메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 26, Issue 6, 2007, Pages 531-574

Promises, contracts and voluntary obligations

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 34548772443     PISSN: 01675249     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1007/s10982-006-9003-1     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (22)

References (146)
  • 1
    • 34548810644 scopus 로고
    • Promises in Morality and Law
    • See, e.g
    • See, e.g., Raz, Joseph, 'Promises in Morality and Law', Harvard Law Review 95 (1982): 916.
    • (1982) Harvard Law Review , vol.95 , pp. 916
    • Raz, J.1
  • 2
    • 0009364321 scopus 로고
    • Is an Agreement an Exchange of Promises?
    • For the view that agreements are different in kind from promise-exchanges, see
    • For the view that agreements are different in kind from promise-exchanges, see Gilbert, Margaret, 'Is an Agreement an Exchange of Promises?', J. Philosophy 90 (1993): 627
    • (1993) J. Philosophy , vol.90 , pp. 627
    • Gilbert, M.1
  • 3
    • 34548759443 scopus 로고
    • Are Contracts Promises?
    • Eekelaar J. and Bell J, eds, Clarendon
    • and De Moor, Ann, 'Are Contracts Promises?', in Eekelaar J. and Bell J. (eds.), Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence (Clarendon, 1987), p. 103.
    • (1987) Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence , pp. 103
    • De Moor, A.1
  • 4
    • 34548776246 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The traditional and still orthodox view of the nature of contractual obligations is that they are self-imposed promissory obligations
    • Smith, Stephen, Clarendon, Emphasis in original
    • 'The traditional and still orthodox view of the nature of contractual obligations is that they are self-imposed promissory obligations.' Smith, Stephen, Contract Theory (Clarendon, 2004), p. 56. (Emphasis in original.)
    • (2004) Contract Theory , pp. 56
  • 5
    • 34548746174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When contractual liability is described by jurists as 'promissory,' it is the justificatory sense that is almost always intended. As Smith writes, the 'promissory' label 'emphasizes that contractual obligations are obligations that are created by the parties -that they are, in other words, voluntary or self-imposed obligations.' Ibid.
    • When contractual liability is described by jurists as 'promissory,' it is the justificatory sense that is almost always intended. As Smith writes, the 'promissory' label 'emphasizes that contractual obligations are obligations that are created by the parties -that they are, in other words, " voluntary" or "self-imposed" obligations.' Ibid.
  • 6
    • 34548753790 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A recent search in the Philosopher's Index turned up 237 entries with 'promise' or one of its derivatives listed as a subject. Eddie, Yeghiayan's 1981 bibliography on promises runs to 37 pages: 'Promises: A Bibliography', Philosophical Research Archives 7 (1981): 1054.
    • A recent search in the Philosopher's Index turned up 237 entries with 'promise' or one of its derivatives listed as a subject. Eddie, Yeghiayan's 1981 bibliography on promises runs to 37 pages: 'Promises: A Bibliography', Philosophical Research Archives 7 (1981): 1054.
  • 7
    • 34548771001 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This school takes its name from the title of Charles Fried's well-known 1981 monograph. As a description of its theoretical stance, however, the name is ambiguous between the two ways in which, as I pointed out earlier, contractual liability can be promissory. Most contract-as-promise scholars see contractual liability as promissory in a formal sense, but the school of thought is defined by its view that contractual liability is promissory in a justificatory sense
    • This school takes its name from the title of Charles Fried's well-known 1981 monograph. As a description of its theoretical stance, however, the name is ambiguous between the two ways in which, as I pointed out earlier, contractual liability can be promissory. Most contract-as-promise scholars see contractual liability as promissory in a formal sense, but the school of thought is defined by its view that contractual liability is promissory in a justificatory sense.
  • 8
    • 34548739996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Charles Fried's is the best-known moralistic theory of contract. The central thesis of his now classic work, Contract as Promise, is that 'since a contract is first of all a promise,
    • Charles Fried's is the best-known moralistic theory of contract. The central thesis of his now classic work, Contract as Promise, is that 'since a contract is first of all a promise,
  • 9
    • 34548769875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • the contract must be kept because a promise must be kept.' Contract as Promise (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University-Press, 1981), p. 17.
    • the contract must be kept because a promise must be kept.' Contract as Promise (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University-Press, 1981), p. 17.
  • 10
    • 34548747866 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As to why promises ought to be kept, Fried invokes the 'promise principle, whereby] persons may impose on themselves obligations where none existed before, at
    • As to why promises ought to be kept, Fried invokes the 'promise principle, [whereby] persons may impose on themselves obligations where none existed before.' Ibid, at 2.
    • Ibid , pp. 2
  • 11
    • 34548769103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an insightful criticism of Fried's account of promise, see Kimel, Dori, From Promise to Contract: Towards a Liberal Theory of Contract (Oxford: Hart, 2002), p. 8. Stephen Smith has recently proposed a different moralistic account of contract as promise. 1 discuss his theory of promise later in the paper.
    • For an insightful criticism of Fried's account of promise, see Kimel, Dori, From Promise to Contract: Towards a Liberal Theory of Contract (Oxford: Hart, 2002), p. 8. Stephen Smith has recently proposed a different moralistic account of contract as promise. 1 discuss his theory of promise later in the paper.
