메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 35, Issue 3, 2007, Pages 203-232

The hybrid nature of promissory obligation

(1)  Tognazzini, Neal A a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 35348990234     PISSN: 00483915     EISSN: 10884963     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1088-4963.2007.00108.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (12)

References (47)
  • 1
    • 35348969656 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an example of this kind of view, see John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), especially pp. 344-50.
    • For an example of this kind of view, see John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971), especially pp. 344-50.
  • 2
    • 33744540383 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon on Promissory Obligation: The Problem of Promisee's Rights
    • As it turns out, this 'special complaint' objection may have force against more than just a social practice view. See
    • As it turns out, this 'special complaint' objection may have force against more than just a social practice view. See Margaret Gilbert, "Scanlon on Promissory Obligation: The Problem of Promisee's Rights," Journal of Philosophy 101 (2004): 83-109.
    • (2004) Journal of Philosophy , vol.101 , pp. 83-109
    • Gilbert, M.1
  • 3
    • 0003867020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, Cambridge, Mass, Harvard University Press, chap. 7. All further references to Scanlon will be to this work
    • See T. M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1998), chap. 7. All further references to Scanlon will be to this work.
    • (1998) What We Owe to Each Other
    • Scanlon, T.M.1
  • 4
    • 66749131592 scopus 로고
    • Promises and Practices
    • See also
    • See also Scanlon, "Promises and Practices," Philosophy & Public Affairs 19 (1990): 199-226
    • (1990) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.19 , pp. 199-226
    • Scanlon1
  • 5
    • 35348967725 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Promises and Contracts, in The Difficulty of Tolerance: Essays in Political Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003).
    • and "Promises and Contracts," in The Difficulty of Tolerance: Essays in Political Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003).
  • 6
    • 35348981112 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The term 'expectation view' is meant to contrast with a class of theories that might be called 'normative power views.' According to normative power views, a promissory obligation is created in virtue of the fact that when one utters certain words, one intends to undertake, by that very act of communication, an obligation so to act. A pure social practice view can be seen as a species of normative power view. For another species of normative power view that does not rely on a social practice, see Joseph Raz, Voluntary Obligations and Normative Powers, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplement 46 (1972): 79-102.
    • The term 'expectation view' is meant to contrast with a class of theories that might be called 'normative power views.' According to normative power views, a promissory obligation is created in virtue of the fact that when one utters certain words, one intends to undertake, by that very act of communication, an obligation so to act. A pure social practice view can be seen as a species of normative power view. For another species of normative power view that does not rely on a social practice, see Joseph Raz, "Voluntary Obligations and Normative Powers," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplement 46 (1972): 79-102.
  • 7
    • 84909336834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I owe the terms 'expectation view' and 'normative power view,' as well as their respective explanations, to Gary Watson. For a similar taxonomy of theories into volitional and perlocutionary varieties, see Michael Pratt, Promises and Perlocutions, in Scanlon and Contractualism, ed. Matt Matravers (London: Frank Cass & Co., 2003), p. 93.
    • I owe the terms 'expectation view' and 'normative power view,' as well as their respective explanations, to Gary Watson. For a similar taxonomy of theories into volitional and perlocutionary varieties, see Michael Pratt, "Promises and Perlocutions," in Scanlon and Contractualism, ed. Matt Matravers (London: Frank Cass & Co., 2003), p. 93.
  • 8
    • 35348971280 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This point in particular is why I have chosen to discuss Scanlon's view below, despite the fact that there are other plausible theories that also eschew the need for a social practice of promising. I am grateful to an Editor of Philosophy & Public Affairs for pushing me to be clear about this issue
    • This point in particular is why I have chosen to discuss Scanlon's view below, despite the fact that there are other plausible theories that also eschew the need for a social practice of promising. I am grateful to an Editor of Philosophy & Public Affairs for pushing me to be clear about this issue.
  • 10
    • 35348990666 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon, p. 298
    • Scanlon, p. 298.
  • 11
    • 35348973870 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon, p. 300
    • Scanlon, p. 300.
  • 12
    • 35349026544 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon, p. 300-01
    • Scanlon, p. 300-01.
  • 13
    • 35348988541 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The central concern of the morality of promises is therefore with the obligation to perform
    • p
    • Scanlon: "The central concern of the morality of promises is therefore with the obligation to perform; the idea of compensation is of at most secondary interest," p. 302.
    • the idea of compensation is of at most secondary interest , pp. 302
    • Scanlon1
  • 14
    • 35348980047 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For more on the value of assurance, seemy discussion of Scanlon's case of the Guilty Secret in Section VII below.
    • For more on the value of assurance, seemy discussion of Scanlon's case of the Guilty Secret in Section VII below.
