메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 60, Issue 1, 2007, Pages 155-212

If people would be outraged by their rulings, should judges care?

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 34548634032     PISSN: 00389765     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (57)

References (232)
  • 1
    • 37849005319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Court avoided this issue in Elk Grove Unified School District v. Newdow, 542 U.S. 1 (2004).
    • The Court avoided this issue in Elk Grove Unified School District v. Newdow, 542 U.S. 1 (2004).
  • 2
    • 37849008425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ALEXANDER M. BICKEL, THE LEAST DANGEROUS BRANCH: THE SUPREME COURT AT THE BAR OF POLITICS 16-23 (1962).
    • See ALEXANDER M. BICKEL, THE LEAST DANGEROUS BRANCH: THE SUPREME COURT AT THE BAR OF POLITICS 16-23 (1962).
  • 3
    • 37849026662 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an early treatment, see Robert A. Dahl, Decision-Making in a Democracy: The Supreme Court as a National Policy-Maker, 6 J. PUB. L. 279 (1957) (arguing that the Court's decisions generally follow the public opinion of the majority). For a recent and broadly compatible discussion,
    • For an early treatment, see Robert A. Dahl, Decision-Making in a Democracy: The Supreme Court as a National Policy-Maker, 6 J. PUB. L. 279 (1957) (arguing that the Court's decisions generally follow the public opinion of the majority). For a recent and broadly compatible discussion,
  • 4
    • 37849004050 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see MICHAEL J. KLARMAN, FROM JIM CROW TO CIVIL RIGHTS: THE SUPREME COURT AND THE STRUGGLE FOR RACIAL EQUALITY (2004). For instructive analysis of the general problem,
    • see MICHAEL J. KLARMAN, FROM JIM CROW TO CIVIL RIGHTS: THE SUPREME COURT AND THE STRUGGLE FOR RACIAL EQUALITY (2004). For instructive analysis of the general problem,
  • 5
    • 37849018166 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Barry Friedman, Dialogue and Judicial Review, 91 MICH. L. REV. 577 (1993); Barry Friedman, Mediated Popular Constitutionalism, 101 MICH. L. REV. 2596 (2003). For a valuable collection,
    • see Barry Friedman, Dialogue and Judicial Review, 91 MICH. L. REV. 577 (1993); Barry Friedman, Mediated Popular Constitutionalism, 101 MICH. L. REV. 2596 (2003). For a valuable collection,
  • 6
    • 37849018977 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see PUBLIC OPINION AND CONSTITUTIONAL CONTROVERSY (Nathaniel Persily et al. eds., forthcoming 2008).
    • see PUBLIC OPINION AND CONSTITUTIONAL CONTROVERSY (Nathaniel Persily et al. eds., forthcoming 2008).
  • 8
    • 37849010222 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Dahl, supra note 3
    • See Dahl, supra note 3.
  • 9
    • 37849010507 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare BICKEL, supra note 2, at 111-98 (supporting the use of justiciability doctrines to assist the Court in exercising the passive virtues),
    • Compare BICKEL, supra note 2, at 111-98 (supporting the use of justiciability doctrines to assist the Court in exercising the "passive virtues"),
  • 10
    • 37849022049 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • with Gerald Gunther, The Subtle Vices of the Passive Virtues - A Comment on Principle and Expediency in Judicial Review, 64 COLUM. L. REV. 1 (1964) (book review) (criticizing the use of justiciability doctrines to avoid principled decision making).
    • with Gerald Gunther, The Subtle Vices of the "Passive Virtues" - A Comment on Principle and Expediency in Judicial Review, 64 COLUM. L. REV. 1 (1964) (book review) (criticizing the use of justiciability doctrines to avoid principled decision making).
  • 11
    • 37849029767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 350 U.S. 891 1955
    • 350 U.S. 891 (1955).
  • 12
    • 37849006081 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BICKEL, supra note 2, at 174
    • See BICKEL, supra note 2, at 174.
  • 13
    • 37849020441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Elk Grove Unified Sch. Dist. v. Newdow, 542 U.S. 1 (2004).
    • See Elk Grove Unified Sch. Dist. v. Newdow, 542 U.S. 1 (2004).
  • 14
    • 37849017373 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BICKEL, supra note 2
    • See BICKEL, supra note 2.
  • 15
    • 37849027217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The most sustained treatment is given in BICKEL, id., with the emphasis on the passive virtues as a response, in part, to the problem of public outrage. As we shall see, however, Bickel did not provide firm underpinnings for the Court's consideration of public disapproval of its decisions, and he was hence left vulnerable to the charge of opportunism.
    • The most sustained treatment is given in BICKEL, id., with the emphasis on the "passive virtues" as a response, in part, to the problem of public outrage. As we shall see, however, Bickel did not provide firm underpinnings for the Court's consideration of public disapproval of its decisions, and he was hence left vulnerable to the charge of opportunism.
  • 16
    • 37849008162 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Gunther, supra note 6 criticizing the use of passive virtues as unprincipled
    • See Gunther, supra note 6 (criticizing the use of "passive virtues" as unprincipled).
  • 17
    • 37849043606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is an obvious relationship between this topic and the general one of popular constitutionalism, which sees We the People as a kind of tribunal of last resort. See KRAMER, supra note 4. I offer a few remarks on this relationship below. Some strands of popular constitutionalism, of course, have a strong normative feature,
    • There is an obvious relationship between this topic and the general one of "popular constitutionalism," which sees "We the People" as a kind of tribunal of last resort. See KRAMER, supra note 4. I offer a few remarks on this relationship below. Some strands of popular constitutionalism, of course, have a strong normative feature,
  • 19
    • 37849040693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This view can be found, in one or another form, in RONALD DWORKIN, JUSTICE IN ROBES (2006);
    • This view can be found, in one or another form, in RONALD DWORKIN, JUSTICE IN ROBES (2006);
  • 21
    • 37849004904 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and Antonin Scalia, The Rule of Law as a Law of Rules, 56 U. CHI. L. REV. 1175, 1180 (1989). We might take this view as standard while acknowledging that many people believe that doctrines of justiciability are properly used to limit the Court's intervention in deference to public reaction.
    • and Antonin Scalia, The Rule of Law as a Law of Rules, 56 U. CHI. L. REV. 1175, 1180 (1989). We might take this view as standard while acknowledging that many people believe that doctrines of justiciability are properly used to limit the Court's intervention in deference to public reaction.
  • 22
    • 37849020948 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BICKEL, supra note 2. To the extent that this belief is widely held, as it seems to be, the argument here might be seen as an effort to explain how it is best defended.
    • See BICKEL, supra note 2. To the extent that this belief is widely held, as it seems to be, the argument here might be seen as an effort to explain how it is best defended.
  • 23
    • 37849029454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I use this phrase as a placeholder for real disaster. I explore below some of the complexities in deciding what sorts of bad consequences should be considered in constitutional adjudication
    • I use this phrase as a placeholder for real disaster. I explore below some of the complexities in deciding what sorts of bad consequences should be considered in constitutional adjudication.
  • 24
    • 0000351211 scopus 로고
    • The Origin and Scope of the American Doctrine of Constitutional Law, 1
    • See
    • See James B. Thayer, The Origin and Scope of the American Doctrine of Constitutional Law, 1 HARV. L. REV. 129 (1893).
    • (1893) HARV. L. REV , vol.129
    • Thayer, J.B.1
  • 25
    • 37849008966 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See KRAMER, supra note 4;
    • See KRAMER, supra note 4;
  • 26
    • 37849001092 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • JEREMY WALDRON, LAW AND DISAGREEMENT (2004).
    • JEREMY WALDRON, LAW AND DISAGREEMENT (2004).
  • 27
    • 37849022696 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., ADRIAN VERMEULE, JUDGING UNDER UNCERTAINTY: AN INSTITUTIONAL THEORY OF LEGAL INTERPRETATION (2006).
    • See, e.g., ADRIAN VERMEULE, JUDGING UNDER UNCERTAINTY: AN INSTITUTIONAL THEORY OF LEGAL INTERPRETATION (2006).
  • 28
    • 37849027775 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MARK TUSHNET, TAKING THE CONSTITUTION AWAY FROM THE COURTS (1999).
    • See MARK TUSHNET, TAKING THE CONSTITUTION AWAY FROM THE COURTS (1999).
  • 29
    • 37849048604 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a popular presentation, see, for a more academic treatment
    • For a popular presentation, see JAMES SUROWIECKI, THE WISDOM OF CROWDS (2004); for a more academic treatment,
    • (2004)
    • SUROWIECKI, J.1    WISDOM, T.2    CROWDS, O.3
  • 30
    • 37849044122 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see SCOTT E. PAGE, THE DIFFERENCE: HOW THE POWER OF DIVERSITY CREATES BETTER GROUPS, FIRMS, SCHOOLS, AND SOCIETIES (2007).