  • 12
    • 34548711645 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • H.L.A. Hart wrote that the duties that attach to an office or role in social life, such as the duty of a husband to his wife or of a father to his child, are 'assumed by entry upon the particular role...' 'Legal and Moral Obligation', in A.I. Melden (ed.), Essays in Moral Philosophy (Seattle: University of Washington Press, 1958), p. 82 at 103-104.
    • H.L.A. Hart wrote that the duties that attach to an office or role in social life, such as the duty of a husband to his wife or of a father to his child, are 'assumed by entry upon the particular role...' 'Legal and Moral Obligation', in A.I. Melden (ed.), Essays in Moral Philosophy (Seattle: University of Washington Press, 1958), p. 82 at 103-104.
  • 13
    • 0000982081 scopus 로고
    • Are There Any Natural Rights?
    • See also, at
    • See also Hart, H.L.A., 'Are There Any Natural Rights?', Philosophical Review 64 (1955): 175 at 183.
    • (1955) Philosophical Review , vol.64 , Issue.175 , pp. 183
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 15
    • 34548775529 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz, Joseph, 'Voluntary Obligations and Normative Powers', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 46(supp.) (1972): 79 at 97. (Emphasis added.) Elsewhere Raz provides an example of someone relocating to a town that levies a local tax on all residents. Taking up residence in the town is avoidable behavior, and anyone who moves there will (let us suppose) be aware of the tax. But on the voluntarist view the tax obligations that 1 assume by taking up residence in the town arenot voluntary, certainly not in the sense that the obligation of a promise is voluntary.
    • Raz, Joseph, 'Voluntary Obligations and Normative Powers', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 46(supp.) (1972): 79 at 97. (Emphasis added.) Elsewhere Raz provides an example of someone relocating to a town that levies a local tax on all residents. Taking up residence in the town is avoidable behavior, and anyone who moves there will (let us suppose) be aware of the tax. But on the voluntarist view the tax obligations that 1 assume by taking up residence in the town arenot voluntary, certainly not in the sense that the obligation of a promise is voluntary.
  • 16
    • 34548720181 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Raz, (1982, p. 929).
    • See Raz, (1982, p. 929).
  • 17
    • 3142738942 scopus 로고
    • D.M. Walker ed, Edinburgh: University of Edinburgh Press
    • Dalrymple, James, 'The Institutions of the Law of Scotland', in D.M. Walker (ed.) (Edinburgh: University of Edinburgh Press, 1981), p. 100.
    • (1981) The Institutions of the Law of Scotland , pp. 100
    • Dalrymple, J.1
  • 18
    • 34548766409 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dalrymple 1981, p. 195, 197
    • Dalrymple (1981, p. 195, 197)
  • 19
    • 34548720771 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart (1958, p. 103). Hume wrote that the obligation of a promise 'arises from our mere will and pleasure.' Hume, David, A Treatise of Human Nature, in D. Norton and M. Norton (eds.) (Oxford: OUP, 2000), p. 332.
    • Hart (1958, p. 103). Hume wrote that the obligation of a promise 'arises from our mere will and pleasure.' Hume, David, A Treatise of Human Nature, in D. Norton and M. Norton (eds.) (Oxford: OUP, 2000), p. 332.
  • 20
    • 0347669677 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A contracting party's choice to bind herself is, as Gillian Hadfield observes, traditionally understood to be of 'constitutive' importance to her liability, since the 'very obligations that an individual is under in contract are [thought to be] a product of that individual's choice.' 'An Expressive Theory of Contract: From Feminist Dilemmas to a Reconceptualization of Rational Choice in Contract', university of Pennsylvania Law Review 146 (1998): 1235 at 1236.
    • A contracting party's choice to bind herself is, as Gillian Hadfield observes, traditionally understood to be of 'constitutive' importance to her liability, since the 'very obligations that an individual is under in contract are [thought to be] a product of that individual's choice.' 'An Expressive Theory of Contract: From Feminist Dilemmas to a Reconceptualization of Rational Choice in Contract', university of Pennsylvania Law Review 146 (1998): 1235 at 1236.
  • 21
    • 34548746712 scopus 로고
    • Cough's remark in Henderson v. Merret Syndicates Ltd
    • Judicial references to the will of the parties as the source of contractual obligations abound. See, e.g, AC 145 while tortious duties are 'imposed by the general law, contractual duties are 'attributable to the will of the parties
    • Judicial references to the will of the parties as the source of contractual obligations abound. See, e.g., Lord Cough's remark in Henderson v. Merret Syndicates Ltd. [1995] 2 AC 145 at 194 that while tortious duties are 'imposed by the general law, contractual duties are 'attributable to the will of the parties.'
    • (1995) at 194 that , vol.2
    • Lord1
  • 22
    • 34548808950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz 1982, p. 930
    • Raz (1982, p. 930)
  • 23
    • 0004237063 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On the concept of normative and legal powers generally, see, Oxford: OUP
    • On the concept of normative and legal powers generally, see Raz, Joseph, Practical Reason and Norms (Oxford: OUP, 1999), pp. 97-106;
    • (1999) Practical Reason and Norms , pp. 97-106
    • Raz, J.1
  • 26
    • 34548791562 scopus 로고
    • Bentham on Legal Powers
    • Hart, H.L.A., 'Bentham on Legal Powers' Yale Law Journal 81 (1972): 799.
