메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 35, Issue 6, 2007, Pages 732-755

The force of ideas in Spinoza

Author keywords

Althusser; Ideology; Materialism; Spinoza

Indexed keywords


EID: 35648932044     PISSN: 00905917     EISSN: 15527476     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/0090591707307326     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (30)

References (65)
  • 3
    • 27744537840 scopus 로고
    • trans. Timothy S. Murphy Manchester: Manchester University Press
    • Antonio Negri, Subversive Spinoza, trans. Timothy S. Murphy (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1994).
    • (1994) Subversive Spinoza
    • Negri, A.1
  • 4
    • 35648932505 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Most notably, Etienne Balibar and Pierre Macherey
    • Most notably, Etienne Balibar and Pierre Macherey.
  • 5
    • 35648943756 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Louis Althusser, The Only Materialist Tradition, Part I: Spinoza, trans. T. Stolze, in The New Spinoza, edited by Warren Montag and Ted Stolze (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1997), 7. Hereafter The Only Materialist Tradition.
    • Louis Althusser, "The Only Materialist Tradition, Part I: Spinoza," trans. T. Stolze, in The New Spinoza, edited by Warren Montag and Ted Stolze (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1997), 7. Hereafter "The Only Materialist Tradition."
  • 6
    • 35648960329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I use ideology in the broadest possible sense, which I defend below. It is perhaps closest to Althusser's use of Ideology in his essay, Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses: Notes Toward an Investigation, even as I refer to something excessive of human representation. Althusser distinguishes between Ideology in the capitalized singular and ideologies. Ideology is the invariant fact that human representations are mediated by the peculiar character of the social structure in which subjects live. Ideologies, on the other hand, refer to particular discourses that are motivated by a set of interests. Following Althusser, I consider ideology in the singular to refer to the more neutral sense of the social (though, any distinction between social and natural makes little sense in Spinoza's terms) determination of ideas rather than an explicitly interested discourse. In Lenin and Philosophy, trans. B. Brewster
    • I use ideology in the broadest possible sense, which I defend below. It is perhaps closest to Althusser's use of "Ideology" in his essay, "Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses: Notes Toward an Investigation," even as I refer to something excessive of human representation. Althusser distinguishes between "Ideology" in the capitalized singular and "ideologies." Ideology is the invariant fact that human representations are mediated by the peculiar character of the social structure in which subjects live. Ideologies, on the other hand, refer to particular discourses that are motivated by a set of interests. Following Althusser, I consider ideology in the singular to refer to the more neutral sense of the social (though, any distinction between "social" and "natural" makes little sense in Spinoza's terms) determination of ideas rather than an explicitly interested discourse. In Lenin and Philosophy, trans. B. Brewster (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1971). Hereafter "Ideology."
  • 8
    • 35648997015 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I will proceed to cite Spinoza parenthetically in the body of the paper with the standard notation, using Edwin Curley's edition and translation, The Collected Works of Spinoza, 1 (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985). Citations refer to the part (= Roman numeral), proposition (= p), demonstration (= d), scholium (= s), corollary (= c), appendix (= app), preface (= pref), and definition (= def).
    • I will proceed to cite Spinoza parenthetically in the body of the paper with the standard notation, using Edwin Curley's edition and translation, The Collected Works of Spinoza, vol. 1 (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985). Citations refer to the part (= Roman numeral), proposition (= p), demonstration (= d), scholium (= s), corollary (= c), appendix (= app), preface (= pref), and definition (= def).
  • 10
    • 35649023268 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, especially Chapter 2 of Bodies, Masses, Power: Spinoza and his Contemporaries (London: Verso, 1999). For other examinations of the relationship between Spinoza and Althusser,
    • See, especially Chapter 2 of Bodies, Masses, Power: Spinoza and his Contemporaries (London: Verso, 1999). For other examinations of the relationship between Spinoza and Althusser,
  • 11
    • 34247453836 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Peter Thomas, Philosophical Strategies: Spinoza and Althusser Historical Materialism 10.3 (December 2002): 71-113;
    • see Peter Thomas, "Philosophical Strategies: Spinoza and Althusser" Historical Materialism 10.3 (December 2002): 71-113;
  • 14
    • 84858364301 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Althusser et Spinoza
    • edited by Paul-Laurent Assoun Paris: Presses Universitaires de France
    • Jean-Pierre Cotten, "Althusser et Spinoza," in Spinoza au XXième Siècle, edited by Paul-Laurent Assoun (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France),
    • Spinoza au XXième Siècle
    • Cotten, J.1
  • 15
    • 35648938722 scopus 로고
    • On Spinoza
    • trans. B. Brewster London: New Left Books
    • and Althusser himself, "On Spinoza," Elements of 'Self-Criticism, trans. B. Brewster (London: New Left Books, 1976).