    • see SCOTT E. PAGE, THE DIFFERENCE: HOW THE POWER OF DIVERSITY CREATES BETTER GROUPS, FIRMS, SCHOOLS, AND SOCIETIES (2007).
  • 31
    • 37849016569 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See infra Part IV.C Of course it is also true that, in many cases, much of the public will be unaware of the Court's decisions, or largely indifferent to them even if aware. The focus here is on those unusual cases in which the public is both aware and intensely interested.
    • See infra Part IV.C Of course it is also true that, in many cases, much of the public will be unaware of the Court's decisions, or largely indifferent to them even if aware. The focus here is on those unusual cases in which the public is both aware and intensely interested.
  • 32
    • 37849027938 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • These statements raise obvious complexities; I return to them below. To understand Bentham's dilemma for purposes of the inquiry I am exploring here, it is not necessary to know exactly why Bentham has decided in favor of propositions 1A-1F.
    • These statements raise obvious complexities; I return to them below. To understand Bentham's dilemma for purposes of the inquiry I am exploring here, it is not necessary to know exactly why Bentham has decided in favor of propositions 1A-1F.
  • 33
    • 37849041537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See supra notes 2-11.
    • See supra notes 2-11.
  • 34
    • 37849002011 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Scalia, supra note 13, at 1180
    • See Scalia, supra note 13, at 1180.
  • 35
    • 37849041233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • §§ 1531-1544 2000 & Supp. 2004
    • 16 U.S.C. §§ 1531-1544 (2000 & Supp. 2004).
    • 16 U.S.C
  • 36
    • 37849047399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. TVA v. Hill, 437 U.S. 153 (1978) (enjoining such a project under the Endangered Species Act).
    • Cf. TVA v. Hill, 437 U.S. 153 (1978) (enjoining such a project under the Endangered Species Act).
  • 37
    • 34548316845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • §§ 2000d to 2000d-7 2000
    • 42 U.S.C. §§ 2000d to 2000d-7 (2000).
    • 42 U.S.C
  • 38
    • 37849003692 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. United Steelworkers of Am. v. Weber, 443 U.S. 193 (1979) (upholding affirmative action plan).
    • Cf. United Steelworkers of Am. v. Weber, 443 U.S. 193 (1979) (upholding affirmative action plan).
  • 39
    • 33846467857 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Part III
    • See infra Part III.
    • See infra
  • 40
    • 0041719767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deontology at the Threshold, 37
    • For an overview, see
    • For an overview, see Larry Alexander, Deontology at the Threshold, 37 SAN DIEGO L. REV. 893, 898-901 (2000).
    • (2000) SAN DIEGO L. REV , vol.893 , pp. 898-901
    • Alexander, L.1
  • 41
    • 37849052970 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.S. 214, 248 (1944) (Jackson, J., dissenting).
    • Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.S. 214, 248 (1944) (Jackson, J., dissenting).
  • 42
    • 37849031462 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I note below some complexities in the question whether this consequence is relevant, and whether this self-defeating sense is the right one
    • I note below some complexities in the question whether this consequence is relevant, and whether this self-defeating sense is the right one.
  • 43
    • 37849038856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a good discussion, see Christine M. Korsgaard, The Right to Lie: Kant on Dealing with Evil, 15 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 325 (1986).
    • For a good discussion, see Christine M. Korsgaard, The Right to Lie: Kant on Dealing with Evil, 15 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 325 (1986).
  • 44
    • 26644474098 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Cass R. Sunstein, Moral Heuristics, 28 BEHAV. & BRAIN SCI. 531 (2005).
    • See Cass R. Sunstein, Moral Heuristics, 28 BEHAV. & BRAIN SCI. 531 (2005).
  • 45
    • 37849029453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See STEPHEN BREYER, ACTIVE LIBERTY: INTERPRETING OUR DEMOCRATIC CONSTITUTION (2005) (invoking consequences to assess theory of interpretation);
    • See STEPHEN BREYER, ACTIVE LIBERTY: INTERPRETING OUR DEMOCRATIC CONSTITUTION (2005) (invoking consequences to assess theory of interpretation);
  • 46
    • 37849047921 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RICHARD A. POSNER, LAW, PRAGMATISM, AND DEMOCRACY (2003) (same).
    • RICHARD A. POSNER, LAW, PRAGMATISM, AND DEMOCRACY (2003) (same).
  • 47
    • 37849010225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BREYER, supra note 34;
    • See BREYER, supra note 34;
  • 48
    • 37849041884 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Supreme Court, 2004 Term-Foreword: A Political Court, 119
    • Richard A. Posner, The Supreme Court, 2004 Term-Foreword: A Political Court, 119 HARV. L. REV. 31, 90-102 (2005).
    • (2005) HARV. L. REV , vol.31 , pp. 90-102
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 49
    • 37849042770 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Saikrishna Prakash, Radicals in Tweed Jackets: Why Extreme Left-Wing Law Professors Are Wrong for America, 106 COLUM. L. REV. 2207 (2006) (book review) (arguing that a form of originalism is required by the very notion of interpretation).
    • See Saikrishna Prakash, Radicals in Tweed Jackets: Why Extreme Left-Wing Law Professors Are Wrong for America, 106 COLUM. L. REV. 2207 (2006) (book review) (arguing that a form of originalism is required by the very notion of interpretation).
  • 50
    • 33846631093 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See note 6, for an account of why this view might be coherent
    • See Gunther, supra note 6, for an account of why this view might be coherent.
    • supra
    • Gunther1
  • 51
    • 37849002498 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BREYER, supra note 34
    • See BREYER, supra note 34.
  • 52
    • 37849028245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See VERMEULE, supra note 17, at 21-24
    • See VERMEULE, supra note 17, at 21-24.
  • 53
    • 13444274868 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Samuel lssacharoff & Richard H. Pildes, Between Civil Libertarianism and Executive Unilateralism: An Institutional Process Approach to Rights During Wartime, 5 THEORETICAL INQUIRIES IN L. 1 (2004).
    • See Samuel lssacharoff & Richard H. Pildes, Between Civil Libertarianism and Executive Unilateralism: An Institutional Process Approach to Rights During Wartime, 5 THEORETICAL INQUIRIES IN L. 1 (2004).
  • 55
    • 37849035630 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BICKEL, supra note 2, at 111-98
    • See BICKEL, supra note 2, at 111-98.
  • 56
    • 37849035911 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Gunther, supra note 6 (objecting that the Court should be principled and that use of the passive virtues is too opportunistic).
    • But see Gunther, supra note 6 (objecting that the Court should be principled and that use of the passive virtues is too opportunistic).
  • 57
    • 37849002784 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BICKEL, supra note 2, at 25
    • See BICKEL, supra note 2, at 25.
  • 58
    • 37849016820 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 24-26
    • Id. at 24-26.
  • 59
    • 37849020136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 64
    • Id. at 64.
  • 60
    • 37849039143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 61
    • 37849054228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See CASS R. SUNSTEIN, ONE CASE AT A TIME: JUDICIAL MINIMALISM ON THE SUPREME COURT (1999).
    • See CASS R. SUNSTEIN, ONE CASE AT A TIME: JUDICIAL MINIMALISM ON THE SUPREME COURT (1999).
  • 62
    • 37849031457 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This point itself raises serious puzzles. If Bentham is a consequentialist, is it so clear that he will refuse to lie about the grounds for his judgment, even if lying would produce good consequences? One answer is that lies ultimately produce bad consequences; the publicity condition, requiring officials to act in ways that can be defended honestly and in public, might be understood as a way of ensuring against those bad consequences
    • This point itself raises serious puzzles. If Bentham is a consequentialist, is it so clear that he will refuse to lie about the grounds for his judgment, even if lying would produce good consequences? One answer is that lies ultimately produce bad consequences; the publicity condition, requiring officials to act in ways that can be defended honestly and in public, might be understood as a way of ensuring against those bad consequences.
  • 63
    • 37849034838 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See David Luban, The Publicity Principle, in THE THEORY OF INSTITUTIONAL DESIGN 154 (Robert E. Goodin ed., 1996). Another answer is that notwithstanding his name, Bentham may believe that lying is an intrinsic wrong, because it does not treat his fellow citizens with respect.
    • See David Luban, The Publicity Principle, in THE THEORY OF INSTITUTIONAL DESIGN 154 (Robert E. Goodin ed., 1996). Another answer is that notwithstanding his name, Bentham may believe that lying is an intrinsic wrong, because it does not treat his fellow citizens with respect.
