메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 27, Issue 4, 2007, Pages 609-632

What is a crime?

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 36849044556     PISSN: 01436503     EISSN: 14643820     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1093/ojls/gqm018     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (51)

References (74)
  • 1
    • 0011270544 scopus 로고
    • The Definition of Crime
    • E.g, at
    • E.g. G. Williams, 'The Definition of Crime' (1955) Current Legal Problems 107, at 130,
    • (1955) Current Legal Problems , vol.107 , pp. 130
    • Williams, G.1
  • 3
    • 36849094683 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See G. Williams, above n 1 and D. Ormerod, Smith and Hogan Criminal Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 11th edn, 2005), Ch. 2, especially 9-10, 16-17. On the procedural aspects of criminal law,
    • See G. Williams, above n 1 and D. Ormerod, Smith and Hogan Criminal Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 11th edn, 2005), Ch. 2, especially 9-10, 16-17. On the procedural aspects of criminal law,
  • 4
    • 36849076468 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also A. Ashworth, 'Is the Criminal Law a Lost Cause?' (2000) 116 LQR 225, at 230-2.
    • see also A. Ashworth, 'Is the Criminal Law a Lost Cause?' (2000) 116 LQR 225, at 230-2.
  • 5
    • 23944437280 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a recent overview, see, Oxford: Oxford University Press, Ch. 2
    • For a recent overview, see L. Zedner, Criminal Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004) Ch. 2
    • (2004) Criminal Justice
    • Zedner, L.1
  • 6
    • 36849070105 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and for doctrinal accounts particularly sensitive to these issues, see A. Ashworth, Principles of Criminal Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 5th edn, 2005), 1-6 and Simester and Sullivan, above n 1 at 1-5.
    • and for doctrinal accounts particularly sensitive to these issues, see A. Ashworth, Principles of Criminal Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 5th edn, 2005), 1-6 and Simester and Sullivan, above n 1 at 1-5.
  • 7
    • 36849036584 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, Berkeley: University of California Press, Ch. 5
    • See, e.g. A. Brudner, The Unity of the Common Law (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995), Ch. 5.
    • (1995) The Unity of the Common Law
    • Brudner, A.1
  • 8
    • 36849051631 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The English crime of unlawful and dangerous act manslaughter, for instance, requires the defendant to have killed another while doing something that was both criminal and dangerous (in the sense that it created the risk of some harm), but the death of the victim need not have been foreseen by the defendant nor foreseeable by a reasonable person: Newbury [1977] AG 500 (HL).
    • The English crime of unlawful and dangerous act manslaughter, for instance, requires the defendant to have killed another while doing something that was both criminal and dangerous (in the sense that it created the risk of some harm), but the death of the victim need not have been foreseen by the defendant nor foreseeable by a reasonable person: Newbury [1977] AG 500 (HL).
  • 9
    • 36849013768 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The arguments in this article neither justify nor rule out the legitimacy of constructive liability in cases of fault-based crime
    • The arguments in this article neither justify nor rule out the legitimacy of constructive liability in cases of fault-based crime.
  • 10
    • 36849035632 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See e.g, 2 AC 428 HL
    • See e.g. B v DPP [2000] 2 AC 428 (HL).
    • (2000) B v DPP
  • 11
    • 36848998566 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There are a handful of exceptions: See D. Ormerod, above n 2, at 140-1.
    • There are a handful of exceptions: See D. Ormerod, above n 2, at 140-1.
  • 12
    • 36849083770 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Most markedly in English law with the offence of manslaughter by gross negligence, which requires the jury to ask whether the negligence resulting in death was 'so bad in all the circumstances as to amount to a criminal act': Adomako [1995] 1 AC 171, at 187 (HL).
    • Most markedly in English law with the offence of manslaughter by gross negligence, which requires the jury to ask whether the negligence resulting in death was 'so bad in all the circumstances as to amount to a criminal act': Adomako [1995] 1 AC 171, at 187 (HL).
  • 13
    • 0004251932 scopus 로고
    • On the idea of 'family resemblance' see, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 3rd edn, at
    • On the idea of 'family resemblance' see L. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 3rd edn, 1967), at 65-66
    • (1967) Philosophical Investigations , pp. 65-66
    • Wittgenstein, L.1
  • 14
    • 0001997715 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 2nd edn, at
    • and R.J. Fogelin, Wittgenstein, (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 2nd edn, 1987), at 133-8.