    • (1976) Elements of 'Self-Criticism
    • himself, A.1
  • 17
    • 35649004421 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 6, and E Iapp.
    • Ibid., 6, and E Iapp.
  • 18
    • 84881937786 scopus 로고
    • trans. B. Fowkes New York: Penguin Books
    • Karl Marx, Capital, volume 1, trans. B. Fowkes (New York: Penguin Books, 1976), 280.
    • (1976) Capital , vol.1 , pp. 280
    • Marx, K.1
  • 19
    • 35648966578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Palgrave MacMillan
    • Warren Montag, Louis Althusser (New York: Palgrave MacMillan, 2003), 78.
    • (2003) Louis Althusser , pp. 78
    • Montag, W.1
  • 21
    • 35648963151 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One can likewise approach the question of freedom from the point of view that one is but a tiny particle within the infinite power of extension, a singular body amidst infinitely many other bodies, as Montag's work has done elegantly. My focus here, however, is how ideas move ideas
    • One can likewise approach the question of freedom from the point of view that one is but a tiny particle within the infinite power of extension, a singular body amidst infinitely many other bodies, as Montag's work has done elegantly. My focus here, however, is how ideas move ideas.
  • 22
    • 31644442641 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Matthew Sharpe's is an interesting recent discussion of ideology as structurally analogous to aesthetic judgment, The Aesthetics of Ideology, or 'The Critique of Ideological Judgment in Eagleton and Žižek, Political Theory 34.1 (February 2006): 95-120.
    • Matthew Sharpe's is an interesting recent discussion of ideology as structurally analogous to aesthetic judgment, "The Aesthetics of Ideology, or 'The Critique of Ideological Judgment in Eagleton and Žižek, " Political Theory 34.1 (February 2006): 95-120.
  • 23
    • 84858364083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Most notably, Terry Eagleton, Ernesto Lacalu, and Slavoj Žižek
    • Most notably, Terry Eagleton, Ernesto Lacalu, and Slavoj Žižek.
  • 25
    • 0000353566 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Death and Resurrection of the Theory of Ideology
    • 1.3
    • "The Death and Resurrection of the Theory of Ideology," Journal of Political Ideologies 1.3 (1996): 201-220,
    • (1996) Journal of Political Ideologies , pp. 201-220
  • 26
    • 84858364297 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and the introductory essay in Mapping Ideology (London: Verso, 1994), edited by Žižek, respectively.
    • and the introductory essay in Mapping Ideology (London: Verso, 1994), edited by Žižek, respectively.
  • 28
    • 35649022732 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Although Marx's texts themselves are considerably more ambivalent and complicated than some, perhaps even most, of the traditions to which they gave rise, his texts can be understood, at least partly, to be objectively responsible for the effects they produced. From a Spinozan perspective, texts are bodies that affect and are affected by other bodies, some of which accord with the striving unique to them, or their particular nature, but most of which are accidental products of energetic interactions between myriad forces
    • Although Marx's texts themselves are considerably more ambivalent and complicated than some, perhaps even most, of the traditions to which they gave rise, his texts can be understood, at least partly, to be objectively responsible for the effects they produced. From a Spinozan perspective, texts are bodies that affect and are affected by other bodies, some of which accord with the striving unique to them, or their particular "nature," but most of which are accidental products of energetic interactions between myriad forces.
  • 30
    • 35649012788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Evidence for this claim can be found throughout the Ethics, but especially, E Idef2, IIp7, IIIp2.
    • Evidence for this claim can be found throughout the Ethics, but especially, E Idef2, IIp7, IIIp2.
