메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 28, Issue 1, 2008, Pages 33-55

Does dworkin commit dworkin's fallacy?: A reply to justice in robes

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 41349094852     PISSN: 01436503     EISSN: 14643820     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1093/ojls/gqm025     Document Type: Note
Times cited : (4)

References (117)
  • 1
    • 0742324002 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin's Fallacy, Or What the Philosophy of Language Can't Teach Us About the Law', 89
    • Michael Steven Green, 'Dworkin's Fallacy, Or What the Philosophy of Language Can't Teach Us About the Law', 89 Virginia L Rev 1897-1952 (2003).
    • (2003) Virginia L Rev , vol.1897-1952
    • Steven Green, M.1
  • 2
    • 84936068266 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press
    • Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1986).
    • (1986) Law's Empire
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 3
    • 41349114703 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Green, above n 1 at 1915-1927.
    • See Green, above n 1 at 1915-1927.
  • 4
    • 41349105195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid at 1915, 1927-29.
    • Ibid at 1915, 1927-29.
  • 5
    • 33748926618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, at
    • Ronald Dworkin, Justice in Robes (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 2006) at 226.
    • (2006) Justice in Robes , pp. 226
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 8
    • 41349117469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 2 at Chs 4-6.
    • Dworkin, above n 2 at Chs 4-6.
  • 9
    • 41349108978 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 226-227
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 226-227.
  • 10
    • 41349084055 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In fact, sometimes Hart speaks of the rule of recognition not as a social practice but as a proposition specifying the criteria for enforceability within the legal system. See Benjamin C. Zipursky, The Model of Social Facts' in J. Coleman (ed, Hart's Postscript: Essays on the Postscript to the Concept of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001) 219 at 227-228
    • In fact, sometimes Hart speaks of the rule of recognition not as a social practice but as a proposition specifying the criteria for enforceability within the legal system. See Benjamin C. Zipursky, 'The Model of Social Facts' in J. Coleman (ed.), Hart's Postscript: Essays on the Postscript to the Concept of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001) 219 at 227-228.
  • 11
    • 41349108102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But he also uses the term to refer to the social fact that a certain rule of recognition (in the propositional sense) is practised by officials. The proposition is practised in the sense that officials agree to enforce only that which satisfies the criteria in the proposition. On the distinction between a rule of recognition in the propositional sense and the practice of that rule, see Jules L. Coleman, Practice of Principle: In Defence of a Pragmatist Approach to Legal Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001) at 77-78.
    • But he also uses the term to refer to the social fact that a certain rule of recognition (in the propositional sense) is practised by officials. The proposition is practised in the sense that officials agree to enforce only that which satisfies the criteria in the proposition. On the distinction between a rule of recognition in the propositional sense and the practice of that rule, see Jules L. Coleman, Practice of Principle: In Defence of a Pragmatist Approach to Legal Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001) at 77-78.
  • 12
    • 41349098020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin equates a theory of law with an account of the truth conditions of propositions of law at Dworkin, above n 5 at 230, 244, 246-247
    • Dworkin equates a theory of law with an account of the truth conditions of propositions of law at Dworkin, above n 5 at 230, 244, 246-247.
  • 13
    • 41349088258 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sometimes, however, he treats a theory of law as being articulated at the 'jurisprudential stage' of legal theory and an account of the truth conditions of propositions of law as occurring later in the 'doctrinal stage, See especially ibid 12-14. Dworkin's theory of law as integrity, which occurs at the doctrinal stage, would therefore be an account of the truth conditions of propositions of law, not a theory of law. I shall argue below that law as integrity (as well as the two other positions Dworkin entertains at the doctrinal stage, namely Dworkinian conventionalism and pragmatism) are actually applications of Dworkin's theory of law to particular jurisdictions. They should therefore be understood as accounts of the truth conditions of propositions that describe the law of a particular jurisdiction. A theory of law, in turn, should be understood as an account of the truth conditions of all propositions of law, no matter what particular jurisdiction they happen to be about
    • Sometimes, however, he treats a theory of law as being articulated at the 'jurisprudential stage' of legal theory and an account of the truth conditions of propositions of law as occurring later in the 'doctrinal stage'. See especially ibid 12-14. Dworkin's theory of law as integrity, which occurs at the doctrinal stage, would therefore be an account of the truth conditions of propositions of law, not a theory of law. I shall argue below that law as integrity (as well as the two other positions Dworkin entertains at the doctrinal stage, namely Dworkinian conventionalism and pragmatism) are actually applications of Dworkin's theory of law to particular jurisdictions. They should therefore be understood as accounts of the truth conditions of propositions that describe the law of a particular jurisdiction. A theory of law, in turn, should be understood as an account of the truth conditions of all propositions of law, no matter what particular jurisdiction they happen to be about.
