메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 18, Issue 1, 2001, Pages 115-145

Law as justice

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 4043061172     PISSN: 02650525     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0265052501181057     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (15)

References (108)
  • 1
    • 0008200920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Law as a Functional Kind
    • Robert George, ed., Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Michael Moore, "Law as a Functional Kind," in Robert George, ed., Natural Law Theories (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992), reprinted as chap. 9 of Michael Moore, Educating Oneself in Public: Critical Essays in Jurisprudence (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).
    • (1992) Natural Law Theories
    • Moore, M.1
  • 2
    • 0346113712 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • reprinted as chap. 9 Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Michael Moore, "Law as a Functional Kind," in Robert George, ed., Natural Law Theories (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992), reprinted as chap. 9 of Michael Moore, Educating Oneself in Public: Critical Essays in Jurisprudence (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).
    • (2000) Educating Oneself in Public: Critical Essays in Jurisprudence
    • Moore, M.1
  • 3
    • 0041010195 scopus 로고
    • Moral Reality
    • 1982, November/December
    • My views on the metaethical thesis are presented in Michael Moore, "Moral Reality," Wisconsin Law Review 1982, no. 6 (November/December 1982): 1061-156; Michael Moore, "Moral Reality Revisited," Michigan Law Review 90, no. 8 (August 1992): 2424-533; and Michael Moore, "Good without God," in Robert George, ed., Natural Law, Liberalism, and Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995).
    • (1982) Wisconsin Law Review , Issue.6 , pp. 1061-1156
    • Moore, M.1
  • 4
    • 0041010194 scopus 로고
    • Moral Reality Revisited
    • August
    • My views on the metaethical thesis are presented in Michael Moore, "Moral Reality," Wisconsin Law Review 1982, no. 6 (November/December 1982): 1061-156; Michael Moore, "Moral Reality Revisited," Michigan Law Review 90, no. 8 (August 1992): 2424-533; and Michael Moore, "Good without God," in Robert George, ed., Natural Law, Liberalism, and Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995).
    • (1992) Michigan Law Review , vol.90 , Issue.8 , pp. 2424-2533
    • Moore, M.1
  • 5
    • 8344269344 scopus 로고
    • Good without God
    • Robert George, ed., Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • My views on the metaethical thesis are presented in Michael Moore, "Moral Reality," Wisconsin Law Review 1982, no. 6 (November/December 1982): 1061-156; Michael Moore, "Moral Reality Revisited," Michigan Law Review 90, no. 8 (August 1992): 2424-533; and Michael Moore, "Good without God," in Robert George, ed., Natural Law, Liberalism, and Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995).
    • (1995) Natural Law, Liberalism, and Morality
    • Moore, M.1
  • 7
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • These attributes are the concern of H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961); and Joseph Raz, The Concept of a Legal System (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1970).
    • (1961) The Concept of Law
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 8
    • 0009327079 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • These attributes are the concern of H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961); and Joseph Raz, The Concept of a Legal System (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1970).
    • (1970) The Concept of a Legal System
    • Raz, J.1
  • 9
    • 0000580092 scopus 로고
    • Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morality
    • February
    • Herbert Hart nicely distinguished this concern about laws from more general concerns about legal systems, in his "Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morality," Harvard Law Review 71, no. 4 (February 1958): 593-629.
    • (1958) Harvard Law Review , vol.71 , Issue.4 , pp. 593-629
    • Hart, H.1
  • 10
    • 0013096712 scopus 로고
    • The Common Law and Legal Theory
    • A. W. B. Simpson, ed., 2d ser. Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • On Bentham's distaste for the common law, see A. W. B. Simpson, "The Common Law and Legal Theory," in A. W. B. Simpson, ed., Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence, 2d ser. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1973); and Gerald Postema, Bentham and the Common Law Tradition (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984).
    • (1973) Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence
    • Simpson, A.W.B.1
  • 11
    • 0003883951 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • On Bentham's distaste for the common law, see A. W. B. Simpson, "The Common Law and Legal Theory," in A. W. B. Simpson, ed., Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence, 2d ser. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1973); and Gerald Postema, Bentham and the Common Law Tradition (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984).
    • (1984) Bentham and the Common Law Tradition
    • Postema, G.1
  • 12
    • 0009419107 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge and Kegan Paul
    • When Michael Detmold urges the unity of law and morality, this is what he seems to have in mind. See M. J. Detmold, The Unity of Law and Morality (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1987).
