메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 27, Issue 3, 2007, Pages 403-427

Raz on detachment, acceptance and describability

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 34548472223     PISSN: 01436503     EISSN: 14643820     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1093/ojls/gqm001     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (37)

References (150)
  • 1
    • 0004220262 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press 2nd edn, at
    • H.L.A. Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press 2nd edn, 1994) at vi.
    • (1994) The Concept of Law
    • Hart, H.L.A.1
  • 3
    • 34548503785 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Such a presumption against describability seems quite common in the present-day humanities in general, including anthropology, as indicated by Clifford Geertz's somewhat bemused characterization of E.E. Evans-Pritchard's writings that I have quoted at the beginning of this article. See Clifford Geertz, Works and Lives: The Anthropologist as Author (Stanford: Stanford University Press 1988) at 68
    • Such a presumption against describability seems quite common in the present-day humanities in general, including anthropology, as indicated by Clifford Geertz's somewhat bemused characterization of E.E. Evans-Pritchard's writings that I have quoted at the beginning of this article. See Clifford Geertz, Works and Lives: The Anthropologist as Author (Stanford: Stanford University Press 1988) at 68.
  • 4
    • 34548500966 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hart, above n 1 at vi, 89-91, 102-3, 291.
    • See Hart, above n 1 at vi, 89-91, 102-3, 291.
  • 5
    • 0001975022 scopus 로고
    • Definition and Theory in Jurisprudence' (1954) in Hart
    • In his inaugural lecture, Hart spoke of the difficulties in defining crucial legal terms, and of an alternative philosophical approach of making careful descriptions of their typical uses in legal contexts. See, Oxford: Clarendon Press, Most likely, Hart was here influenced by the then-prevalent thought that one way of giving an analysis of a word is to describe its typical uses
    • In his inaugural lecture, Hart spoke of the difficulties in defining crucial legal terms, and of an alternative philosophical approach of making careful descriptions of their typical uses in legal contexts. See Hart, 'Definition and Theory in Jurisprudence' (1954) in Hart, Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1983). Most likely, Hart was here influenced by the then-prevalent thought that one way of giving an analysis of a word is to describe its typical uses.
    • (1983) Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy
    • Hart1
  • 6
    • 34548501682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See e.g. Friedrich Waismann, 'How I See Philosophy' (1956) in Waismann, How I See Philosophy (London: MacMillan Press 1968). These semantic ideas provide the theoretical setting for Hart's characterization of internal legal statements in The Concept of Law
    • See e.g. Friedrich Waismann, 'How I See Philosophy' (1956) in Waismann, How I See Philosophy (London: MacMillan Press 1968). These semantic ideas provide the theoretical setting for Hart's characterization of internal legal statements in The Concept of Law
  • 7
    • 34548496822 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Allan Gibbard distinguishes between 'straight' and 'oblique' analyses in his Thinking How to Live (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 2003) at 185. But the idea behind the distinction is of older vintage and can be found in the thought, referred to in the previous note, that one way of giving an analysis of a word is to describe its typical uses.
    • Allan Gibbard distinguishes between 'straight' and 'oblique' analyses in his Thinking How to Live (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 2003) at 185. But the idea behind the distinction is of older vintage and can be found in the thought, referred to in the previous note, that one way of giving an analysis of a word is to describe its typical uses.
  • 8
    • 34548479868 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The only other people that I am aware of are John Devlin and Michael Smith. Devlin was the first to urge me to read Hart as an expressivist
    • The only other people that I am aware of are John Devlin and Michael Smith. Devlin was the first to urge me to read Hart as an expressivist.
  • 9
    • 34548472333 scopus 로고
    • H.L.A. Hart
    • Raz, 'H.L.A. Hart (1907-1992)' (1993) 5 Utilitas 148.
    • (1993) Utilitas , vol.5 , pp. 148
    • Raz1
  • 10
    • 0041339420 scopus 로고
    • The Purity of the Pure Theory
    • See a similar characterization in, 448
    • See a similar characterization in Raz, 'The Purity of the Pure Theory' (1981) 35 Revue International de Philosophie 448.