  • 14
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2nd edn, at
    • H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2nd edn, 1994) at 94.
    • (1994) The Concept of Law , pp. 94
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 15
    • 41349084447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The existence of a rule of recognition in a legal system also requires that the primary rules that are valid according to the rule of recognition are generally - although not necessarily always-obeyed by the population. Ibid at 116-117.
    • The existence of a rule of recognition in a legal system also requires that the primary rules that are valid according to the rule of recognition are generally - although not necessarily always-obeyed by the population. Ibid at 116-117.
  • 16
    • 41349117682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, officials might disagree about how a case should turn out even though they agree on enforcement criteria, for they might disagree about whether those criteria are in fact satisfied, They might agree, for example, that the case could be resolved only by statutes enacted by the legislature but disagree about whether there was a quorum required for enactment
    • Of course, officials might disagree about how a case should turn out even though they agree on enforcement criteria, for they might disagree about whether those criteria are in fact satisfied. 'They might agree, for example, that the case could be resolved only by statutes enacted by the legislature but disagree about whether there was a quorum required for enactment.
  • 17
    • 41349088045 scopus 로고
    • In speaking of Hart's theory as conventionalist, I mean only and vaguely that the rule of recognition rests upon agreement within the jurisdiction. I do not take a stand on whether it should be understood as the solution to a coordination problem. See, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press
    • In speaking of Hart's theory as conventionalist, I mean only and vaguely that the rule of recognition rests upon agreement within the jurisdiction. I do not take a stand on whether it should be understood as the solution to a coordination problem. See David K. Lewis, Convention: A Philosophical Study (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1969).
    • (1969) Convention: A Philosophical Study
    • Lewis, D.K.1
  • 18
    • 0009328204 scopus 로고
    • Coordination and Convention at the Foundations of Law', 11
    • For such an account of the rule of recognition, see
    • For such an account of the rule of recognition, see Gerald J. Postema, 'Coordination and Convention at the Foundations of Law', 11 Journal of Legal Studies 165-203 (1982)
    • (1982) Journal of Legal Studies , vol.165-203
    • Postema, G.J.1
  • 19
    • 41349089128 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jules Coleman, 'Incorporationism, Conventionality, and the Practical Difference Thesis' in J. Coleman (ed.), Hart's Postscript: Essays on the Postscript to the Concept of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001) 99 at 114-121.
    • Jules Coleman, 'Incorporationism, Conventionality, and the Practical Difference Thesis' in J. Coleman (ed.), Hart's Postscript: Essays on the Postscript to the Concept of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001) 99 at 114-121.
  • 20
    • 41349121030 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nor do I take a stand on whether it should be understood as a shared cooperative activity in Michael Bratman's sense: Michael E. Bratman, Shared Cooperative Activity: Three Features, 101 Philosophical Review 327-341 1992
    • Nor do I take a stand on whether it should be understood as a shared cooperative activity in Michael Bratman's sense: Michael E. Bratman, 'Shared Cooperative Activity: Three Features', 101 Philosophical Review 327-341 (1992).
  • 21
    • 41349098673 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For such an account of the rule of recognition, see Coleman, above n 10 at 96-99.
    • For such an account of the rule of recognition, see Coleman, above n 10 at 96-99.
  • 22
    • 41349095316 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See n 19 below
    • See n 19 below.