  • 15
    • 35348945198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon, p. 304
    • Scanlon, p. 304.
  • 16
    • 35348980612 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon, p. 306
    • Scanlon, p. 306.
  • 17
    • 35348936993 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon, p. 306
    • Scanlon, p. 306.
  • 18
    • 35348966693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon, p. 306
    • Scanlon, p. 306.
  • 19
    • 26644461080 scopus 로고
    • Utilitarianism and Truthfulness
    • For a similar problem in a different context, see
    • For a similar problem in a different context, see David Lewis, "Utilitarianism and Truthfulness," Australasian Journal of Philosophy 50 (1972): 17-19.
    • (1972) Australasian Journal of Philosophy , vol.50 , pp. 17-19
    • Lewis, D.1
  • 20
    • 35349030132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The objection can be found in Michael Pratt, Promises and Perlocutions, pp. 106-09.
    • The objection can be found in Michael Pratt, "Promises and Perlocutions," pp. 106-09.
  • 21
    • 35349012910 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is worth pointing out that the criticism of Scanlon's response that I have focused on in this section is distinct from the criticism that Kolodny and Wallace raise in their article. Kolodny and Wallace object that Scanlon's response does not allow promises to be created when the would-be promisor has no prior or nonmoral practice-based reasons to do as promised. Since the distinctive utility of promising is not simply that it allows A to assure B that A will do X when A has prior or [nonmoral practice-based] reasons to do X, but also that it allows A to assure B when A does not have any prior or [nonmoral practice-based] reasons to do X at all, Scanlon's response to the Circularity Objection entails that promising loses its distinctive utility Kolodny and Wallace, p. 143, The objection I have been pushing, on the other hand, maintains that the prior reasons A has to do X in virtue of PrinciplesMand D will not even be enough to produce the assurance nee
    • It is worth pointing out that the criticism of Scanlon's response that I have focused on in this section is distinct from the criticism that Kolodny and Wallace raise in their article. Kolodny and Wallace object that Scanlon's response does not allow promises to be created when the would-be promisor has no prior or nonmoral practice-based reasons to do as promised. Since "the distinctive utility of promising is not simply that it allows A to assure B that A will do X when A has prior or [nonmoral practice-based] reasons to do X ... but also that it allows A to assure B when A does not have any prior or [nonmoral practice-based] reasons to do X at all," Scanlon's response to the Circularity Objection entails that promising loses its distinctive utility (Kolodny and Wallace, p. 143). The objection I have been pushing, on the other hand, maintains that the prior reasons A has to do X in virtue of PrinciplesMand D will not even be enough to produce the assurance needed to trigger Principle F, if F is indeed a valid moral principle. Insofar as the objection from Kolodny and Wallace is a good one (and I aminclined to think it is), Scanlon's response fails for more than one reason.
  • 22
    • 35348979535 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Of course, not all hybrid views need involve components from Scanlon's theory per se they may involve elements of some other expectation view, but since the two I discuss below do, I gloss over this point in the text
    • Of course, not all hybrid views need involve components from Scanlon's theory per se (they may involve elements of some other expectation view), but since the two I discuss below do, I gloss over this point in the text.
  • 24
    • 35349031527 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kolodny and Wallace point out that this consequence may seem counterintuitive, but they give compelling considerations in favor of this consequence, despite its initial counterintuitiveness (p. 153). It is also worth noting that this feature is not limited to hybrid accounts per se. Indeed, even the defender of an expectation view will have to admit, if something like Rawls's principle of fairness is plausible, that every time someone takes part in the social practice of promising in order to make a promise, that person acquires two obligations.
    • Kolodny and Wallace point out that this consequence may seem counterintuitive, but they give compelling considerations in favor of this consequence, despite its initial counterintuitiveness (p. 153). It is also worth noting that this feature is not limited to hybrid accounts per se. Indeed, even the defender of an expectation view will have to admit, if something like Rawls's principle of fairness is plausible, that every time someone takes part in the social practice of promising in order to make a promise, that person acquires two obligations.
  • 26
    • 35348966692 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon, p. 297. Although Principle F is not yet formulated by this point in the book, it is clear from what Scanlon says later that this particular example is meant to be a nonpromissory scenario in which principle F is nevertheless engaged. See p. 306.
    • Scanlon, p. 297. Although Principle F is not yet formulated by this point in the book, it is clear from what Scanlon says later that this particular example is meant to be a nonpromissory scenario in which principle F is nevertheless engaged. See p. 306.
  • 27
    • 35348971279 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Michael Pratt has also noted the peculiarity of Scanlon's use of parentheses in condition (1). See Pratt, Promises and Perlocutions, p. 117, n. 18. Scanlon must have noted it as well, since in his more recent discussion, Promises and Contracts, the parentheses are omitted.
