메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 11, Issue 4, 2007, Pages 377-403

Intransitivity and vague preferences

Author keywords

Preference; Rational choice theory; Rationality; Transitivity; Vagueness

Indexed keywords


EID: 34548583756     PISSN: 13824554     EISSN: 15728609     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1007/s10892-005-7977-9     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (11)

References (85)
  • 1
    • 84971936140 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I believe transitivity and reflexiveness are requirements of logic, because any comparative relation... must conform to them, J. Broome, Deontology and Economics, Economics and Philosophy 8 (1992), p. 274.
    • "I believe transitivity and reflexiveness are requirements of logic, because any comparative relation... must conform to them," J. Broome, "Deontology and Economics," Economics and Philosophy 8 (1992), p. 274.
  • 3
    • 0006979404 scopus 로고
    • The Irrationality of Intransitivity
    • G. Tullock, "The Irrationality of Intransitivity," Oxford Economic Papers 16 (1964), pp. 401-406.
    • (1964) Oxford Economic Papers , vol.16 , pp. 401-406
    • Tullock, G.1
  • 4
    • 0006661302 scopus 로고
    • The Philosophy of Intransitive Preference
    • For critiques, see
    • For critiques, see P. Anand, "The Philosophy of Intransitive Preference," Economic Journal 103 (1993), pp. 337-346;
    • (1993) Economic Journal , vol.103 , pp. 337-346
    • Anand, P.1
  • 5
    • 0042860418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why Preference is Not Transitive
    • S. Gendin, "Why Preference is Not Transitive," The Philosophical Quarterly 46 (1996), pp. 482-488;
    • (1996) The Philosophical Quarterly , vol.46 , pp. 482-488
    • Gendin, S.1
  • 6
    • 0347204280 scopus 로고
    • Rationality and Intransitive Preferences
    • R. Hughes, "Rationality and Intransitive Preferences," Analysis 40 (1980), pp. 132-143;
    • (1980) Analysis , vol.40 , pp. 132-143
    • Hughes, R.1
  • 7
    • 84929068446 scopus 로고
    • Must Rational Preferences be Transitive?
    • M. Philips, "Must Rational Preferences be Transitive?" The Philosophical Quarterly 39 (1989), pp. 477-483.
    • (1989) The Philosophical Quarterly , vol.39 , pp. 477-483
    • Philips, M.1
  • 8
    • 0042735375 scopus 로고
    • How Vicious are Cycles of Intransitive Choice?
    • offer a lengthy review of many multidimensional examples of intransitive preference
    • M. Bar-Hillel and A. Margalit, "How Vicious are Cycles of Intransitive Choice?" Theory and Decision 24 (1988), pp. 119-145, offer a lengthy review of many multidimensional examples of intransitive preference.
    • (1988) Theory and Decision , vol.24 , pp. 119-145
    • Bar-Hillel, M.1    Margalit, A.2
  • 10
    • 33745298630 scopus 로고
    • Can a Humean Be Moderate?
    • R. Frey and C. Morris eds, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • J. Broome, "Can a Humean Be Moderate?" in R. Frey and C. Morris (eds.), Value, Welfare and Morality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), p. 53;
    • (1993) Value, Welfare and Morality , pp. 53
    • Broome, J.1
  • 11
    • 0004241736 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • S. Hurley, Natural Reasons (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989);
    • (1989) Natural Reasons
    • Hurley, S.1
  • 12
    • 0001202145 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Maximization and the Act of Choice
    • and A. Sen, "Maximization and the Act of Choice," Econometrica 65 (1997), pp. 745-779,
    • (1997) Econometrica , vol.65 , pp. 745-779
    • Sen, A.1
  • 13
    • 34548555901 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • have all discussed individuation in detail, while P. Anand, Foundations of Rational Choice Under Risk (Oxford: Clarendon, 1993), pp. 103-106, has argued that any set of intransitive preferences can be given a transitive re-description, and vice-versa.
    • have all discussed individuation in detail, while P. Anand, Foundations of Rational Choice Under Risk (Oxford: Clarendon, 1993), pp. 103-106, has argued that any set of intransitive preferences can be given a transitive re-description, and vice-versa.