  • 64
    • 37849014253 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See David A. Strauss, Persuasion, Autonomy, and Freedom of Expression, 91 COLUM. L. REV. 334, 353-60 (1991). Note that Bentham is a consequentialist, not a utilitarian; he may therefore believe that treating people disrespectfully is an independent wrong, one that counts in the consequentialist calculus.
    • See David A. Strauss, Persuasion, Autonomy, and Freedom of Expression, 91 COLUM. L. REV. 334, 353-60 (1991). Note that Bentham is a consequentialist, not a utilitarian; he may therefore believe that treating people disrespectfully is an independent wrong, one that counts in the consequentialist calculus.
  • 65
    • 0347878287 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Amartya Sen, Fertility and Coercion, 63 U. CHI. L. REV. 1035, 1038-39 (1996) (noting the possibility of considering rights violations as part of the assessment of consequences).
    • See Amartya Sen, Fertility and Coercion, 63 U. CHI. L. REV. 1035, 1038-39 (1996) (noting the possibility of considering rights violations as part of the assessment of consequences).
  • 66
    • 37849007863 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Rostker v. Goldberg, 453 U.S. 57, 64 (1981) (emphasizing the need to attend to constitutional judgments of other branches).
    • See Rostker v. Goldberg, 453 U.S. 57, 64 (1981) (emphasizing the need to attend to constitutional judgments of other branches).
  • 67
    • 37849027216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Van Orden v. Perry, 545 U.S. 677, 704 (2005) (Breyer, J., concurring) (fearing that deeming a Ten Commandments display a violation of the Establishment Clause would encourage disputes concerning the removal of longstanding depictions of the Ten Commandments and create the very kind of. . . divisiveness that the Establishment Clause seeks to avoid);
    • See Van Orden v. Perry, 545 U.S. 677, 704 (2005) (Breyer, J., concurring) (fearing that deeming a Ten Commandments display a violation of the Establishment Clause would "encourage disputes concerning the removal of longstanding depictions of the Ten Commandments" and "create the very kind of. . . divisiveness that the Establishment Clause seeks to avoid");
  • 68
    • 37849045506 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Elk Grove Unified Sch. Dist. v. Newdow, 542 U.S. 1, 15 (2004) (referring to a highly public debate over ... the propriety of a widespread national ritual, and the meaning of our Constitution).
    • Elk Grove Unified Sch. Dist. v. Newdow, 542 U.S. 1, 15 (2004) (referring to "a highly public debate over ... the propriety of a widespread national ritual, and the meaning of our Constitution").
  • 69
    • 37849040401 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A straightforwardly consequentialist argument in favor of a distinctive approach to interpretation can be found in BREYER, note 34
    • A straightforwardly consequentialist argument in favor of a distinctive approach to interpretation can be found in BREYER, supra note 34.
    • supra
  • 70
    • 37849005195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I borrow here from ALBERT O. HIRSCHMAN, THE RHETORIC OF REACTION: PERVERSITY, FUTILITY, JEOPARDY (1991).
    • I borrow here from ALBERT O. HIRSCHMAN, THE RHETORIC OF REACTION: PERVERSITY, FUTILITY, JEOPARDY (1991).
  • 71
    • 37849012482 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 349 U.S. 294, 301 (1955).
    • 349 U.S. 294, 301 (1955).
  • 72
    • 37849007043 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For illuminating discussions of the controversy over the all deliberate speed formulation, see KLARMAN, supra note 3;
    • For illuminating discussions of the controversy over the "all deliberate speed" formulation, see KLARMAN, supra note 3;
  • 73
    • 37849024537 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RICHARD KLUGER, SIMPLE JUSTICE: THE HISTORY OF BROWN V. BOARD OF EDUCATION AND BLACK AMERICA'S STRUGGLE FOR RACIAL EQUALITY (2d ed. 2004);
    • RICHARD KLUGER, SIMPLE JUSTICE: THE HISTORY OF BROWN V. BOARD OF EDUCATION AND BLACK AMERICA'S STRUGGLE FOR RACIAL EQUALITY (2d ed. 2004);
  • 74
    • 37849013232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and J. HARVIE WILKINSON IH, FROM BROWN TO BAKKE: THE SUPREME COURT AND SCHOOL INTEGRATION: 1954 TO 1978 (1979).
    • and J. HARVIE WILKINSON IH, FROM BROWN TO BAKKE: THE SUPREME COURT AND SCHOOL INTEGRATION: 1954 TO 1978 (1979).
  • 75
    • 37849045134 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paul Gewirtz, Remedies and Resistance, 92 YALE L.J. 585 (1983), offers a valuable discussion of the role of public resistance, and outrage, in the selection of remedies.
    • Paul Gewirtz, Remedies and Resistance, 92 YALE L.J. 585 (1983), offers a valuable discussion of the role of public resistance, and outrage, in the selection of remedies.
  • 76
    • 37849053586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Howard Gruenspecht, Zero Emission Vehicles: A Dirty Little Secret, POLICY MATTERS (AEI-Brookings Joint Center, Washington, D.C.), Oct. 2000, available at http://www.aei.brookings.org/ policy/page.php?id=51 (contending that the requirement of low-polluting new vehicles will actually increase pollution in the short run, by extending the life of older, high-polluting vehicles).
    • See Howard Gruenspecht, Zero Emission Vehicles: A Dirty Little Secret, POLICY MATTERS (AEI-Brookings Joint Center, Washington, D.C.), Oct. 2000, available at http://www.aei.brookings.org/ policy/page.php?id=51 (contending that the requirement of low-polluting new vehicles will actually increase pollution in the short run, by extending the life of older, high-polluting vehicles).
  • 77
    • 37849038857 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Nairn v. Nairn, 350 U.S. 891 (1955) (declining to decide whether bans on racial intermarriage are unconstitutional). There are of course difficult issues about how to characterize the underlying goals, such that a particular decision would turn out to be perverse.
    • See Nairn v. Nairn, 350 U.S. 891 (1955) (declining to decide whether bans on racial intermarriage are unconstitutional). There are of course difficult issues about how to characterize the underlying goals, such that a particular decision would turn out to be perverse.
  • 78
    • 37849031711 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is the fear expressed in Justice Jackson's dissent in Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.S. 214, 248 1944, Jackson, J, dissenting, and probably in the Court's opinion as well
    • This is the fear expressed in Justice Jackson's dissent in Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.S. 214, 248 (1944) (Jackson, J., dissenting), and probably in the Court's opinion as well,
  • 79
    • 37849008658 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see id. at 220 (majority opinion) ([W]hen under conditions of modern warfare our shores are threatened by hostile forces, the power to protect must be commensurate with the threatened danger.).
    • see id. at 220 (majority opinion) ("[W]hen under conditions of modern warfare our shores are threatened by hostile forces, the power to protect must be commensurate with the threatened danger.").
  • 80
    • 37849020947 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See RICHARD A. POSNER, NOT A SUICIDE PACT: THE CONSTITUTION IN A TIME OF NATIONAL EMERGENCY (2006) (arguing for a pragmatic approach to the Constitution in the context of national security, in a way that allows the executive wide room to maneuver).
    • See RICHARD A. POSNER, NOT A SUICIDE PACT: THE CONSTITUTION IN A TIME OF NATIONAL EMERGENCY (2006) (arguing for a pragmatic approach to the Constitution in the context of national security, in a way that allows the executive wide room to maneuver).
  • 81
    • 37849050904 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, BICKEL, supra note 2
    • See, e.g., BICKEL, supra note 2.
  • 82
    • 37849032010 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 13
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 13.
  • 83
    • 37849008161 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 410 U.S. 113 1973
    • 410 U.S. 113 (1973).
  • 84
    • 37849027215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See GERALD N. ROSENBERG, THE HOLLOW HOPE: CAN COURTS BRING ABOUT SOCIAL CHANGE? (1991).
    • See GERALD N. ROSENBERG, THE HOLLOW HOPE: CAN COURTS BRING ABOUT SOCIAL CHANGE? (1991).
  • 85
    • 37849009940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Admittedly, this belief will be based partly on the consequences of failing or not failing to allow same-sex marriages
    • Admittedly, this belief will be based partly on the consequences of failing or not failing to allow same-sex marriages.
  • 86
    • 37848999310 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ROSENBERG, supra note 62. Recall that Bentham is a consequentialist; his deepest convictions are a product of his judgments about the effects of various outcomes.
    • See ROSENBERG, supra note 62. Recall that Bentham is a consequentialist; his deepest convictions are a product of his judgments about the effects of various outcomes.