    • (1987) The Unity of Law and Morality
    • Detmold, M.J.1
  • 13
    • 8344223673 scopus 로고
    • A Theory of Criminal Law Theories
    • Dan Friedmann, ed., Tel Aviv, Israel: Tel Aviv University Press
    • On areas of law, see Michael Moore, "A Theory of Criminal Law Theories," in Dan Friedmann, ed., Tel Aviv University Studies in Law, vol. 8 (Tel Aviv, Israel: Tel Aviv University Press, 1990), revised and reprinted as chap. 1 of Moore, Placing Blame: A General Theory of the Criminal Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997).
    • (1990) Tel Aviv University Studies in Law , vol.8
    • Moore, M.1
  • 14
    • 0039233110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • revised and reprinted as chap. 1 Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • On areas of law, see Michael Moore, "A Theory of Criminal Law Theories," in Dan Friedmann, ed., Tel Aviv University Studies in Law, vol. 8 (Tel Aviv, Israel: Tel Aviv University Press, 1990), revised and reprinted as chap. 1 of Moore, Placing Blame: A General Theory of the Criminal Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997).
    • (1997) Placing Blame: A General Theory of the Criminal Law
    • Moore1
  • 16
    • 85037273384 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 90, a. 4
    • Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, I-II, q. 90, a. 4, in Anton C. Pegis, Basic Writings of Saint Thomas Aquinas (New York: Random House, 1945), 2:746-47.
    • Summa Theologiae , vol.1-2
    • Aquinas, T.1
  • 17
    • 8344281321 scopus 로고
    • New York: Random House
    • Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, I-II, q. 90, a. 4, in Anton C. Pegis, Basic Writings of Saint Thomas Aquinas (New York: Random House, 1945), 2:746-47.
    • (1945) Basic Writings of Saint Thomas Aquinas , vol.2 , pp. 746-747
    • Pegis, A.C.1
  • 18
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We can contrast this position with the legal positivism of Austin and Bentham, for whom there were two kinds of obligations: moral obligations and legal obligations. For them, legal obligations were not a kind of moral obligation; legal obligations were simply liability to legal sanctions. This is a very Pickwickian sense of "obligation," because in no real sense is one obligated by threats of painful consequences. As Hart put it, one may be obliged to yield to such threats without being obligated to yield to them. See Hart, The Concept of Law.
    • The Concept of Law
    • Hart1
  • 19
    • 0004255702 scopus 로고
    • ed. H. L. A. Hart New York: Noonday Press
    • John Austin argues against a natural law position by using this sort of semantic analysis to analyze the meaning of "law." John Austin, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined, ed. H. L. A. Hart (New York: Noonday Press, 1954).
    • (1954) The Province of Jurisprudence Determined
    • Austin, J.1
  • 20
    • 84936068266 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • See, for example, Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986).
    • (1986) Law's Empire
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 22
    • 0004237063 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • In contemporary jurisprudence, this approach is most closely associated with Joseph Raz. See particularly Raz, Practical Reason and Norms (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1975).
    • (1975) Practical Reason and Norms
    • Raz1
  • 23
    • 3843095500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • These two roles are worth distinguishing for purposes of argument even if one accepts Heidi Hurd's thesis that the obligation of judge and of citizen correspond with one another. Heidi Hurd, Moral Combat (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999). There are expository advantages served if we separate the roles because in various instances the tugs of intuition are different for the two roles.
    • (1999) Moral Combat
    • Hurd, H.1
  • 24
    • 0004287799 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • See, for example, Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1909).
    • (1909) Leviathan
    • Hobbes, T.1
  • 25
    • 0004296633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Aquinas, Summa Theologiae; and John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980).
    • Summa Theologiae
    • Aquinas1
  • 29
    • 0038948337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the example used in the Hart/Fuller debate. Hart, "Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morality"; Lon Fuller, "Positivism and Fidelity to Law - A Reply to Professor Hart," Harvard law Review 71, no. 4 (February 1958): 630-72.
    • Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morality
    • Hart1
  • 30
    • 0000842517 scopus 로고
    • Positivism and Fidelity to Law - A Reply to Professor Hart
    • February
    • This is the example used in the Hart/Fuller debate. Hart, "Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morality"; Lon Fuller, "Positivism and Fidelity to Law - A Reply to Professor Hart," Harvard law Review 71, no. 4 (February 1958): 630-72.
