-
1
-
-
0004170493
-
-
Cambridge: Harvard University Press
-
Shklar, Legalism (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1964), 1.
-
(1964)
Legalism
, pp. 1
-
-
Shklar1
-
2
-
-
84968783129
-
-
All parenthetical references are to student ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press cited by and section
-
All parenthetical references are to John Locke Two Treatises of Government, ec Laslett, student ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), cited by and section.
-
(1988)
Two Treatises of Government, ec Laslett
-
-
Locke, J.1
-
3
-
-
3242811242
-
Constitutional and Presidential Prerogative: Jeffersonian and Hamiltonian Perspectives
-
July esp. 439-40
-
Clement Fatovic, “Constitutional and Presidential Prerogative: Jeffersonian and Hamiltonian Perspectives,” American Journal of Political Science 43, no. 3 (July 2004): 429–444, esp. 439-40;
-
(2004)
American Journal of Political Science
, vol.43
, Issue.3
, pp. 429-444
-
-
Fatovic, C.1
-
4
-
-
3242755044
-
Constitutionalism and Contingency: Locke's Theory of Prerogative
-
see also Summer
-
see also Fatovic, “Constitutionalism and Contingency: Locke's Theory of Prerogative,” History of Political Thought 25, no. 2 (Summer 2004): 276–297.
-
(2004)
History of Political Thought
, vol.25
, Issue.2
, pp. 276-297
-
-
Fatovic1
-
5
-
-
34248033422
-
Prerogative and the Rule of Law in John Locke and the Lincoln Presidency
-
Winter
-
Sean Mattie, “Prerogative and the Rule of Law in John Locke and the Lincoln Presidency,” Review of Politics 67, no. 1 (Winter 2005): 77–111.
-
(2005)
Review of Politics
, vol.67
, Issue.1
, pp. 77-111
-
-
Mattie, S.1
-
6
-
-
0031287750
-
Locke, Leadership, and the Federalist
-
April
-
David Weaver, “Locke, Leadership, and the Federalist,” American Journal of Political Science 41, no. 2 (April 1997): 420–446.
-
(1997)
American Journal of Political Science
, vol.41
, Issue.2
, pp. 420-446
-
-
Weaver, D.1
-
7
-
-
0005585988
-
The First Liberal Democrat: Locke's Popular Government
-
Winter 5-39, esp. 12-13
-
Robert Faulkner, “The First Liberal Democrat: Locke's Popular Government,” Review of Politics 63, no. 1 (Winter 2001): 5-39, esp. 12-13, 29–33.
-
(2001)
Review of Politics
, vol.63
, Issue.1
, pp. 29-33
-
-
Faulkner, R.1
-
8
-
-
84928439136
-
John Locke and the Limits of Presidential Prerogative
-
Thomas Langston and Michael Lind also conclude that “any prerogative of the President to act in the silence of the laws, or against the laws, exists only at the sufferance of Congress,” but they do not agree that all prerogative is conventional; Fall 68
-
Thomas Langston and Michael Lind also conclude that “any prerogative of the President to act in the silence of the laws, or against the laws, exists only at the sufferance of Congress,” but they do not agree that all prerogative is conventional; “John Locke and the Limits of Presidential Prerogative,” Polity 24, no. 1 (Fall 1991): 49–68, 68.
-
(1991)
Polity
, vol.24
, Issue.1
, pp. 49-68
-
-
-
9
-
-
47249135832
-
Constitutionalism and Contingency
-
Fatovic, “Constitutionalism and Contingency.”
-
-
-
Fatovic1
-
10
-
-
85022466892
-
Prerogative and the Rule of Law
-
esp
-
Mattie, “Prerogative and the Rule of Law,” esp. 85–88.
-
-
-
Mattie1
-
13
-
-
0032370751
-
Locke on King's Prerogative
-
See also April
-
See also Pasquale Pasquino, “Locke on King's Prerogative,” Political Theory 26, no. 2 (April 1998): 198–208.
-
(1998)
Political Theory
, vol.26
, Issue.2
, pp. 198-208
-
-
Pasquino, P.1
-
14
-
-
0010133875
-
-
esp see also note 36, below, and context
-
Mansfield, Taming the Prince, esp. 13–20; see also note 36, below, and context.
-
Taming the Prince
, pp. 13-20
-
-
Mansfield1
-
15
-
-
0000852991
-
Rules and Standards
-
For this distinction, see December
-
For this distinction, see Pierre Schlag, “Rules and Standards,” UCLA Law Review 33 (December 1985): 379–429
-
(1985)
UCLA Law Review
, vol.33
, pp. 379-429
-
-
Schlag, P.1
-
16
-
-
71849112032
-
Problems with Rules
-
July
-
Cass Sunstein, “Problems with Rules,” California Law Review 83 (July 1995): 953–1023.
