메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 83, Issue , 2003, Pages 67-96

Hamlet or Hecuba: Carl Schmitt's decision

(1)  Kahn, Victoria a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 42949149065     PISSN: 07346018     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1525/rep.2003.83.1.67     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (64)

References (111)
  • 3
    • 0001493123 scopus 로고
    • Force of Law: The 'Mystical Foundation of Authority,' Cardozo
    • Jacques Derrida, "Force of Law: The 'Mystical Foundation of Authority,'" Cardozo Law Review 11 (1990): 919-1046
    • (1990) Law Review , vol.11 , pp. 919-1046
    • Derrida, J.1
  • 7
    • 84970759054 scopus 로고
    • Fear, Technology, and the State: Carl Schmitt, Leo Strauss, and the Revival of Hobbes in Weimar and National Socialist Germany
    • John McCormick, "Fear, Technology, and the State: Carl Schmitt, Leo Strauss, and the Revival of Hobbes in Weimar and National Socialist Germany," Political Theory 22 (1994): 619-52
    • (1994) Political Theory , vol.22 , pp. 619-652
    • McCormick, J.1
  • 11
    • 60949732389 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • David Dyzenhaus, ed., Law as Politics: Carl Schmitt's Critique of Liberalism (Durham, N.C., 1998);
    • David Dyzenhaus, ed., Law as Politics: Carl Schmitt's Critique of Liberalism (Durham, N.C., 1998)
  • 13
    • 0004352052 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Daniel Heller-Roazen Stanford
    • Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer, trans. Daniel Heller-Roazen (Stanford, 1998)
    • (1998) Homo Sacer
    • Agamben, G.1
  • 16
    • 84998183750 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political Theory and Political Theology
    • the review article by
    • See also the review article by John McCormick, "Political Theory and Political Theology," Political Theory 26 (1998): 830-54
    • (1998) Political Theory , vol.26 , pp. 830-854
    • McCormick, J.1
  • 17
    • 60949618447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In addition, Telos 71 (1987) has a special section on Schmitt and the Frankfurt School;
    • In addition, Telos 71 (1987) has a special section on Schmitt and the Frankfurt School
  • 18
    • 79954775767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and the entire issue of Telos 72 (1987) is devoted to Schmitt. For the specifically aesthetic dimension of Schmitt's work, the studies cited in note 7. Needless to say, there is also an extensive bibliography of recent works on Schmitt in German, Italian, and French.
    • and the entire issue of Telos 72 (1987) is devoted to Schmitt. For the specifically aesthetic dimension of Schmitt's work, see the studies cited in note 7. Needless to say, there is also an extensive bibliography of recent works on Schmitt in German, Italian, and French
  • 19
    • 60949670534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Carl Schmitt, The Age of Neutralizations and Depoliticizations, trans. Matthias Konzett and John P. McCormick, Telos 96 (1993): 130-42; here 131. Schmitt emphasizes that this is not a unidirectional, unidimensional process: there is always a plurality of diverse, already spent stages coexisting (131).
    • Carl Schmitt, "The Age of Neutralizations and Depoliticizations, " trans. Matthias Konzett and John P. McCormick, Telos 96 (1993): 130-42; here 131. Schmitt emphasizes that this is not a unidirectional, unidimensional process: "there is always a plurality of diverse, already spent stages coexisting" (131)
  • 20
    • 33748885525 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Concept of the Political, trans
    • Carl Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, trans. George Schwab (Chicago, 1996), 65-66, 72
    • (1996) George Schwab (Chicago , vol.65 , pp. 72
    • Schmitt, C.1
  • 22
    • 0004148030 scopus 로고
    • trans. Guy Oakes Cambridge, Mass
    • Carl Schmitt, Political Romanticism, trans. Guy Oakes (Cambridge, Mass., 1986), 18-19
    • (1986) Political Romanticism , pp. 18-19
    • Schmitt, C.1
  • 23
    • 0003222564 scopus 로고
    • The Occasional Decisionism of Carl Schmitt
    • ed, trans. Gary Steiner New York, 141, 146. This essay was originally published in
    • Karl Löwith, "The Occasional Decisionism of Carl Schmitt," in Martin Heidegger and European Nihilism, ed. Richard Wolin, trans. Gary Steiner (New York, 1995), 141, 146. This essay was originally published in 1935
    • (1935) Martin Heidegger and European Nihilism
    • Löwith, K.1
  • 24
    • 79954764143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Carl Schmitt, Political Theology, trans. George Schwab (Cambridge, Mass., 1988), 15: The exception is more interesting than the rule.
    • See Carl Schmitt, Political Theology, trans. George Schwab (Cambridge, Mass., 1988), 15: "The exception is more interesting than the rule."