    • (1987) Wittgenstein , pp. 133-138
    • Fogelin, R.J.1
  • 16
    • 84925885652 scopus 로고
    • Criminal Attempts and the Theory of the Law of Crimes
    • at
    • L. Becker, 'Criminal Attempts and the Theory of the Law of Crimes' (1974) 3 Philosophy & Public Affairs 262, at 273.
    • (1974) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.3
    • Becker, L.1
  • 19
    • 36849094681 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, as a psychological phenomenon this is not always true: What characterizes phobias is the irrational basis (or degree) of the aversion. But I take it that there are good reasons for being fearful of (some) crimes
    • Of course, as a psychological phenomenon this is not always true: What characterizes phobias is the irrational basis (or degree) of the aversion. But I take it that there are good reasons for being fearful of (some) crimes.
  • 21
    • 36849018733 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In his later work, Duff's position seems somewhat different: (a) that the wrong is shared by the community because it is a wrong against the victim as a member of the community (Punishment, Communication, and Community (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001) at 60-4
    • In his later work, Duff's position seems somewhat different: (a) that the wrong is shared by the community because it is a wrong against the victim as a member of the community (Punishment, Communication, and Community (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001) at 60-4
  • 22
    • 36849076951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and (b) that the proposal is not meant to provide a criterion for which wrongs are public ones, but is simply saying that those wrongs that are apt for public condenmation are public wrongs: S 6, 'Theories of Criminal Law', The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2002 Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/ win2002/entries/criminal-law/.
    • and (b) that the proposal is not meant to provide a criterion for which wrongs are public ones, but is simply saying that those wrongs that are apt for public condenmation are public wrongs: S 6, 'Theories of Criminal Law', The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2002 Edition), E.N. Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/ win2002/entries/criminal-law/.
  • 23
    • 36849021273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Marshall and Duff, above n 16, at 19.
    • Marshall and Duff, above n 16, at 19.
  • 25
    • 36849093676 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nor are the values constitutive in the sense that they are regarded as important because they make the community the type of community that it is. See for some arguments along these lines P. Nicholson, 'Hegel on Crime' (1982) 3 History of Political Thought 103
    • Nor are the values constitutive in the sense that they are regarded as important because they make the community the type of community that it is. See for some arguments along these lines P. Nicholson, 'Hegel on Crime' (1982) 3 History of Political Thought 103
  • 26
    • 18644375073 scopus 로고
    • Mens rea
    • E.F. Paul et al, eds, Oxford: Basil Blackwell
    • and J. Hampton, 'Mens rea' in E.F. Paul et al. (eds), Crime, Culpability, and Remedy (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1990).
    • (1990) Crime, Culpability, and Remedy
    • Hampton, J.1
  • 27
    • 36849077406 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although there are Hegelian roots to this view, Hegel's own account of crime is different: See G.W.F. Hegel, Elements of the Philosophy of Right [A.W. Wood ed, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991, ss 90-104, 218-229
    • Although there are Hegelian roots to this view, Hegel's own account of crime is different: See G.W.F. Hegel, Elements of the Philosophy of Right [A.W. Wood (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991], ss 90-104, 218-229,
  • 28
    • 36849047548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and for a modern interpretation of the common law in Hegelian terms: Brudner, above n 4, Ch. 5.
    • and for a modern interpretation of the common law in Hegelian terms: Brudner, above n 4, Ch. 5.
  • 29
    • 36849027397 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note T. Honoré 'Real Laws' in his Making Law Bind (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987), at 76-7: Typical criminal statutes do not prohibit murder, theft, etc., but simply lay down the punishment for their commission, and sometimes provide an authoritative definition of their elements. The underlying assumption seems to be that it is unnecessary to state that these actions are wrong.
    • Note T. Honoré 'Real Laws' in his Making Law Bind (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987), at 76-7: Typical criminal statutes do not prohibit murder, theft, etc., but simply lay down the punishment for their commission, and sometimes provide an authoritative definition of their elements. The underlying assumption seems to be that it is unnecessary to state that these actions are wrong.
  • 30
    • 36849079569 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, the victim (where there is one) also has a special interest in the defendant being held to account for their wrongdoing, and will have a grievance if (for inappropriate reasons) this fails to occur. See, for example, the Code for Crown Prosecutors England and Wales, s 6
    • Of course, the victim (where there is one) also has a special interest in the defendant being held to account for their wrongdoing, and will have a grievance if (for inappropriate reasons) this fails to occur. See, for example, the Code for Crown Prosecutors (England and Wales), s 6.