  • 23
    • 84864061889 scopus 로고
    • Jhering's Heaven of Concepts and Modern Analytical Jurisprudence
    • See, Oxford: Oxford University Press, at
    • See H.L.A. Hart, 'Jhering's Heaven of Concepts and Modern Analytical Jurisprudence' in Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983) 265 at 274
    • (1983) Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy , vol.265 , pp. 274
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 25
    • 41349108977 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, in Justice in Robes, Dworkin notes that '[i]n one respect... Hart and I are in the same boat. We both believe that we will understand legal practice and phenomena better if we undertake to study, not law in some particular manifestation, like the law of product liability in Scotland, but the very concept of law.'
    • For example, in Justice in Robes, Dworkin notes that '[i]n one respect... Hart and I are in the same boat. We both believe that we will understand legal practice and phenomena better if we undertake to study, not law in some particular manifestation, like the law of product liability in Scotland, but the very concept of law.'
  • 26
    • 41349096130 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 145
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 145.
  • 28
    • 41349083635 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Ibid at 9.
  • 29
    • 41349098672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • He argues that some confusion has resulted from the failure to distinguish the doctrinal from other concepts of law. Ibid at 2-5. I will accept, at least for the purposes of argument, Dworkin's position that a theory of law reveals the content of the doctrinal concept of law.
    • He argues that some confusion has resulted from the failure to distinguish the doctrinal from other concepts of law. Ibid at 2-5. I will accept, at least for the purposes of argument, Dworkin's position that a theory of law reveals the content of the doctrinal concept of law.
  • 30
    • 41349107475 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • David Kaplan, 'Afterthoughts' in J. Almog et al. (eds), Themes from Kaplan (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989) 565 at 573-576
    • David Kaplan, 'Afterthoughts' in J. Almog et al. (eds), Themes from Kaplan (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989) 565 at 573-576
  • 31
    • 41349091115 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Green, above n 1 at 1905 n 21
    • Green, above n 1 at 1905 n 21
  • 33
    • 17044400602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I follow him in using the word 'semantic' in this way in Michael Steven Green, 'Halpin on Dworkin's Fallacy: A Surreply', 91 Virginia L Rev 187-201 (2005).
    • I follow him in using the word 'semantic' in this way in Michael Steven Green, 'Halpin on Dworkin's Fallacy: A Surreply', 91 Virginia L Rev 187-201 (2005).
  • 34
    • 41349085877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 9
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 9.
  • 35
    • 41349104349 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Law's Empire, Dworkin describes as 'semantic' the view that '[w]e follow shared rules... in using any word: These rules set out criteria that supply the word's meaning'. Dworkin, above n 2 at 31.
    • In Law's Empire, Dworkin describes as 'semantic' the view that '[w]e follow shared rules... in using any word: These rules set out criteria that supply the word's meaning'. Dworkin, above n 2 at 31.
  • 36
    • 41349091335 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 9
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 9.
  • 37
    • 41349095539 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a fuller description of the metasemantic conventionalist approach, see Green, above n 1 at 1899-1903.
    • For a fuller description of the metasemantic conventionalist approach, see Green, above n 1 at 1899-1903.
  • 38
    • 41349099262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 2 at 31-35
    • Dworkin, above n 2 at 31-35.
  • 39
    • 41349122103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 30 33, 165-166, 225-226
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 30 33, 165-166, 225-226.
  • 40
    • 36049035883 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid at 225. I explore this example of Dworkin's fallacy more fully in Michael Steven Green, 'Dworkin v. The Philosophers: A Review Essay on Justice in Robes', U of Illinois L Rev 1477-1503 (2007).
    • Ibid at 225. I explore this example of Dworkin's fallacy more fully in Michael Steven Green, 'Dworkin v. The Philosophers: A Review Essay on Justice in Robes', U of Illinois L Rev 1477-1503 (2007).
  • 41
    • 41349086943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart, above n 12 at 246
    • Hart, above n 12 at 246.
  • 42
    • 41349096303 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Green, above n 25 at 1496-1497
    • Green, above n 25 at 1496-1497
  • 43
    • 41349099925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stavropoulos, above n 16
    • Stavropoulos, above n 16.