  • 14
    • 33750000372 scopus 로고
    • A Theory of Beneficence,
    • I thank an anonymous referee for pressing this point. See, unpublished undergraduate thesis, University of Oxford
    • I thank an anonymous referee for pressing this point. See S. Rachels, "A Theory of Beneficence," unpublished undergraduate thesis, University of Oxford, 1993;
    • (1993)
    • Rachels, S.1
  • 15
    • 22544472841 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Counterexamples to the Transitivity of Better Than
    • S. Rachels, "Counterexamples to the Transitivity of Better Than," Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76 (1998), pp. 71-83;
    • (1998) Australasian Journal of Philosophy , vol.76 , pp. 71-83
    • Rachels, S.1
  • 16
    • 1042287762 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Continuum Argument for Intransitivity
    • L. Temkin, "A Continuum Argument for Intransitivity," Philosophy and Public Affairs 25 (1996), pp. 175-210.
    • (1996) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.25 , pp. 175-210
    • Temkin, L.1
  • 17
    • 2142737476 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • An interesting discussion may be found in P. Mongin, Does Optimization Imply Rationality? Synthese 124 2000, pp. 73-111. Mongin is very sympathetic to the possibility of rational intransitive preferences, but implies that all existing examples of intransitivity rely heavily on their multidimensionality. Notably he assumes the coherence of the uni/multidimensional distinction without defining or defending it
    • An interesting discussion may be found in P. Mongin, "Does Optimization Imply Rationality?" Synthese 124 (2000), pp. 73-111. Mongin is very sympathetic to the possibility of rational intransitive preferences, but implies that all existing examples of intransitivity rely heavily on their multidimensionality. Notably he assumes the coherence of the uni/multidimensional distinction without defining or defending it.
  • 18
    • 34548577134 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The following all provide examples which make such an assumption: W. Armstrong, Uncertainty and the Utility Function, Economic Journal 58 (1948), pp. 1-10;
    • The following all provide examples which make such an assumption: W. Armstrong, "Uncertainty and the Utility Function," Economic Journal 58 (1948), pp. 1-10;
  • 19
    • 0000365128 scopus 로고
    • Intransitive Indifference with Unequal Indifference Intervals
    • P. Fishburn, "Intransitive Indifference with Unequal Indifference Intervals," Journal of Mathematical Psychology 7 (1970), pp. 144-149;
    • (1970) Journal of Mathematical Psychology , vol.7 , pp. 144-149
    • Fishburn, P.1
  • 22
    • 0346763532 scopus 로고
    • The Puzzle of the Self-Torturer
    • W. Quinn, "The Puzzle of the Self-Torturer," Philosophical Studies 59 (1990), pp. 79-90.
    • (1990) Philosophical Studies , vol.59 , pp. 79-90
    • Quinn, W.1
  • 23
    • 34548565920 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Perceiving Imperceptible Harms
    • M. Almeida ed, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers
    • D. Regan, "Perceiving Imperceptible Harms," in M. Almeida (ed.), Imperceptible Harms and Benefits (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2000), pp. 4973.
    • (2000) Imperceptible Harms and Benefits , pp. 4973
    • Regan, D.1
  • 24
    • 34548558956 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bounded rationality here follows H. Simon's usage to describe a decisionmaker whose reasoning and calculating capacities are both limited and prone to error. See H. Simon, Models of Bounded Rationality (Cambridge: The MIT Press, 1983).
    • "Bounded rationality" here follows H. Simon's usage to describe a decisionmaker whose reasoning and calculating capacities are both limited and prone to error. See H. Simon, Models of Bounded Rationality (Cambridge: The MIT Press, 1983).
  • 25
    • 34548572160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Or some variation on this formulation. For example, the agent may be indifferent between successive developments of the magnitude specified in the DC example, unless a threshold level of development has been crossed, after which she ceases to be indifferent. Or the threshold may be defined as a proportion rather than a level, etc. These possibilities are ignored for the sake of simplicity in what follows; they either make no difference to the argument in this paragraph, or strengthen it.
    • Or some variation on this formulation. For example, the agent may be indifferent between successive developments of the magnitude specified in the DC example, unless a threshold level of development has been crossed, after which she ceases to be indifferent. Or the threshold may be defined as a proportion rather than a level, etc. These possibilities are ignored for the sake of simplicity in what follows; they either make no difference to the argument in this paragraph, or strengthen it.