    • (1958) Harvard Law Review , vol.71 , Issue.4 , pp. 630-672
    • Fuller, L.1
  • 31
    • 0346368833 scopus 로고
    • Precedent, Induction, and Ethical Generalization
    • Laurence Goldstein, ed., Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See Michael Moore, "Precedent, Induction, and Ethical Generalization," in Laurence Goldstein, ed., Precedent in Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988).
    • (1988) Precedent in Law
    • Moore, M.1
  • 33
    • 0346680446 scopus 로고
    • Natural Law, Positivism, and the Limits of Jurisprudence: A Modern Round
    • May
    • Ruth Gavison suggests this objection. Ruth Gavison, "Natural Law, Positivism, and the Limits of Jurisprudence: A Modern Round," Yale Law Journal 91, no. 6 (May 1982): 1266-67. See also Daniel Robinson, "Antigone's Defense: A Critical Study of Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays," Review of Metaphysics 45, no. 2 (December 1991): 382.
    • (1982) Yale Law Journal , vol.91 , Issue.6 , pp. 1266-1267
    • Gavison, R.1
  • 34
    • 8344232554 scopus 로고
    • Antigone's Defense: A Critical Study of Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays
    • December
    • Ruth Gavison suggests this objection. Ruth Gavison, "Natural Law, Positivism, and the Limits of Jurisprudence: A Modern Round," Yale Law Journal 91, no. 6 (May 1982): 1266-67. See also Daniel Robinson, "Antigone's Defense: A Critical Study of Natural Law Theory: Contemporary Essays," Review of Metaphysics 45, no. 2 (December 1991): 382.
    • (1991) Review of Metaphysics , vol.45 , Issue.2 , pp. 382
    • Robinson, D.1
  • 35
    • 8344221175 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Dilemmas of Judges Who Must Interpret 'Immoral Laws,'
    • Joel Feinberg and Jules Coleman, eds., Belmont, CA: Wordsworth/ Thomson Learning
    • Joel Feinberg, "The Dilemmas of Judges Who Must Interpret 'Immoral Laws,'" in Joel Feinberg and Jules Coleman, eds., Philosophy of Law, 6th ed. (Belmont, CA: Wordsworth/ Thomson Learning, 2000), 108-29.
    • (2000) Philosophy of Law, 6th Ed. , pp. 108-129
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 37
    • 8344244497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Book Review - The Morality of Law
    • April
    • H. L. A. Hart, "Book Review - The Morality of Law," Harvard Law Review 78, no. 6 (April 1965): 1281-96.
    • (1965) Harvard Law Review , vol.78 , Issue.6 , pp. 1281-1296
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 38
    • 0005615340 scopus 로고
    • New Haven, CT: Yale University Press
    • Grant Gilmore's nice paraphrase of Hart's point. Grant Gilmore, The Ages of American Law (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1974), 111.
    • (1974) The Ages of American Law , pp. 111
    • Gilmore, G.1
  • 39
    • 84900182679 scopus 로고
    • What the Law Schools Can Contribute to the Making of Lawyers
    • Winter
    • Lon Fuller, "What the Law Schools Can Contribute to the Making of Lawyers," Journal of Legal Education 1, no. 2 (Winter 1948): 204; Fuller, The Morality of Law, 152-86, 223-24; Fuller, "Fidelity to Law," 636, 643, 661; and Lon Fuller, "A Reply to Professors Cohen and Dworkin," Villanova Law Review 10, no. 4 (Summer 1965): 661-66.
    • (1948) Journal of Legal Education , vol.1 , Issue.2 , pp. 204
    • Fuller, L.1
  • 40
    • 85037270616 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lon Fuller, "What the Law Schools Can Contribute to the Making of Lawyers," Journal of Legal Education 1, no. 2 (Winter 1948): 204; Fuller, The Morality of Law, 152-86, 223-24; Fuller, "Fidelity to Law," 636, 643, 661; and Lon Fuller, "A Reply to Professors Cohen and Dworkin," Villanova Law Review 10, no. 4 (Summer 1965): 661-66.