  • 31
    • 36849060806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the case of private prosecutions in England and Wales, the community exercises a supervisory jurisdiction through the power to take over and discontinue a prosecution that is not in the public interest: Prosecution of Offences Act 1985, s 62, Permitting private prosecutions may be justified as a fail-safe device against the fallibility of prosecuting bodies, so long as these prosecutions are subject to such a supervisory jurisdiction
    • In the case of private prosecutions in England and Wales, the community exercises a supervisory jurisdiction through the power to take over and discontinue a prosecution that is not in the public interest: Prosecution of Offences Act 1985, s 6(2). Permitting private prosecutions may be justified as a fail-safe device against the fallibility of prosecuting bodies, so long as these prosecutions are subject to such a supervisory jurisdiction.
  • 32
    • 0041161623 scopus 로고
    • On the connections between censure and punishment, see e.g, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Ch. 2
    • On the connections between censure and punishment, see e.g. R.A. Duff, Trials and Punishments (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), Ch. 2
    • (1986) Trials and Punishments
    • Duff, R.A.1
  • 33
    • 0004016848 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press, especially Ch. 2
    • and A. von Hirsch, Censure and Sanctions (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993), especially Ch. 2.
    • (1993) Censure and Sanctions
    • von Hirsch, A.1
  • 34
    • 36849032609 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One important type of excuse arises where the wrongdoer was unaware of the existence of the duty or the risk of its violation, and it is not the case that their ignorance was itself blameworthy.
    • One important type of excuse arises where the wrongdoer was unaware of the existence of the duty or the risk of its violation, and it is not the case that their ignorance was itself blameworthy.
  • 35
    • 8844253270 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See e.g. M. Bayles' proposal for a character view of culpability in 'Character, Purpose, and Criminal Responsibility' (1982) 1 Law and Philosophy 5.
    • See e.g. M. Bayles' proposal for a character view of culpability in 'Character, Purpose, and Criminal Responsibility' (1982) 1 Law and Philosophy 5.
  • 36
    • 1842461701 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Virtue, Vice and Criminal Liability
    • For a critique of tying culpability to vice see, 147
    • For a critique of tying culpability to vice see R. A. Duff, 'Virtue, Vice and Criminal Liability' (2002) 6 Buffalo Criminal Law Review 147.
    • (2002) Buffalo Criminal Law Review , vol.6
    • Duff, R.A.1
  • 37
    • 36849032610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See above nn 11-14
    • See above nn 11-14.
  • 38
    • 0003529325 scopus 로고
    • On specification, see, Oxford: Oxford University Press, at
    • On specification, see Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980), at 284-6.
    • (1980) Natural Law and Natural Rights , pp. 284-286
    • Finnis1
  • 39
    • 0042408084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Alexander has argued that the central forms of mens rea display a unitary vice, viz. insufficient concern for the interests of others, and that all involve imposing an unjustified risk of harm on others: 'Insufficient concern: A Unified Conception of Criminal Culpability' (2000) 88 California Law Review 931. The account in the text turns this central claim inside on-the disrespect necessary for punishment can be manifested in a variety of ways, and no form of mens rea necessarily displays it in every context.
    • Alexander has argued that the central forms of mens rea display a unitary vice, viz. insufficient concern for the interests of others, and that all involve imposing an unjustified risk of harm on others: 'Insufficient concern: A Unified Conception of Criminal Culpability' (2000) 88 California Law Review 931. The account in the text turns this central claim inside on-the disrespect necessary for punishment can be manifested in a variety of ways, and no form of mens rea necessarily displays it in every context.
  • 40
    • 36849094188 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Victor Tadros has also argued that criminal responsibility depends upon actions that manifest 'moral vices', i.e. actions that display an insufficient concern for the interests of others, Criminal Responsibility (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), Ch. 3.
    • Victor Tadros has also argued that criminal responsibility depends upon actions that manifest 'moral vices', i.e. actions that display an insufficient concern for the interests of others, Criminal Responsibility (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), Ch. 3.
  • 41
    • 36849043348 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Secton 1(1) Criminal Damage Act 1971 (Eng.).
    • Secton 1(1) Criminal Damage Act 1971 (Eng.).