  • 25
    • 34548685176 scopus 로고
    • Carl Schmitt oder die Fundierung der Politik auf Asthetik
    • ed, Bürger (Frankfurt, 173 unless otherwise noted, all translations are my own
    • Peter Bürger, "Carl Schmitt oder die Fundierung der Politik auf Asthetik," in Zerstörung, Rettung des Mythos durch Licht, ed. Christa Bürger (Frankfurt, 1986), 173 (unless otherwise noted, all translations are my own)
    • (1986) Zerstörung, Rettung des Mythos durch Licht
    • Bürger, P.1
  • 26
    • 84970724617 scopus 로고
    • The Conservative Revolutionary Habitus and the Aesthetics of Horror
    • 443
    • Richard Wolin, "The Conservative Revolutionary Habitus and the Aesthetics of Horror," Political Theory 20(1992), 433, 443, 445
    • (1992) Political Theory , vol.20 , Issue.433 , pp. 445
    • Wolin, R.1
  • 27
    • 79954834270 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Schmitt's aestheticization of politics, Jürgen Habermas, The Horrors of Autonomy: Carl Schmitt in English, in The New Conservatism, ed. and trans. Shierry Weber Nicholsen (Cambridge, Mass., 1992), 137.
    • On Schmitt's aestheticization of politics, see also Jürgen Habermas, "The Horrors of Autonomy: Carl Schmitt in English," in The New Conservatism, ed. and trans. Shierry Weber Nicholsen (Cambridge, Mass., 1992), 137
  • 28
    • 79954674188 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment, trans. J. H. Bernard (New York, 1951), Introduction, section 9, 34.
    • See Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment, trans. J. H. Bernard (New York, 1951), Introduction, section 9, 34
  • 29
    • 79954687766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Schmitt's attack on the liberal notion of culture, the excellent article by Miguel E. Vatter, Taking Exception to Liberalism: Heinrich Meier's Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss: The Hidden Dialogue Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 19 (1997): 323-44, esp. 331-32,
    • On Schmitt's attack on the liberal notion of culture, see the excellent article by Miguel E. Vatter, "Taking Exception to Liberalism: Heinrich Meier's Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss: The Hidden Dialogue" Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 19 (1997): 323-44, esp. 331-32
  • 30
    • 60950274061 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • referring to Kant's Critique of Judgment, section 84.
    • referring to Kant's Critique of Judgment, section 84
  • 31
    • 60949868273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paul Hirst, Carl Schmitt's Decisionism, in Mouffe, The Challenge of Carl Schmitt, 11.
    • Paul Hirst, "Carl Schmitt's Decisionism," in Mouffe, The Challenge of Carl Schmitt, 11
  • 32
    • 60949736665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Thomas Hobbes of Political Theology is, however, not quite as sublime as this would suggest. Hobbes has the right conception of sovereignty, but he hovers on the threshold of liberal modernity. Hobbes was influenced by the natural sciences and mathematical relativism (34). Still, juristic thought in those days had not yet become so overpowered by the natural sciences that Hobbes neglected the importance of the person of the sovereign.
    • The Thomas Hobbes of Political Theology is, however, not quite as sublime as this would suggest. Hobbes has the right conception of sovereignty, but he hovers on the threshold of liberal modernity. Hobbes was influenced by the natural sciences and "mathematical relativism" (34). Still, "juristic thought in those days had not yet become so overpowered by the natural sciences" that Hobbes neglected the importance of the person of the sovereign
  • 34
    • 60950107578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • on how later editions of The Concept of the Political reflect Schmitt's accommodation to the Nazi regime: among other changes, Schmitt deleted references to Karl Marx and Georg Lukács that had appeared in the first edition.
    • on how later editions of The Concept of the Political reflect Schmitt's accommodation to the Nazi regime: among other changes, Schmitt deleted references to Karl Marx and Georg Lukács that had appeared in the first edition
  • 35
    • 60949621125 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • All quotations in this and the next paragraph are from Carl Schmitt, The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy, trans. Ellen Kennedy (Cambridge, Mass., 1992), here 66.
    • All quotations in this and the next paragraph are from Carl Schmitt, The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy, trans. Ellen Kennedy (Cambridge, Mass., 1992), here 66
  • 36
    • 79954937163 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Carl Schmitt, Roman Catholicism and Political Form, trans. G. L. Ulmen (Westport, Conn., 1996), 13-24. 21 on materialism, and 19 on the incarnation.
    • Carl Schmitt, Roman Catholicism and Political Form, trans. G. L. Ulmen (Westport, Conn., 1996), 13-24. See 21 on materialism, and 19 on the incarnation
  • 38
    • 60949884583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To a literary critic, Schmitt's distinction between myth and representation seems remarkably close to J. W. von Goethe's aesthetic preference for symbol over allegory, which Walter Benjamin famously criticized in his book on German tragic drama.