  • 31
    • 35648973779 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am thinking, especially, of Warren Montag to whom I am deeply indebted, even as I offer this corrective supplement to his analysis of corporeal determination;
    • I am thinking, especially, of Warren Montag to whom I am deeply indebted, even as I offer this corrective supplement to his analysis of corporeal determination;
  • 32
    • 35649003118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Bodies, Masses, Power (London: Verso, 1999).
    • see Bodies, Masses, Power (London: Verso, 1999).
  • 33
    • 35648975334 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is a bit of an overstatement, since Negri, Balibar, and Montag all examine the play of imagination and reason, the first two kinds of knowledge, but the sensual, affective, and corporeal remain the privileged sites of explanation for the tradition of Marxist interpretation
    • This is a bit of an overstatement, since Negri, Balibar, and Montag all examine the play of imagination and reason, the first two kinds of knowledge, but the sensual, affective, and corporeal remain the privileged sites of explanation for the tradition of Marxist interpretation.
  • 34
    • 35649003896 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Spinoza famously remarks: To man, then, there is nothing more useful to man. Man, I say, can wish for nothing more helpful to the preservation of his being than that all should so agree in all things that the minds and bodies of all would compose, as it were, one mind and one body; that all should strive together as far as they can, to preserve their being, and that all, together, should seek for themselves the common advantage of all (E IVp18s). Space prohibits an analysis of this notion of utility, which I will take up in another paper.
    • Spinoza famously remarks: "To man, then, there is nothing more useful to man. Man, I say, can wish for nothing more helpful to the preservation of his being than that all should so agree in all things that the minds and bodies of all would compose, as it were, one mind and one body; that all should strive together as far as they can, to preserve their being, and that all, together, should seek for themselves the common advantage of all" (E IVp18s). Space prohibits an analysis of this notion of utility, which I will take up in another paper.
  • 35
    • 35648985154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Objects, Ideas, and 'Minds' : Comments on Spinoza's Theory
    • For example, Princeton: Princeton University Press
    • For example, Margaret Wilson, "Objects, Ideas, and 'Minds' : Comments on Spinoza's Theory," in Ideas and Mechanism: Essays on Early Modern Philosophy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1999).
    • (1999) Ideas and Mechanism: Essays on Early Modern Philosophy
    • Wilson, M.1
  • 36
    • 84858367834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Althusser, Underground Current of the Materialism of the Encounter, in Philosophy of the Encounter: Later Writings, 1978-1987, edited by François Matheron and Olivier Corpet, trans. G.M. Goshgarian (London: Verso, 2006), 183. Hereafter Underground Current.
    • Althusser, "Underground Current of the Materialism of the Encounter," in Philosophy of the Encounter: Later Writings, 1978-1987, edited by François Matheron and Olivier Corpet, trans. G.M. Goshgarian (London: Verso, 2006), 183. Hereafter "Underground Current."
  • 37
    • 35648983496 scopus 로고
    • Fable of the Beaver
    • New York: International Publishers
    • Antonio Gramsci, "Fable of the Beaver," in Selections from the Prison Notebooks (New York: International Publishers, 1971).
    • (1971) Selections from the Prison Notebooks
    • Gramsci, A.1
  • 38
    • 35648987188 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Spinoza, The Letters, trans. S. Shirley Indianapolis: Hackett Publishers, 1995, Epistle 58. Although I cannot address this within the scope of the paper, Spinoza and Althusser have different targets in their critiques of conscious freedom. Althusser is likely critical of a phenomenological or existentialist model of consciousness as radically free interiority, which is alien to Spinoza except insofar as it originates in Descartes. Althusser rather polemically equates Ideology in the omnihistorical sense to consciousness itself, suggesting that the precious consciousness of his peer intellectuals is invariably an expression of its social relations structured by domination. Spinoza, however, is concerned with superstitious and theological subjectivity that imagines human and divine freedom as unconstrained caprice rather than natural necessity
    • Spinoza, The Letters, trans. S. Shirley (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishers, 1995), Epistle 58. Although I cannot address this within the scope of the paper, Spinoza and Althusser have different targets in their critiques of conscious freedom. Althusser is likely critical of a phenomenological or existentialist model of "consciousness" as radically free interiority, which is alien to Spinoza except insofar as it originates in Descartes. Althusser rather polemically equates Ideology in the omnihistorical sense to consciousness itself, suggesting that the precious consciousness of his peer intellectuals is invariably an expression of its social relations structured by domination. Spinoza, however, is concerned with superstitious and theological subjectivity that imagines human and divine freedom as unconstrained caprice rather than natural necessity.
