메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 36, Issue 1, 2008, Pages 9-36

The insufficiency of non-domination

Author keywords

Agency; Democracy; Imperialism; Pettit; Republicanism; Slavery

Indexed keywords


EID: 38049042744     PISSN: 00905917     EISSN: 15527476     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/0090591707310084     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (119)

References (71)
  • 2
    • 38049083417 scopus 로고
    • Mnich: Piper (Book XV), 1973, 1953
    • Denktagebuch, 1950 - 1973, ed. Ursula Ludz and Ingeborg Nordmann, vol. 1 (Mnich: Piper, 2002). 367 (Book XV, May 1953, No. 33), my translation.
    • (1950) Ursula Ludz and Ingeborg Nordmann , pp. 367
    • Denktagebuch1
  • 3
    • 0004215813 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Republicanism: A theory of freedom and government
    • Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press
    • Philip Pettit, Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 1999). A Theory of Freedom: The Psychology and Politics of Agency (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2001). Hereafter R and TF.
    • (1999) A Theory of Freedom: The Psychology and Politics of Agency
    • Pettit, P.1
  • 4
    • 69049110088 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Domination Complaint
    • Reply to Bader and Vatter, Political Exclusion and Domination, 185, New York: New York University Press
    • Philip Pettit, " The Domination Complaint, " 92, and " Reply to Bader and Vatter, " 185, both in Melissa S. Williams and Stephen Macedo, Political Exclusion and Domination, Nomos 46 ( New York: New York University Press, 2005 ).
    • (2005) Nomos , vol.46 , pp. 92
    • Pettit, P.1    Williams, M.S.2    MacEdo, S.3
  • 5
    • 1442333829 scopus 로고
    • Empire: The Rise and Demise of the British World Order and the Lessons for Global Power
    • New York : Basic Books, New Haven: Yale University Press
    • See, for example, Niall Ferguson, Empire: The Rise and Demise of the British World Order and the Lessons for Global Power (New York: Basic Books, 2004). 315 - 16 ; on the Philippine war, see Stuart Creighton Miller, "Benevolent Assimilation": The American Conquest of the Philippines, 1899-1903 ( New Haven: Yale University Press, 1982 ).
    • (1982) "benevolent Assimilation": The American Conquest of the Philippines, 1899-1903 , pp. 315-16
    • Ferguson, N.1    Creighton Miller, S.2
  • 6
    • 38049091287 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Empire's New Clothes: Paradigms Lost, and Regained
    • Chicago: Prickly Paradigm Press, New York: Henry Holt, 2004
    • See, for example, Harry Harootunian, The Empire's New Clothes: Paradigms Lost, and Regained (Chicago: Prickly Paradigm Press, 2004). and Chalmers Johnson, The Sorrows of Empire: Militarism, Secrecy, and the End of the Republic ( New York: Henry Holt, 2004 ).
    • (2004) The Sorrows of Empire: Militarism, Secrecy, and the End of the Republic
    • Harootunian, H.1    Johnson, C.2
  • 8
    • 38049049919 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See Pettit's brief comments about the "colonial" state at R 291.
  • 9
    • 38049021207 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Speeches on the impeachment of Warren Hastings
    • Edmund Burke, " Speeches on the Impeachment of Warren Hastings, " in The Portable Edmund Burke, ed. Isaac Kramnick (New York: Penguin, 1999). 394ff ;
    • (1999) The Portable Edmund Burke
    • Burke, E.1
  • 12
    • 0003497566 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press
    • For the emergence of this ideology see Eric Stokes, The English Utilitarians and India (Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press, 1959). esp. chap. 1.
    • (1959) The English Utilitarians and India
    • Stokes, E.1
  • 13
    • 34248032418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Republicanism and Democratic Injustice
    • For an analogous argument, focusing on a different insufficiency, see Henry S. Richardson, " Republicanism and Democratic Injustice, " Politics, Philosophy, and Economics 5, no. 2 (2006). 172 - 200.