  • 44
    • 36048990476 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Can Theories of Meaning and Reference Solve the Problem of Legal Determinacy?', 16
    • For arguments that metasemantic theories would not necessarily have such consequences, see
    • For arguments that metasemantic theories would not necessarily have such consequences, see Brian H. Bix, 'Can Theories of Meaning and Reference Solve the Problem of Legal Determinacy?', 16 Ratio Juris 281-295 (2003)
    • (2003) Ratio Juris , vol.281-295
    • Bix, B.H.1
  • 45
    • 41349099044 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Green, above n 1 at 1946-1948
    • Green, above n 1 at 1946-1948.
  • 46
    • 41349085063 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid at 1919-1929. I explore this source of Dworkin's fallacy in greater detail in Green, above n 25 at 1491-1495.
    • Ibid at 1919-1929. I explore this source of Dworkin's fallacy in greater detail in Green, above n 25 at 1491-1495.
  • 47
    • 41349118848 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 9
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 9.
  • 48
    • 41349110944 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 2 at 73
    • Dworkin, above n 2 at 73.
  • 49
    • 41349098671 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Ibid at 43-46
  • 50
    • 41349098230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 223-26
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 223-26.
  • 51
    • 41349093226 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At times, however, Hart suggests that he and Dworkin are indeed talking past one another. Hart, above n 12 at 239-244
    • At times, however, Hart suggests that he and Dworkin are indeed talking past one another. Hart, above n 12 at 239-244.
  • 52
    • 41349092386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 226
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 226.
  • 53
    • 41349095540 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 2 at Chs 4-6.
    • Dworkin, above n 2 at Chs 4-6.
  • 54
    • 41349107885 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 226
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 226.
  • 55
    • 41349091116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Ibid at 12.
  • 56
    • 41349110500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 2 at 66
    • Dworkin, above n 2 at 66.
  • 57
    • 41349099926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid at 87; Dworkin, above n 5 at 226-227.
    • Ibid at 87; Dworkin, above n 5 at 226-227.
  • 58
    • 41349103081 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Green, above n 1 at 1921
    • Green, above n 1 at 1921.
  • 59
    • 41349117070 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 11
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 11.
  • 60
    • 41349083425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Green, above n 1 at 1920 n 63
    • Green, above n 1 at 1920 n 63.
  • 61
    • 41349092601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 2 at 96
    • Dworkin, above n 2 at 96.
  • 62
    • 41349116406 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 226
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 226.
  • 63
    • 41349113454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 2 at 226
    • Dworkin, above n 2 at 226.
  • 64
    • 41349084052 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 226 (emphasis mine). At times Dworkin suggests that the laws of other jurisdictions can be understood only in the light of the moral interpretation of the legal practices of one's own jurisdiction. Having determined that law as integrity is the proper approach to our jurisdiction, the laws of all other jurisdictions would be seen in the light of law as integrity as well.
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 226 (emphasis mine). At times Dworkin suggests that the laws of other jurisdictions can be understood only in the light of the moral interpretation of the legal practices of one's own jurisdiction. Having determined that law as integrity is the proper approach to our jurisdiction, the laws of all other jurisdictions would be seen in the light of law as integrity as well.
  • 65
    • 41349087174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Dworkin, above n 2 at 102 (useful theories of law are 'interpretive of a particular stage of a historically developing practice' and 'are by their nature addressed to a particular legal culture, generally the culture to which their authors belong').
    • See Dworkin, above n 2 at 102 (useful theories of law are 'interpretive of a particular stage of a historically developing practice' and 'are by their nature addressed to a particular legal culture, generally the culture to which their authors belong').
  • 66
    • 41349118616 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Dworkin, above n 5 at 163 (he seeks to answer the question of what makes a claim of law true 'not just for a particular legal system, like English law, but for law in general, whether in Alabama or Afghanistan'.)
    • But see Dworkin, above n 5 at 163 (he seeks to answer the question of what makes a claim of law true 'not just for a particular legal system, like English law, but for law in general, whether in Alabama or Afghanistan'.)
  • 67
    • 41349093005 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ibid at 185 (his account 'aims at very great generality')
    • ibid at 185 (his account 'aims at very great generality')
  • 68
    • 41349096129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ibid at 230-231 (same). One problem with the suggestion that the laws of other jurisdictions are seen in the light of the moral purposes of the practices of one's own jurisdiction is it makes Dworkin vulnerable to the charge of parochialism. If we must see all legal systems in the light of law as integrity, wouldn't people in my hypothetical jurisdiction see us in the light of Dworkinian conventionalism?