    • (1981) Revue International de Philosophie , vol.35
    • Raz1
  • 11
    • 85011437030 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart's Expressivism and His Benthamite Project
    • Toh, 'Hart's Expressivism and His Benthamite Project' (2005) 11 Legal Theory 75.
    • (2005) Legal Theory , vol.11 , pp. 75
    • Toh1
  • 12
    • 34548508817 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Considerations for this alteration (as well as some others) are provided ibid at s IV. In formulating (A2) above, I am relying on Robert Stalnaker's pragmatic conception of presupposition. According to that conception, a speaker presupposes a proposition when he takes its truth for granted, and assumes that others involved in the conversation do the same. See Stalnaker, 'Pragmatic Presuppositions' (1974) in Stalnaker, Content and Context (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1999) at 49.
    • Considerations for this alteration (as well as some others) are provided ibid at s IV. In formulating (A2) above, I am relying on Robert Stalnaker's pragmatic conception of presupposition. According to that conception, a speaker presupposes a proposition when he takes its truth for granted, and assumes that others involved in the conversation do the same. See Stalnaker, 'Pragmatic Presuppositions' (1974) in Stalnaker, Content and Context (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1999) at 49.
  • 13
    • 84900538529 scopus 로고
    • Bentham and the Demystification of the Law' (1973) in Hart
    • Oxford: Clarendon Press, at
    • Cf. Hart, 'Bentham and the Demystification of the Law' (1973) in Hart, Essays on Bentham (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1982) at 28.
    • (1982) Essays on Bentham , pp. 28
    • Hart, C.1
  • 14
    • 0004237063 scopus 로고
    • See, Princeton: Princeton University Press 2nd edn, at
    • See Raz, Practical Reason and Norms (Princeton: Princeton University Press 2nd edn, 1990) at 172 3;
    • (1990) Practical Reason and Norms , pp. 172-173
    • Raz1
  • 15
    • 34548508348 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legal Validity' (1977) in Raz, The Authority of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1979) at 155;
    • Legal Validity' (1977) in Raz, The Authority of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1979) at 155;
  • 16
    • 34548474458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Sources, Normativity, and Individuation', postscript to Raz, The Concept of a Legal System (Oxford: Clarendon Press 2nd edn, 1980) at 235-6.
    • 'Sources, Normativity, and Individuation', postscript to Raz, The Concept of a Legal System (Oxford: Clarendon Press 2nd edn, 1980) at 235-6.
  • 17
    • 0041921779 scopus 로고
    • Defeasibility and Meaning
    • See also, P.M.S. Hacker and J. Raz eds, Oxford: Clarendon Press, at
    • See also G.P. Baker, 'Defeasibility and Meaning' in P.M.S. Hacker and J. Raz (eds), Law, Morality, and Society (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1977) at 41-2;
    • (1977) Law, Morality, and Society , pp. 41-42
    • Baker, G.P.1
  • 19
    • 34548478724 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In a comment on an earlier draft of this article, Raz objected to my classification of detached legal statements as internal legal statements. Raz thinks of the phenomenon of detached legal statements as one of the reasons for being sceptical generally about Hart's distinction between internal and external legal statements. I am much more sanguine about Hart's taxonomy. I believe that Hart's distinction is roughly a linguistic variant of the distinction between the deliberative standpoint and the theoretical standpoint, which has been a useful mainstay of philosophy of action and of ethics at least since Kant. In any case, at the beginning of s 2 earlier, I introduced the distinction between the two kinds of legal statements as the distinction between statements of law and statements about laws and legal systems. In light of Hart's analysis of the latter legal statements as descriptions of a community's patterns of behaviour and their psychological attitudes towards such patterns of be
    • In a comment on an earlier draft of this article, Raz objected to my classification of detached legal statements as internal legal statements. Raz thinks of the phenomenon of detached legal statements as one of the reasons for being sceptical generally about Hart's distinction between internal and external legal statements. I am much more sanguine about Hart's taxonomy. I believe that Hart's distinction is roughly a linguistic variant of the distinction between the deliberative standpoint and the theoretical standpoint, which has been a useful mainstay of philosophy of action and of ethics at least since Kant. In any case, at the beginning of s 2 earlier, I introduced the distinction between the two kinds of legal statements as the distinction between statements of law and statements about laws and legal systems. In light of Hart's analysis of the latter legal statements as descriptions of a community's patterns of behaviour and their psychological attitudes towards such patterns of behaviour, we see that Raz's characterization of detached legal statements puts them squarely in the category of internal legal statements: 'A detached legal statement is a statement of law, of what legal rights or duties people have, not a statement about people's beliefs, attitudes or actions, not even about their beliefs, attitudes or actions about the law.' See Raz, 'Legal Validity', above n 12 at 153.