    • (2006) Politics, Philosophy, and Economics , vol.5 , Issue.2 , pp. 172-200
    • Henry, S.1    Richardson2
  • 14
    • 38049085442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political Exclusion and Domination
    • New York: New York University Press What concerns Vatter is a form of "domination" that consists in the fact of subjection to law
    • This way of putting it reflects both my debt to, and disagreement with, Miguel Vatter's recent argument that Pettit's framework fails to attend to the phenomenon of "nonarbitrary" domination ("Pettit and Modern Republican Thought," in Melissa S. Williams and Stephen Macedo, Political Exclusion and Domination, Nomos 46 [ New York: New York University Press, 2005 ], 129). What concerns Vatter is a form of "domination" that consists in the fact of subjection to law, which the law cannot produce on its own and which must therefore be produced through a prior act of sovereign decision (126-29). Yet this characterization of the problem reproduces the idea that domination consists in a kind of arbitrariness-in this case, an arbitrary decision that stands behind the law as its condition of possibility. (Vatter's insistence that this kind of domination is "nonarbitrary" depends on the claim that for Pettit "arbitrary power only refers to the sway that private arbitrary decisions can have over the lives of others" [128], but in fact, Pettit explicitly indicates that both public and private power can be arbitrary and therefore dominating [R 130, 150]). The problem, I contend, lies in the term "domination" itself: Pettit is right to see a tight connection between domination and arbitrariness, but wrong to think that domination can capture the full range of forms of injustice; identifying the limits of Pettit's approach therefore requires a more radical departure from the concept of domination than Vatter performs.
    • (2005) Nomos , vol.46 , pp. 129
    • Williams, M.S.1    MacEdo, S.2
  • 15
    • 0004260025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Quentin Skinner, Liberty before Liberalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998). 38 - 40.
    • (1998) Liberty before Liberalism , pp. 38-40
    • Skinner, Q.1
  • 16
    • 10644290741 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Skinner, Pettit, and Livy: The Conflict of the Orders and the Ambiguity of Republican Liberty
    • On paternalism in Roman and neo-Roman republicanism, see Daniel Kapust's excellent " Skinner, Pettit, and Livy: The Conflict of the Orders and the Ambiguity of Republican Liberty, " History of Political Thought 25, no. 3 (Autumn 2004). 377 - 401.
    • (2004) History of Political Thought , vol.25 , Issue.3 , pp. 377-401
  • 17
    • 38049056885 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The difference between these two kinds of paternalism is important. Pettit claims that republicanism outlaws something like paternalism in the first sense-a state that "fails to take account of people's perceptions of their interests" (R 291). But paternalism in the second sense flies below the radar both of Pettit's republicanism and of conventional liberal treatments of paternalism, which tend to focus either on cases of interference with individual choices or on the substitution of one person's judgment for another's.
  • 18
    • 0003984012 scopus 로고
    • Garden City, NY: Anchor Books
    • The terms are taken from Tocqueville's account of "democratic despotism" in Democracy in America, ed. J. P. Mayer, trans. George Lawrence (Garden City, NY: Anchor Books, 1969). 692.
    • (1969) Democracy in America , pp. 692
    • Mayer, J.P.1
  • 19
    • 0003664196 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • For example, from Roman jurists' catalogues of corporeal objects subject to ownership: "land, a slave, clothing, gold, silver, and countless others." Gaius Inst. 2. 13 (Gaius, Elements of Roman Law, trans. Edward Poste [ Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1890 ], 147). On the trouble with reducing slavery to the ownership of persons, see Orlando Patterson, Slavery and Social Death: A Comparative Study ( Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982 ).
    • (1982) Slavery and Social Death: A Comparative Study
    • Patterson, O.1
  • 20
    • 38049021728 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Liberty conceived as the opposite of slavery
    • Bonnie Honig and David R. Mapel, eds., (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press)
    • On the fantasy of "the slave as a perfectly responsive instrument" see Richard Friedman, " Liberty Conceived as the Opposite of Slavery, " in Bonnie Honig and David R. Mapel, eds., Skepticism, Individuality, and Freedom: The Reluctant Liberalism of Richard Flathman (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2002). 175.
    • (2002) Skepticism, Individuality, and Freedom: The Reluctant Liberalism of Richard Flathman , pp. 175
    • Friedman, R.1
  • 21
    • 38049030337 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This point suggests something important about the ways in which political language carries historical legacies. The risk involved in using a political language that originated in a hierarchical context-as the language of republicanism did-is not that it will tend to reproduce anti-egalitarianism wherever it goes, as though terms and concepts were agents of transhistorical contamination; for political languages can and have been turned against the very hierarchies, such as slavery, that their originators supported or countenanced. What remains most problematic in such languages is not that they were once used to support hierarchy; it is that they were useful in this respect because they tendentiously misrepresented the nature and operation of the hierarchical institutions they supported; correspondingly, the danger in trying to use such language to other ends is not that, in doing so, we will somehow be drawn back toward an endorsement of subordination, but that we will misunderstand the very phenomena we wish to criticize.