    • To a literary critic, Schmitt's distinction between myth and representation seems remarkably close to J. W. von Goethe's aesthetic preference for symbol over allegory, which Walter Benjamin famously criticized in his book on German tragic drama
  • 39
    • 79954738617 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the mutually reinforcing relationship between myth and technology,
    • On the mutually reinforcing relationship between myth and technology, see McCormick, "Fear, Technology and the State," 642
    • Fear, Technology and the State , vol.642
    • McCormick1
  • 40
    • 60949792739 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • citing Walter Benjamin, The Artwork in the Age of its Mechanical Reproducibility (1936).
    • citing Walter Benjamin, "The Artwork in the Age of its Mechanical Reproducibility" (1936)
  • 41
    • 60949673321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McCormick also points out that the mutual relationship between myth and technology is more familiar to us as the relationship between myth and enlightenment in T. W. Adorno and Max Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment
    • McCormick also points out that the mutual relationship between myth and technology is more familiar to us as the relationship between myth and enlightenment in T. W. Adorno and Max Horkheimer's Dialectic of Enlightenment
  • 42
    • 60949613393 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fear, Technology, and the State
    • Helpful discussions of Strauss's commentary on Schmitt can be found in, McCormick
    • Helpful discussions of Strauss's commentary on Schmitt can be found in John McCormick, "Fear, Technology, and the State"; McCormick, Carl Schmitt, 250-66
    • Carl Schmitt , pp. 250-266
    • McCormick, J.1
  • 44
    • 60949825623 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Robert Howse, From Legitimacy to Dictatorship - and Back Again: Leo Strauss's Critique of the Anti-Liberalism of Carl Schmitt, in Dyzenhaus, Law as Politics, 56-91. Vatter and Howse, who completely disagree about Strauss's views, are a good introduction to the conflicting interpretations of Strauss's work in general.
    • and Robert Howse, "From Legitimacy to Dictatorship - and Back Again: Leo Strauss's Critique of the Anti-Liberalism of Carl Schmitt," in Dyzenhaus, Law as Politics, 56-91. Vatter and Howse, who completely disagree about Strauss's views, are a good introduction to the conflicting interpretations of Strauss's work in general
  • 45
    • 60949710478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Strauss's critique of Schmitt's indecision anticipates all those modern readers who have argued that Schmitt falls into the errors of Romanticism or aesthetics that he criticized both in The Concept of the Political and in Political Romanticism. Strauss cites the passage from The Concept of the Political where Schmitt asserts that a world without the political is a world of culture, civilization and above all entertainment. According to Schmitt, this world might be very interesting (here one is reminded that the interesting was the mark of the aesthetic for Seren Kierkegaard) but it could never be serious 101, 103, This is Schmitt's aporia, according to Strauss: Schmitt cannot critique the aesthetic and affirm the seriousness of the political without making a moral claim, a moral distinction between the political and the ostensibly apolitical world of modernity. To do so, he must either affirm the moral seriousness of the polit
    • Strauss's critique of Schmitt's indecision anticipates all those modern readers who have argued that Schmitt falls into the errors of Romanticism or aesthetics that he criticized both in The Concept of the Political and in Political Romanticism. Strauss cites the passage from The Concept of the Political where Schmitt asserts that a world without the political is a world "of culture, civilization" and above all "entertainment." According to Schmitt, this world might be very "interesting" (here one is reminded that the interesting was the mark of the aesthetic for Seren Kierkegaard) but it could never be serious (101, 103). This is Schmitt's aporia, according to Strauss: Schmitt cannot critique the aesthetic and affirm the seriousness of the political without making a moral claim, a moral distinction between the political and the ostensibly apolitical world of modernity. To do so, he must either affirm the moral seriousness of the political by subjecting the political to the liberal concept of morality from which he earlier distinguished it; or he must elaborate a different notion of morality, a new "transprivate" basis of "obligation" (104). But Schmitt has not done so. He has not described the new "order of the human things" (106). He has merely substituted the notion of "necessity" for that of obligation, thereby concealing his moral judgment (105). In doing so, he has acted in accordance with the individualism of liberal society
  • 46
    • 79954874083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, Strauss was also vulnerable to the charge of existentialist historicism. McCormick, Fear, Technology, and the State, 648 n. 31
    • Of course, Strauss was also vulnerable to the charge of existentialist historicism. See McCormick, "Fear, Technology, and the State," 648 n. 31
  • 48
    • 60950069443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The book was originally published in 1936. McCormick, Fear, Technology, and the State, argues that Strauss's book on Hobbes pointed Schmitt to the importance of myth in instilling fear of violent death, but gives no specific references to Strauss's discussion of myth (636). In contrast, I believe Strauss saw the myth of Leviathan as complicit with the rise of the aesthetic.
    • The book was originally published in 1936. McCormick, "Fear, Technology, and the State," argues that Strauss's book on Hobbes pointed Schmitt to the importance of myth in instilling fear of violent death, but gives no specific references to Strauss's discussion of myth (636). In contrast, I believe Strauss saw the myth of Leviathan as complicit with the rise of the aesthetic
  • 49
    • 79954639318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. Richard Tuck (Cambridge, 1994), Review and Conclusion. All subsequent references are to chapter first, then page.