    • (1972) Yale Law Journal , vol.81 , pp. 799
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 27
    • 5344243534 scopus 로고
    • Intention and Purpose in Law
    • R.S. Summers ed, Berkeley: University of California Press
    • Kenny, Anthony, 'Intention and Purpose in Law', in R.S. Summers (ed.), Essays in Legal Philosophy (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1968), p. 146.
    • (1968) Essays in Legal Philosophy , pp. 146
    • Kenny, A.1
  • 28
    • 34548777932 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kenny 1968, p. 150
    • Kenny (1968, p. 150).
  • 30
    • 34548761764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz 1999, p. 103
    • Raz (1999, p. 103).
  • 31
    • 34548720178 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Andrew Halpin provides a nice discussion of this point. See
    • Andrew Halpin provides a nice discussion of this point. See Halpin (1996, pp. 142-143).
    • (1996) , pp. 142-143
    • Halpin1
  • 32
    • 34548762307 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart 1958, pp. 101-103
    • Hart (1958, pp. 101-103).
  • 33
    • 84864557594 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reasoning with Rules
    • See, at
    • See Raz, Joseph, 'Reasoning with Rules', Current Legal Problems 54 (2001): 1 at 3ff.
    • (2001) Current Legal Problems , vol.54 , Issue.1
    • Raz, J.1
  • 34
    • 34548728386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz 1999, p. 102
    • Raz (1999, p. 102).
  • 35
    • 34548739992 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Obligation' derives from the Latin ob, 'towards,' and ligare, 'to bind.'
    • 'Obligation' derives from the Latin ob, 'towards,' and ligare, 'to bind.'
  • 37
    • 34548735805 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon
    • Butler, Samuel, Hudibras (Oxford: Clarendon, 1967), p. 130.
    • (1967) Hudibras , pp. 130
    • Butler, S.1
  • 38
    • 34548775530 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • He continued: 'Too feeble implements to bind;/And hold with deeds proportion, so/As shadows to a substance do.' Cf. Troilus's remark in Shakespeare's The History of Troilus and Cressida (Act v. Scene III): 'Words, words, mere words, no matter from the heart.'
    • He continued: 'Too feeble implements to bind;/And hold with deeds proportion, so/As shadows to a substance do.' Cf. Troilus's remark in Shakespeare's The History of Troilus and Cressida (Act v. Scene III): 'Words, words, mere words, no matter from the heart.'
  • 39
    • 34548760621 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hume 1999, p. 336
    • Hume (1999, p. 336).
  • 40
    • 34548787067 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hume 1999, p. 336
    • Hume (1999, p. 336).
  • 41
    • 34548721354 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hume 1999, p. 332
    • Hume (1999, p. 332).
  • 42
    • 34548734552 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A promise, therefore, is naturally something altogether unintelligible
    • 'A promise, therefore, is naturally something altogether unintelligible.' Ibid.
    • Ibid
  • 43
    • 34548773774 scopus 로고
    • Promises, Promises, Promises
    • For a full account of Hume's theory of promise, see, A. Baier ed, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
    • For a full account of Hume's theory of promise, see Baier, Annette, 'Promises, Promises, Promises', in A. Baier (ed.), Postures of the Mind (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1985), p. 174.
    • (1985) Postures of the Mind , pp. 174
    • Baier, A.1
  • 44
    • 34548737484 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It was one of the central points of dispute between Joseph Raz and Neil MacCormick in their well-known exchange in 1972, which I discuss below. See text accompanying note 67
    • It was one of the central points of dispute between Joseph Raz and Neil MacCormick in their well-known exchange in 1972, which I discuss below. See text accompanying note 67.
  • 45
    • 34548708320 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon's essay on promising first appeared in Philosophy & Public Affairs in 1991, but its influence escalated markedly after its reappearance (with minor changes) seven years later as a chapter in his book, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991), pp. 295-327.
    • Scanlon's essay on promising first appeared in Philosophy & Public Affairs in 1991, but its influence escalated markedly after its reappearance (with minor changes) seven years later as a chapter in his book, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991), pp. 295-327.
  • 46
    • 84909336834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Promises and Perlocutions
    • For some responses to Scanlon, see, M. Matravers ed, London: Frank Cass
    • For some responses to Scanlon, see Pratt, Michael, 'Promises and Perlocutions', in M. Matravers (ed.), Scanlon and Contractualism (London: Frank Cass, 2003), p. 93;
    • (2003) Scanlon and Contractualism , pp. 93
    • Pratt, M.1
  • 47
    • 34548788321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Contractualist Account of Promising
    • Cholbi, Michael, 'A Contractualist Account of Promising', Southern Journal of Philosophy 40 (2002): 475;
    • (2002) Southern Journal of Philosophy , vol.40 , pp. 475
    • Cholbi, M.1
  • 48
    • 10744224006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Promises Under Fire
    • Deigh, John, 'Promises Under Fire', Ethics 112 (2002): 483;
    • (2002) Ethics , vol.112 , pp. 483
    • Deigh, J.1
  • 50
    • 33744540383 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Scanlon on Promissory Obligation: The Problem of Promisee's Rights
    • Gilbert, Margaret, 'Scanlon on Promissory Obligation: The Problem of Promisee's Rights', Journal of Philosophy, 2004 (101): p. 83.