  • 20
    • 34548512958 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Raz, 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm' (1974) in The Authority of Law, above n 12 at 141;
    • See Raz, 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm' (1974) in The Authority of Law, above n 12 at 141;
  • 22
    • 34548476885 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Sources, Normativity, and Individuation', above n 12 at 237;
    • 'Sources, Normativity, and Individuation', above n 12 at 237;
  • 23
    • 34548491325 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'The Purity of the Pure Theory', above n 8 at 453. Interestingly, Hart discusses the phenomenon of detached legal statements, though he does not use that term, in a couple of places that predate Raz's more sustained discussion.
    • 'The Purity of the Pure Theory', above n 8 at 453. Interestingly, Hart discusses the phenomenon of detached legal statements, though he does not use that term, in a couple of places that predate Raz's more sustained discussion.
  • 24
  • 25
    • 34548481453 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart, 'Legal Duty and Obligation' (1966) revised and reprinted in Essays on Bentham, above n 11 at 146. But in these places, Hart does not seem bothered by the fact that the analysis of internal legal statements that he proposes in The Concept of Law does not account for these detached statements.
    • Hart, 'Legal Duty and Obligation' (1966) revised and reprinted in Essays on Bentham, above n 11 at 146. But in these places, Hart does not seem bothered by the fact that the analysis of internal legal statements that he proposes in The Concept of Law does not account for these detached statements.
  • 26
    • 34548484726 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Practical Reason and Norms, above n 12 at 172, 176-7;
    • See Practical Reason and Norms, above n 12 at 172, 176-7;
  • 27
    • 34548502120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Kelsen's General Theory of Norms' (1976) 6 Philosophia 499, at 500;
    • 'Kelsen's General Theory of Norms' (1976) 6 Philosophia 499, at 500;
  • 28
    • 34548514750 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Legal Validity', above n 12 at 153, 155-6;
    • 'Legal Validity', above n 12 at 153, 155-6;
  • 29
    • 34548483582 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Sources, Normativity, and Individuation', above n 12 at 236.
    • 'Sources, Normativity, and Individuation', above n 12 at 236.
  • 30
    • 34548493378 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', above n 14 at 140;
    • See 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', above n 14 at 140;
  • 32
    • 34548494284 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Kelsen's General Theory of Norms', above n 15 at 499, 500;
    • 'Kelsen's General Theory of Norms', above n 15 at 499, 500;
  • 33
    • 34548512959 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Legal Validity', above n 12 at 153, 155-6;
    • 'Legal Validity', above n 12 at 153, 155-6;
  • 34
    • 34548501458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Sources, Normativity, and Individuation', above n 12 at 236.
    • 'Sources, Normativity, and Individuation', above n 12 at 236.
  • 35
    • 34548488138 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Practical Reason and Norms, above n 12 at 170-1, 174-5.
    • See Practical Reason and Norms, above n 12 at 170-1, 174-5.
  • 36
    • 34548487438 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz's detached legal statements are supposed to be equivalent to Kelsen's Rechtssätze. It may be worth pointing out here that at least one influential Kelsen commentator has argued that Kelsen's Rechtssätze are equivalent to Hart's external legal statements. See, Eugenion Bulygin, 'Enunciados Juridicos y Positivismo: Repuesta a Raz' (1981) in Carlos E. Alchourrón and Eugenio Bulygin, Análisis Lógico y Derecho (Madrid: Centro Estudios Constitucionales 1991) at 433.