  • 87
    • 37849014252 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See MARY ANN GLENDON, ABORTION AND DFVORCE IN WESTERN LAW (1987) (arguing Roe v. Wade produced polarization that reduced possibility of compromise solutions).
    • See MARY ANN GLENDON, ABORTION AND DFVORCE IN WESTERN LAW (1987) (arguing Roe v. Wade produced polarization that reduced possibility of compromise solutions).
  • 88
    • 37849037633 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare the debate over Bush v. Gore, 531 U.S. 98 (2000). No one contended that a member of the Court could legitimately take account of whether George W. Bush or Al Gore would be a better president. It is interesting that pragmatic judges, insistent on taking account of consequences, implicitly ruled that consideration entirely out of bounds.
    • Compare the debate over Bush v. Gore, 531 U.S. 98 (2000). No one contended that a member of the Court could legitimately take account of whether George W. Bush or Al Gore would be a better president. It is interesting that pragmatic judges, insistent on taking account of consequences, implicitly ruled that consideration entirely out of bounds.
  • 89
    • 37849008964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See RICHARD A. POSNER, BREAKING THE DEADLOCK: THE 2000 ELECTION, THE CONSTITUTION, AND THE COURTS (2001). The puzzle for the committed consequentialist is: why?
    • See RICHARD A. POSNER, BREAKING THE DEADLOCK: THE 2000 ELECTION, THE CONSTITUTION, AND THE COURTS (2001). The puzzle for the committed consequentialist is: why?
  • 90
    • 37849032621 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An illustration is confirmation bias, by which people's judgments about what is true are influenced by their desire to have their own beliefs confirmed. See, e.g, Barbara O'Brien & Phoebe C. Ellsworth, Confirmation Bias in Criminal Investigations Sept. 19, 2006, unpublished manuscript, available at
    • An illustration is "confirmation bias," by which people's judgments about what is true are influenced by their desire to have their own beliefs confirmed. See, e.g., Barbara O'Brien & Phoebe C. Ellsworth, Confirmation Bias in Criminal Investigations (Sept. 19, 2006) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=913357.
  • 91
    • 37849044125 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Gunther, supra note 6, at 5
    • See Gunther, supra note 6, at 5.
  • 92
    • 37849036231 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Scalia, supra note 13 defending firm rules on the ground that they stiffen the judicial spine when the stakes are high
    • See Scalia, supra note 13 (defending firm rules on the ground that they stiffen the judicial spine when the stakes are high).
  • 93
    • 37849006083 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ZECHARIAH CHAFEE, JR., FREE SPEECH IN THE UNITED STATES (1941);
    • See ZECHARIAH CHAFEE, JR., FREE SPEECH IN THE UNITED STATES (1941);
  • 94
    • 37849047165 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • STONE, supra note 13
    • STONE, supra note 13.
  • 95
    • 37849032359 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Scalia, supra note 13, at 1180 (emphasizing the value of rules in allowing judges to stand firm when popular pressure is intense).
    • Cf. Scalia, supra note 13, at 1180 (emphasizing the value of rules in allowing judges to stand firm when popular pressure is intense).
  • 96
    • 37849042453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As I have noted, a judge needs to make supplemental judgments to decide what counts as such; recall here Justice Jackson's suggestion that his conclusion that courts ought not to enforce the military order to detain Japanese-Americans on the West Coast need not be taken to suggest that the courts should have attempted to interfere with the Army in carrying out its task. Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.S. 214, 248 (1944) (Jackson, J., dissenting).
    • As I have noted, a judge needs to make supplemental judgments to decide what counts as such; recall here Justice Jackson's suggestion that his conclusion that courts ought not to enforce the military order to detain Japanese-Americans on the West Coast need not be taken to "suggest that the courts should have attempted to interfere with the Army in carrying out its task." Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.S. 214, 248 (1944) (Jackson, J., dissenting).
  • 97
    • 37849026030 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Richard Wasserstrom, Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues, 5 HUM. RTS. 1, 6 (1975) (noting that once a lawyer-client relationship with a criminal defendant is established it is appropriate and obligatory for the attorney to put on a vigorous defense even if the attorney believes the client to be guilty).
    • See Richard Wasserstrom, Lawyers as Professionals: Some Moral Issues, 5 HUM. RTS. 1, 6 (1975) (noting that once a lawyer-client relationship with a criminal defendant is established it is "appropriate and obligatory" for the attorney to put on a vigorous defense even if the attorney believes the client to be guilty).
  • 98
    • 32844463431 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Carol S. Steiker, No, Capital Punishment Is Not Morally Required: Deterrence, Deontology, and the Death Penalty, 58 STAN. L. REV. 751 (2005) (objecting on deontological grounds to convictions of innocent people, even if consequentialism calls for such convictions).
    • Cf. Carol S. Steiker, No, Capital Punishment Is Not Morally Required: Deterrence, Deontology, and the Death Penalty, 58 STAN. L. REV. 751 (2005) (objecting on deontological grounds to convictions of innocent people, even if consequentialism calls for such convictions).
  • 99
    • 37849017377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Sen, supra note 48, at 1038-39 arguing for a form of consequentialism that sees rights violations as relevant consequences
    • See Sen, supra note 48, at 1038-39 (arguing for a form of consequentialism that sees rights violations as relevant consequences).
  • 100
    • 37849024293 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare Bernard Williams's well-known suggestion that in certain domains those who make consequentialist assessments have one thought too many. If someone makes such an assessment before deciding to save his wife rather than a stranger from a burning building, we might well conclude that he is having an excessive thought. See Bernard Williams, Persons, Character, and Morality, in MORAL LUCK: PHILOSOPHICAL PAPERS, 1973-1980, at 18 1981, So too, it might be thought, for those in certain institutional roles. If a doctor asks whether a patient is benefiting society before undertaking a diagnosis, or if a judge thinks about the consequences for the unemployment rate of a certain ruling, excessive thinking is taking place. It is worth considering the possibility that Williams's claim is correct, but only for reasons of system design: the consequences are best if spouses do not think that way, and so too for doctors and judges. F
    • Compare Bernard Williams's well-known suggestion that in certain domains those who make consequentialist assessments have "one thought too many." If someone makes such an assessment before deciding to save his wife rather than a stranger from a burning building, we might well conclude that he is having an excessive thought. See Bernard Williams, Persons, Character, and Morality, in MORAL LUCK: PHILOSOPHICAL PAPERS, 1973-1980, at 18 (1981). So too, it might be thought, for those in certain institutional roles. If a doctor asks whether a patient is benefiting society before undertaking a diagnosis, or if a judge thinks about the consequences for the unemployment rate of a certain ruling, excessive thinking is taking place. It is worth considering the possibility that Williams's claim is correct, but only for reasons of system design: the consequences are best if spouses do not think that way, and so too for doctors and judges. For a critique of Williams's position,
  • 101
    • 37849011844 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Do Consequentialists Have One Thought Too Many?
    • see
    • see Elinor Mason, Do Consequentialists Have One Thought Too Many?, 2 ETHICAL THEORY & MORAL PRAC. 243 (1999).
    • (1999) ETHICAL THEORY & MORAL PRAC , vol.2 , pp. 243
    • Mason, E.1
  • 102
    • 37849021239 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf BREYER, supra note 34 (defending validation of affirmative action on the ground that it would promote inclusion and active democracy). Justice Breyer's point is not that the reaction to the Court's decision would itself be a good consequence, or produce good consequences, but he certainly offers a consequentialist defense of the Court's validation of affirmative action.
    • Cf BREYER, supra note 34 (defending validation of affirmative action on the ground that it would promote inclusion and active democracy). Justice Breyer's point is not that the reaction to the Court's decision would itself be a good consequence, or produce good consequences, but he certainly offers a consequentialist defense of the Court's validation of affirmative action.
  • 103
    • 37849013377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare the public reaction to Kelo v. City of New London, 545 U.S. 469 (2005). President Bush, for example, reacted to the decision with an executive order instructing the federal government to use eminent domain for the purpose of benefiting the general public and not merely for the purpose of advancing the economic interest of private parties to be given ownership or use of the property taken. Exec. Order No. 13,406, 71 Fed. Reg. 36,973 (June 23, 2006), available at http://www.whitehouse.gov/news/ releases/2006/06/20060623-10.html. For a valuable treatment of the controversy,
    • Compare the public reaction to Kelo v. City of New London, 545 U.S. 469 (2005). President Bush, for example, reacted to the decision with an executive order instructing the federal government to use eminent domain "for the purpose of benefiting the general public and not merely for the purpose of advancing the economic interest of private parties to be given ownership or use of the property taken." Exec. Order No. 13,406, 71 Fed. Reg. 36,973 (June 23, 2006), available at http://www.whitehouse.gov/news/ releases/2006/06/20060623-10.html. For a valuable treatment of the controversy,
  • 104
    • 37849002782 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Janice Nadler et al., Government Takings of Private Property: Kelo and the Perfect Storm (Northwestern Sch. of Law Pub. Law & Legal Theory Series, Working Paper No. 07-05, 2007), available at http://ssrn.com/abstracts=962170.