  • 42
    • 36849039205 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See e.g. Alexander, above n 30, at 949-53 and M. Moore 'Choice, Character, and Excuse' in E.F. Paul et al. (eds) Crime, Culpability, and Remedy (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1990) cf. Moore's later views in Placing Blame (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997) Ch. 9 and 588-92.
    • See e.g. Alexander, above n 30, at 949-53 and M. Moore 'Choice, Character, and Excuse' in E.F. Paul et al. (eds) Crime, Culpability, and Remedy (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1990) cf. Moore's later views in Placing Blame (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997) Ch. 9 and 588-92.
  • 43
    • 36849011781 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is a second important objection to negligence based on the use of an objective standard of care that some people are incapable of meeting. But negligence can be made relative to the capacities of the wrongdoer, and it is this case that is the most relevant. See e.g. H.L.A. Hart's defence of negligence as culpable where the defendant fails to do what the reasonable person would have done despite having the mental and physical capacities at the time to do so-'Negligence, Mens Rea, and Criminal Responsibility' Punishment and Responsibility (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1968) -
    • There is a second important objection to negligence based on the use of an objective standard of care that some people are incapable of meeting. But negligence can be made relative to the capacities of the wrongdoer, and it is this case that is the most relevant. See e.g. H.L.A. Hart's defence of negligence as culpable where the defendant fails to do what the reasonable person would have done despite having the mental and physical capacities at the time to do so-'Negligence, Mens Rea, and Criminal Responsibility' Punishment and Responsibility (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1968) -
  • 44
    • 36849015594 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A.P. Simester's alternative in terms of whether the defendant failed to do what they could reasonably have done given their mental and physical capacities: 'Can Negligence be Culpable?' in J. Horder (ed.), Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence: Fourth Series (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).
    • A.P. Simester's alternative in terms of whether the defendant failed to do what they could reasonably have done given their mental and physical capacities: 'Can Negligence be Culpable?' in J. Horder (ed.), Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence: Fourth Series (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).
  • 45
    • 36849051630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, in particular, R.A. Duff's work on 'practical indifference' in recklessness, e.g. Intention, Agency and Criminal Liability (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1990), Ch. 7.
    • See, in particular, R.A. Duff's work on 'practical indifference' in recklessness, e.g. Intention, Agency and Criminal Liability (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1990), Ch. 7.
  • 46
    • 36849001568 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gross Negligence and Criminal Culpability
    • See also, at
    • See also J. Horder, 'Gross Negligence and Criminal Culpability' (1997) 47 University of Toronto Law Journal 495, at 500-9.
    • (1997) University of Toronto Law Journal , vol.47
    • Horder, J.1
  • 47
    • 36849022821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See e.g. clause 2 of the draft bill 'Involuntary Manslaughter' in Legislating the Criminal Code: Iuvoluntary Manslaughter (Law Commission Report 237, 1996).
    • See e.g. clause 2 of the draft bill 'Involuntary Manslaughter' in Legislating the Criminal Code: Iuvoluntary Manslaughter (Law Commission Report 237, 1996).
  • 48
    • 36849043347 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the context of homicide, see the interesting discussion of reckless indifference in A New Homicide Act for England and Wales, Law Commission Consultation Paper 177, 2005, §§3.149-3.170. On recklessness
    • In the context of homicide, see the interesting discussion of reckless indifference in A New Homicide Act for England and Wales? (Law Commission Consultation Paper 177, 2005), §§3.149-3.170. On recklessness,
  • 49
    • 36849047547 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Recklessness and the Duty to Take Care
    • see also, S. Shute and A.P. Simester eds, Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • see also V. Tadros 'Recklessness and the Duty to Take Care' in S. Shute and A.P. Simester (eds) Criminal Law Theory: Doctrines of the General Part (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002).
    • (2002) Criminal Law Theory: Doctrines of the General Part
    • Tadros, V.1
  • 50
    • 36849043862 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g
    • See, e.g. R v G [2003] UKHL 50, [41].