  • 26
    • 34548550555 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A related point is developed in more detail in Regan, Perceiving Imperceptible Harms, pp. 59-60, in connection with Quinn's self-torturer example.
    • A related point is developed in more detail in Regan, "Perceiving Imperceptible Harms," pp. 59-60, in connection with Quinn's self-torturer example.
  • 30
    • 14544296315 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Language-Mastery and the Sorites Paradox
    • R. Keefe and P. Smith eds, Cambridge: The MIT press
    • C. Wright, "Language-Mastery and the Sorites Paradox," in R. Keefe and P. Smith (eds.), Vagueness: A Reader (Cambridge: The MIT press, 1996), p. 156.
    • (1996) Vagueness: A Reader , pp. 156
    • Wright, C.1
  • 35
    • 34548577133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It might be objected that spoilt could have a meaning involving, say, expert assessment of the viability of the land as a particular species habitat. But this sense of spoilt is not the one at work in the DC example.
    • It might be objected that "spoilt" could have a meaning involving, say, expert assessment of the viability of the land as a particular species habitat. But this sense of "spoilt" is not the one at work in the DC example.
  • 39
    • 34548567208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Book-length treatments of vagueness include L. Burns, Vagueness: An Investigation Into Natural Languages and the Sorites Paradox (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1991);
    • Book-length treatments of vagueness include L. Burns, Vagueness: An Investigation Into Natural Languages and the Sorites Paradox (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1991);
  • 41
    • 34548573011 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and R. Keefe and P. Smith (eds.), Vagueness: A Reader (Cambridge: The MIT Press, 1996).
    • and R. Keefe and P. Smith (eds.), Vagueness: A Reader (Cambridge: The MIT Press, 1996).
  • 43
    • 34548558954 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • If the interpretation is that rational preferences - what the rational agent ought to prefer - exist, but are unknowable to the agent or anyone else, then Completeness is not threatened. However, unknowable preferences appear to be incomplete preferences according to the originators of the axiom: J. von Neumann, and O. Morgenstern, Theory of Games and Economic Behavior (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1944), p. 19,
    • If the interpretation is that rational preferences - what the rational agent ought to prefer - exist, but are unknowable to the agent or anyone else, then Completeness is not threatened. However, unknowable preferences appear to be incomplete preferences according to the originators of the axiom: J. von Neumann, and O. Morgenstern, Theory of Games and Economic Behavior (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1944), p. 19,
  • 44
    • 34548561801 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • describe incompleteness as where the individual is neither able to state which of two alternatives he prefers nor that they are equally desirable; L. Savage, The Foundations of Statistics (New York: Dover Press, 1954), p. 21, refers to introspective sensations of indecision or vacillation, which we may be reluctant to identify with indifference.
    • describe incompleteness as "where the individual is neither able to state which of two alternatives he prefers nor that they are equally desirable;" L. Savage, The Foundations of Statistics (New York: Dover Press, 1954), p. 21, refers to "introspective sensations of indecision or vacillation, which we may be reluctant to identify with indifference."
  • 45
    • 34548573007 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Consider the instance where α= 100 so (¬S1) is if a 100 grained collection is a heap, then a 99 grained collection is not a heap. Consider the sharpening of heap which treats all 99 or more grained collections as heaps and all smaller collections as non-heaps. Then an (x-1) grained collection is not a heap will be false for α = 100. On. the proposed sharpening, the consequent of ¬S1) is false even though the antecedent is true. Thus(¬S1) is false. By the law of excluded middlfi,¬(¬S1)⇒(S1). On the proposed sharpening, (S1) is true. Since (S1) can be false if and only if false with respect to all sharpenings, it is not false for α= 100. Similar reasoning demonstrates this result for other instances.
    • Consider the instance where α= 100 so (¬S1) is "if a 100 grained collection is a heap, then a 99 grained collection is not a heap." Consider the sharpening of heap which treats all "99 or more" grained collections as heaps and all smaller collections as non-heaps. Then "an (x-1) grained collection is not a heap" will be false for α = 100. On. the proposed sharpening, the consequent of ¬S1) is false even though the antecedent is true. Thus(¬S1) is false. By the law of excluded middlfi,¬(¬S1)⇒(S1). On the proposed sharpening, (S1) is true. Since (S1) can be false if and only if false with respect to all sharpenings, it is not false for α= 100. Similar reasoning demonstrates this result for other instances.