    • Michael Pratt has also noted the peculiarity of Scanlon's use of parentheses in condition (1). See Pratt, "Promises and Perlocutions," p. 117, n. 18. Scanlon must have noted it as well, since in his more recent discussion, "Promises and Contracts," the parentheses are omitted.
  • 28
    • 35348950444 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In personal correspondence, Niko Kolodny has suggested an alternative way of understanding how the parentheses in condition (1) function. He suggests we might read condition (1) as follows: A voluntarily and intentionally leads B either to expect that A will do X, or to expect that A will do X unless B consents to A's not doing X. On this reading, merely creating an expectation that Awill do X is enough to satisfy condition (1) of Principle F. But, as we saw in connection with the Circularity Objection, any principle according to which one can gain an obligation to do X unless someone consents otherwise merely by creating the expectation that A will do X (which one can do by including a relevant escape clause) must surely be an invalid moral principle.
    • In personal correspondence, Niko Kolodny has suggested an alternative way of understanding how the parentheses in condition (1) function. He suggests we might read condition (1) as follows: "A voluntarily and intentionally leads B either to expect that A will do X, or to expect that A will do X unless B consents to A's not doing X." On this reading, merely creating an expectation that Awill do X is enough to satisfy condition (1) of Principle F. But, as we saw in connection with the Circularity Objection, any principle according to which one can gain an obligation to do X unless someone consents otherwise merely by creating the expectation that A will do X (which one can do by including a relevant escape clause) must surely be an invalid moral principle.
  • 29
    • 35348955196 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon, p. 298
    • Scanlon, p. 298.
  • 30
    • 35348976491 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thanks to an Editor of Philosophy & Public Affairs here.
    • Thanks to an Editor of Philosophy & Public Affairs here.
  • 31
    • 35349027095 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon, p. 298. Scanlon intentionally leaves it open whether the Sacred Brotherhood of the Reindeer is a real organization, and whether A is in fact a member of this organization. All that Scanlon needs is that B believes both that A is a member of this organization and that being a Reindeer Brother is something that A takes seriously.
    • Scanlon, p. 298. Scanlon intentionally leaves it open whether the Sacred Brotherhood of the Reindeer is a real organization, and whether A is in fact a member of this organization. All that Scanlon needs is that B believes both that A is a member of this organization and that being a Reindeer Brother is something that A takes seriously.
  • 32
    • 35348994204 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the intuitive synonymy of I promise and I swear (as well as a number of other linguistic utterances),
    • On the intuitive synonymy of "I promise" and "I swear" (as well as a number of other linguistic utterances),
  • 33
    • 0004266379 scopus 로고
    • see, Cambridge, Mass, Harvard University Press, chap. 12
    • see Judith Jarvis Thomson, The Realm of Rights (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1990), chap. 12.
    • (1990) The Realm of Rights
    • Jarvis Thomson, J.1
  • 34
    • 35348967724 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon, pp. 323-26
    • Scanlon, pp. 323-26.
  • 35
    • 35348935397 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon himself points out that one of the distinguishing features of F-obligations is that when an F-obligation has been created, the hearer has a 'right to rely' on this performance: That is to say, the second party has grounds for insisting that the first party fulfill the expectation he or she has created p. 305, It is exactly these grounds for insisting that I am denying exist in mere cases of oath taking
    • Scanlon himself points out that one of the distinguishing features of F-obligations is that when an F-obligation has been created, the hearer "has a 'right to rely' on this performance: That is to say, the second party has grounds for insisting that the first party fulfill the expectation he or she has created" (p. 305). It is exactly these "grounds for insisting" that I am denying exist in mere cases of oath taking.
  • 36
    • 35348982716 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am grateful to Niko Kolodny and an Editor of Philosophy & Public Affairs for pushing me to strengthen my argument here.
    • I am grateful to Niko Kolodny and an Editor of Philosophy & Public Affairs for pushing me to strengthen my argument here.
  • 37
    • 35348995324 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • KW offer a scenario of their own, as well, but I think its fate is the same as that of scenario 1. See KW, p. 132. An Editor of Philosophy & Public Affairs suggests that testimony alone might create the required assurance, as in a scenario where I say, I hereby assure you that I will perform. But unless this statement is meant as some sort of a promise, I do not think it can succeed in creating the expectations required for genuine assurance. It would seem that such complex expectations cannot be createdmerely by uttering words to the effect that one is trying to create such expectations. The hearer needs some reason to believe that the speaker will in fact perform before she will be assured, and merely hearing the speaker utter the words above, it seems, cannot provide such a reason
    • KW offer a scenario of their own, as well, but I think its fate is the same as that of scenario 1. See KW, p. 132. An Editor of Philosophy & Public Affairs suggests that testimony alone might create the required assurance, as in a scenario where I say, "I hereby assure you that I will perform." But unless this statement is meant as some sort of a promise, I do not think it can succeed in creating the expectations required for genuine assurance. It would seem that such complex expectations cannot be createdmerely by uttering words to the effect that one is trying to create such expectations. The hearer needs some reason to believe that the speaker will in fact perform before she will be assured, and merely hearing the speaker utter the words above, it seems, cannot provide such a reason.