    • Raz's detached legal statements are supposed to be equivalent to Kelsen's Rechtssätze. It may be worth pointing out here that at least one influential Kelsen commentator has argued that Kelsen's Rechtssätze are equivalent to Hart's external legal statements. See, Eugenion Bulygin, 'Enunciados Juridicos y Positivismo: Repuesta a Raz' (1981) in Carlos E. Alchourrón and Eugenio Bulygin, Análisis Lógico y Derecho (Madrid: Centro Estudios Constitucionales 1991) at 433.
  • 38
    • 34548493124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz is similarly terse in 'Legal Validity', above n 12 at 153,
    • Raz is similarly terse in 'Legal Validity', above n 12 at 153,
  • 39
    • 34548500965 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • and The 'Purity of the Pure Theory', above n 8 at 455. In these places Raz is far more concerned to show that detached legal statements are not equivalent to committed legal statements, and seems to consider the non-equivalence of detached and external legal statements obvious, or at least fairly easy to show.
    • and The 'Purity of the Pure Theory', above n 8 at 455. In these places Raz is far more concerned to show that detached legal statements are not equivalent to committed legal statements, and seems to consider the non-equivalence of detached and external legal statements obvious, or at least fairly easy to show.
  • 40
    • 34548474703 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Sources, Normativity, and Individuation', above n 12 at 235-6.
    • 'Sources, Normativity, and Individuation', above n 12 at 235-6.
  • 41
    • 34548516094 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The mental attitudes that Raz speaks of in the above passage are beliefs. But, at least in exploring ways to extend Hart's analysis of internal legal statements, it would be more accurate to speak of norm-acceptances instead.
    • The mental attitudes that Raz speaks of in the above passage are beliefs. But, at least in exploring ways to extend Hart's analysis of internal legal statements, it would be more accurate to speak of norm-acceptances instead.
  • 42
    • 34548473972 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The two possibilities I am outlining in this paragraph and the next are intended to approximate the theory and mental simulation approaches, respectively, to explaining mental state attributions. I have benefited from the articles collected in Martin Davies and Tony Stone (eds, Folk Psychology Oxford: Blackwell Publishers 1995, especially the introduction by the editors
    • The two possibilities I am outlining in this paragraph and the next are intended to approximate the theory and mental simulation approaches, respectively, to explaining mental state attributions. I have benefited from the articles collected in Martin Davies and Tony Stone (eds), Folk Psychology (Oxford: Blackwell Publishers 1995), especially the introduction by the editors.
  • 43
    • 34548499802 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One consideration that Alvin Goldman relies on to argue against folk-theory theories is the conjunction of young children's ability to interpret others, and the implausibility of attributing to them the knowledge of the laws of folk psychology. See Goldman, Interpretation Psychologized, 1986) in Davies and Stone eds, Folk Psychology, above n 22 at 80
    • One consideration that Alvin Goldman relies on to argue against folk-theory theories is the conjunction of young children's ability to interpret others, and the implausibility of attributing to them the knowledge of the laws of folk psychology. See Goldman, 'Interpretation Psychologized' (1986) in Davies and Stone (eds), Folk Psychology, above n 22 at 80.
  • 44
    • 34548514603 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. ibid at 94.
    • Cf. ibid at 94.
  • 45
    • 34548495239 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Raz, 'The Purity of the Pure -Theory', above n 8 at 453, 457.
    • Cf. Raz, 'The Purity of the Pure -Theory', above n 8 at 453, 457.
  • 46
    • 34548477819 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at, Gilbert Harman, for one, has noticed their uses in the moral discourse
    • Practical Reason and Norms, above n 12 at 177. Gilbert Harman, for one, has noticed their uses in the moral discourse.
    • Practical Reason and Norms, above , Issue.12 , pp. 177
  • 47
    • 34548499244 scopus 로고
    • in Harman
    • See, Oxford: Clarendon Press, at
    • See 'Moral Relativism Defended' (1975) in Harman, Explaining Value (Oxford: Clarendon Press 2000) at 9-10.