    • (2004) Journal of Philosophy , vol.101 , pp. 83
    • Gilbert, M.1
  • 51
    • 10744232200 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reasons, Responsibility, and Reliance: Replies to Wallace, Dworkin, and Deigh
    • See also, 112 2002, 507
    • (See also Scanlon, Thomas, 'Reasons, Responsibility, and Reliance: Replies to Wallace, Dworkin, and Deigh', Ethics 112 (2002): 507.)
    • Ethics
    • Scanlon, T.1
  • 52
    • 34548783655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Michael Stocker illustrates the relationship between natural facts and moral obligations by considering the role played by the natural fact of Jones having typhoid in Smith's having a moral duty to rid Jones of typhoid. For Smith to have this moral obligation Jones must have typhoid, Nonetheless, Jones having) typhoid is not morally relevant, except in regard to its effects, e.g, suffering and death. Typhoid itself, does not create, ground, or explain Smith's moral obligation, even though typhoid figures in its description and even though the obligation presupposes the existence of typhoid, Stocker, Michael, Moral Duties, Institutional, and Natural Facts, Monist, 54 1970, 602 at 607
    • Michael Stocker illustrates the relationship between natural facts and moral obligations by considering the role played by the natural fact of Jones having typhoid in Smith's having a moral duty to rid Jones of typhoid. For Smith to have this moral obligation Jones must have typhoid. 'Nonetheless, (Jones having) typhoid is not morally relevant - except in regard to its effects, e.g., suffering and death. Typhoid itself, does not create, ground, or explain Smith's moral obligation, even though "typhoid" figures in its description and even though the obligation presupposes the existence of typhoid.' Stocker, Michael, 'Moral Duties, Institutional, and Natural Facts', Monist, 54 (1970): 602 at 607.
  • 53
    • 0002921553 scopus 로고
    • Two Concepts of Rules
    • The influence of this paper is manifest in John Searle's speech act analysis of promising
    • Rawls, John, 'Two Concepts of Rules', Philosophical Review 64 (1955): 3. The influence of this paper is manifest in John Searle's speech act analysis of promising.
    • (1955) Philosophical Review , vol.64 , pp. 3
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 54
    • 34548707769 scopus 로고
    • See
    • See Searle (1969, pp. 33-42; 54-61).
    • (1969)
    • Searle1
  • 55
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), pp. 342-350.
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice , pp. 342-350
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 56
    • 34548716758 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls 1971, p. 347
    • Rawls (1971, p. 347).
  • 57
    • 34548772170 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'While we normally think of moral requirements as bonds laid upon us,' writes Rawls, 'they are sometimes deliberately self-imposed for our advantage. Thus promising is an act done with the public intention of deliberately incurring an obligation the existence of which in the circumstances will further one's ends.' Rawls (1971, p. 347).
    • 'While we normally think of moral requirements as bonds laid upon us,' writes Rawls, 'they are sometimes deliberately self-imposed for our advantage. Thus promising is an act done with the public intention of deliberately incurring an obligation the existence of which in the circumstances will further one's ends.' Rawls (1971, p. 347).
  • 58
    • 34548802798 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls 1971, p. 345
    • Rawls (1971, p. 345).
  • 59
    • 34548754859 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls 1971, p. 344
    • Rawls (1971, p. 344).
  • 60
    • 34548717425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls 1971, p. 113
    • Rawls (1971, p. 113).
  • 61
    • 34548729517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls 1955, p. 3
    • Rawls (1955, p. 3).
  • 62
    • 34548778957 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Rawls (1955, p. 3)
    • See Rawls (1955, p. 3)
  • 63
    • 34548724283 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Searle (1969, pp. 33-42).
    • and Searle (1969, pp. 33-42).
  • 64
    • 34548705208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Searle 1969, p. 33-34
    • Searle (1969, p. 33-34).
  • 65
    • 34548774922 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls 1955, p. 30
    • Rawls (1955, p. 30).
  • 66
    • 34548785382 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls 1955, p. 30
    • Rawls (1955, p. 30).
  • 67
    • 34548738025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart 1958, p. 101
    • Hart (1958, p. 101).
  • 68
    • 34548777931 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls (1971, p. 348). 'It is essential...to distinguish between the rule of promising and the principle of fidelity. The rule is simply a constitutive convention, whereas the principle of fidelity is a moral principle.'
    • Rawls (1971, p. 348). 'It is essential...to distinguish between the rule of promising and the principle of fidelity. The rule is simply a constitutive convention, whereas the principle of fidelity is a moral principle.'
  • 69
    • 34548754858 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Ibid, at 346.
  • 70
    • 34548807870 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That is, in the hypothetical situation in which people 'who engage in social cooperation choose together, in one joint act, the principles which are to assign basic rights and duties to determine the division of social benefits.' Rawls (1971, p. 11).