    • The Morality of Law , vol.152 , Issue.86 , pp. 223-224
    • Fuller1
  • 41
    • 85037277057 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lon Fuller, "What the Law Schools Can Contribute to the Making of Lawyers," Journal of Legal Education 1, no. 2 (Winter 1948): 204; Fuller, The Morality of Law, 152-86, 223-24; Fuller, "Fidelity to Law," 636, 643, 661; and Lon Fuller, "A Reply to Professors Cohen and Dworkin," Villanova Law Review 10, no. 4 (Summer 1965): 661-66.
    • Fidelity to Law , pp. 636
    • Fuller1
  • 42
    • 8344234946 scopus 로고
    • A Reply to Professors Cohen and Dworkin
    • Summer
    • Lon Fuller, "What the Law Schools Can Contribute to the Making of Lawyers," Journal of Legal Education 1, no. 2 (Winter 1948): 204; Fuller, The Morality of Law, 152-86, 223-24; Fuller, "Fidelity to Law," 636, 643, 661; and Lon Fuller, "A Reply to Professors Cohen and Dworkin," Villanova Law Review 10, no. 4 (Summer 1965): 661-66.
    • (1965) Villanova Law Review , vol.10 , Issue.4 , pp. 661-666
    • Fuller, L.1
  • 52
    • 85037277057 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On Aquinas's side, see Fuller, "Fidelity to Law"; and Max Radin, "Statutory Interpretation," Harvard Law Review 43, no. 6 (April 1930): 863-90. On the other side, see, e.g., Frank Easterbrook, "Statute's Domains," University of Chicago Law Review 50, no. 2 (Spring 1983): 533-52.
    • Fidelity to Law
    • Fuller1
  • 53
    • 0039639438 scopus 로고
    • Statutory Interpretation
    • April
    • On Aquinas's side, see Fuller, "Fidelity to Law"; and Max Radin, "Statutory Interpretation," Harvard Law Review 43, no. 6 (April 1930): 863-90. On the other side, see, e.g., Frank Easterbrook, "Statute's Domains," University of Chicago Law Review 50, no. 2 (Spring 1983): 533-52.
    • (1930) Harvard Law Review , vol.43 , Issue.6 , pp. 863-890
    • Radin, M.1
  • 54
    • 84859076105 scopus 로고
    • Statute's Domains
    • Spring
    • On Aquinas's side, see Fuller, "Fidelity to Law"; and Max Radin, "Statutory Interpretation," Harvard Law Review 43, no. 6 (April 1930): 863-90. On the other side, see, e.g., Frank Easterbrook, "Statute's Domains," University of Chicago Law Review 50, no. 2 (Spring 1983): 533-52.
    • (1983) University of Chicago Law Review , vol.50 , Issue.2 , pp. 533-552
    • Easterbrook, F.1
  • 57
    • 85037283116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In re Erickson, 815 F.2d 1090 7th Cir.
    • Compare Easterbrook's preaching in "Statute's Domains" with his practice in In re Erickson, 815 F.2d 1090 (7th Cir. 1987).
    • (1987) Statute's Domains
    • Easterbrook1
  • 58
    • 0042560346 scopus 로고
    • quoted in Learned Hand, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr., quoted in Learned Hand, The Bill of Rights (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1958), 18.
    • (1958) The Bill of Rights , pp. 18
    • Holmes Jr., O.W.1
  • 59
    • 84925928737 scopus 로고
    • Authority and Consent
    • February
    • See, e.g., Joseph Raz, "Authority and Consent," Virginia Law Review 67, no. 1 (February 1981): 103-31.
    • (1981) Virginia Law Review , vol.67 , Issue.1 , pp. 103-131
    • Raz, J.1
  • 60
    • 0345569990 scopus 로고
    • The Semantics of Judging
    • January
    • For one of many critiques, see Michael Moore, "The Semantics of Judging," Southern California Law Review 54, no. 2 (January 1981): 256-70.
    • (1981) Southern California Law Review , vol.54 , Issue.2 , pp. 256-270
    • Moore, M.1
  • 61
    • 0040161705 scopus 로고
    • The Forum of Principle
    • May/June
    • Dworkin stresses this point in his "The Forum of Principle," New York University Law Review 56, nos. 2-3 (May/June 1981): 469-518, reprinted in A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985). See also Moore, "The Semantics of Judging."