    • (1975) Explaining Value , pp. 9-10
    • Relativism Defended', M.1
  • 48
    • 34548482178 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I owe this observation to David Hills. See also Allan Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press 1990) at 246-8.
    • I owe this observation to David Hills. See also Allan Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press 1990) at 246-8.
  • 50
    • 34548477114 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gibbard relies on a strikingly similar characterization of norm-acceptance: See, at
    • Gibbard relies on a strikingly similar characterization of norm-acceptance: See Wise Choices, Apt Feelings, above n 27 at 74, 75.
    • Choices, Apt Feelings, above , Issue.27
    • Wise1
  • 52
    • 34548509130 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Legal Duty and Obligation', above n 14 at 154-5.
    • 'Legal Duty and Obligation', above n 14 at 154-5.
  • 53
    • 34548504023 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In fact, Raz has also said that committed internal statements are 'primary' legal statements, and that detached internal statements are 'parasitic' on the committed statements. See Raz, Legal Rights' in Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1994) at 254. Raz, however, does not indicate how exactly the parasitic relation holds, as I try to do subsequently
    • In fact, Raz has also said that committed internal statements are 'primary' legal statements, and that detached internal statements are 'parasitic' on the committed statements. See Raz, 'Legal Rights' in Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1994) at 254. Raz, however, does not indicate how exactly the parasitic relation holds, as I try to do subsequently.
  • 55
    • 34548487066 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 'The Purity of the Pure Theory', above n 8 at 447-8;
    • See 'The Purity of the Pure Theory', above n 8 at 447-8;
  • 56
    • 34548507868 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'H.L.A. Hart (1907-1992)', above n 8 at 147;
    • 'H.L.A. Hart (1907-1992)', above n 8 at 147;
  • 57
    • 34548506665 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also Baker, 'Defeasibility and Meaning', above n 12.
    • see also Baker, 'Defeasibility and Meaning', above n 12.
  • 58
    • 34548511244 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I discussed briefly the difference between straight and oblique analyses in s 2 above
    • I discussed briefly the difference between straight and oblique analyses in s 2 above.
  • 59
    • 0001079518 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It may be thought that (A3)(ii, as currently formulated, is inaccurate because a speaker of a detached legal statement need not sincerely presuppose the relevant descriptive content. But nothing in Stalnaker's conception of presupposition requires the commitment involved in presupposing a proposition to be a sincere one. Stalnaker has suggested that participants in a conversation need not literally take the truth of the presupposed proposition for granted. Instead, participants may accept a known falsehood or a doubtful proposition for the purpose of furthering conversation. See Stalnaker, Presuppositions, 1973) 2 Journal of Philosophical Logic 449. In other words, participants in a conversation may assume and abandon presuppositions at will. And that seems to depict accurately what speakers of detached legal statements are up to
    • It may be thought that (A3)(ii), as currently formulated, is inaccurate because a speaker of a detached legal statement need not sincerely presuppose the relevant descriptive content. But nothing in Stalnaker's conception of presupposition requires the commitment involved in presupposing a proposition to be a sincere one. Stalnaker has suggested that participants in a conversation need not literally take the truth of the presupposed proposition for granted. Instead, participants may accept a known falsehood or a doubtful proposition for the purpose of furthering conversation. See Stalnaker, 'Presuppositions' (1973) 2 Journal of Philosophical Logic 449. In other words, participants in a conversation may assume and abandon presuppositions at will. And that seems to depict accurately what speakers of detached legal statements are up to.
  • 60
    • 34548507408 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Raz, 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', above n 14 at 145. I should emphasize that I am not actually proposing (A3) as a plausible analysis of detached legal statements. (A3) merely indicates how an analysis of committed legal statements can be extended to cover detached ones. I am not of the view that (A2) is a plausible analysis of committed legal statements, and have proposed what I consider a better analysis elsewhere.
    • See Raz, 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', above n 14 at 145. I should emphasize that I am not actually proposing (A3) as a plausible analysis of detached legal statements. (A3) merely indicates how an analysis of committed legal statements can be extended to cover detached ones. I am not of the view that (A2) is a plausible analysis of committed legal statements, and have proposed what I consider a better analysis elsewhere.