    • see Janice Nadler et al., Government Takings of Private Property: Kelo and the Perfect Storm (Northwestern Sch. of Law Pub. Law & Legal Theory Series, Working Paper No. 07-05, 2007), available at http://ssrn.com/abstracts=962170.
  • 105
    • 37849026663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 578 (2003).
    • See Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 578 (2003).
  • 106
    • 37849032008 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See STEPHEN G. BREYER ET AL., ADMINISTRATIVE LAW AND REGULATORY POLICY 335-36 (6th ed. 2006).
    • See STEPHEN G. BREYER ET AL., ADMINISTRATIVE LAW AND REGULATORY POLICY 335-36 (6th ed. 2006).
  • 107
    • 37849030676 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See VALUING ENVIRONMENTAL PREFERENCES: THEORY AND PRACTICE OF THE CONTINGENT VALUATION METHOD IN THE US, EU, AND DEVELOPING COUNTRIES (Ian J. Bateman & Kenneth G. Willis eds., 1999).
    • See VALUING ENVIRONMENTAL PREFERENCES: THEORY AND PRACTICE OF THE CONTINGENT VALUATION METHOD IN THE US, EU, AND DEVELOPING COUNTRIES (Ian J. Bateman & Kenneth G. Willis eds., 1999).
  • 108
    • 37849026973 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Matthew D. Adler, Fear Assessment: Cost-Benefit Analysis and the Pricing of Fear and Anxiety, 79 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 977, 987-89 (2004) (describing how a particular negative feeling-fear-is a welfare setback and should be counted as a cost in cost-benefit analyses).
    • See Matthew D. Adler, Fear Assessment: Cost-Benefit Analysis and the Pricing of Fear and Anxiety, 79 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 977, 987-89 (2004) (describing how a particular negative feeling-fear-is a welfare setback and should be counted as a cost in cost-benefit analyses).
  • 109
    • 37849026332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a discussion with relevant citations, see
    • For a discussion with relevant citations, see LOUIS KAPLOW & STEVEN SHAVELL, FAIRNESS VERSUS WELFARE (2002).
    • (2002)
    • LOUIS, K.1    STEVEN SHAVELL, F.2    VERSUS, W.3
  • 110
    • 37849027769 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See STEPHEN HOLMES, PASSIONS AND CONSTRAINT: ON THE THEORY OF LIBERAL DEMOCRACY (1995).
    • See STEPHEN HOLMES, PASSIONS AND CONSTRAINT: ON THE THEORY OF LIBERAL DEMOCRACY (1995).
  • 111
    • 37849022050 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BICKEL, supra note 2, at 174-75
    • See BICKEL, supra note 2, at 174-75.
  • 112
    • 37849051585 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Nairn v. Nairn, 350 U.S. 891 (1955).
    • See Nairn v. Nairn, 350 U.S. 891 (1955).
  • 113
    • 37849022341 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973);
    • See Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973);
  • 114
    • 0022008092 scopus 로고
    • Some Thoughts on Autonomy and Equality in Relation to Roe v. Wade, 63
    • see also
    • see also Ruth Bader Ginsburg, Some Thoughts on Autonomy and Equality in Relation to Roe v. Wade, 63 N.C. L. REV. 375 (1985).
    • (1985) N.C. L. REV , vol.375
    • Bader Ginsburg, R.1
  • 115
    • 37849045132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., RICHARD A. EPSTEIN, TAKINGS: PRIVATE PROPERTY AND THE POWER OF EMINENT DOMAIN (1985) (calling for such an expansion).
    • See, e.g., RICHARD A. EPSTEIN, TAKINGS: PRIVATE PROPERTY AND THE POWER OF EMINENT DOMAIN (1985) (calling for such an expansion).
  • 116
    • 84886342665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • text accompanying note 43
    • See supra text accompanying note 43.
    • See supra
  • 117
    • 37849039744 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a sketch, see CASS R. SUNSTEIN, INFOTOPIA: HOW MANY MINDS PRODUCE KNOWLEDGE 25-28 (2006).
    • For a sketch, see CASS R. SUNSTEIN, INFOTOPIA: HOW MANY MINDS PRODUCE KNOWLEDGE 25-28 (2006).
  • 118
    • 37849052186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See SUROWEECKI, supra note 19
    • See SUROWEECKI, supra note 19.
  • 119
    • 37849040692 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An especially helpful discussion is found in PAGE, supra note 19
    • An especially helpful discussion is found in PAGE, supra note 19.
  • 120
    • 0035603046 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Christian List & Robert E. Goodin, Epistemic Democracy: Generalizing the Condorcet Jury Theorem, 9 J. POL. PHIL. 277, 283-88, 295-97 (2001). A good discussion can also be found in PAGE, supra note 19.
    • See Christian List & Robert E. Goodin, Epistemic Democracy: Generalizing the Condorcet Jury Theorem, 9 J. POL. PHIL. 277, 283-88, 295-97 (2001). A good discussion can also be found in PAGE, supra note 19.
  • 121
    • 37849011109 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A useful, brisk discussion can be found in BERNARD WILLIAMS, MORALITY: AN INTRODUCTION TO ETHICS (1972).
    • A useful, brisk discussion can be found in BERNARD WILLIAMS, MORALITY: AN INTRODUCTION TO ETHICS (1972).
  • 122
    • 37849051300 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, DWORKIN, supra note 13
    • See, e.g., DWORKIN, supra note 13.
  • 123
    • 37849019488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 572, 576 (2003).
    • See Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 572, 576 (2003).
  • 125
    • 37849052971 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See SUNSTEIN, supra note 90, at 29-30
    • See SUNSTEIN, supra note 90, at 29-30.
  • 126
    • 37849048222 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Norbert Schwarz & Leigh Ann Vaughn, The Availability Heuristic Revisited, in HEURISTICS AND BIASES: THE PSYCHOLOGY OF INTUITIVE JUDGMENT 103 (Thomas Gilovich et al. eds., 2002).
    • See, e.g., Norbert Schwarz & Leigh Ann Vaughn, The Availability Heuristic Revisited, in HEURISTICS AND BIASES: THE PSYCHOLOGY OF INTUITIVE JUDGMENT 103 (Thomas Gilovich et al. eds., 2002).
  • 127
    • 37848999309 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • CONDORCET: SELECTED WRITINGS 62 (Keith Michael Baker ed., 1976).
    • CONDORCET: SELECTED WRITINGS 62 (Keith Michael Baker ed., 1976).
  • 128
    • 37849040043 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BICKEL, supra note 2, at 23-28
    • See BICKEL, supra note 2, at 23-28.
  • 129
    • 33846088199 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Eric A. Posner & Cass R. Sunstein, The Law of Other States, 59 STAN. L. REV. 131 (2006) (exploring the view that courts should take into account decisions of other courts on the Condorcetian ground that they provide valuable information).
    • See Eric A. Posner & Cass R. Sunstein, The Law of Other States, 59 STAN. L. REV. 131 (2006) (exploring the view that courts should take into account decisions of other courts on the Condorcetian ground that they provide valuable information).
  • 130
    • 0001015501 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Learning from the Behavior of Others: Conformity, Fads, and Informational Cascades, 12
    • See
    • See Sushil Bikhchandani et al., Learning from the Behavior of Others: Conformity, Fads, and Informational Cascades, 12 J. ECON. PERSP. 151, 154-56 (1998).
    • (1998) J. ECON. PERSP , vol.151 , pp. 154-156
    • Bikhchandani, S.1
  • 131
    • 0001478273 scopus 로고
    • The Perpetuation of an Arbitrary Tradition Through Several Generations of a Laboratory Microculture, 62
    • For fascinating experimental evidence, see
    • For fascinating experimental evidence, see Robert C Jacobs & Donald T. Campbell, The Perpetuation of an Arbitrary Tradition Through Several Generations of a Laboratory Microculture, 62 J. ABNORMAL & Soc. PSYCHOL. 649 (1961),
    • (1961) J. ABNORMAL & Soc. PSYCHOL , vol.649
    • Jacobs, R.C.1    Campbell, D.T.2
  • 132
    • 34548609811 scopus 로고
    • Individual Maintenance and Perpetuation of a Means/Ends Arbitrary Tradition, 40
    • and Gregory J. Moschetti, Individual Maintenance and Perpetuation of a Means/Ends Arbitrary Tradition, 40 SOCIOMETRY 78 (1977).