    • (1981) New York University Law Review , vol.56 , Issue.2-3 , pp. 469-518
    • Dworkin1
  • 62
    • 0003981612 scopus 로고
    • reprinted in Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Dworkin stresses this point in his "The Forum of Principle," New York University Law Review 56, nos. 2-3 (May/June 1981): 469-518, reprinted in A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985). See also Moore, "The Semantics of Judging."
    • (1985) A Matter of Principle
  • 63
    • 0040416083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dworkin stresses this point in his "The Forum of Principle," New York University Law Review 56, nos. 2-3 (May/June 1981): 469-518, reprinted in A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985). See also Moore, "The Semantics of Judging."
    • The Semantics of Judging
    • Moore1
  • 64
    • 27144549758 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Radin, "Statutory Interpretation"; Moore, "The Semantics of Judging"; and Antonin Scalia, A Matter of Interpretation, ed. Amy Gutmann (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1997), 17.
    • Statutory Interpretation
    • Radin1
  • 65
    • 0040416083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Radin, "Statutory Interpretation"; Moore, "The Semantics of Judging"; and Antonin Scalia, A Matter of Interpretation, ed. Amy Gutmann (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1997), 17.
    • The Semantics of Judging
    • Moore1
  • 66
    • 0039884712 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Amy Gutmann Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • See Radin, "Statutory Interpretation"; Moore, "The Semantics of Judging"; and Antonin Scalia, A Matter of Interpretation, ed. Amy Gutmann (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1997), 17.
    • (1997) A Matter of Interpretation , pp. 17
    • Scalia, A.1
  • 67
    • 8344244497 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart made this point against both Fuller and Dworkin. Hart, "Book Review - The Morality of Law"; Hart, "Comment," in Ruth Gavison, ed., Issues in Contemporary Legal Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987).
    • Book Review - The Morality of Law
    • Hart1
  • 68
    • 8344269343 scopus 로고
    • Comment
    • Ruth Gavison, ed., Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • Hart made this point against both Fuller and Dworkin. Hart, "Book Review - The Morality of Law"; Hart, "Comment," in Ruth Gavison, ed., Issues in Contemporary Legal Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987).
    • (1987) Contemporary Legal Philosophy
    • Hart1
  • 69
    • 8344224474 scopus 로고
    • Review of Cover's Justice Accused
    • December 5
    • This is one of Dworkin's favorite examples. Compare Dworkin, "Review of Cover's Justice Accused," Times Literary Supplement, December 5, 1975, with J. L. Mackie, "The Third Theory of Law," Philosophy and Public Affairs 7, no. 1 (Autumn 1977): 3-16; and with Joel Feinberg, "The Dilemmas of Judges Who Must Interpret 'Immoral Laws.'"
    • (1975) Times Literary Supplement
    • Dworkin1
  • 70
    • 84925906459 scopus 로고
    • The Third Theory of Law
    • Autumn
    • This is one of Dworkin's favorite examples. Compare Dworkin, "Review of Cover's Justice Accused," Times Literary Supplement, December 5, 1975, with J. L. Mackie, "The Third Theory of Law," Philosophy and Public Affairs 7, no. 1 (Autumn 1977): 3-16; and with Joel Feinberg, "The Dilemmas of Judges Who Must Interpret 'Immoral Laws.'"
    • (1977) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.7 , Issue.1 , pp. 3-16
    • Mackie, J.L.1
  • 71
    • 85037259338 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is one of Dworkin's favorite examples. Compare Dworkin, "Review of Cover's Justice Accused," Times Literary Supplement, December 5, 1975, with J. L. Mackie, "The Third Theory of Law," Philosophy and Public Affairs 7, no. 1 (Autumn 1977): 3-16; and with Joel Feinberg, "The Dilemmas of Judges Who Must Interpret 'Immoral Laws.'"
    • The Dilemmas of Judges Who Must Interpret 'Immoral Laws.'
    • Feinberg, J.1
  • 72
    • 85037263916 scopus 로고
    • Either-or or Neither-nor
    • Sidney Hook, ed., New York: New York University Press
    • This example is Kenneth Stem's, from his "Either-or or Neither-nor," in Sidney Hook, ed., Law and Philosophy (New York: New York University Press, 1963), 249-50.
    • (1963) Law and Philosophy , pp. 249-250
    • Stem, K.1
  • 73
    • 85037263668 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kirby v. United States, 74 U.S. (7 Wall.) 482 (1869)
    • Kirby v. United States, 74 U.S. (7 Wall.) 482 (1869).