    • ibid at 230-231 (same). One problem with the suggestion that the laws of other jurisdictions are seen in the light of the moral purposes of the practices of one's own jurisdiction is it makes Dworkin vulnerable to the charge of parochialism. If we must see all legal systems in the light of law as integrity, wouldn't people in my hypothetical jurisdiction see us in the light of Dworkinian conventionalism?
  • 69
    • 41349086749 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But setting this problem aside, it would still be the case that law as integrity is the application of Dworkin's interpretive theory of law and thus not a theory of law in its own right, for the fact would remain that the criteria that identify the laws of our jurisdiction (and, through it, all other jurisdictions) are whatever result from the moral interpretation of our legal practices.
    • But setting this problem aside, it would still be the case that law as integrity is the application of Dworkin's interpretive theory of law and thus not a theory of law in its own right, for the fact would remain that the criteria that identify the laws of our jurisdiction (and, through it, all other jurisdictions) are whatever result from the moral interpretation of our legal practices.
  • 70
    • 41349120586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hart, above n 12 at 241-242, 248-250.
    • See Hart, above n 12 at 241-242, 248-250.
  • 71
    • 41349104761 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Indeed Dworkin himself admits that the argument for Dworkinian conventionalism is 'self-defeating' for the positivist. Dworkin, above n 5 at 180.
    • Indeed Dworkin himself admits that the argument for Dworkinian conventionalism is 'self-defeating' for the positivist. Dworkin, above n 5 at 180.
  • 72
    • 41349089599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Ibid at 226.
  • 73
    • 41349104987 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At Green, above n 1 at 1916, for example, I characterized Dworkin's interpretive theory of law in the following way
    • At Green, above n 1 at 1916, for example, I characterized Dworkin's interpretive theory of law in the following way:
  • 74
    • 41349094668 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • According to Dworkin's interpretive jurisprudence, the law consists of the set of norms that would be accepted after a process in which 'the interpreter settles on some general justification for the main elements of [legal] practice' and then reforms it by 'adjust[ing] his sense of what the practice really requires so as better to serve the justification'.
    • According to Dworkin's interpretive jurisprudence, the law consists of the set of norms that would be accepted after a process in which 'the interpreter settles on some general justification for the main elements of [legal] practice' and then reforms it by 'adjust[ing] his sense of what the practice "really" requires so as better to serve the justification'.
  • 75
    • 41349105194 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The quoted passage is from Law's Empire, Dworkin, above n 2 at 66, where Dworkin describes interpretive concepts. I repeatedly spoke of Dworkin's theory of law as involving moral interpretation of legal practices, and never as involving moral interpretation of the bulk of pertinent standing law. Green, above n 1 at 1916, 1919, 1920 n 62, 1921, 1925, 1928 n 76.
    • The quoted passage is from Law's Empire, Dworkin, above n 2 at 66, where Dworkin describes interpretive concepts. I repeatedly spoke of Dworkin's theory of law as involving moral interpretation of legal practices, and never as involving moral interpretation of the bulk of pertinent standing law. Green, above n 1 at 1916, 1919, 1920 n 62, 1921, 1925, 1928 n 76.
  • 76
    • 41349123783 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid at 1909-1915; 1918 (arguing that 'it took a good deal of interpretation on my part to draw an interpretive theory of meaning out of Dworkin's work').
    • Ibid at 1909-1915; 1918 (arguing that 'it took a good deal of interpretation on my part to draw an interpretive theory of meaning out of Dworkin's work').
  • 77
    • 41349110945 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Ibid at 1904.
  • 78
    • 41349086275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Ibid at 1909-1910.
  • 79
    • 41349106024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 152
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 152.
  • 80
    • 41349111166 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Ibid at 153.
  • 81
    • 41349123139 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Ibid at 166.
  • 82
    • 41349092823 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid at 11-12. Unfortunately, Dworkin cannot seem to make up his mind on this issue, for elsewhere in Justice in Robes he suggests that '[t]he purpose of my semantic sting argument was to make [the following] point: Sharing a concept does not necessarily mean sharing criteria for its application, but might instead mean sharing paradigms as the basis for interpretive claims'.