    • (1977) SOCIOMETRY , vol.78
    • Moschetti, G.J.1
  • 133
    • 37849024831 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See STANLEY COHEN, FOLK DEVILS AND MORAL PANICS: THE CREATION OF THE MODS AND ROCKERS (3d ed. 2002). Of course moral judgments might well be a product of relevant information, in which case moral cascades are informational cascades too.
    • See STANLEY COHEN, FOLK DEVILS AND MORAL PANICS: THE CREATION OF THE MODS AND ROCKERS (3d ed. 2002). Of course moral judgments might well be a product of relevant information, in which case moral cascades are informational cascades too.
  • 134
    • 2442602908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Alan B. Krueger & Jitka Malečková, Education, Poverty, and Terrorism: Is There a Causal Connection?, 17 J. ECON. PERSP. 119, 119 (2003) (suggesting that terrorism is more accurately viewed as a response to political conditions and long-standing feelings of indignity and frustration that have little to do with economics).
    • See Alan B. Krueger & Jitka Malečková, Education, Poverty, and Terrorism: Is There a Causal Connection?, 17 J. ECON. PERSP. 119, 119 (2003) (suggesting that terrorism "is more accurately viewed as a response to political conditions and long-standing feelings of indignity and frustration that have little to do with economics").
  • 135
    • 23044517902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Deliberating About Dollars: The Severity Shift, 100
    • See
    • See David Schkade et al., Deliberating About Dollars: The Severity Shift, 100 COLUM. L. REV. 1139 (2000).
    • (2000) COLUM. L. REV , vol.1139
    • Schkade, D.1
  • 136
    • 37849048606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 137
    • 37849015416 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Andrew F. Daughety & Jennifer F. Reinganum, Stampede to Judgment: Persuasive Influence and Herding Behavior by Courts, 1 AM. L. & ECON. REV. 158 (1999).
    • See Andrew F. Daughety & Jennifer F. Reinganum, Stampede to Judgment: Persuasive Influence and Herding Behavior by Courts, 1 AM. L. & ECON. REV. 158 (1999).
  • 138
    • 34548629694 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What Happened on Deliberation Day?, 95
    • See
    • See David Schkade et al., What Happened on Deliberation Day?, 95 CAL. L. REV. 915 (2007).
    • (2007) CAL. L. REV , vol.915
    • Schkade, D.1
  • 140
    • 37849028244 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Schkade et al, supra note 107, at 1164
    • See Schkade et al., supra note 107, at 1164.
  • 141
    • 37848998995 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. PAGE, supra note 19, at 209-11 (suggesting that on factual questions, diverse groups regularly outperform individuals).
    • Cf. PAGE, supra note 19, at 209-11 (suggesting that on factual questions, diverse groups regularly outperform individuals).
  • 143
    • 37849036953 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Condorcet has to be careful here. What groups count as powerful, and what groups count as powerless, may not be a mere question of fact; it might well have a normative component as well. See Bruce A. Ackerman, Beyond Carolene Products, 98 HARV. L. REV. 713 (1985) (discussing how to distinguish groups that deserve special protection under Carolene Products). And if a powerful group is large, Condorcet might hesitate before rejecting its view, notwithstanding its power.
    • Condorcet has to be careful here. What groups count as powerful, and what groups count as powerless, may not be a mere question of fact; it might well have a normative component as well. See Bruce A. Ackerman, Beyond Carolene Products, 98 HARV. L. REV. 713 (1985) (discussing how to distinguish groups that deserve special protection under Carolene Products). And if a powerful group is large, Condorcet might hesitate before rejecting its view, notwithstanding its power.
  • 144
    • 37849013378 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Dahl, supra note 3, at 283-91 (showing that courts rarely reject a public consensus);
    • See Dahl, supra note 3, at 283-91 (showing that courts rarely reject a public consensus);
  • 145
    • 37849038858 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • PUBLIC OPINION AND CONSTITUTIONAL CONTROVERSY (Nathaniel Persily et al. eds., forthcoming 2008).
    • PUBLIC OPINION AND CONSTITUTIONAL CONTROVERSY (Nathaniel Persily et al. eds., forthcoming 2008).
  • 146
    • 37849030101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Posner & Sunstein, supra note 102 (arguing that general practice of states and nations has epistemic value, and not concentrating on outrage or any particular affective state).
    • Cf. Posner & Sunstein, supra note 102 (arguing that general practice of states and nations has epistemic value, and not concentrating on outrage or any particular affective state).
  • 147
    • 37849020444 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 572, 576 (2003).
    • See Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 572, 576 (2003).
  • 148
    • 37849022989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 576
    • Id. at 576.
  • 149
    • 37849026664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 572
    • Id. at 572.
  • 150
    • 37849021514 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See VERMEULE, supra note 17, at 254;
    • See VERMEULE, supra note 17, at 254;
  • 151
    • 37849053936 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thayer, supra note 15
    • Thayer, supra note 15.
  • 152
    • 37849010223 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Thayer, supra note 15, at 144 (noting that laws which will seem unconstitutional to one man, or body of men, may reasonably not seem so to another;... the constitution often admits of different interpretations; . . . there is often a range of choice and judgment).
    • See Thayer, supra note 15, at 144 (noting that laws "which will seem unconstitutional to one man, or body of men, may reasonably not seem so to another;... the constitution often admits of different interpretations; . . . there is often a range of choice and judgment").
  • 153
    • 37849002326 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 154
    • 37849046364 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 151
    • Id. at 151.
  • 155
    • 37849035160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 156
    • 37849037632 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Rostker v. Goldberg, 453 U.S. 57, 64 (1981) (holding that when Congress has specifically considered the question of an act's constitutionality the customary deference accorded the judgments of Congress is certainly appropriate).
    • See, e.g., Rostker v. Goldberg, 453 U.S. 57, 64 (1981) (holding that when Congress has specifically considered the question of an act's constitutionality the "customary deference accorded the judgments of Congress is certainly appropriate").
  • 157
    • 37849053587 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Posner & Sunstein, supra note 102
    • See Posner & Sunstein, supra note 102.
  • 158
    • 37849033443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., KLARMAN, supra note 3 (defending Brown on such grounds);
    • See, e.g., KLARMAN, supra note 3 (defending Brown on such grounds);
  • 159
    • 37849003693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • RICHARD A. POSNER, SEX AND REASON 324 (reprint ed. 1994) (defending Griswold on such grounds);
    • RICHARD A. POSNER, SEX AND REASON 324 (reprint ed. 1994) (defending Griswold on such grounds);
  • 160
    • 33750847591 scopus 로고
    • Common Law Rules and Constitutional Double Standards: Some Notes on Adjudication, 83
    • defending Roe on such grounds
    • Harry H. Wellington, Common Law Rules and Constitutional Double Standards: Some Notes on Adjudication, 83 YALE L.J. 221, 297-311 (1973) (defending Roe on such grounds).
    • (1973) YALE L.J , vol.221 , pp. 297-311
    • Wellington, H.H.1
  • 161
    • 37849011110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Roper v. Simmons, 543 U.S. 551 (2005);
    • See, e.g., Roper v. Simmons, 543 U.S. 551 (2005);
  • 162
    • 37849004317 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003).
    • Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003).
  • 164
    • 0030295788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Robert S. Baron et al, Social Corroboration and Opinion Extremity, 32 J. EXPERIMENTAL SOC. PSYCHOL. 537, 538 (1996) (suggesting that confidence produces more extremity, with the implication that a lack of confidence produces moderation).
    • See Robert S. Baron et al, Social Corroboration and Opinion Extremity, 32 J. EXPERIMENTAL SOC. PSYCHOL. 537, 538 (1996) (suggesting that confidence produces more extremity, with the implication that a lack of confidence produces moderation).
  • 166
    • 37849027937 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 148.
    • See id. at 148.