  • 74
    • 0039233113 scopus 로고
    • A Natural Law Theory of Interpretation
    • January
    • I defend this view of statutory interpretation at length in Michael Moore, "A Natural Law Theory of Interpretation," Southern California Law Review 58, no. 2 (January 1985): 277-398.
    • (1985) Southern California Law Review , vol.58 , Issue.2 , pp. 277-398
    • Moore, M.1
  • 76
    • 0001417422 scopus 로고
    • The Path of the Law
    • March
    • Oliver Wendell Holmes, "The Path of the Law," Harvard Law Review 10, no. 8 (March 1897): 457-68.
    • (1897) Harvard Law Review , vol.10 , Issue.8 , pp. 457-468
    • Holmes, O.W.1
  • 78
    • 0003880778 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • This is Raz's term. Joseph Raz, The Authority of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979).
    • (1979) The Authority of Law
    • Raz, J.1
  • 81
    • 85008228042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart's Concluding Scientific Postscript
    • September
    • I defend the possibility of this kind of external jurisprudence against Dworkin and others in Michael Moore, "Hart's Concluding Scientific Postscript," Legal Theory 4, no. 3 (September 1998): 301-27; and in Moore, Educating Oneself in Public, chaps. 1, 3.
    • (1998) Legal Theory , vol.4 , Issue.3 , pp. 301-327
    • Moore, M.1
  • 82
    • 85008228042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chaps. 1, 3
    • I defend the possibility of this kind of external jurisprudence against Dworkin and others in Michael Moore, "Hart's Concluding Scientific Postscript," Legal Theory 4, no. 3 (September 1998): 301-27; and in Moore, Educating Oneself in Public, chaps. 1, 3.
    • Educating Oneself in Public
    • Moore1
  • 84
    • 0346049026 scopus 로고
    • American Jurisprudence through English Eyes: The Nightmare and the Noble Dream
    • September
    • H. L. A. Hart, "American Jurisprudence through English Eyes: The Nightmare and the Noble Dream," Georgia Law Review 11, no. 5 (September 1977): 969-89, reprinted in H. L. A. Hart, Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983).
    • (1977) Georgia Law Review , vol.11 , Issue.5 , pp. 969-989
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 85
    • 0003811485 scopus 로고
    • reprinted in Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • H. L. A. Hart, "American Jurisprudence through English Eyes: The Nightmare and the Noble Dream," Georgia Law Review 11, no. 5 (September 1977): 969-89, reprinted in H. L. A. Hart, Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983).
    • (1983) Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 86
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Hart's The Concept of Law, judges must regard the rule of recognition as obligatory for a legal system to exist.
    • The Concept of Law
    • Hart1
  • 87
    • 3843095500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is perhaps almost as intuitive that Kirby's legal rights and obligations were the same as those the judge was obligated to discover in his decision. Still, I leave for another day the question of whether the laws of cases necessarily obligate citizens as well as judges. (In this regard, however, see Hurd, Moral Combat.) If they do, this stronger first step of the traditional argument for natural law makes the second step easier, since in comparison to judicial obligations, which express just those values defining a discrete role, citizens' obligations are more easily seen as an expression of all the values there are.
    • Moral Combat
    • Hurd1
  • 88
    • 0042019758 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: M. Bender
    • In the Anglo-American legal system, we have for centuries tempered the desire for finality in legal judgments with a desire to reopen "final" judgments in order to correct serious substantive or procedural errors. At common law, this was accomplished procedurally by the ancient writs of coram nobis and audita querela, and in Equity, by bills in equity seeking injunctions against the enforcement of legal judgments. (See J. W. Moore, Moore's Federal Practice, 3rd ed. [New York: M. Bender, 1999], sees. 60 App. 105-8.) Even under current federal American law, the old view that courts have inherent power to reopen their own judgments survives; Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 60(b) enumerates five traditional grounds for reopening a judgment and then adds a safety-valve provision specifying that a judgment can also be reopened for "any other reason justifying relief from the operation of the judgment." Under this provision, "[t]he degree of unfairness may properly be considered in determining whether a court is justified in disturbing the finality of a judgment." Moore, Moore's Federal Practice, sec. 60 App. 37. As courts recognize, this "catch-all" or safety-valve provision is a "grand reservoir of equitable power to do justice in a particular case." Campion v. Alton Steamship Co., 608 F.2d 96, 106 (5th Cir. 1979). Currently, the above-referenced procedures for reopening a judgment are available only to the court that rendered the judgment. However, when the degree of injustice caused by an erroneous judgment is serious enough, a "collateral attack" on that judgment can be launched from a different court. See, e.g., Fay v. Noia, 372 U.S. 391 (1963), and Townsend v. Sain, 372 U.S. 293 (1963), where collateral review of state court factual findings was allowed by the U.S. Supreme Court in order to protect constitutional values. In a civil context, see Feinberg, "The Dilemmas of Judges Who Must Interpret 'Immoral Laws,'" for a discussion of the various techniques used by state court judges in the antebellum North to avoid giving "full faith and credit" to Southern court findings pertaining to escaped slaves.