    • Ibid at 11-12. Unfortunately, Dworkin cannot seem to make up his mind on this issue, for elsewhere in Justice in Robes he suggests that '[t]he purpose of my "semantic sting" argument was to make [the following] point: Sharing a concept does not necessarily mean sharing criteria for its application, but might instead mean sharing paradigms as the basis for interpretive claims'.
  • 83
    • 41349091528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 218
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 218.
  • 84
    • 41349096530 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At one point in Justice in Robes Dworkin concludes, bizarrely, that the metasemantic theory I attribute to him is realist: [Green] discusses at some length a philosophical dispute between what he calls a 'traditionalist' and a 'realist' view of the concepts of gold, water and tiger. The former view treats these concepts as criterial, and the latter insists that they are not criterial but function rather as natural kind concepts. Green apparently assumes that this is a dispute about how all concepts should be understood. So he says that I make 'arguments about meaning similar to those of the realists in order to attack the jurisprudential position that law is exhausted by agreement or convention, That is not correct, and the misunderstanding is important. I did reject a criterial account of the doctrinal concept of law. But I did not adopt a natural kind semantics for that concept; in Chapter 6 of this book I explicitly rejected a natural kind interpretation of any
    • At one point in Justice in Robes Dworkin concludes, bizarrely, that the metasemantic theory I attribute to him is realist: [Green] discusses at some length a philosophical dispute between what he calls a 'traditionalist' and a 'realist' view of the concepts of gold, water and tiger. The former view treats these concepts as criterial, and the latter insists that they are not criterial but function rather as natural kind concepts. Green apparently assumes that this is a dispute about how all concepts should be understood. So he says that I make 'arguments about meaning similar to those of the realists in order to attack the jurisprudential position that law is exhausted by agreement or convention'. That is not correct, and the misunderstanding is important. I did reject a criterial account of the doctrinal concept of law. But I did not adopt a natural kind semantics for that concept; in Chapter 6 of this book I explicitly rejected a natural kind interpretation of any of the concepts of law. Instead I said that the doctrinal concept, like other important political concepts, is interpretive.
  • 85
    • 41349118187 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid at 227. Dworkin comes to this conclusion about my argument on the basis of my single observation that Dworkin 'employs arguments about meaning similar to those of the realists'.
    • Ibid at 227. Dworkin comes to this conclusion about my argument on the basis of my single observation that Dworkin 'employs arguments about meaning similar to those of the realists'.
  • 86
    • 41349091734 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Green, above n I at 1908. But Dworkin does employ arguments similar to the realists, since he insists that questions about the content of the concept of law can have right answers even when there is disagreement about what that content is. Indeed, in Justice in Robes Dworkin himself speaks of 'instructive similarities' between natural-kind concepts and interpretive concepts like the concept of law, because the content of these concepts is not beholden to people's current attitudes.
    • Green, above n I at 1908. But Dworkin does employ arguments similar to the realists, since he insists that questions about the content of the concept of law can have right answers even when there is disagreement about what that content is. Indeed, in Justice in Robes Dworkin himself speaks of 'instructive similarities' between natural-kind concepts and interpretive concepts like the concept of law, because the content of these concepts is not beholden to people's current attitudes.
  • 87
    • 41349094248 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 154
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 154.
  • 88
    • 33748936105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin on the Semantics of Legal and Political Concepts
    • See also
    • See also Dennis M. Patterson, 'Dworkin on the Semantics of Legal and Political Concepts' (2006) 26 OFLS 545-557.
    • (2006) OFLS , vol.26 , pp. 545-557
    • Patterson, D.M.1
  • 89
    • 41349112814 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To say that Dworkin's metasemantics is similar to realism in this respect is not to say that he was a realist. Indeed, after introducing the possibility that Dworkin's metasemantic theory is realist, I immediately and clearly reject the idea, Green, above n 1 at 1909-1910, and attribute an interpretive theory of meaning to him repeatedly in the rest of the article.
    • To say that Dworkin's metasemantics is similar to realism in this respect is not to say that he was a realist. Indeed, after introducing the possibility that Dworkin's metasemantic theory is realist, I immediately and clearly reject the idea, Green, above n 1 at 1909-1910, and attribute an interpretive theory of meaning to him repeatedly in the rest of the article.