    • (2003) R v G , vol.UKHL 50 , pp. 41
  • 51
    • 36849078379 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In addition, it has a residual authority over those who commit wrongs against its members, even when this occurs outside its territory, if there is no more appropriate body willing to take such action, There is also a further question of the existence of 'universal jurisdiction' over certain crimes like piracy and genocide, even when it takes place outside the state's territory and none of its members are involved as either victims or wrongdoers. The better view is probably that the world community has jurisdiction over these wrongs, because they merit condemnation in the name of the world community, but that for practical reasons this jurisdiction is delegated to national states in order to ensure that these crimes are punished
    • In addition, it has a residual authority over those who commit wrongs against its members, even when this occurs outside its territory, if there is no more appropriate body willing to take such action. (There is also a further question of the existence of 'universal jurisdiction' over certain crimes like piracy and genocide, even when it takes place outside the state's territory and none of its members are involved as either victims or wrongdoers. The better view is probably that the world community has jurisdiction over these wrongs, because they merit condemnation in the name of the world community, but that for practical reasons this jurisdiction is delegated to national states in order to ensure that these crimes are punished.)
  • 52
    • 36849048059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The scope of the state's proper role in community life is, of course, a controversial question in political philosophy that this article does not attempt to address
    • The scope of the state's proper role in community life is, of course, a controversial question in political philosophy that this article does not attempt to address.
  • 53
    • 36849068645 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A. Duff, 'Theories of Criminal Law' The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2002 edn), E.N. Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2002/entries/criminal-law/s 6.
    • A. Duff, 'Theories of Criminal Law' The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2002 edn), E.N. Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2002/entries/criminal-law/s 6.
  • 54
    • 36849032500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Such as the 'harm principle', i.e. the principle that only harms (or perhaps harms to others) should be coercively restrained. For some sceptical evaluations of this limiting role of the harm principle, see J. Stanton-Ife, 'The Limits of Law' The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2006 edn), E.N. Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2006/entries/law-limits/
    • Such as the 'harm principle', i.e. the principle that only harms (or perhaps harms to others) should be coercively restrained. For some sceptical evaluations of this limiting role of the harm principle, see J. Stanton-Ife, 'The Limits of Law' The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2006 edn), E.N. Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2006/entries/law-limits/
  • 55
    • 4143123039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Philosophy of Criminal Law
    • J. Coleman and S. Shapiro eds, Oxford: Oxford University Press, at
    • and L. Alexander, 'The Philosophy of Criminal Law' in J. Coleman and S. Shapiro (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Legal Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), at 851-64.
    • (2002) The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Legal Philosophy , pp. 851-864
    • Alexander, L.1
  • 56
    • 1342298676 scopus 로고
    • A Right to do Wrong' in his
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • J. Waldron, 'A Right to do Wrong' in his Liberal Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993).
    • (1993) Liberal Rights
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 57
    • 36849069153 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If there was a general right to liberty this would have a more systematic effect on criminalization, e.g. by creating a threshold against wrongs being punished. For a defence of such a right see M. Moore, Placing Blame, Ch. 18
    • If there was a general right to liberty this would have a more systematic effect on criminalization, e.g. by creating a threshold against wrongs being punished. For a defence of such a right see M. Moore, Placing Blame, Ch. 18.
  • 58
    • 36849086149 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also, D. Husak's argument that there is a right not to be punished in 'The Criminal Law as Last Resort' (2004) 24 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 207, at 232-5.
    • See also, D. Husak's argument that there is a right not to be punished in 'The Criminal Law as Last Resort' (2004) 24 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 207, at 232-5.
  • 59
    • 36849008376 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Among non-rights-based arguments, the most prominent is one advanced by Raz over the value of personal autonomy. According to Raz all coercion infringes personal autonomy, and the only justification for such infringement by the state is the promotion of autonomy (the agent's or others, itself: The Morality of Freedom Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986, at 412-20. But this only follows if there are no situations in which it can be more important to secure conformity to a vaine other than autonomy than to avoid the use of coercion. A more limited general presumption against punishment could, however, be based on his argument, viz, that wrongs may only be punished where this is worth the invasion of personal autonomy. Depending upon the importance of personal autonomy, this could set quite a high threshold
    • Among non-rights-based arguments, the most prominent is one advanced by Raz over the value of personal autonomy. According to Raz all coercion infringes personal autonomy, and the only justification for such infringement by the state is the promotion of autonomy (the agent's or others') itself: The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986), at 412-20. But this only follows if there are no situations in which it can be more important to secure conformity to a vaine other than autonomy than to avoid the use of coercion. A more limited general presumption against punishment could, however, be based on his argument, viz., that wrongs may only be punished where this is worth the invasion of personal autonomy. Depending upon the importance of personal autonomy, this could set quite a high threshold.