-
(1995)
California Law Review
, vol.83
, pp. 953-1023
-
-
Sunstein, C.1
-
18
-
-
84927457428
-
Locke and the Rejection of the Ancient Constitution
-
See February
-
See David Resnick, “Locke and the Rejection of the Ancient Constitution,” Political Theory 12, no. 1 (February 1984): 97–114.
-
(1984)
Political Theory
, vol.12
, Issue.1
, pp. 97-114
-
-
Resnick, D.1
-
19
-
-
0003744274
-
-
What it reveals is the subject of some debate. See Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
What it reveals is the subject of some debate. See John Dunn, The Political Thought of John Locke (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969), esp. 148–156
-
(1969)
The Political Thought of John Locke
, pp. 148-156
-
-
Dunn, J.1
-
20
-
-
84872151055
-
Locke on King's Prerogative
-
Pasquino, “Locke on King's Prerogative.”
-
-
-
Pasquino1
-
21
-
-
52849132923
-
Patriarcha
-
See ed. Johann P. Sommerville (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press esp. 44-5
-
See Robert Filmer, “Patriarcha,” in Patriarcha and Other Writings, ed. Johann P. Sommerville (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991): 1–68, esp. 44-5.
-
(1991)
Patriarcha and Other Writings
, pp. 1-68
-
-
Filmer, R.1
-
23
-
-
84876110235
-
-
[eebo.chadwyck.com; hereafter EEBO], Wing R2386
-
Early English Books Online [eebo.chadwyck.com; hereafter EEBO], Wing R2386), 218 ff;
-
Early English Books Online
, pp. 218
-
-
-
24
-
-
85022574907
-
Vox Populi: Or the Peoples Claim to Their Parliament's Sitting
-
London EEBO, Wing S5331) 219
-
Anon., “Vox Populi: Or the Peoples Claim to Their Parliament's Sitting,” Reprinted in State Tracts, vol. 2 (London: 1692; EEBO, Wing S5331): 219–224, 219.
-
(1692)
Reprinted in State Tracts
, vol.2
, pp. 219-224
-
-
-
25
-
-
84900256208
-
-
Cf. de Legibus III. iii; see also
-
Cf. de Legibus III. iii; see also Rutherford, Lex Rex, 218 ff
-
Lex Rex
, pp. 218
-
-
Rutherford1
-
29
-
-
85022585981
-
First Liberal Democrat
-
Faulkner attempts to address this difficulty as well, but is forced to understate the limits that government by consent places on the use of political power; cf
-
Faulkner attempts to address this difficulty as well, but is forced to understate the limits that government by consent places on the use of political power; cf. “First Liberal Democrat,” 12–4.
-
-
-
-
30
-
-
85014467102
-
Leadership, Locke, and the Federalist
-
esp 430, 433-35
-
Weaver, “Leadership, Locke, and the Federalist,” esp. 426, 430, 433-35.
-
-
-
Weaver1
-
31
-
-
84872140218
-
John Locke and the Limits of Presidential Prerogative
-
Langston and Lind, “John Locke and the Limits of Presidential Prerogative.”
-
-
-
Langston1
Lind2
-
32
-
-
85055765182
-
Locke's Theory of Revolutionary Action
-
This is only a problem if consent implies more than bare acquiescence, or if government by consent means something more than a submissive population. This is denied by Faulkner, “First Liberal Democrat,” 13; see also Sep. 1963)
-
This is only a problem if consent implies more than bare acquiescence, or if government by consent means something more than a submissive population. This is denied by Faulkner, “First Liberal Democrat,” 13; see also Martin Seliger, “Locke's Theory of Revolutionary Action,” Western Political Quarterly 16, no. 3 (Sep. 1963): 548–568.
-
Western Political Quarterly
, vol.16
, Issue.3
, pp. 548-568
-
-
Seliger, M.1
-
33
-
-
84917217137
-
A Rope of Sand: Interpreting Locke's ‘First Treatise of Government
-
But every people has submitted to those that rule them (cf. 1: 43; esp. 56-59). A normatively interesting consensual government demands a bit more (cf. II 186). Otherwise, every government is legitimate: Locke wouldn't be the correction of Hobbes on Hobbesian principles that many scholars see him as—he would be Hobbes, albeit with better spin
-
But every people has submitted to those that rule them (cf. 1: 43; Charles Tarlton, “A Rope of Sand: Interpreting Locke's ‘First Treatise of Government’,” The Historical Journal 21, no. 1 [1978]: 43–73, esp. 56-59). A normatively interesting consensual government demands a bit more (cf. II 186). Otherwise, every government is legitimate: Locke wouldn't be the correction of Hobbes on Hobbesian principles that many scholars see him as—he would be Hobbes, albeit with better spin.