  • 46
    • 34548580454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Consider the instance where α = 100 and the sharpening of heap which treats all 100 or more grained collections as heaps and all smaller collections as non-heaps. Then an (α-1) grained collection is a heap will not be true for a = 100. On the proposed sharpening, the consequent is false even though the antecedent is true. Thus (S1) is false.
    • Consider the instance where α = 100 and the sharpening of heap which treats all "100 or more" grained collections as heaps and all smaller collections as non-heaps. Then "an (α-1) grained collection is a heap" will not be true for a = 100. On the proposed sharpening, the consequent is false even though the antecedent is true. Thus (S1) is false.
  • 47
    • 0344771461 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The non-standard behaviour of universal and existential quantifiers in supervaluationism is a persistent source of confusion. On the supervaluational account, a universally quantified proposition can be false, even though no instance is false; an existentially quantified proposition can be true, even though, no instance is true. Thus although supervaluationism recognises no sharp boundary, it holds that (E2) is true, since for every possible sharpening, we can pick some t to make (E2) true. However if we pick t first, so to speak, pick a particular instance of (E2, it will not be true on every possible sharpening, so not true. See M. Dummett, Wang's Paradox, Synthese 30 1975, pp. 301- 324
    • The non-standard behaviour of universal and existential quantifiers in supervaluationism is a persistent source of confusion. On the supervaluational account, a universally quantified proposition can be false, even though no instance is false; an existentially quantified proposition can be true, even though, no instance is true. Thus although supervaluationism recognises no sharp boundary, it holds that (E2) is true, since for every possible sharpening, we can pick some t to make (E2) true. However if we pick t first, so to speak - pick a particular instance of (E2) - it will not be true on every possible sharpening, so not true. See M. Dummett, "Wang's Paradox," Synthese 30 (1975), pp. 301- 324.
  • 48
    • 33845263287 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Vagueness by Degrees
    • R. Keefe and P. Smith eds, Cambridge: The MIT Press, argues this point persuasively using a preference-based example
    • D. Edgington, "Vagueness by Degrees," in R. Keefe and P. Smith (eds.), Vagueness: A Reader (Cambridge: The MIT Press, 1996), pp. 294-316, argues this point persuasively using a preference-based example.
    • (1996) Vagueness: A Reader , pp. 294-316
    • Edgington, D.1
  • 51
    • 0010023020 scopus 로고
    • Vagueness by Degrees;" K. Machina, "Truth, Belief and Vagueness
    • Edgington, "Vagueness by Degrees;" K. Machina, "Truth, Belief and Vagueness," Journal of Philosophical Logic 5 (1976), pp. 47-78.
    • (1976) Journal of Philosophical Logic , vol.5 , pp. 47-78
    • Edgington1
  • 52
    • 34548572157 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It might be objected that normative theories of rational choice often talk of irrationalities by agents, such, as imperfect calculating capacity, even though it is readily conceded that no human will be perfect in this respect. Thus the ignorance springing from epistemic vagueness is not improperly described as irrational. Reply: (i) While a transitive imperfect calculator agent is typically held to be boundedly rational, I know of no standard theory which grants an intransitive perfect calculator the same status. Rather, the latter type is labelled irrational, the status of intransitivity is not the same as that of imperfect calculation, ii) On the epistemic theory, universal ignorance is not an incidental empirical observation, but essential to the account. Vagueness could not be understood without human failure, while there are agents with perfect calculating powers in some situations I have in mind the rare people who can perform
    • It might be objected that normative theories of rational choice often talk of "irrationalities" by agents, such, as imperfect calculating capacity, even though it is readily conceded that no human will be perfect in this respect. Thus the ignorance springing from epistemic vagueness is not improperly described as irrational. Reply: (i) While a "transitive imperfect calculator" agent is typically held to be "boundedly rational," I know of no standard theory which grants an intransitive perfect calculator the same status. Rather, the latter type is labelled irrational - the status of intransitivity is not the same as that of imperfect calculation, (ii) On the epistemic theory, universal ignorance is not an incidental empirical observation, but essential to the account. Vagueness could not be understood without human failure, while there are agents with perfect calculating powers in some situations (I have in mind the rare people who can perform complex integrations in their head).