    • See Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. Richard Tuck (Cambridge, 1994), "Review and Conclusion." All subsequent references are to chapter first, then page
  • 50
    • 79954652280 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to Schmitt, this is the dilemma of liberal democracy; The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy, 28.
    • According to Schmitt, this is the dilemma of liberal democracy; cf. The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy, 28
  • 51
    • 79954824951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McCormick makes the point that Schmitt could have argued that the Nazi state overcomes the dilemmas of liberalism, but conspicuously he does not. For another reading Der Leviathan as an indirect criticism of the Nazi state, George Schwab, The Challenge of the Exception
    • McCormick makes the point that Schmitt could have argued that the Nazi state overcomes the dilemmas of liberalism, but conspicuously he does not. For another reading Der Leviathan as an indirect criticism of the Nazi state, see George Schwab, The Challenge of the Exception
  • 52
    • 79954946143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Schwab's introduction to The Concept of the Political, 13.
    • and Schwab's introduction to The Concept of the Political, 13
  • 55
    • 79954856377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, the emergency power of the Weimar Reichspräsident also means that he did not represent the people in any mimetic way. But, whereas Hobbes stresses convention, Schmitt stresses personalism
    • Of course, the emergency power of the Weimar Reichspräsident also means that he did not represent the people in any mimetic way. But, whereas Hobbes stresses convention, Schmitt stresses personalism
  • 58
    • 79954884840 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The book has been translated into French as Hamlet ou Hécube: L'irruption du temps dans le jeu, by Jean-Louis Besson and Jean Jourdheuil (Paris, 1992).
    • The book has been translated into French as Hamlet ou Hécube: L'irruption du temps dans le jeu, by Jean-Louis Besson and Jean Jourdheuil (Paris, 1992)
  • 59
    • 79954767133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One chapter and the Appendix, A response to Walter Benjamin on The Origin of German Tragic Drama, have been published in English: Carl Schmitt, The Source of the Tragic, trans. David Pan, Telos 72 (1987): 133-51. All quotations are from the Pan translation.
    • One chapter and the Appendix, "A response to Walter Benjamin on The Origin of German Tragic Drama," have been published in English: Carl Schmitt, "The Source of the Tragic," trans. David Pan, Telos 72 (1987): 133-51. All quotations are from the Pan translation
  • 61
    • 79954963089 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Though he doesn't refer to Schmitt's book on Hamlet, Jürgen Habermas discusses Wilhelm Meister as an illustration of the demise of Schmitt's concept of representative publicness in The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere, trans. Thomas Burger with Frederick Lawrence Cambridge, Mass, 1991, 12-14
    • Though he doesn't refer to Schmitt's book on Hamlet, Jürgen Habermas discusses Wilhelm Meister as an illustration of the demise of Schmitt's concept of "representative publicness" in The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere, trans. Thomas Burger with Frederick Lawrence (Cambridge, Mass., 1991), 12-14
  • 62
    • 60949884585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Stuart Barnett New York, esp. 37;
    • Friedrich Schlegel, On the Study of Greek Poetry, trans. Stuart Barnett (New York, 2001), 34-41, esp. 37
    • (2001) On the Study of Greek Poetry , pp. 34-41
    • Schlegel, F.1
  • 63
    • 79954769455 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • G. W. F. Hegel, Aesthetics, trans. T.M. Knox (Oxford, 1979), 231, 583-84, 1225-32; the quote is from 1228.
    • G. W. F. Hegel, Aesthetics, trans. T.M. Knox (Oxford, 1979), 231, 583-84, 1225-32; the quote is from 1228
  • 64
    • 79954767122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Friedrich Schlegel, Uber nordische Dichtkunst, in Characteristiken und Kritiken II (1802-1829), ed. Hans Eichner (Munich, 1975), 257 and 244. This equation of Hamlet with Germany helps to explain why Hamlet figured so prominently in Walter Benjamin's veiled critique of twentieth-century German politics in his book on German tragic drama.