    • (1999) Moore's Federal Practice, 3rd Ed.
    • Moore, J.W.1
  • 89
    • 0042019758 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the Anglo-American legal system, we have for centuries tempered the desire for finality in legal judgments with a desire to reopen "final" judgments in order to correct serious substantive or procedural errors. At common law, this was accomplished procedurally by the ancient writs of coram nobis and audita querela, and in Equity, by bills in equity seeking injunctions against the enforcement of legal judgments. (See J. W. Moore, Moore's Federal Practice, 3rd ed. [New York: M. Bender, 1999], sees. 60 App. 105-8.) Even under current federal American law, the old view that courts have inherent power to reopen their own judgments survives; Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 60(b) enumerates five traditional grounds for reopening a judgment and then adds a safety-valve provision specifying that a judgment can also be reopened for "any other reason justifying relief from the operation of the judgment." Under this provision, "[t]he degree of unfairness may properly be considered in determining whether a court is justified in disturbing the finality of a judgment." Moore, Moore's Federal Practice, sec. 60 App. 37. As courts recognize, this "catch-all" or safety-valve provision is a "grand reservoir of equitable power to do justice in a particular case." Campion v. Alton Steamship Co., 608 F.2d 96, 106 (5th Cir. 1979). Currently, the above-referenced procedures for reopening a judgment are available only to the court that rendered the judgment. However, when the degree of injustice caused by an erroneous judgment is serious enough, a "collateral attack" on that judgment can be launched from a different court. See, e.g., Fay v. Noia, 372 U.S. 391 (1963), and Townsend v. Sain, 372 U.S. 293 (1963), where collateral review of state court factual findings was allowed by the U.S. Supreme Court in order to protect constitutional values. In a civil context, see Feinberg, "The Dilemmas of Judges Who Must Interpret 'Immoral Laws,'" for a discussion of the various techniques used by state court judges in the antebellum North to avoid giving "full faith and credit" to Southern court findings pertaining to escaped slaves.
    • Moore's Federal Practice
    • Moore1
  • 90
    • 85037259338 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the Anglo-American legal system, we have for centuries tempered the desire for finality in legal judgments with a desire to reopen "final" judgments in order to correct serious substantive or procedural errors. At common law, this was accomplished procedurally by the ancient writs of coram nobis and audita querela, and in Equity, by bills in equity seeking injunctions against the enforcement of legal judgments. (See J. W. Moore, Moore's Federal Practice, 3rd ed. [New York: M. Bender, 1999], sees. 60 App. 105-8.) Even under current federal American law, the old view that courts have inherent power to reopen their own judgments survives; Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 60(b) enumerates five traditional grounds for reopening a judgment and then adds a safety-valve provision specifying that a judgment can also be reopened for "any other reason justifying relief from the operation of the judgment." Under this provision, "[t]he degree of unfairness may properly be considered in determining whether a court is justified in disturbing the finality of a judgment." Moore, Moore's Federal Practice, sec. 60 App. 37. As courts recognize, this "catch-all" or safety-valve provision is a "grand reservoir of equitable power to do justice in a particular case." Campion v. Alton Steamship Co., 608 F.2d 96, 106 (5th Cir. 1979). Currently, the above-referenced procedures for reopening a judgment are available only to the court that rendered the judgment. However, when the degree of injustice caused by an erroneous judgment is serious enough, a "collateral attack" on that judgment can be launched from a different court. See, e.g., Fay v. Noia, 372 U.S. 391 (1963), and Townsend v. Sain, 372 U.S. 293 (1963), where collateral review of state court factual findings was allowed by the U.S. Supreme Court in order to protect constitutional values. In a civil context, see Feinberg, "The Dilemmas of Judges Who Must Interpret 'Immoral Laws,'" for a discussion of the various techniques used by state court judges in the antebellum North to avoid giving "full faith and credit" to Southern court findings pertaining to escaped slaves.