  • 60
    • 36849023605 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Likewise, it would be inadequate for some wrongs to be condemned by some body or person other than the community as a whole
    • Likewise, it would be inadequate for some wrongs to be condemned by some body or person other than the community as a whole.
  • 61
    • 36849034686 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A useful summary of a wider range of these problems can be found in M. Moore, Placing Blame above n 32 at 663-5. And even if a crime is created, there is still the question in each case of whether charges should be brought.
    • A useful summary of a wider range of these problems can be found in M. Moore, Placing Blame above n 32 at 663-5. And even if a crime is created, there is still the question in each case of whether charges should be brought.
  • 62
    • 36849053144 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There may be special circumstances, however, where these concerns may be allayed
    • There may be special circumstances, however, where these concerns may be allayed.
  • 63
    • 36849008381 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is also difficult fairly to present a jury with the idea of a personalized standard of negligence
    • It is also difficult fairly to present a jury with the idea of a personalized standard of negligence.
  • 64
    • 36849062372 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There are other ways in which moral considerations are altered in being translated into legal doctrine. The most obvious in the case of crime is the lack of a general defence of mistake of law. And nothing said here touches on the question of the appropriate standards and burdens of proof for different types of crime
    • There are other ways in which moral considerations are altered in being translated into legal doctrine. The most obvious in the case of crime is the lack of a general defence of mistake of law. And nothing said here touches on the question of the appropriate standards and burdens of proof for different types of crime.
  • 65
    • 36849009952 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an account of personal autonomy along these lines see Raz, above n 44, Ch. 14.
    • For an account of personal autonomy along these lines see Raz, above n 44, Ch. 14.
  • 66
    • 36849008881 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, for instance, 'rape of a child under 13' (s 5 Sexual Offences Act 2003, England and Wales) which does not require any mens rea as to the victim's age (nor lack of consent for the actus reus).
    • See, for instance, 'rape of a child under 13' (s 5 Sexual Offences Act 2003, England and Wales) which does not require any mens rea as to the victim's age (nor lack of consent for the actus reus).
  • 67
    • 36849066528 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See e.g. A.P. Simester, 'Is Strict Liability Always Wrong?' in A.P. Simester (ed.), Appraising Strict Liability (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), especially at 25-33. For further discussions of strict liability see the other essays in the Appraising Strict Liabilty
    • See e.g. A.P. Simester, 'Is Strict Liability Always Wrong?' in A.P. Simester (ed.), Appraising Strict Liability (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), especially at 25-33. For further discussions of strict liability see the other essays in the Appraising Strict Liabilty volume.
  • 68
    • 36849028357 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • E.g. motoring offences, health and safety and food standards
    • E.g. motoring offences, health and safety and food standards.
  • 69
    • 36849007874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Arguably some are also intrinsically valuable because they enable members of the community to co-operate in ways that serve the good of the community as a whole: Participation in such schemes realises a form of social solidarity which is itself intrinsically valuable.
    • Arguably some are also intrinsically valuable because they enable members of the community to co-operate in ways that serve the good of the community as a whole: Participation in such schemes realises a form of social solidarity which is itself intrinsically valuable.
  • 70
    • 36849047546 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is a mistake then to think that matters dealt with by 'regulatory offences' are not apt for the criminal law: It is simply that the conduct must be shown to merit punishment.
    • It is a mistake then to think that matters dealt with by 'regulatory offences' are not apt for the criminal law: It is simply that the conduct must be shown to merit punishment.
  • 71
    • 36849082726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • So it does not follow Devlin's approach (P. Devlin, The Enforcement of Morals (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965), especially Ch. 1).
    • So it does not follow Devlin's approach (P. Devlin, The Enforcement of Morals (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965), especially Ch. 1).
  • 72
    • 36849079567 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an alternative legal moralist approach to criminal law see Moore Placing Blame above n 32.
    • For an alternative legal moralist approach to criminal law see Moore Placing Blame above n 32.
  • 73
    • 36849074987 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is an open question whether the invocation of the harm principle would radically alter this picture, even if that principle could be successfully defended
    • It is an open question whether the invocation of the harm principle would radically alter this picture, even if that principle could be successfully defended.
  • 74
    • 36849093124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See J. Feinberg, 'The Expressive Function of Punishment' in his Doing and Deserving (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1970), especially at 95-8.
    • See J. Feinberg, 'The Expressive Function of Punishment' in his Doing and Deserving (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1970), especially at 95-8.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.