  • 40
    • 35648989040 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Conclusions without premises is a notion from Spinoza (E IIp28d) that recalls symptomatic reading as the investigation of answers to questions unconsciously, or not yet posed; Althusser and Etienne Balibar, Reading Capital, trans. B. Brewster (London: Verso, 1970).
    • "Conclusions without premises" is a notion from Spinoza (E IIp28d) that recalls "symptomatic reading" as the investigation of answers to questions unconsciously, or not yet posed; Althusser and Etienne Balibar, Reading Capital, trans. B. Brewster (London: Verso, 1970).
  • 43
    • 35649025395 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That is, usually other humans, but Spinoza would hardly be surprised by wolf and bear children, since corporeal similarity is something that emerges as much through repeated contact as from given biology. There is no such thing as an essential human, bear, or wolf nature, but only infinitely many individual natures, or essences
    • That is, usually other humans, but Spinoza would hardly be surprised by wolf and bear children, since corporeal similarity is something that emerges as much through repeated contact as from given biology. There is no such thing as an essential human, bear, or wolf nature, but only infinitely many individual natures, or essences.
  • 44
    • 35648982457 scopus 로고
    • For a more detailed defense of this claim, see, Ch. 4 Paris: Maspero
    • For a more detailed defense of this claim, see Pierre Macherey, Hegel ou Spinoza, Ch. 4 (Paris: Maspero, 1979).
    • (1979) Hegel ou Spinoza
    • Macherey, P.1
  • 46
    • 84858367827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • page reference is to French edition, Spinoza et le Problème de l'Expression (Paris: Editions de Minuit, 1968), 36.
    • page reference is to French edition, Spinoza et le Problème de l'Expression (Paris: Editions de Minuit, 1968), 36.
  • 47
    • 35649008932 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Montag, Bodies, Masses, Power, xxi
    • Cf. Montag, Bodies, Masses, Power, xxi.
  • 48
    • 35648971600 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • To preserve the irreducibility of the attributes to one another, however, one must bear in mind that the body as a model is an analogy to the life of ideas. Taking the body as a model entails that one understand something by way of something else. The story of the body in Spinoza may be even more properly called allegorical insofar as it tells us about ideas. Allegories, of course, are still indicative and useful ways of understanding things, but the difference (allegory from allos, other or different) that holds apart the phenomena must be kept in mind.
    • To preserve the irreducibility of the attributes to one another, however, one must bear in mind that the "body as a model" is an analogy to the life of ideas. Taking the body as a model entails that one understand something by way of something else. The story of the body in Spinoza may be even more properly called "allegorical" insofar as it tells us about ideas. Allegories, of course, are still indicative and useful ways of understanding things, but the difference (allegory from allos, other or different) that holds apart the phenomena must be kept in mind.
  • 49
    • 0003784108 scopus 로고
    • trans. R. Hurley, San Francisco: City Lights Books
    • Deleuze, Spinoza: Practical Philosophy, trans. R. Hurley. (San Francisco: City Lights Books, 1988), 18-19.
    • (1988) Spinoza: Practical Philosophy , pp. 18-19
    • Deleuze1
  • 52
    • 2542598602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jane Bennett also notes parenthetically that ideas strive to enhance their power of activity, The Force of Things: Steps Toward and Ecology of Matter, Political Theory 32.3 (2004), 353.
    • Jane Bennett also notes parenthetically that "ideas strive to enhance their power of activity," "The Force of Things: Steps Toward and Ecology of Matter," Political Theory 32.3 (2004), 353.