    • The Dilemmas of Judges Who Must Interpret 'Immoral Laws,'
    • Feinberg1
  • 91
    • 85037289127 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Anglo-American law, as formally stated, is different from what I am arguing for in this essay. See, e.g., United States v. United Mine Workers, 330 U.S. 258, 294 (1947), in which it is stated that "[a]n injunction . . . must be obeyed . . . however erroneous the action of the court may be[.]" If our law really means this, it is bad law. I doubt, however, that our law does mean this. To give the proper incentives to most people, it is doubtlessly useful to utter such categorical, exceptionless pronouncements; in actuality, however, courts merely slap on the wrists actors like Martin Luther King when those actors violate judicial orders (subsequently determined to be erroneous for very good reasons.)
  • 92
    • 85037268962 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Union Pacific Ry. v. Cappier, 72 Pac. 281 (Kansas 1903)
    • Union Pacific Ry. v. Cappier, 72 Pac. 281 (Kansas 1903).
  • 93
    • 0039407935 scopus 로고
    • The Model of Rules
    • Autumn
    • Ronald Dworkin, "The Model of Rules," University of Chicago Law Review 35, no. 1 (Autumn 1967): 14-54.
    • (1967) University of Chicago Law Review , vol.35 , Issue.1 , pp. 14-54
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 94
    • 84896306930 scopus 로고
    • Hard Cases
    • April
    • Ronald Dworkin, "Hard Cases," Harvard Law Review 88, no. 6 (April 1975): 1057-109.
    • (1975) Harvard Law Review , vol.88 , Issue.6 , pp. 1057-1109
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 95
    • 0031376242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legal Principles Revisited
    • March
    • Michael Moore, "Legal Principles Revisited," Iowa Law Review 82, no. 3 (March 1997): 867-91, reprinted as chap. 7 of Moore, Educating Oneself in Public.
    • (1997) Iowa Law Review , vol.82 , Issue.3 , pp. 867-891
    • Moore, M.1
  • 96
    • 0031376242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • reprinted as chap. 7
    • Michael Moore, "Legal Principles Revisited," Iowa Law Review 82, no. 3 (March 1997): 867-91, reprinted as chap. 7 of Moore, Educating Oneself in Public.
    • Educating Oneself in Public
    • Moore1
  • 99
    • 33750732404 scopus 로고
    • The Pure Theory of Law
    • July
    • This is Hans Kelsen's view. See Hans Kelsen, "The Pure Theory of Law," Law Quarterly Review 51, no. 203 (July 1935): 528. "There is no such thing, of course, as a genuine gap, in the sense that a legal dispute could not be decided according to the valid norms, owing to the omission of a provision directed to the concrete case. . . . The law says not only that a person is obligated to a certain behavior . . . but also that a person is free to do or not to do what he is not obligated to do."
    • (1935) Law Quarterly Review , vol.51 , Issue.203 , pp. 528
    • Kelsen, H.1
  • 102
    • 84925895162 scopus 로고
    • Encino, CA: Dickenson Publishing
    • A good example of such deep positivism can be found in Rolph Sartorius, Individual Conduct and Social Norms (Encino, CA: Dickenson Publishing, 1975).
    • (1975) Individual Conduct and Social Norms
    • Sartorius, R.1
  • 106
    • 85037283834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid. See also Moore, "Legal Principles Revisited," discussing Dworkin's commitment to seeing equality (rather than integrity) as the function of the common law.
    • Precedent
    • Moore1
  • 107
    • 8344277963 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid. See also Moore, "Legal Principles Revisited," discussing Dworkin's commitment to seeing equality (rather than integrity) as the function of the common law.
    • Legal Principles Revisited
    • Moore1
  • 108
    • 85037285834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Natural Law Theory of St. Thomas Aquinas
    • Feinberg and Coleman, eds.
    • Susan Dimock, "The Natural Law Theory of St. Thomas Aquinas," in Feinberg and Coleman, eds., Philosophy of Law, 31.
    • Philosophy of Law , pp. 31
    • Dimock, S.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.