    • That is, in the hypothetical situation in which people 'who engage in social cooperation choose together, in one joint act, the principles which are to assign basic rights and duties to determine the division of social benefits.' Rawls (1971, p. 11).
  • 71
    • 34548713953 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls (1971, p. 342-343). Here Rawls draws on HLA Hart, who was the first to put the idea of fairness or fair play into the form of a principle: 'When a number of persons conduct any joint enterprise according to rules and thus restrict their liberty, those who have submitted to these restrictions when required have a right to a similar submission by those who have benefited by their submission,'
    • Rawls (1971, p. 342-343). Here Rawls draws on HLA Hart, who was the first to put the idea of fairness or fair play into the form of a principle: 'When a number of persons conduct any joint enterprise according to rules and thus restrict their liberty, those who have submitted to these restrictions when required have a right to a similar submission by those who have benefited by their submission,'
  • 72
    • 34548721353 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart 1958, p. 185
    • Hart (1958, p. 185).
  • 73
    • 34548773776 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls 1971, p. 112
    • Rawls (1971, p. 112).
  • 74
    • 34548781160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls 1971, p. 344
    • Rawls (1971, p. 344).
  • 75
    • 34548786534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls 1971, p. 345
    • Rawls (1971, p. 345).
  • 76
    • 34548771599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls 1971, p. 345
    • Rawls (1971, p. 345).
  • 77
    • 84959780002 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Robins, Michael, 'Promissory Obligations and Rawls's Contractarianism' Analysis 36 (1976): 190 at 193. Cf. A.I. Melden's observation that no 'mutually advantageous exchange of benefits need be involved even in central cases of promises, for that would represent every case of a promise made out of consideration or kindness or compassion for another as a calculating estimate of the profits and losses involved in the transaction.'
    • Robins, Michael, 'Promissory Obligations and Rawls's Contractarianism' Analysis 36 (1976): 190 at 193. Cf. A.I. Melden's observation that no 'mutually advantageous exchange of benefits need be involved even in central cases of promises, for that would represent every case of a promise made out of consideration or kindness or compassion for another as a calculating estimate of the profits and losses involved in the transaction.'
  • 78
    • 0009463691 scopus 로고
    • Los Angeles: University of California Press
    • Melden, A.I., Rights and Persons (Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1980), p. 94.
    • (1980) Rights and Persons , pp. 94
    • Melden, A.I.1
  • 79
    • 34548731136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls 1971, p. 345
    • Rawls (1971, p. 345).
  • 80
    • 34548718019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It follows that there are no real exceptions to the rules of the practice at all: 'An exception is rather a qualification or a further specification of the rule.'Rawls (1955, p. 27).
    • It follows that there are no real exceptions to the rules of the practice at all: 'An exception is rather a qualification or a further specification of the rule.'Rawls (1955, p. 27).
  • 81
    • 34548792159 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls 1955, p. 27
    • Rawls (1955, p. 27).
  • 82
    • 34548735113 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'When a man engaged in a practice is queried about his action he must assume that the questioner either doesn't know that he is engaged in it (Why are you in a hurry to pay him? I promised to pay him today) or doesn't know what the practice is. One doesn't so much justify one's particular action as explain, or show, that it is in accordance with the practice. The reason for this is that it is only against the stage-setting of the practice that one's particular action is described as it is. Only by reference to the practice can one say what one is doing.' Rawls (1955, p. 27).
    • 'When a man engaged in a practice is queried about his action he must assume that the questioner either doesn't know that he is engaged in it ("Why are you in a hurry to pay him?" "I promised to pay him today") or doesn't know what the practice is. One doesn't so much justify one's particular action as explain, or show, that it is in accordance with the practice. The reason for this is that it is only against the stage-setting of the practice that one's particular action is described as it is. Only by reference to the practice can one say what one is doing.' Rawls (1955, p. 27).
  • 83
    • 34548750748 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls 1955, p. 17
    • Rawls (1955, p. 17).
  • 85
    • 84927020422 scopus 로고
    • Three Accounts of Promising
    • R.S. Downie refers to Hume's as a 'jurisprudentiar account of promising. See, at
    • R.S. Downie refers to Hume's as a 'jurisprudentiar account of promising. See Downie, R.S., 'Three Accounts of Promising', Philosophical Quarterly 35 (1985): 259 at 258-263.
    • (1985) Philosophical Quarterly , vol.35 , Issue.259 , pp. 258-263
    • Downie, R.S.1
  • 86
    • 0003529325 scopus 로고
    • I am thinking in particular of Raz, Hart and Finnis see Finnis, John, Oxford: Clarendon
    • I am thinking in particular of Raz, Hart and Finnis (see Finnis, John, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Clarendon, 1980), pp. 298-308.
    • (1980) Natural Law and Natural Rights , pp. 298-308
  • 87
    • 34548725376 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pratt 2003
    • Pratt (2003).
  • 88
    • 34548778959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rawls 1971, p. 112
    • Rawls (1971, p. 112).
  • 89
    • 34548719665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Melden 1980, p. 89-90
    • Melden (1980, p. 89-90).
  • 90
    • 34548757728 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Scanlon (1991, p. 316)
    • See also Scanlon (1991, p. 316)
  • 91
    • 34548779520 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Kolodny and Wallace (2003, p. 125).