    • Friedrich Schlegel, "Uber nordische Dichtkunst," in Characteristiken und Kritiken II (1802-1829), ed. Hans Eichner (Munich, 1975), 257 and 244. This equation of Hamlet with Germany helps to explain why Hamlet figured so prominently in Walter Benjamin's veiled critique of twentieth-century German politics in his book on German tragic drama
  • 65
    • 79954716351 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is an extensive secondary literature on the cultural appropriation of Shakespeare by the Third Reich. among others, Werner Habicht, Shakespeare and Theater Politics in the Third Reich, in Hannah Scolnicov and Peter Holland, eds, The Play Out of Context: Transferring Plays from Culture to Culture Cambridge, 1989, 110-20;
    • There is an extensive secondary literature on the cultural appropriation of Shakespeare by the Third Reich. See, among others, Werner Habicht, "Shakespeare and Theater Politics in the Third Reich," in Hannah Scolnicov and Peter Holland, eds., The Play Out of Context: Transferring Plays from Culture to Culture (Cambridge, 1989), 110-20
  • 67
    • 79954860737 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the last page Hamlet oder Hekuba, Schmitt also refers to a poem by Ferdinand Freiligrath, whose first line is Deutschland ist Hamlet! Schmitt may also have been responding to Karl Jaspers's 1947 book, Von der Wahrheit, which included a discussion of Greek and Shakespearean tragedy that clearly allegorized the events of the second World War and the Nazi perversion of tragic rhetoric, the pseudo-tragic evocation of the racial past.
    • On the last page Hamlet oder Hekuba, Schmitt also refers to a poem by Ferdinand Freiligrath, whose first line is "Deutschland ist Hamlet!" Schmitt may also have been responding to Karl Jaspers's 1947 book, Von der Wahrheit, which included a discussion of Greek and Shakespearean tragedy that clearly allegorized the events of the second World War and the Nazi perversion of tragic rhetoric, the pseudo-tragic evocation of "the racial past."
  • 68
    • 79954787773 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The discussion of tragedy has been translated as Tragedy Is Not Enough, trans. Harald A. T. Reiche, Harry T. Moore, and Karl W. Deutsch (Boston, 1952), here 101. According to Jaspers, tragically, the individual represents the genuine exception which, though opposing the law, yet has truth on his side (48). Jaspers also criticized the merely aesthetic understanding of tragedy, in which the play becomes devoid of moral obligation (87). Jaspers includes a brief analysis of Hamlet, in which he argues that Hamlet can only be condemned for inaction by someone who equates action with unthinking reflex (65).
    • The discussion of tragedy has been translated as Tragedy Is Not Enough, trans. Harald A. T. Reiche, Harry T. Moore, and Karl W. Deutsch (Boston, 1952), here 101. According to Jaspers, "tragically, the individual represents the genuine exception which, though opposing the law, yet has truth on his side" (48). Jaspers also criticized the merely aesthetic understanding of tragedy, in which "the play becomes devoid of moral obligation" (87). Jaspers includes a brief analysis of Hamlet, in which he argues that Hamlet can only be condemned for inaction by someone who equates action with unthinking reflex (65)
  • 70
    • 43949124867 scopus 로고
    • Schmitt at Nuremberg
    • The quotations from Schmitt's subsequent reflection on his exchange with Robert Kempner appear on 122 and 123. Bendersky states that Schmitt's ideas were ignored by the Nazi regime and that he was interrogated mostly because of his notorious reputation outside of Germany. For the transcript of this exchange and commentary
    • For the transcript of this exchange and commentary see Joseph W. Bendersky "Schmitt at Nuremberg," Telos 72 (1987): 91-106. The quotations from Schmitt's subsequent reflection on his exchange with Robert Kempner appear on 122 and 123. Bendersky states that Schmitt's ideas were ignored by the Nazi regime and that he was interrogated mostly because of his notorious reputation outside of Germany
    • (1987) Telos , vol.72 , pp. 91-106
    • Bendersky, J.W.1
  • 71
    • 79954703741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In tragedy the common public sphere (which in every performance encompasses the author, the actors, and the audience) is not based on the accepted rules of language and play but upon a shared historical reality; Schmitt, Source of the Tragic, 143.
    • "In tragedy the common public sphere (which in every performance encompasses the author, the actors, and the audience) is not based on the accepted rules of language and play but upon a shared historical reality"; Schmitt, "Source of the Tragic," 143
  • 72
    • 79954710565 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Carl Schmitt, The Source of the Tragic, 136, 148, and 149,
    • Carl Schmitt, "The Source of the Tragic," 136, 148, and 149
  • 74
    • 79954734103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a good discussion of Schmitt's reading of Benjamin on Hamlet, David Pan, Political Aesthetics: Carl Schmitt on Hamlet, Telos 72 (1987): 153-59.
    • For a good discussion of Schmitt's reading of Benjamin on Hamlet, see David Pan, "Political Aesthetics: Carl Schmitt on Hamlet," Telos 72 (1987): 153-59
  • 75
    • 79954842522 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a discussion of Schmitt's relationship to Benjamin that briefly touches on Schmitt's Hamlet oder Hekuba,
    • For a discussion of Schmitt's relationship to Benjamin that briefly touches on Schmitt's Hamlet oder Hekuba
  • 76
    • 55949112514 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • From Walter Benjamin to Carl Schmitt, via Thomas Hobbes
    • see Horst Bredekamp, "From Walter Benjamin to Carl Schmitt, via Thomas Hobbes," Critical Inquiry 25 (1999): 247-66
    • (1999) Critical Inquiry , vol.25 , pp. 247-266
    • Bredekamp, H.1
  • 78
    • 79954809856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the differences between Schmitt's concept of the sovereign and Benjamin's views of the baroque sovereign, the excellent article by Samuel Weber, Taking Exception to Decision: Walter Benjamin and Carl Schmitt, Diacritics 22 (1992): 5-18.