  • 23
    • 77952433625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also the OED's third sense: "derived from mere opinion or preference, not based in the nature of things; hence, capricious, uncertain, varying." Oxford English Dictionary, 2 nd ed., Ibid.
    • Oxford English Dictionary, 2 Nd Ed.
  • 25
    • 38049080748 scopus 로고
    • On the law of slavery in Greece and Rome see T.E.J. Wiedemann, Slavery, Greece & Rome: New Surveys in the Classics no. 19 (Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press, 1987). 22 - 29.
    • (1987) Slavery , pp. 22-29
    • Wiedemann, T.E.J.1
  • 26
    • 0003803842 scopus 로고
    • New York: Pantheon Books Greece & Rome: New Surveys in the Classics no. 19 (Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press) Ithaca: Cornell University Press. chap. 8
    • On legal codes in British and Latin America see David Brion Davis, The Problem of Slavery in Western Culture (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1966). chap. 8.
    • (1966) The Problem of Slavery in Western Culture
    • Brion Davis, D.1
  • 27
    • 33947304453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The determinacy of republican policy: A reply to McMahon
    • It is not always clear what kind of weight the term "avowable" bears. Often Pettit uses the term to mean "conscious or [able to be] brought to consciousness without great effort" (TF 156), or, as he has more recently said, "avowal-ready" (" The Determinacy of Republican Policy: A Reply to McMahon, " Philosophy and Public Affairs 34, no. 3 [ 2006 ]: 278 - 79).
    • (2006) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.34 , Issue.3 , pp. 278-279
  • 28
    • 0038117682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Republican freedom and contestatory democratization
    • In this sense "avowable" specifies that an agent's interests are defined by what she herself is disposed to say about them. Sometimes, however, Pettit uses "avowable" to specify something like legitimate interests, those that "are consistent with the desire to live under a shared scheme that treats no one as special" (" Republican Freedom and Contestatory Democratization, " in Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-Cordón, eds., Democracy's Value [ Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999 ], 176).
    • (1999) Democracy's Value , pp. 176
  • 29
    • 38049051947 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The capacity to have done otherwise
    • Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-Cordn, eds. [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press] Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • and he has used the verb "to avow" to mean "to commit oneself to" (" The Capacity to Have Done Otherwise, " in Rules, Reasons, and Norms [ Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002 ], 267 - 71).
    • (2002) Rules, Reasons, and Norms , pp. 267-271
  • 30
    • 38049060044 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nondomination and normativity
    • On the stronger sense of "avow," see also Christopher McMahon, " Nondomination and Normativity, " Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 88 (2007). 322.
    • (2007) Pacific Philosophical Quarterly , vol.88 , pp. 322
    • McMahon, C.1
  • 31
    • 33845389980 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The indeterminacy of republican policy
    • On this basis Christopher McMahon has argued that Pettit's idea of arbitrariness is "moralized," a claim that Pettit has resisted. (McMahon, " The Indeterminacy of Republican Policy, " Philosophy and Public Affairs 33, no. 1 [ 2005 ]: 67 - 93 ;
    • (2005) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.33 , Issue.1 , pp. 67-93
    • McMahon1
  • 33
    • 38049031339 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • McMahon, " Nondomination and Normativity.") If to call a conception of arbitrariness "moralized" means that something is arbitrary if it is judged to be immoral through the application of independent standards of evaluation, then Pettit seems to me right that his use of "arbitrary" isn't moralized. But Pettit's second sense of "arbitrary" does seem moralized in a narrower way, insofar as the interests that must be tracked if interference is to be non-arbitrary are not any old interests, but have been passed through the legitimating filters of "commonness" and "avowability." Where McMahon seems to me to go wrong is in assuming that this work of filtering out illegitimate interest-claims is equivalent to having an all-things-considered moral debate about the instance of interference in question.
    • Nondomination and Normativity
    • McMahon1
  • 34
    • 0346275693 scopus 로고
    • Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See Frankfurt, " Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person, " in The Importance of What We Care About ( Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988 ).
    • (1988) The Importance of What We Care about
    • Frankfurt1
  • 35
    • 77952433625 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • s. v. "wanton," sense b.1. Pettit cites Frankfurt's use of "wanton" at TF 52
    • Oxford English Dictionary, s. v. "wanton," sense b.1. Pettit cites Frankfurt's use of "wanton" at TF 52.