    • (2003) , pp. 125
    • Kolodny1    Wallace2
  • 92
    • 34548763623 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Melden 1980, p. 90
    • Melden (1980, p. 90).
  • 93
    • 34548757052 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Melden 1980, p. 90
    • Melden (1980, p. 90).
  • 94
    • 34548789941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Raz (1972, p. 79);
    • See Raz (1972, p. 79);
  • 95
    • 0043240610 scopus 로고
    • Voluntary Obligations and Normative Powers F
    • MacCormick, Neil, 'Voluntary Obligations and Normative Powers F, Proc. of the Aristotelian Soc., supp. vol. 46 (1972): 59.
    • (1972) Proc. of the Aristotelian Soc , vol.46 , Issue.SUPP. , pp. 59
    • MacCormick, N.1
  • 96
    • 34548761208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MacCormick later republished his paper, with some minor revisions, as MacCormick, Neil, 'Voluntary Obligations', in MacCormick, N., Legal Rights and Social Democracy: Essays in Legal and Political Philosophy, (Clarendon, 1982), p. 190.
    • MacCormick later republished his paper, with some minor revisions, as MacCormick, Neil, 'Voluntary Obligations', in MacCormick, N., Legal Rights and Social Democracy: Essays in Legal and Political Philosophy, (Clarendon, 1982), p. 190.
  • 97
    • 34548707463 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz 1972, p. 97
    • Raz (1972, p. 97).
  • 98
    • 0039678166 scopus 로고
    • Promises and Obligations
    • See, P.M.S. Hacker and J. Raz eds, Oxford: Clarendon
    • See Raz, Joseph, 'Promises and Obligations', in P.M.S. Hacker and J. Raz (eds.), Law, Morality and Society: Essays in Honour of HLA Hart (Oxford: Clarendon, 1977), p. 210;
    • (1977) Law, Morality and Society: Essays in Honour of HLA Hart , pp. 210
    • Raz, J.1
  • 99
    • 34548767486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz (1982);
    • Raz (1982);
  • 100
    • 34548730071 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz, Joseph, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon, 1988), pp. 173-176. Stephen Smith has for example recently published a full-blown theory of contract law in which he argues that the state's enforcement of promises can be justified on the basis of a Razian theory of promissory obligation. Smith (2004). I discuss Smith's theory of promise below. Raz's account of promising is also central to Dori Kimel's recent study of the relationship between contract and promise.
    • Raz, Joseph, The Morality of Freedom (Oxford: Clarendon, 1988), pp. 173-176. Stephen Smith has for example recently published a full-blown theory of contract law in which he argues that the state's enforcement of promises can be justified on the basis of a Razian theory of promissory obligation. Smith (2004). I discuss Smith's theory of promise below. Raz's account of promising is also central to Dori Kimel's recent study of the relationship between contract and promise.
  • 101
    • 34548754270 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kimel 2002
    • See Kimel (2002).
  • 102
    • 84860435618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also, Oxford: Hart
    • See also Spence, Michael, Protecting Reliance (Oxford: Hart, 1999), pp. 4-9
    • (1999) Protecting Reliance , pp. 4-9
    • Spence, M.1
  • 103
    • 84920725554 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Penner, James, 'Voluntary Obligations and the Scope of the Law of Contract', Legal Theory 2 (1996): 325. I am aware of no sustained criticism of Raz's account of promise, though his views on practical reason and normative powers (which bear strongly on his understanding of promising) have been the subject of a good deal of discussion in the literature.
    • and Penner, James, 'Voluntary Obligations and the Scope of the Law of Contract', Legal Theory 2 (1996): 325. I am aware of no sustained criticism of Raz's account of promise, though his views on practical reason and normative powers (which bear strongly on his understanding of promising) have been the subject of a good deal of discussion in the literature.
  • 104
    • 34548782017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz 1977, p. 217
    • Raz (1977, p. 217).
  • 105
    • 34548785383 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz may have been alluding to Hume when he wrote that promises do not create obligations 'by any form of magic,' their bindingness being due instead to a norm 'to the effect that if one communicates an intention to undertake, by that communication, an obligation to φ, then one has an obligation to φ, provided some further conditions are met.' Raz (1977, p. 218-219).
    • Raz may have been alluding to Hume when he wrote that promises do not create obligations 'by any form of magic,' their bindingness being due instead to a norm 'to the effect that if one communicates an intention to undertake, by that communication, an obligation to φ, then one has an obligation to φ, provided some further conditions are met.' Raz (1977, p. 218-219).
  • 106
    • 34548710069 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Raz (1972, pp. 96-97).
    • See Raz (1972, pp. 96-97).
  • 107
    • 34548729518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz 1972, p. 98
    • Raz (1972, p. 98).
  • 108
    • 34548758878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Raz (1982, p. 219).
    • Cf. Raz (1982, p. 219).
  • 109
    • 34548765317 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz 2001, p. 12
    • Raz (2001, p. 12).
  • 110
    • 34548781694 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz 2001, p. 12
    • Raz (2001, p. 12).
  • 111
    • 34548724284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz 1977, p. 221
    • Raz (1977, p. 221).