    • On the differences between Schmitt's concept of the sovereign and Benjamin's views of the baroque sovereign, see the excellent article by Samuel Weber, "Taking Exception to Decision: Walter Benjamin and Carl Schmitt," Diacritics 22 (1992): 5-18
  • 79
    • 79954701337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the discontinuous temporality of decision in Trauerspiel, Weber, Taking Exception to Decision, 16-17. In Weber's words, the plotter begins where the sovereign hopes to end: with the ex-clusion of the state of exception (17, Benjamin's argument in the Trauerspiel book applies not only to Hamlet, with its crisis of sovereignty and Hamlet's own indecision, but also to Hobbes. Although the Hobbesian sovereign is he who decides the exception, Hobbes's political theory responds to the crisis of sovereignty that Benjamin sees represented in the baroque play of mourning. In Trauerspiel, Benjamin offered what Weber has called a reconstruction of the political anthropology of the baroque, centered on three figures: the tyrant, the martyr, and the plotter 9, In the world of baroque politics, the sovereign finds himself in a position where a decision is both necessary and impossible. He responds by becoming a tyr
    • On the "discontinuous temporality of decision" in Trauerspiel, see Weber, "Taking Exception to Decision," 16-17. In Weber's words, "the plotter begins where the sovereign hopes to end: with the ex-clusion of the state of exception" (17). Benjamin's argument in the Trauerspiel book applies not only to Hamlet, with its crisis of sovereignty and Hamlet's own indecision, but also to Hobbes. Although the Hobbesian sovereign is he who decides the exception, Hobbes's political theory responds to the crisis of sovereignty that Benjamin sees represented in the baroque play of mourning. In Trauerspiel, Benjamin offered what Weber has called "a reconstruction of the political anthropology of the baroque," centered on three figures: the tyrant, the martyr, and the plotter (9). In the world of baroque politics, the sovereign finds himself in a position where a decision is both necessary and impossible. He responds by becoming a tyrant, but his inevitable ineffectiveness in turn transforms him into a martyr. The violent oscillation between tyrant and martyr in turn produces the plotter. This is a good description of the events leading up to the English civil war, which formed the backdrop of Leviathan. At the outset of the Long Parliament (shortly before the outbreak of civil war), Charles conceded he had abused his power; with his execution, he became a martyr. And these events catapulted Oliver Cromwell to power, whom Andrew Marvell described as a consummate plotter, a hero of Machiavellian virtù. I discuss the differences between the dysfunctional sovereign of the Trauerspiel and the Hobbesian sovereign later in this essay
  • 80
    • 79954848935 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • My emphasis. Parliamentary Democracy
    • My emphasis. Cf. Parliamentary Democracy
  • 81
    • 79954774057 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and The Concept of the Political on liberalism's relativizing of different points of view Spiel is associated not only with fiction but also with liberal relativism.
    • and The Concept of the Political on liberalism's relativizing of different points of view Spiel is associated not only with fiction but also with liberal relativism
  • 82
    • 79954926054 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Spiel, Schmitt, The Source of the Tragic, 139.
    • On Spiel, see Schmitt, "The Source of the Tragic," 139
  • 83
    • 79954887059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I was helped to this point by conversations with my colleague, David Bates
    • I was helped to see this point by conversations with my colleague, David Bates
  • 84
    • 79954772240 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This opposition between civilization and barbarism owes something to Friedrich Nietzsche's critique of civilization in The Genealogy of Morals
    • This opposition between civilization and barbarism owes something to Friedrich Nietzsche's critique of civilization in The Genealogy of Morals
  • 85
    • 79954713158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • or perhaps to Oswald Spengler's defense of blood and tradition against civilization in The Decline of the West. Students of Benjamin will also recall his maxim that every achievement of civilization is simultaneously a record of barbarism.
    • or perhaps to Oswald Spengler's defense of "blood and tradition" against civilization in The Decline of the West. Students of Benjamin will also recall his maxim that every achievement of civilization is simultaneously a record of barbarism
  • 86
    • 79954675831 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One is also reminded here of Schmitt's celebration in Roman Catholicism and Political Form of the antithesis of [the] empire of technology ... nature untouched by civilization, wild and barbarian. In that earlier work, however, Schmitt rejected this idealization of the barbaric: Such a dichotomy between a rationalistic-mechanistic world of human labor and a romantic-virginal state of nature is totally foreign to the Roman Catholic view of nature, which Schmitt was defending (10).