    • Oxford English Dictionary
  • 36
    • 0036280967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Keeping Republican Freedom Simple: On a Difference with Quentin Skinner
    • for other discussions
    • For Pettit's characterization of the theory of freedom as non-domination as, in Berlin's terms, "certainly negative," see " Keeping Republican Freedom Simple: On a Difference with Quentin Skinner, " Political Theory 30, no. 3 (June 2002). 340 ; for other discussions, see R 17-31, 51; TF chap. 6.
    • (2002) Political Theory , vol.30 , Issue.3 , pp. 340
  • 37
    • 38049095837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The foregoing account is simplified: in Pettit's account, the recursive and bystander problems both arise in principle for all three of the candidate theories of freedom he considers (as does a third problem, the "modal" problem, which I don't discuss here). Still, the recursive problem is in the foreground of Pettit's critique of the theory of freedom as rational control, just as the bystander problem is in the foreground of his critique of the theory of freedom as volitional control.
  • 38
    • 8744236518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chicago: University of Chicago Press
    • Notably, Pettit's use of "person" in this context runs counter to the way he uses the term in the rest of the book. Elsewhere, "person" names the third of the three sorts of thing to which "freedom" may be ascribed: theories of freedom as rational control focus on free action; theories of freedom as volitional control focus on the free self-that is, on an agent's "relationship to their own psychology"-and theories of discursive control focus on free personhood, understood as a matter of an agent's "social status" (TF 4). There, "person" is a thicker concept than "self," so it comes as a surprise when Pettit presents the criterion of personal identity as more minimal and less discriminating than the criterion of self-identity. Yet far from being a sign of muddled thinking, Pettit's shifting use of the term "person" is significant because it continues a long history of equivocation about the meaning of personhood, and of uncertainty about how to relate personhood conceived as a brute, bodily fact to personhood conceived as an intersubjectively achieved status, traces of which can be seen in, for example, the doctrine of the king's two bodies, natural and politic, or in the doubled position of slaves in Roman law, suspended between the law of things and the law of persons. (On the parallel between these doublings see Stephen M. Best, The Fugitive's Properties: Law and the Poetics of Possession [ Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2004 ]). I shall return to this theme later.
    • (2004) The Fugitive's Properties: Law and the Poetics of Possession
    • Stephen, M.1    Best2
  • 39
    • 38049090308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I owe this insight into the import of Pettit's reduction of the bystander problem to the problem of the elusive self to Loren Goldman.
  • 41
    • 0041577670 scopus 로고
    • although the classical sources never actually define dominium in these terms, nor offer any general definition of ownership (Barry Nicholas, An Introduction to Roman Law [ Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press, 1977 ], 154;
    • (1977) An Introduction to Roman Law , pp. 154
    • Nicholas, B.1
  • 42
    • 38049050826 scopus 로고
    • The uses and abuses of Roman law texts
    • Shael Herman, " The Uses and Abuses of Roman Law Texts, " American Journal of Comparative Law 29, no. 4 [Autumn 1981 ]: 671 - 90).
    • (1981) American Journal of Comparative Law , vol.29 , Issue.4 , pp. 671-690
    • Herman, S.1
  • 44
    • 38049094397 scopus 로고
    • London: Longmans, Green, and Co. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press Autumn (Kln: Bhlau-Verlag). 306 ff Budapest: Akamiai Kiad
    • György Diósdi, Ownership in Ancient and Preclassical Roman Law (Budapest: Akaémiai Kiadó, 1970). 135 - 6 ;
    • (1970) Ownership in Ancient and Preclassical Roman Law , pp. 135-136
    • Diósdi, G.1
  • 53
    • 38049089511 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Of course, dominium establishes horizontal relationships between owners and non-owners too, but since dominium is by definition exclusive and indivisible, the very term seems to render nonsensical all questions about whether ownership in a particular object is "unduly concentrated." With dominium, the horizontal axis can only become controversial if there is uncertainty about which person is really the exclusive owner of a thing.
  • 54
    • 38049071201 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • If "domination" is the characteristic form of injustice threatened by dominium, it might be tempting to call this second sort of injustice "imperialism," to echo imperium. But this would be misleading, because, unlike "domination," in ordinary language "imperialism" has a concrete referent. Calling this dimension of injustice "imperialism" would thus falsely imply both that imperialism (in its ordinary sense) is the only or primary example of this sort of injustice, and that imperialism (in its ordinary sense) can only be unjust in this way and not also as a source of domination.