  • 53
    • 34548577131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Quinn, The Puzzle of the Self-Torturer, Temkin, A Continuum Argument for Intransitivity.
    • Quinn, "The Puzzle of the Self-Torturer," Temkin, "A Continuum Argument for Intransitivity."
  • 54
    • 34548570187 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • M. Almeida, ed, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers
    • M. Almeida, (ed.) Imperceptible Harms and Benefits (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2000).
    • (2000) Imperceptible Harms and Benefits
  • 55
    • 0003983843 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • J. Broome, Ethics Out of Economics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), p. 9.
    • (1999) Ethics Out of Economics , pp. 9
    • Broome, J.1
  • 57
    • 0348024652 scopus 로고
    • Self Torturer;" G. Schumm, "Transitivity, Preference and Indifference
    • Quinn, "Self Torturer;" G. Schumm, "Transitivity, Preference and Indifference," Philosophical Studies 52 (1987), pp. 435-437.
    • (1987) Philosophical Studies , vol.52 , pp. 435-437
    • Quinn1
  • 58
    • 34548591441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This view of decision theorists is explicitly stated in both. Mongin, Does Optimization Imply Rationality? p. 80
    • This view of decision theorists is explicitly stated in both. Mongin, "Does Optimization Imply Rationality?" p. 80,
  • 61
    • 0003506006 scopus 로고
    • New York: Wiley, are two classics in decision theory which endorse intransitive indifference, although Fishburn at least went on to accept intransitive strict preference too
    • and P. Fishburn, Utility Theory for Decision-Making (New York: Wiley, 1970) are two classics in decision theory which endorse intransitive indifference, although Fishburn at least went on to accept intransitive strict preference too.
    • (1970) Utility Theory for Decision-Making
    • Fishburn, P.1
  • 64
    • 34548570186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This presentation of the Schumm model is due to W. Rabinowicz, Money Pump with Foresight, in M. Almeida (ed, Imperceptible Harms and Benefits Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic publishers, 2000, pp. 123-154
    • This presentation of the Schumm model is due to W. Rabinowicz, "Money Pump with Foresight," in M. Almeida (ed.), Imperceptible Harms and Benefits (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic publishers, 2000), pp. 123-154.
  • 66
    • 34548558955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Mongin, Optimization, p. 80; Rabinowicz, Money Pump with Foresight, p. 128.
    • See Mongin, "Optimization," p. 80; Rabinowicz, "Money Pump with Foresight," p. 128.
  • 67
    • 34548593465 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the next sub-section for a statement of the argument
    • See the next sub-section for a statement of the argument.
  • 69
    • 0006657077 scopus 로고
    • Outlines of a Formal Theory of Value, I
    • The argument was initiated by, they developed a suggestion by Frank Ramsey
    • The argument was initiated by D. Davidson, J. McKinsey, and P. Suppes, "Outlines of a Formal Theory of Value, I," Philosophy of Science 22 (1955), pp. 140160; they developed a suggestion by Frank Ramsey.
    • (1955) Philosophy of Science , vol.22 , pp. 140160
    • Davidson, D.1    McKinsey, J.2    Suppes, P.3
  • 70
    • 84963437832 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Put differently, standard money pumps require the assumption that the agent's preference between any two successive stages in the cycle is strong enough not to be reversed by her payment to move along a stage. The analogous assumption here is that the agent's preference between end states of the cycle is strong enough not to be reversed by the sum of small payments she has received along the way. There may be a problem with these assumptions (or relatedly, with the assumption that each such payment is arbitrarily small, but this does not disturb the analogy between Dodgy Developers' activities and standard money pumps S. Hansson, Money Pumps, Self-Torturers and the Demons of Real Life, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (1993, pp. 476-485, has shown formally that the only difference between money pumps based on indifference cycles and standard cyclic preference pumps is that the former make an additional mild (and uncontroversial) monotonicity assumption
    • Put differently, standard money pumps require the assumption that the agent's preference between any two successive stages in the cycle is strong enough not to be reversed by her payment to move along a stage. The analogous assumption here is that the agent's preference between end states of the cycle is strong enough not to be reversed by the sum of small payments she has received along the way. There may be a problem with these assumptions (or relatedly, with the assumption that each such payment is arbitrarily small), but this does not disturb the analogy between Dodgy Developers' activities and standard money pumps S. Hansson, "Money Pumps, Self-Torturers and the Demons of Real Life," Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (1993), pp. 476-485, has shown formally that the only difference between money pumps based on indifference cycles and standard cyclic preference pumps is that the former make an additional mild (and uncontroversial) monotonicity assumption.
