in Discriminatory Markets
    • 1219
    • Samuel Issacharoff, "Contractual Liberties in Discriminatory Markets," Texas Law Review 70, no. 5 (1992): 1219, 1225-34;
    • (1992) Texas Law Review , vol.70 , Issue.5 , pp. 1225-1234
    • Issacharoff, S.1
  • 146
    • 10944241068 scopus 로고
    • Free to Search
    • 2080
    • and J. Hoult Verkerke, "Free to Search," Harvard Law Review 105, no. 8 (1992): 2080, 2088-96.
    • (1992) Harvard Law Review , vol.105 , Issue.8 , pp. 2088-2096
    • Hoult Verkerke, J.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.