  • 38
    • 35348969655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the end of the current section for more about how promise-breakers exploit the social practice of promising according to my modified hybrid view. Thanks to an Editor of Philosophy & Public Affairs for pressing me on this issue.
    • See the end of the current section for more about how promise-breakers exploit the social practice of promising according to my modified hybrid view. Thanks to an Editor of Philosophy & Public Affairs for pressing me on this issue.
  • 39
    • 35348981649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At first, it may seem that my modified hybrid view does not deserve to be called a 'hybrid, For according to KW's hybrid view, promissory obligation is explained by, as it were, fusing Scanlon's expectation view with a social practice view. My modified account, by contrast, seems merely to acknowledge the existence of an obligation associated with a social practice view and an obligation associated with Scanlon's expectation view sans F, Gary Watson makes this point in an unpublished manuscript, But see note 43 below, along with the associated text
    • At first, it may seem that my modified hybrid view does not deserve to be called a 'hybrid.' For according to KW's hybrid view, promissory obligation is explained by, as it were, fusing Scanlon's expectation view with a social practice view. My modified account, by contrast, seems merely to acknowledge the existence of an obligation associated with a social practice view and an obligation associated with Scanlon's expectation view sans F. (Gary Watson makes this point in an unpublished manuscript.) But see note 43 below, along with the associated text.
  • 40
    • 35349001019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Both Gary Watson and an Editor of Philosophy & Public Affairs suggested something like this worry to me, although Watson credits Kolodny and Wallace with suggesting it to him.
    • Both Gary Watson and an Editor of Philosophy & Public Affairs suggested something like this worry to me, although Watson credits Kolodny and Wallace with suggesting it to him.
  • 41
    • 35348975428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon, pp. 300-01
    • Scanlon, pp. 300-01.
  • 42
    • 35349012545 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But why think that mere disappointed assurance is a significant enough loss to fall in the scope of Principle L? After all, Principle L is specifically about significant losses. Although it is not altogether clear what Scanlon meant by including the qualification 'significant, I think we have good reason to think that disappointed assurance is indeed significant. See the case of the Guilty Secret that I discuss in the text below for this reason
    • But why think that mere disappointed assurance is a significant enough loss to fall in the scope of Principle L? After all, Principle L is specifically about significant losses. Although it is not altogether clear what Scanlon meant by including the qualification 'significant,' I think we have good reason to think that disappointed assurance is indeed significant. See the case of the Guilty Secret that I discuss in the text below for this reason.
  • 43
    • 35348970751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am grateful to an Editor of Philosophy & Public Affairs for pressing this objection.
    • I am grateful to an Editor of Philosophy & Public Affairs for pressing this objection.
  • 44
    • 35349008918 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon, p. 302, emphasis added
    • Scanlon, p. 302, emphasis added.
  • 45
    • 35348953028 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon, pp. 302-03
    • Scanlon, pp. 302-03.
  • 46
    • 35348969259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I am grateful to an Editor of Philosophy & Public Affairs for this point.
    • I am grateful to an Editor of Philosophy & Public Affairs for this point.
  • 47
    • 35348977596 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Since one important interpersonal wrong that Scanlon's weaker principles explain is the wrong of disappointing assurance, and since assurance can only be created on my account by invoking the social practice of promising, my view is a genuine hybrid view after all (contrary to the objection raised in note 35). It is not just that two sets of obligations arise in parallel. Rather, there is one obligation in particular, the obligation not to disappoint assurance, that is governed by Principle L, but which can only arise given that there is a mechanism for creating assurance in the first place. Thismechanism can only be the social practice of promising.
    • Since one important interpersonal wrong that Scanlon's weaker principles explain is the wrong of disappointing assurance, and since assurance can only be created on my account by invoking the social practice of promising, my view is a genuine hybrid view after all (contrary to the objection raised in note 35). It is not just that two sets of obligations arise in parallel. Rather, there is one obligation in particular, the obligation not to disappoint assurance, that is governed by Principle L, but which can only arise given that there is a mechanism for creating assurance in the first place. Thismechanism can only be the social practice of promising.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.