  • 167
    • 37849005620 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The analysis thus far has broader implications. The tension between judicial review and democracy qualifies as such only on the basis of certain understandings of both judicial capacities and democracy itself. The tension is serious if we believe that democratic self-government requires the public, and not the judges, to decide relevant moral questions. But why, exactly, might we think that? The consequentialist and epistemic arguments help to provide answers. If Thayerism is understood through a Condorcetian lens, a deferential judicial role is best defended on the ground that the public is far more likely to be right than the federal judiciary. An evident problem with this position is that a systematic bias, a cascade, or polarization might have led the public in the wrong direction; an additional problem is that the views of the public may not involve any proposition that bears on constitutional meaning. If Thayerism is understood in consequentialist terms, the argument would be tha
    • The analysis thus far has broader implications. The tension between judicial review and democracy qualifies as such only on the basis of certain understandings of both judicial capacities and democracy itself. The tension is serious if we believe that democratic self-government requires the public, and not the judges, to decide relevant moral questions. But why, exactly, might we think that? The consequentialist and epistemic arguments help to provide answers. If Thayerism is understood through a Condorcetian lens, a deferential judicial role is best defended on the ground that the public is far more likely to be right than the federal judiciary. An evident problem with this position is that a systematic bias, a cascade, or polarization might have led the public in the wrong direction; an additional problem is that the views of the public may not involve any proposition that bears on constitutional meaning. If Thayerism is understood in consequentialist terms, the argument would be that even if judges have special access to the document's meaning, the results will be better, at least on occasion, if they attend to the public's view. It is certainly open for a consequentialist to believe that self-government is an intrinsic as well as an instrumental good, and that any decision to thwart the democratic will creates a bad consequence by definition. My goal with these brief remarks is not to take sides in this large debate, but to specify some of the grounds on which democratic objections to judicial review might be both defended and challenged.
  • 168
    • 37849013380 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a discussion, see Cass R. Sunstein, Clear Statement Principles and National Security: Hamdan and Beyond, SUP. CT. REV. (forthcoming 2007), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract= 922406. Thayer himself emphasized the need to defer to Congress, not state governments or the President; I understand Justice Thayer, and Thayerism more generally, to suggest a broader posture of restraint.
    • For a discussion, see Cass R. Sunstein, Clear Statement Principles and National Security: Hamdan and Beyond, SUP. CT. REV. (forthcoming 2007), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract= 922406. Thayer himself emphasized the need to defer to Congress, not state governments or the President; I understand Justice Thayer, and Thayerism more generally, to suggest a broader posture of restraint.
  • 169
    • 37849014066 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Kelo v. City of New London, 545 U.S. 469 (2005) (offering a broad interpretation of the public use requirement).
    • Cf. Kelo v. City of New London, 545 U.S. 469 (2005) (offering a broad interpretation of the "public use" requirement).
  • 170
    • 37849017863 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Thayer, supra note 15
    • See Thayer, supra note 15.
  • 171
    • 37849018173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See VERMEULE, supra note 17 defending a form of Thayerism on consequentialist grounds
    • See VERMEULE, supra note 17 (defending a form of Thayerism on consequentialist grounds).
  • 172
    • 37849026966 scopus 로고
    • U.S. 165
    • Rochin v. California, 342 U.S. 165, 169 (1952).
    • (1952) California , vol.342 , pp. 169
    • Rochin1
  • 173
    • 37849041234 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The test originated in Trop v. Dulles, 356 U.S. 86, 101 (1958).
    • The test originated in Trop v. Dulles, 356 U.S. 86, 101 (1958).
  • 174
    • 37849002500 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Roper v. Simmons, 543 U.S. 551, 564-68 (2005) (evaluating whether there was truly a national consensus against imposition of a juvenile death penalty and finding it persuasive that a majority of states had rejected such a penalty).
    • See Roper v. Simmons, 543 U.S. 551, 564-68 (2005) (evaluating whether there was truly a "national consensus" against imposition of a juvenile death penalty and finding it persuasive that a majority of states had rejected such a penalty).
  • 175
    • 37849032305 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 572, 576 (2003).
    • See Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 572, 576 (2003).
  • 176
    • 37849046368 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See VERMEULE, supra note 17, at 239
    • See VERMEULE, supra note 17, at 239.
  • 177
    • 37849037224 scopus 로고
    • 467 U.S, famously holds that courts must respect agency interpretations of ambiguous terms, so long as those interpretations are reasonable. Chevron can therefore be understood as a testimonial to judicial humility in the face of statutory ambiguity, not for Condorcetian reasons, but because of a belief in the superior accountability and technical specialization of the relevant agency
    • Chevron U.S.A. Inc. v. Natural Resources Defense Council, Inc., 467 U.S. 837 (1984), famously holds that courts must respect agency interpretations of ambiguous terms, so long as those interpretations are reasonable. Chevron can therefore be understood as a testimonial to judicial humility in the face of statutory ambiguity, not for Condorcetian reasons, but because of a belief in the superior accountability and technical specialization of the relevant agency.
    • (1984) Chevron U.S.A. Inc. v. Natural Resources Defense Council, Inc , pp. 837
  • 178
    • 0036949036 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Einer Elhauge, Preference-Estimating Statutory Default Rules, 102 COLUM. L. REV. 2027 (2002) (arguing that statutes might be interpreted by reference to the preferences of the current legislature).
    • Cf. Einer Elhauge, Preference-Estimating Statutory Default Rules, 102 COLUM. L. REV. 2027 (2002) (arguing that statutes might be interpreted by reference to the preferences of the current legislature).
  • 179
    • 37849034032 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see id
    • But see id.
  • 180
    • 37849047163 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 97
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 97.
  • 181
    • 37849031173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Elhauge, supra note 145
    • See Elhauge, supra note 145.
  • 182
    • 37849026333 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Consider Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479 (1965),
    • Consider Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479 (1965),
  • 183
    • 37849009606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in which the Court struck down a ban on the use of contraceptives by married people, a ban that was limited to two states and that was widely regarded as indefensible or even outrageous within the nation. See POSNER, supra note 128, at 326. In a federal system, it is entirely predictable that one state will sometimes engage in actions that other states will find outrageous.
    • in which the Court struck down a ban on the use of contraceptives by married people, a ban that was limited to two states and that was widely regarded as indefensible or even outrageous within the nation. See POSNER, supra note 128, at 326. In a federal system, it is entirely predictable that one state will sometimes engage in actions that other states will find outrageous.
  • 184
    • 84963456897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • notes 139-41 and accompanying text
    • See supra notes 139-41 and accompanying text.
    • See supra
  • 185
    • 37849035631 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Nadler et al., supra note 78 (considering such widespread disapproval with respect to Kelo v. City of New London, 545 U.S. 469 (2005)).
    • See Nadler et al., supra note 78 (considering such widespread disapproval with respect to Kelo v. City of New London, 545 U.S. 469 (2005)).
  • 186
    • 37849034329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 187
    • 37849046367 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • But see Griswold, 381 U.S. 479.
    • But see Griswold, 381 U.S. 479.
  • 188
    • 37849020446 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Validation of the statute in Griswold, even in 1965, would have met widespread public disapproval. See POSNER, supra note 128, at 324-31.
    • Validation of the statute in Griswold, even in 1965, would have met widespread public disapproval. See POSNER, supra note 128, at 324-31.
  • 189
    • 37849043602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • DWORKIN, note 97, at
    • Cf. DWORKIN, supra note 97, at 148.
    • supra , pp. 148
    • Cf1
  • 190
    • 37849038234 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I do not mean to suggest that these positions are, in fact, compelled by the original understanding
    • I do not mean to suggest that these positions are, in fact, compelled by the original understanding.
  • 191
    • 37849045229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is apparently Justice Thomas's view; Justice Scalia has said that Justice Thomas doesn't believe in stare decisis, period, I]f a constitutional line of authority is wrong, Thomas] would say 'Let's get it right, I wouldn't do that. Stephen B. Presser, Touting Thomas, LEGAL AFF, Jan.-Feb. 2005, at 68, 68-69, available at
    • This is apparently Justice Thomas's view; Justice Scalia has said that Justice Thomas "doesn't believe in stare decisis, period. . . . [I]f a constitutional line of authority is wrong, [Thomas] would say 'Let's get it right.' I wouldn't do that." Stephen B. Presser, Touting Thomas, LEGAL AFF., Jan.-Feb. 2005, at 68, 68-69, available at http://www.legalaffairs.org/issues/January-February-2005/ review_presser_janfeb05.msp.
  • 192
    • 37848999308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Prakash, supra note 36, at 2210-11
    • See Prakash, supra note 36, at 2210-11.
  • 193
    • 37849023716 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Antonin Scalia, Originalism: The Lesser Evil, 57 U. CLN. L. REV. 849 (1989).
    • See Antonin Scalia, Originalism: The Lesser Evil, 57 U. CLN. L. REV. 849 (1989).
  • 194
    • 37849014538 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Posting of Randy Barnett to Debate Club, Constitution in Exile?, http://legalaffairs.org/webexclusive/debateclub_cie0505.msp (May 3, 2005, 1:43 P.M.).