  • 72
    • 0003048369 scopus 로고
    • Dutch Bookies and Money Pumps
    • F. Schick, "Dutch Bookies and Money Pumps," The Journal of Philosophy 83 (1986), p. 118.
    • (1986) The Journal of Philosophy , vol.83 , pp. 118
    • Schick, F.1
  • 74
    • 0035190951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is a large literature on the money pump but two important recent contributions are made by R. Cubitt, and R. Sugden, On Money Pumps, Games and Economic Behavior 37 (2001), pp. 121-160, and Rabinowicz, Money Pump. After a very formal, analysis, Cubitt and Sugden conclude that the money pump objection to intransitivity does not stand. Rabinowicz's position is more complicated, but his ultimate conclusion also rejects the money pump argument.
    • There is a large literature on the money pump but two important recent contributions are made by R. Cubitt, and R. Sugden, "On Money Pumps," Games and Economic Behavior 37 (2001), pp. 121-160, and Rabinowicz, "Money Pump." After a very formal, analysis, Cubitt and Sugden conclude that the money pump objection to intransitivity does not stand. Rabinowicz's position is more complicated, but his ultimate conclusion also rejects the money pump argument.
  • 75
    • 33745290809 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Money Pump Revisited
    • See also
    • See also J. Aldred, "The Money Pump Revisited," Risk, Decision and Policy 8 (2003), pp. 59-76.
    • (2003) Risk, Decision and Policy , vol.8 , pp. 59-76
    • Aldred, J.1
  • 76
    • 34548596836 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Quinn, The Puzzle of the Self-Torturer, Rachels, Counterexamples, Temkin, A Continuum Argument.
    • Quinn, "The Puzzle of the Self-Torturer," Rachels, "Counterexamples," Temkin, "A Continuum Argument."
  • 77
    • 22544480957 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A. Set of Solutions to Parfit's Problems
    • Rachels, "A. Set of Solutions to Parfit's Problems," Nous 35 (2001), pp. 214238.
    • (2001) Nous , vol.35 , pp. 214238
    • Rachels1
  • 79
    • 34548596837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Anand's ideas are anticipated by T. Schwartz, Rationality and the Myth of the Maximum, Noûs 6 (1972), pp. 97-117.
    • Anand's ideas are anticipated by T. Schwartz, "Rationality and the Myth of the Maximum," Noûs 6 (1972), pp. 97-117.
  • 80
    • 34548555900 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is true that a well-known principle, variously known as the Chemoff or contraction condition or Property a, allows us to deduce binary preferences from ternary ones. However, the contraction condition is closely linked to transitivity (formulations of both, axioms vary, but in most versions contraction implies transitivity), so the appeal probably begs the question. Moreover, A, Sen,Is the Idea of Purely Internal Consistency of Choice Bizarre? in J. Altham and R. Harrison (eds.), World, Mind and Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1.995), has developed a number of examples and arguments suggesting the contraction condition is implausible.
    • It is true that a well-known principle, variously known as the Chemoff or contraction condition or Property a, allows us to deduce binary preferences from ternary ones. However, the contraction condition is closely linked to transitivity (formulations of both, axioms vary, but in most versions contraction implies transitivity), so the appeal probably begs the question. Moreover, A, Sen,"Is the Idea of Purely Internal Consistency of Choice Bizarre?" in J. Altham and R. Harrison (eds.), World, Mind and Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1.995), has developed a number of examples and arguments suggesting the contraction condition is implausible.
  • 82
    • 0004293486 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon
    • J. Griffin, Well-Being (Oxford: Clarendon, 1986), p. 96.
    • (1986) Well-Being , pp. 96
    • Griffin, J.1
  • 85
    • 0042370848 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cyclical Preferences and World Bayesianism
    • J. Sobel, "Cyclical Preferences and World Bayesianism," Philosophy of Science 64 (1997), pp. 42-73.
    • (1997) Philosophy of Science , vol.64 , pp. 42-73
    • Sobel, J.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.