    • One is also reminded here of Schmitt's celebration in Roman Catholicism and Political Form of "the antithesis of [the] empire of technology ... nature untouched by civilization, wild and barbarian." In that earlier work, however, Schmitt rejected this idealization of the barbaric: "Such a dichotomy between a rationalistic-mechanistic world of human labor and a romantic-virginal state of nature is totally foreign to the Roman Catholic view of nature," which Schmitt was defending (10)
  • 87
    • 79954959096 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Parliamentary Democracy on the revolutionary use of force by the masses as an expression of immediate life and barbarity 68-72, Benjamin himself, according to Schmitt, neglected the differences between Elizabethan England and absolutist France and so missed the distinction between the barbaric and the political. He thus misapplied Schmitt's conception of the sovereign to Shakespeare's Trauerspiele: In Shakespeare's Elizabethan England the baroque theatrification of life was still unfounded and elementary, not yet incorporated into the strict framework of the sovereign state and its establishment of public peace, security and order, as was the theater of Corneille and Racine in the France of Louis XIV In comparison with this classic theater, Shakespeare's play in its comic as well as melancholic aspects was coarse and elementary, barbaric and not yet political in the sense of the state at that time, 140
    • Cf. Parliamentary Democracy on the revolutionary use of force by the masses as an expression of immediate life and barbarity (68-72). Benjamin himself, according to Schmitt, neglected the differences between Elizabethan England and absolutist France and so missed the distinction between the barbaric and the political. He thus misapplied Schmitt's conception of the sovereign to Shakespeare's Trauerspiele: In Shakespeare's Elizabethan England the baroque theatrification of life was still unfounded and elementary - not yet incorporated into the strict framework of the sovereign state and its establishment of public peace, security and order, as was the theater of Corneille and Racine in the France of Louis XIV In comparison with this classic theater, Shakespeare's play in its comic as well as melancholic aspects was coarse and elementary, barbaric and not yet "political" in the sense of the state at that time. (140)
  • 88
    • 79954779959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Franco Moretti reads Shakespearean tragedy in terms of the shift from a theological to a secular worldview in Signs Taken for Wonders London, 1983, 42-82
    • Franco Moretti reads Shakespearean tragedy in terms of the shift from a theological to a secular worldview in Signs Taken for Wonders (London, 1983), 42-82
  • 89
    • 79954687750 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Moretti briefly discusses the relevance of Schmitt's notion of sovereignty for Tudor-Stuart drama early in this essay.) Stephen Greenblatt reads Hamlet as dramatizing contemporary anxiety about the shift from a Catholic notion of purgatory and fullness of ritual to a vitiated Protestant theatricality in Hamlet in Purgatory (Princeton, 2001).
    • (Moretti briefly discusses the relevance of Schmitt's notion of sovereignty for Tudor-Stuart drama early in this essay.) Stephen Greenblatt reads Hamlet as dramatizing contemporary anxiety about the shift from a Catholic notion of purgatory and fullness of ritual to a vitiated Protestant theatricality in Hamlet in Purgatory (Princeton, 2001)
  • 90
    • 79954970183 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schmitt draws on Lilian Winstanley, Hamlet and the Scottish Succession (Cambridge, 1921),
    • Schmitt draws on Lilian Winstanley, Hamlet and the Scottish Succession (Cambridge, 1921)
  • 92
    • 79954906540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The first quarto was a pirated edition, half as long as the second quarto of 1604, and is not considered a reliable text. It may have been edited or pirated for performance in the provinces. For an excellent modern account of the differences between the first quarto, the second quarto, and the first folio editions of Hamlet, Leah S. Marcus, Bad Taste and Bad Hamlet, in her Unediting the Renaissance New York, 1996, 132-76. Marcus makes it clear that the Hamlet of the first quarto is far less self-reflective and melancholic, and far more capable of action, than the later Hamlets: While Q2 frequently doubles back upon itself and slows down the action with long meditative speeches, Q1 Hamlet has no time for prolonged meditation and very litde time for soliloquies; But what is lost in terms of Hamlet's relentless, nearly manic probing of the dark borders of human existence is partly gained back by his increased capacity for act
    • The first quarto was a pirated edition, half as long as the second quarto of 1604, and is not considered a reliable text. It may have been edited or pirated for performance in the provinces. For an excellent modern account of the differences between the first quarto, the second quarto, and the first folio editions of Hamlet, see Leah S. Marcus, "Bad Taste and Bad Hamlet," in her Unediting the Renaissance (New York, 1996), 132-76. Marcus makes it clear that the Hamlet of the first quarto is far less self-reflective and melancholic, and far more capable of action, than the later Hamlets: "While Q2 frequently doubles back upon itself and slows down the action with long meditative speeches, Q1 Hamlet has no time for prolonged meditation and very litde time for soliloquies"; "But what is lost in terms of Hamlet's relentless, nearly manic probing of the dark borders of human existence is partly gained back by his increased capacity for action" (145)
  • 94
    • 79954687751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It's as though Hamlet were anticipating Benjamin's analysis of the indecision and theatricality characteristic of German baroque drama in contrast to genuine tragedy. In The Origin of German Tragic Drama, Benjamin writes: In the European Trauerspiel as a whole ... the stage is also not strictly fixable, not an actual place, but it too is dialectically split. Bound to the court, it yet remains a travelling theatre; metaphorically its boards represent the earth as the setting created for the enactment of history; it follows the court from town to town (119).