    • Posting of Randy Barnett to Debate Club, Constitution in Exile?, http://legalaffairs.org/webexclusive/debateclub_cie0505.msp (May 3, 2005, 1:43 P.M.).
  • 195
    • 37849001693 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See RONALD DWORKIN, FREEDOM'S LAW: THE MORAL READING OF THE AMERICAN CONSTITUTION (1996).
    • See RONALD DWORKIN, FREEDOM'S LAW: THE MORAL READING OF THE AMERICAN CONSTITUTION (1996).
  • 196
    • 37849040925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003);
    • See, e.g., Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003);
  • 197
    • 37848998697 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brown v. Bd. of Educ., 347 U.S. 483 (1954).
    • Brown v. Bd. of Educ., 347 U.S. 483 (1954).
  • 198
    • 37848998699 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 97, at 239
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 97, at 239.
  • 199
    • 37849036229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., United States v. Virginia, 518 U.S. 515 (1996) (sex discrimination);
    • See, e.g., United States v. Virginia, 518 U.S. 515 (1996) (sex discrimination);
  • 200
    • 37849023714 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395 U.S. 444 (1969) (censorship);
    • Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395 U.S. 444 (1969) (censorship);
  • 201
    • 37849021238 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Brown, 347 U.S. 483 (school desegregation).
    • Brown, 347 U.S. 483 (school desegregation).
  • 202
    • 37849003375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 160;
    • See DWORKIN, supra note 160;
  • 203
    • 37849027771 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • FLEMING, supra note 41
    • FLEMING, supra note 41.
  • 204
    • 37849016567 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. 397 (1989).
    • See Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. 397 (1989).
  • 205
    • 37849012480 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • As many as 79% of Americans disapproved of this decision. Nadler et al., supra note 78, at 16.
    • As many as 79% of Americans disapproved of this decision. Nadler et al., supra note 78, at 16.
  • 206
    • 37849028845 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sch. Dist. of Abington Twp. v. Schempp, 374 U.S. 203 (1963).
    • Sch. Dist. of Abington Twp. v. Schempp, 374 U.S. 203 (1963).
  • 207
    • 37849054229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The rate of disapproval of the Court's school prayer decisions was as high as 67% in the period 1974-2005. Nadler et al., supra note 78, at 16.
    • The rate of disapproval of the Court's school prayer decisions was as high as 67% in the period 1974-2005. Nadler et al., supra note 78, at 16.
  • 208
    • 36348992232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, U.S
    • See Kelo v. City of New London, 545 U.S. 469 (2005).
    • (2005) City of New London , vol.545 , pp. 469
    • Kelo1
  • 209
    • 37849045228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, note 78, at, reporting 80-90% disapproval rate
    • See Nadler et al., supra note 78, at 16 (reporting 80-90% disapproval rate).
    • supra , pp. 16
    • Nadler1
  • 210
    • 37849038545 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Brown v. Bd. of Educ., 347 U.S. 483 (1954).
    • See Brown v. Bd. of Educ., 347 U.S. 483 (1954).
  • 211
    • 37849009607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here the disapproval rate ranged from 40-45%. Nadler et al., supra note 78, at 16.
    • Here the disapproval rate ranged from 40-45%. Nadler et al., supra note 78, at 16.
  • 212
    • 37849034549 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973).
    • See Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973).
  • 214
    • 37849030102 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See KRAMER, supra note 4
    • See KRAMER, supra note 4.
  • 215
    • 37849054230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See FLEMING, supra note 41
    • See FLEMING, supra note 41.
  • 216
    • 33846585474 scopus 로고
    • Fair Measure: The Legal Status of Underenforced Constitutional Norms, 91
    • See
    • See Lawrence Gene Sager, Fair Measure: The Legal Status of Underenforced Constitutional Norms, 91 HARV. L. REV. 1212 (1978).
    • (1978) HARV. L. REV , vol.1212
    • Gene Sager, L.1
  • 217
    • 37849029451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Note, for example, President Reagan's executive orders on federalism and takings. Exec. Order No. 12,612, 52 Fed. Reg. 41,685 (Oct. 26, 1987) (requiring that executive agencies follow certain enumerated principles of federalism and consult states to the extent practicable before pursuing policies that would limit state policymaking discretion);
    • Note, for example, President Reagan's executive orders on federalism and takings. Exec. Order No. 12,612, 52 Fed. Reg. 41,685 (Oct. 26, 1987) (requiring that executive agencies follow certain enumerated principles of federalism and consult states to the extent practicable before pursuing policies that would limit state "policymaking discretion");
  • 218
    • 37849027488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Exec. Order No. 12,630, 53 Fed. Reg. 8859 (Mar. 15, 1988, reprinted in 5 U.S.C. § 601 2000, requiring executive agencies to conduct takings impact assessments when making regulatory decisions that may impact private property rights
    • Exec. Order No. 12,630, 53 Fed. Reg. 8859 (Mar. 15, 1988), reprinted in 5 U.S.C. § 601 (2000) (requiring executive agencies to conduct takings impact assessments when making regulatory decisions that may impact private property rights).
  • 219
    • 37849050461 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a recent example, see Kelo and the public reaction thereto, as explored in Nadler et al., supra note 78.
    • For a recent example, see Kelo and the public reaction thereto, as explored in Nadler et al., supra note 78.
  • 221
    • 37849018170 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See JANET E. HALLEY, DON'T: A READER'S GUIDE TO THE MILITARY'S ANTI- GAY POLICY (1999).
    • See JANET E. HALLEY, DON'T: A READER'S GUIDE TO THE MILITARY'S ANTI- GAY POLICY (1999).
  • 222
    • 37849020668 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BICKEL, supra note 2, at 64-68;
    • See BICKEL, supra note 2, at 64-68;
  • 223
    • 37849036952 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • HARRY V. JAFFA, CRISIS OF THE HOUSE DIVIDED (1959).
    • HARRY V. JAFFA, CRISIS OF THE HOUSE DIVIDED (1959).
  • 224
    • 37849046868 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • BICKEL, supra note 2, at 66
    • BICKEL, supra note 2, at 66
  • 225
    • 37849017862 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (quoting II THE COLLECTED WORKS OF ABRAHAM LINCOLN 256 (Roy P. Basler ed., 1953) (speech at Peoria, Illinois, Oct. 16, 1854)).
    • (quoting II THE COLLECTED WORKS OF ABRAHAM LINCOLN 256 (Roy P. Basler ed., 1953) (speech at Peoria, Illinois, Oct. 16, 1854)).
  • 226
    • 37849042768 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 227
    • 37849001093 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See BICKEL, supra note 2, at 68-69
    • See BICKEL, supra note 2, at 68-69.
  • 228
    • 37849016118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See PITKIN, supra note 177
    • See PITKIN, supra note 177.
  • 229
    • 37849008427 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The latter view is implicit in The Federalist No. 10, with its reference to refin[ing] and enlarg[ing] the public view. THE FEDERALIST No. 10, at 47 (James Madison) (George W. Carey & James McClellan eds., 1989).
    • The latter view is implicit in The Federalist No. 10, with its reference to "refin[ing] and enlarg[ing]" the public view. THE FEDERALIST No. 10, at 47 (James Madison) (George W. Carey & James McClellan eds., 1989).
  • 230
    • 0032391326 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For evidence that the moral views of the jury are indeed likely to be representative of the moral views of the public, see Daniel Kahneman et al, Shared Outrage and Erratic Awards: The Psychology of Punitive Damages, 16 J. RISK & UNCERTAINTY 49 1998
    • For evidence that the moral views of the jury are indeed likely to be representative of the moral views of the public, see Daniel Kahneman et al., Shared Outrage and Erratic Awards: The Psychology of Punitive Damages, 16 J. RISK & UNCERTAINTY 49 (1998).
  • 231
    • 37849012479 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Consider the discussion of the deliberative opinion poll in JAMES S. FISHKIN, THE VOICE OF THE PEOPLE (1995). Fishkin convincingly contends that the results of a deliberative poll, conducted among informed citizens, are far more worthwhile than the results of a mere opinion poll, conducted by asking people simply to state their views on questions on which they have not reflected. A jury has an analogous advantage over the public generally.
    • Consider the discussion of the deliberative opinion poll in JAMES S. FISHKIN, THE VOICE OF THE PEOPLE (1995). Fishkin convincingly contends that the results of a deliberative poll, conducted among informed citizens, are far more worthwhile than the results of a mere opinion poll, conducted by asking people simply to state their views on questions on which they have not reflected. A jury has an analogous advantage over the public generally.
  • 232
    • 37849013233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g, Steiker, supra note 74
    • See, e.g., Steiker, supra note 74.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.