  • 53
    • 35648933503 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What I call human truth refers to Spinoza's doctrine of adequate ideas, which are ideas that contain the ideas of their causes. Due to the autonomy of the attributes, in my interpretation, Spinoza's is not a correspondence theory of truth, where an idea is true insofar as it corresponds to its object (except in the case of the divine intellect, which has a grasp of the totality of ideas). For humans, we have adequate ideas that include knowledge of their causes, when ideas emerge more from our power of thinking than from external powers. Since we are largely moved by external powers, we mostly generate inadequate ideas, or ideas that do not include an apprehension of what brought them into being. (E IIdef4).
    • What I call "human truth" refers to Spinoza's doctrine of adequate ideas, which are ideas that contain the ideas of their causes. Due to the autonomy of the attributes, in my interpretation, Spinoza's is not a correspondence theory of truth, where an idea is true insofar as it corresponds to its object (except in the case of the divine intellect, which has a grasp of the totality of ideas). For humans, we have adequate ideas that include knowledge of their causes, when ideas emerge more from our power of thinking than from external powers. Since we are largely moved by external powers, we mostly generate inadequate ideas, or ideas that do not include an apprehension of what brought them into being. (E IIdef4).
  • 54
    • 35648961939 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Spinoza seems to attribute a kind of spontaneous, yet mistaken (in contrast to Hobbes), ontological individualism to the fact that our bodies filter our experience of the world. The Marxist analyses of, for example, Macpherson, force us to ask whether such an interpretation of our experience is historically imposed rather than the inevitable consequence of embodied subjectivity. See C.B. MacPherson, The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to Locke (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1964).
    • Spinoza seems to attribute a kind of spontaneous, yet mistaken (in contrast to Hobbes), ontological individualism to the fact that our bodies filter our experience of the world. The Marxist analyses of, for example, Macpherson, force us to ask whether such an interpretation of our experience is historically imposed rather than the inevitable consequence of embodied subjectivity. See C.B. MacPherson, The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to Locke (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1964).
  • 55
    • 34247652951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a Spinozist analysis of our affective milieu during the war on terror, see Hasana Sharp, Why Spinoza Today? Or, 'A Strategy of Anti-Fear,' Rethinking Marxism 17.4 (October 2005): 591-608.
    • For a Spinozist analysis of our affective milieu during the war on terror, see Hasana Sharp, "Why Spinoza Today? Or, 'A Strategy of Anti-Fear,'" Rethinking Marxism 17.4 (October 2005): 591-608.
  • 58
    • 12944275405 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Smith, What Kind of Democrat was Spinoza?, Political Theory 33.1 (2005), 13.
    • Cf. Smith, "What Kind of Democrat was Spinoza?," Political Theory 33.1 (2005), 13.
  • 59
    • 35649022729 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Vittorio Morfino, An Althusserian. Lexicon, Borderlands e-journal 4.2 (2005).
    • Vittorio Morfino, "An Althusserian. Lexicon," Borderlands e-journal 4.2 (2005).
  • 63
    • 35648974788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Many do not share my interpretation and argue that freedom and rationality for Spinoza can only be had by few individuals and are largely solitary projects. My argument here leads to the notion that even thinking, wisdom, and philosophy must be collective efforts, where collective is interpreted broadly to include inorganic conditions as well as human assemblies. For an argument that wisdom and philosophy are solitary endeavors, see Steven B. Smith, Spinoza, Liberalism, and the Question of Jewish Identity
    • Many do not share my interpretation and argue that freedom and rationality for Spinoza can only be had by few individuals and are largely solitary projects. My argument here leads to the notion that even thinking, wisdom, and philosophy must be collective efforts, where collective is interpreted broadly to include inorganic conditions as well as human assemblies. For an argument that wisdom and philosophy are solitary endeavors, see Steven B. Smith, Spinoza, Liberalism, and the Question of Jewish Identity.
  • 64
    • 35649005481 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. S. Shirley Indianapolis: Hackett, Ch. 16
    • Spinoza, Theological-Political Treatise, trans. S. Shirley (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2001), Ch. 16, 178.
    • (2001) Theological-Political Treatise , pp. 178
    • Spinoza1
  • 65
    • 35648989039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Political Treatise, trans. S. Shirley (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2000), Ch. 9, par. 14, my emphasis.
    • Political Treatise, trans. S. Shirley (Indianapolis: Hackett, 2000), Ch. 9, par. 14, my emphasis.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.