  • 55
    • 0343611803 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rev. Canon Roberts [ New York: Dutton, n.d.], translation modified [substituting the literal "usurped possession" for "won back," and "honor" for "dignity"]).
    • Livy 6.34.4 ( Livy, History of Rome, ed. Rev. Canon Roberts [ New York: Dutton, n.d.], translation modified [substituting the literal "usurped possession" for "won back," and "honor" for "dignity"]).
    • History of Rome
    • Livy1
  • 56
    • 38049090821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Livy 34.32.2
    • Livy 34.32.2.
  • 57
    • 38049070459 scopus 로고
    • Cic. Leg. agr. 2.17-18 (The Orations of Marcus Tullius Cicero, trans. C. D. Yonge, vol. 2 [ London: George Bell, 1909 ], 220)
    • (1909) The Orations of Marcus Tullius Cicero , vol.2
  • 59
    • 0004020987 scopus 로고
    • Here it is important to resist the modern association of "usurpation" with the theft of another's property. In classical Latin, usurpare was not invariably negative, but often meant simply "to take into use" or "make use of" something; and usurpatio commonly referred to a "taking into use" or "making use" of a thing, or the use of a word or expression. (Charlton T. Lewis and Charles Short, A Latin Dictionary [ Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press, 1879 ]).
    • (1879) A Latin Dictionary
    • Lewis, C.T.1    Short, C.2
  • 60
    • 0346811597 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Usurpatio could also mean an inappropriate "seizing" or "using"-but even in such contexts, its character as a usurpation was not necessarily rooted in a strong counter-claim of ownership in the sense of dominium. See the discussions of usucapio and usurpatio in Justinian Digesta 41.3 (The Digest of Justinian, English translation ed. Alan Watson [ Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1998 ]).
    • (1998) The Digest of Justinian
  • 61
    • 38049084096 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press English translation ed. Alan Watson [ Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press]) 122 ff
    • and Nicholas, Introduction to Roman Law, 122 ff. I hope to trace some of the subsequent history of "usurpation" as a political term in future work.
    • Introduction to Roman Law
    • Nicholas1
  • 63
    • 0003798006 scopus 로고
    • James Scott's distinction between "public" and "hidden" transcripts represents one effort to negotiate this dilemma (Domination and the Arts of Resistance: Hidden Transcripts [ New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1990 ]).
    • (1990) Domination and the Arts of Resistance: Hidden Transcripts
  • 66
    • 33444477281 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deviance as Resistance: A New Research Agenda for the Study of Black Politics
    • For an analogous point about the contingent relationship between deviant practices and political resistance in contemporary politics, see Cathy J. Cohen, " Deviance as Resistance: A New Research Agenda for the Study of Black Politics, " Du Bois Review 1, no. 1 (2004). esp. 37-41.
    • (2004) Du Bois Review , vol.1 , Issue.1
    • Cathy, J.1    Cohen2
  • 67
    • 33746084965 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Republican Freedom and Contestatory Democratization
    • Democracy's Value, Depoliticizing Democracy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • For Pettit's view of democracy see especially R 8 and chap. 6; TF chap. 7; " Republican Freedom and Contestatory Democratization, " in Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-Cordn, eds., Democracy's Value (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999). " Depoliticizing Democracy, " Ratio Juris 17, no. 1 (March 2004). 52 - 65.
    • (1999) Ratio Juris , vol.17 , Issue.1 , pp. 52-65
  • 68
    • 0141707726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Depoliticizing Democracy
    • Machiavelli Against Republicanism: On the Cambridge School's 'Guicciardinian Moments,', 633-636
    • See also his rejection of democracy understood as collective autonomy in " Depoliticizing Democracy, " 58 - 60. For another democratic critique of Pettit's turn to Rome, see John P. McCormick, " Machiavelli Against Republicanism: On the Cambridge School's 'Guicciardinian Moments,' " Political Theory 31, no. 5 (October 2003). 633 - 636.
    • (2003) Political Theory , vol.31 , Issue.5 , pp. 58-60
    • John, P.1    McCormick2
  • 70
    • 38049013967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See e.g. Arist. Pol. 1.5 (1254b16-26)
    • See e.g. Arist. Pol. 1.5 (1254b16-26).


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.