-
(1978)
The Historical Journal
, vol.21
, Issue.1
, pp. 43-73
-
-
Tarlton, C.1
-
35
-
-
84872140218
-
John Locke and the Limits of Presidential Prerogative
-
See
-
See Langston and Lind, “John Locke and the Limits of Presidential Prerogative,” esp. 59–60.
-
-
-
Langston1
Lind2
-
36
-
-
0011666793
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
Cox, Locke on War and Peace (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1960), esp. 128–130
-
(1960)
Locke on War and Peace
, pp. 128-130
-
-
Cox1
-
37
-
-
85022514672
-
First Liberal Democrat
-
Faulkner, “First Liberal Democrat,” esp. 29–36
-
-
-
Faulkner1
-
38
-
-
47249135832
-
Constitutionalism and Contingency
-
Mattie calls prerogative both “executive power” and a “natural power,” “Prerogative and the Rule of Law,” esp. 86. It can at times appear that Mansfield also interprets Locke as blending prerogative and executive power. He is clear, however, that what Locke expands is the power available to the executive, not his definition of executive power per se: “Executive power is subordinate, but the executive person may not be;” Taming the Prince, 201. It is instructive to contrast Mansfield's procedure with Cox's. Cox melts the federative, executive, and prerogative powers together, going so far as to quote passages concerning one to make a point about another; cf. Locke on War and Peace, 127. Mansfield also depicts Locke's discussion of the federative power as the entering wedge in the argument for broad extralegal discretion. Yet even if the “practical alliance … observed between the executive and federative powers … overrides their theoretical distinctness,” they do remain theoretically distinct for Mansfield; Taming the Prince, 201. It is this distinction between executive power and prerogative that permits the modern executive to have the formal weakness that, when contrasted with its informal strength accounts for its ambivalence
-
Fatovic, “Constitutionalism and Contingency,” esp. 280–287 Mattie calls prerogative both “executive power” and a “natural power,” “Prerogative and the Rule of Law,” esp. 86. It can at times appear that Mansfield also interprets Locke as blending prerogative and executive power. He is clear, however, that what Locke expands is the power available to the executive, not his definition of executive power per se: “Executive power is subordinate, but the executive person may not be;” Taming the Prince, 201. It is instructive to contrast Mansfield's procedure with Cox's. Cox melts the federative, executive, and prerogative powers together, going so far as to quote passages concerning one to make a point about another; cf. Locke on War and Peace, 127. Mansfield also depicts Locke's discussion of the federative power as the entering wedge in the argument for broad extralegal discretion. Yet even if the “practical alliance … observed between the executive and federative powers … overrides their theoretical distinctness,” they do remain theoretically distinct for Mansfield; Taming the Prince, 201. It is this distinction between executive power and prerogative that permits the modern executive to have the formal weakness that, when contrasted with its informal strength accounts for its ambivalence.
-
-
-
Fatovic1
-
39
-
-
85022489621
-
John Locke and the Limits of Presidential Prerogative
-
William King's 1692 The State of the Protestants of Ireland explicitly states just this (EEBO, Wing K538, 67-68). Langston and Lind rely on this fact for their assertion that the Constitution does not grant the President any “antilegal prerogative” above that of any other citizen
-
William King's 1692 The State of the Protestants of Ireland explicitly states just this (EEBO, Wing K538, 67-68). Langston and Lind rely on this fact for their assertion that the Constitution does not grant the President any “antilegal prerogative” above that of any other citizen; “John Locke and the Limits of Presidential Prerogative,” 59–60, 66.
-
, vol.66
, pp. 59-60
-
-
-
40
-
-
85022564717
-
-
On the rise, fall, and possible resurgence of the nondelegation doctrine, see 3d ed. (New York: Foundation Press esp. 978-79
-
On the rise, fall, and possible resurgence of the nondelegation doctrine, see Laurence Tribe, American Constitutional Law, 3d ed. (New York: Foundation Press, 2000), 1: 977–1011, esp. 978-79, n. 4.
-
(2000)
American Constitutional Law
, vol.1
, Issue.4
, pp. 977-1011
-
-
Tribe, L.1
-
41
-
-
47249135832
-
Constitutionalism and Contingency
-
Fatovic, “Constitutionalism and Contingency,” 296.
-
-
-
Fatovic1
|