  • 90
    • 41349093852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid at 1914, 1915, 1920, 1921, 1924.
    • Ibid at 1914, 1915, 1920, 1921, 1924.
  • 92
    • 41349096533 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 289
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 289.
  • 93
    • 0347612996 scopus 로고
    • The New Riddle of Induction
    • Indianapolis, Indiana, 3rd edn
    • Nelson Goodman, "The New Riddle of Induction' in Fact, Fiction, and Forecast (Indianapolis, Indiana, 3rd edn, 1979) 59.
    • (1979) Fact, Fiction, and Forecast , pp. 59
    • Goodman, N.1
  • 94
    • 41349115141 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 289
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 289.
  • 95
    • 41349090690 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Green, above n 1 at 1915
    • Green, above n 1 at 1915
  • 96
    • 41349084054 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also ibid at 1916.
    • see also ibid at 1916.
  • 97
    • 41349086750 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Ibid at 1914.
  • 98
    • 41349084254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Goodman, above n 61 at 63
    • Goodman, above n 61 at 63.
  • 99
    • 41349119912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid.
  • 100
    • 0004223277 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press
    • Nelson Goodman, The Structure of Appearance (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1951).
    • (1951) The Structure of Appearance
    • Goodman, N.1
  • 101
    • 41349100556 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Green, above n 1 at 1912
    • Green, above n 1 at 1912.
  • 102
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, rev edn
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, rev edn, 1999) 17-18.
    • (1999) A Theory of Justice , pp. 17-18
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 103
    • 41349118617 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Green, above n 1 at 1912
    • Green, above n 1 at 1912.
  • 104
    • 41349097805 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 2 at 424 n 17
    • Dworkin, above n 2 at 424 n 17
  • 105
    • 41349120813 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 161
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 161.
  • 106
    • 41349117277 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Green, above n 1 at 1914 n 50
    • Green, above n 1 at 1914 n 50.
  • 107
    • 41349100982 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 141
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 141
  • 108
    • 0010915611 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Objectivity and Truth: You'd Better Believe It', 25
    • describing as 'archimedean' a theoretical approach that 'purport[s] to stand outside a whole body of belief, and to judge it as a whole from premises or attitudes that owe nothing to it, see also, at
    • see also Ronald Dworkin, 'Objectivity and Truth: You'd Better Believe It', 25 Philosophy & Public Affairs 87-139 at 88 (1996) (describing as 'archimedean' a theoretical approach that 'purport[s] to stand outside a whole body of belief, and to judge it as a whole from premises or attitudes that owe nothing to it').
    • (1996) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.87-139 , pp. 88
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 109
    • 41349092157 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Green, above n 1 at 1910, 1913
    • Green, above n 1 at 1910, 1913.
  • 110
    • 41349092387 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Patterson, above n 58.
    • See Patterson, above n 58.
  • 111
    • 41349122961 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 11
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 11.
  • 112
    • 41349103080 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Law's Empire, Dworkin also suggests that language-users' current attitudes are what determine the content of their concepts. He argues, for example, that the concept of law is interpretive because '[j]Judges normally recognize a duty to continue rather than discard the practice they have joined. So they develop, in response to their own convictions and instincts, working theories about the best interpretation of their responsibilities under that practice'. Dworkin, above n 2 at 87.
    • In Law's Empire, Dworkin also suggests that language-users' current attitudes are what determine the content of their concepts. He argues, for example, that the concept of law is interpretive because '[j]Judges normally recognize a duty to continue rather than discard the practice they have joined. So they develop, in response to their own convictions and instincts, working theories about the best interpretation of their responsibilities under that practice'. Dworkin, above n 2 at 87.
  • 113
    • 41349119245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 221
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 221.
  • 114
    • 41349099263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Ibid at 224.
  • 115
    • 41349113455 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also ibid at 221.
    • See also ibid at 221.
  • 116
    • 41349088930 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 2 at 87
    • Dworkin, above n 2 at 87.
  • 117
    • 41349090898 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 12
    • Dworkin, above n 5 at 12.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.