    • It's as though Hamlet were anticipating Benjamin's analysis of the indecision and theatricality characteristic of German baroque drama in contrast to genuine tragedy. In The Origin of German Tragic Drama, Benjamin writes: "In the European Trauerspiel as a whole ... the stage is also not strictly fixable, not an actual place, but it too is dialectically split. Bound to the court, it yet remains a travelling theatre; metaphorically its boards represent the earth as the setting created for the enactment of history; it follows the court from town to town" (119)
  • 95
    • 79954648699 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In this light, Hamlet's decision to act would be analogous to what Löwith, Occasional Decisionism, describes as Schmitt's decision in favor of decisiveness (158), or as the radical indifference of purely formal decision to any kind of political content (150).
    • In this light, Hamlet's decision to act would be analogous to what Löwith, "Occasional Decisionism," describes as Schmitt's "decision in favor of decisiveness" (158), or as the "radical indifference of purely formal decision to any kind of political content" (150)
  • 96
    • 79954843141 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Schmitt himself writes that Elizabethan society largely perceived its own action as theater but his remarks on Hamlet and Hecuba seem designed precisely to eradicate the difference between theater and historical fact; The Source of the Tragic, 140.
    • Schmitt himself writes that Elizabethan society "largely perceived its own action as theater" but his remarks on Hamlet and Hecuba seem designed precisely to eradicate the difference between theater and historical fact; "The Source of the Tragic," 140
  • 97
    • 79954840743 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That is, it's the indecision that's tragic, rather than the facts of the succession. This is why Hamlet is a modern tragedy, rather than an ancient tragedy.
    • That is, it's the indecision that's tragic, rather than the facts of the succession. This is why Hamlet is a modern tragedy, rather than an ancient tragedy
  • 100
    • 0004323335 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a variety of arguments regarding Shakespeare's theatrical critique of absolutism,
    • For a variety of arguments regarding Shakespeare's theatrical critique of absolutism, see Moretti, Signs Taken for Wonders
    • Signs Taken for Wonders
    • Moretti1
  • 103
    • 33645980447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Not the King's Two Bodies
    • Victoria Kahn and Lorna Hutson, eds, New Haven
    • Lorna Hutson, "Not the King's Two Bodies," in Victoria Kahn and Lorna Hutson, eds., Rhetoric and Law in Early Modern Europe (New Haven, 2001), 266-98
    • (2001) Rhetoric and Law in Early Modern Europe , pp. 266-298
    • Hutson, L.1
  • 106
    • 79954756903 scopus 로고
    • Either/Or
    • trans. David F. Swenson and Lillian Marvin, Johnson Garden City, N.Y
    • Søren Kierkegaard, Either/Or, trans. David F. Swenson and Lillian Marvin Swenson with revisions by Howard A. Johnson (Garden City, N.Y., 1959), 1:139
    • (1959) Swenson with revisions by Howard A , vol.1 , pp. 139
    • Kierkegaard, S.1
  • 107
    • 79954928360 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kierkegaard allows for modern tragedy, but argues that the proportion of subjective and objective, pain and sorrow, differs from that of ancient tragedy
    • Kierkegaard allows for modern tragedy - but argues that the proportion of subjective and objective, pain and sorrow, differs from that of ancient tragedy
  • 108
    • 28244465364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a tendentious reading of Hobbes as a political realist, New York
    • For a tendentious reading of Hobbes as a political realist, see Robert D. Kaplan, Warrior Politics (New York, 2002)
    • (2002) Warrior Politics
    • Kaplan, R.D.1
  • 110
    • 79954793018 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kagan is usefully reviewed by Tony Judt in America and the World, New York Review of Books, 10 May 2003, 28-31.
    • Kagan is usefully reviewed by Tony Judt in "America and the World," New York Review of Books, 10 May 2003, 28-31
  • 111
    • 35548938226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Should We Read Carl Schmitt Today?
    • For a different analysis of why we should read Schmitt, though one that is ultimately compatible with my own,
    • For a different analysis of why we should read Schmitt, though one that is ultimately compatible with my own, see D. A. Jeremy Tolman, "Should We Read Carl Schmitt Today?" Berkeley Journal of International Law 19 (2001): 127-60
    • (2001) Berkeley Journal of International Law , vol.19 , pp. 127-160
    • Jeremy Tolman, D.A.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.