  • 112
    • 34548763621 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Exclusionary reasons belong to the class of 'secondary' reasons, a secondary reason being a 'reason to act for a reason or to refrain from acting for a reason.' Raz (1999, p. 39).
    • Exclusionary reasons belong to the class of 'secondary' reasons, a secondary reason being a 'reason to act for a reason or to refrain from acting for a reason.' Raz (1999, p. 39).
  • 113
    • 34548768592 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz discusses exclusionary reasons at length in Raz (1999, pp. 5-48).
    • Raz discusses exclusionary reasons at length in Raz (1999, pp. 5-48).
  • 114
    • 34548742694 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz 2001, p. 15
    • Raz (2001, p. 15).
  • 115
    • 34548746172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz 1977, p. 228
    • Raz (1977, p. 228).
  • 116
    • 34548802260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Raz (1977, p. 227).
    • See Raz (1977, p. 227).
  • 117
    • 34548774923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz 1977, p. 227, 228
    • Raz (1977, p. 227, 228).
  • 118
    • 34548744997 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Raz (1977, p. 228). James Penner, an adherent of Razian non-conventionalist voluntarism, elaborates on the nature and importance of these special bonds in Penner (1996, p. 325). For a non-Razian, contractualist argument that the value of promises lies in the value of the relationships they acknowledge and strengthen,
    • See Raz (1977, p. 228). James Penner, an adherent of Razian non-conventionalist voluntarism, elaborates on the nature and importance of these special bonds in Penner (1996, p. 325). For a non-Razian, contractualist argument that the value of promises lies in the value of the relationships they acknowledge and strengthen,
  • 119
    • 34548786533 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Cholbi 2002
    • see Cholbi (2002).
  • 120
    • 34250110449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In fact, I suspect that the concept of an exclusionary reason is unstable, but since others have put this case well, and since Raz employs the concept generally and not just in his characterization of promissory reasons, I will not take issue with it here. See Gans, Chaim, Mandatory Rules and Exclusionary Reasons, Philosophia 15 1986, 373
    • In fact, I suspect that the concept of an exclusionary reason is unstable, but since others have put this case well, and since Raz employs the concept generally and not just in his characterization of promissory reasons, I will not take issue with it here. See Gans, Chaim, 'Mandatory Rules and Exclusionary Reasons', Philosophia 15 (1986): 373
  • 121
    • 0009419105 scopus 로고
    • Authority, Law, and Razian Reasons
    • and Moore, Michael, 'Authority, Law, and Razian Reasons', Southern California Law Review 62 (1989): 827.
    • (1989) Southern California Law Review , vol.62 , pp. 827
    • Moore, M.1
  • 122
    • 34548760622 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Elsewhere Raz writes that 'promises are binding because it is desirable to make it possible for people to bind themselves and give rights to others if they so wish.' Raz (1972, p. 101). If by 'binding' Raz means 'morally binding' then, again, the objection is manifest: that it is desirable does not make it so.
    • Elsewhere Raz writes that 'promises are binding because it is desirable to make it possible for people to bind themselves and give rights to others if they so wish.' Raz (1972, p. 101). If by 'binding' Raz means 'morally binding' then, again, the objection is manifest: that it is desirable does not make it so.
  • 123
    • 79951923813 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Performance, Punishment and the Nature of Contractual Obligation
    • Smith, Stephen, 'Performance, Punishment and the Nature of Contractual Obligation', Modern Law Review 60 (1997): 35;
    • (1997) Modern Law Review , vol.60 , pp. 35
    • Smith, S.1
  • 124
    • 34548710068 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Towards a Theory of Contract
    • J. Horder ed, Oxford: OUP
    • Smith, Stephen, 'Towards a Theory of Contract', in J. Horder (ed.), Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence, (Oxford: OUP, 2000), p. 107;
    • (2000) Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence , pp. 107
    • Smith, S.1
  • 125
    • 34548789367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Reliance Interest in Contract Damages and the Morality of Contract Law
    • Smith
    • and Smith, Stephen, '"The Reliance Interest in Contract Damages" and the Morality of Contract Law',Issues in Legal Scholarship 1 (2001); Smith (2004).
    • (2001) Issues in Legal Scholarship , pp. 1
    • Smith, S.1
  • 126
    • 34548741110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Raz (1982, pp. 933-938).
    • See Raz (1982, pp. 933-938).
  • 127
    • 34548802796 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith 1997, p. 369
    • Smith (1997, p. 369).
  • 128
    • 34548770999 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cf. Fried (1981, p. 17.) Elsewhere Smith qualifies this by indicating that contracts might be agreements.
    • (Cf. Fried (1981, p. 17.) Elsewhere Smith qualifies this by indicating that contracts might be agreements.
  • 129
    • 34548735806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Smith (2004, pp. 56-57).
    • See Smith (2004, pp. 56-57).
  • 130
    • 34548720770 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith 2001, p. 30
    • Smith (2001, p. 30).
  • 131
    • 34548806815 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith 2004, p. 74
    • Smith (2004, p. 74).
  • 132
    • 34548704664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith 2004, p. 74
    • Smith (2004, p. 74).
  • 133
    • 34548755947 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith 2000, p. 128
    • Smith (2000, p. 128).
  • 134
    • 34548791561 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith 2004, p. 74
    • Smith (2004, p. 74).
  • 135
    • 34548733471 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Emphasis in original
    • Smith (2000, p. 128). (Emphasis in original.)
    • (2000) , pp. 128
    • Smith1
  • 136
    • 34548768044 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Smith 2004, p. 138
    • Smith (2004, p. 138).
  • 137
    • 34548794623 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Emphasis added
    • Smith (1997, p. 369). (Emphasis added.)
    • (1997) , pp. 369
    • Smith1
  • 138
    • 34548778958 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Emphasis added
    • Smith (2004, p. 74). (Emphasis added.)
    • (2004) , pp. 74
    • Smith1
  • 139
    • 34548738808 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz may object that he makes it clear that promises are not merely exclusionary reasons. Promises, like all sources of exclusionary reasons, also provide positive reasons for acting: 'The fact that it is a valid rule that one ought to φ, is both a reason for φ-ing and a reason for not acting for certain reasons for not (φ-ing. In so far as the rule is a reason for (φ-ing it merely relays the force of the reasons for (φ-ing on which it is based.' Raz (1999, p. 221). Raz uses the term 'protected reason' to describe the kind of reason for acting that is supplied by a valid rule that one ought to φ.
    • Raz may object that he makes it clear that promises are not merely exclusionary reasons. Promises, like all sources of exclusionary reasons, also provide positive reasons for acting: 'The fact that it is a valid rule that one ought to φ, is both a reason for φ-ing and a reason for not acting for certain reasons for not (φ-ing. In so far as the rule is a reason for (φ-ing it merely relays the force of the reasons for (φ-ing on which it is based.' Raz (1999, p. 221). Raz uses the term 'protected reason' to describe the kind of reason for acting that is supplied by a valid rule that one ought to φ.
  • 140
    • 34548705775 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Raz 2001, p. 15). It is protected in the sense that it enters into practical reasoning almost alone, most of the reasons for not (φ-ing having been excluded from consideration by the rule that one must (φ. A promise to (φ, therefore, is a protected reason for the promisor for φ-ing. But what reason is it? Presumably it is the fact that the promisee has a claim on the promisor to φ. But whence this claim? Again, Raz provides no answer.
    • (Raz 2001, p. 15). It is protected in the sense that it enters into practical reasoning almost alone, most of the reasons for not (φ-ing having been excluded from consideration by the rule that one must (φ. A promise to (φ, therefore, is a protected reason for the promisor for (φ-ing. But what reason is it? Presumably it is the fact that the promisee has a claim on the promisor to φ. But whence this claim? Again, Raz provides no answer.
  • 141
    • 34548719663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz 1977, p. 228
    • Raz (1977, p. 228).
  • 142
    • 34548786530 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the paragraph accompanying note 84, above
    • See the paragraph accompanying note 84, above.
  • 143
    • 84886888447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Remedial Rights and Substantive Rights in Contract Law
    • at
    • Kimel, Dori, 'Remedial Rights and Substantive Rights in Contract Law', Legal Theory 8 (2002): 313 at 326.
    • (2002) Legal Theory , vol.8 , Issue.313 , pp. 326
    • Kimel, D.1
  • 144
    • 34548792158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I make no case for the claim here, but I doubt that there exists anything like a settled practice of promising capable of affording a facility by which to resolve the sort of coordination problems Hume and Rawls supposed it to resolve, The Humean and Rawlsian practices of promising bear an almost uncanny resemblance to the rules of contract, Regardless, even if there does exist such a practice, I have argued that the moral obligation of a promise cannot be validly justified in terms of a power-conferring norm embedded in a social practice of promising
    • I make no case for the claim here, but I doubt that there exists anything like a settled practice of promising capable of affording a facility by which to resolve the sort of coordination problems Hume and Rawls supposed it to resolve. (The Humean and Rawlsian practices of promising bear an almost uncanny resemblance to the rules of contract.) Regardless, even if there does exist such a practice, I have argued that the moral obligation of a promise cannot be validly justified in terms of a power-conferring norm embedded in a social practice of promising.
  • 145
    • 34548713301 scopus 로고
    • New York: Random House, Emphasis omitted
    • Scherman, Harry, The Promises Men Live By (New York: Random House, 1938), p. 6. (Emphasis omitted.)
    • (1938) The Promises Men Live By , pp. 6
    • Scherman, H.1
  • 146
    • 34548757051 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Dori Kimel has argued, for example, that contracts also possesses an important intrinsic value, which he calls the 'value of personal detachment.' This value consists in the framework 'contracts provide for doing certain things with others not only outside the context of already existing personal relationships but also without a commitment to the future prospect of such relationships, without being required to know much or form opinions about the personal attributes of others, and without having to allow others to know much and form opinions about oneself.' Kimel (2002, p. 327).
    • Dori Kimel has argued, for example, that contracts also possesses an important intrinsic value, which he calls the 'value of personal detachment.' This value consists in the framework 'contracts provide for doing certain things with others not only outside the context of already existing personal relationships but also without a commitment to the future prospect of such relationships, without being required to know much or form opinions about the personal attributes of others, and without having to allow others to know much and form opinions about oneself.' Kimel (2002, p. 327).


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.