  • 62
    • 34548501198 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This distinction must be kept separate from the distinction between committed and detached normative statements
    • This distinction must be kept separate from the distinction between committed and detached normative statements.
  • 63
    • 34548514602 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Raz, 'Legal Validity', above n 12 at 155;
    • See Raz, 'Legal Validity', above n 12 at 155;
  • 64
    • 34548478725 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see also 'The Purity of the Pure Theory', above n 8 at 454-5;
    • see also 'The Purity of the Pure Theory', above n 8 at 454-5;
  • 65
    • 0041532436 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Hart on Moral Rights and Legal Duties' (1984) 4 OJLS 130.
    • 'Hart on Moral Rights and Legal Duties' (1984) 4 OJLS 130.
  • 66
    • 34548486617 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Given that Raz is himself not an expressivist like Hart, sentences such as the one in the text can be thought misleading. Raz is a cognitivist who conceives normative statements, including internal legal statements, as descriptive statements. For him, an acceptance is a belief. For ease of exposition, however, I will be speaking throughout this article as if Raz were an expressivist. I assume that this will not compromise my subsequent arguments. After all, I am trying to determine whether Hart's approach to analysing internal legal statements can be defended; my goal is not to evaluate Raz's own views. Thanks to Antony Hatzistavrou for asking me to clarify this issue.
    • Given that Raz is himself not an expressivist like Hart, sentences such as the one in the text can be thought misleading. Raz is a cognitivist who conceives normative statements, including internal legal statements, as descriptive statements. For him, an acceptance is a belief. For ease of exposition, however, I will be speaking throughout this article as if Raz were an expressivist. I assume that this will not compromise my subsequent arguments. After all, I am trying to determine whether Hart's approach to analysing internal legal statements can be defended; my goal is not to evaluate Raz's own views. Thanks to Antony Hatzistavrou for asking me to clarify this issue.
  • 67
    • 34548498033 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 'The Purity of the Pure Theory', above n 8 at 454-5;
    • See 'The Purity of the Pure Theory', above n 8 at 454-5;
  • 68
    • 34548498536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Hart on Moral Rights and Legal Duties', above n 38 at 130-1.
    • 'Hart on Moral Rights and Legal Duties', above n 38 at 130-1.
  • 69
    • 34548497314 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'The Purity of the Pure Theory', ibid at 453, 457.
    • 'The Purity of the Pure Theory', ibid at 453, 457.
  • 70
    • 34548511243 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • My experience of presenting this article in Oxford tells me that I am making a controversial claim here. The local lore there (and perhaps elsewhere as well) seems to be that Hart never thought that internal legal judgements involve what Raz calls full acceptances, but only weak acceptances. This was certainly the position that Hart adopted in his writings of the early 1980s. I believe that Hart changed his mind (in my view, mistakenly) between the time of The Concept of Law and his later writings. I hope my discussion in ss 8-10 of this article makes a plausible case for this reading
    • My experience of presenting this article in Oxford tells me that I am making a controversial claim here. The local lore there (and perhaps elsewhere as well) seems to be that Hart never thought that internal legal judgements involve what Raz calls full acceptances, but only weak acceptances. This was certainly the position that Hart adopted in his writings of the early 1980s. I believe that Hart changed his mind (in my view, mistakenly) between the time of The Concept of Law and his later writings. I hope my discussion in ss 8-10 of this article makes a plausible case for this reading.
  • 72
    • 34548499438 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Ibid at 116.
  • 73
    • 34548510492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'The Purity of the Pure Theory', above n 8 at 454-455.
    • 'The Purity of the Pure Theory', above n 8 at 454-455.
  • 74
    • 34548497548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Commands and Authoritative Reasons' (1982) in Essays on Bentham, above n 11 at 265.
    • 'Commands and Authoritative Reasons' (1982) in Essays on Bentham, above n 11 at 265.
  • 75
    • 34548500268 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Ibid at 266;
  • 76
    • 34548506915 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf. 'Legal Duty and Obligation', above n 14 at 159-160.
    • cf. 'Legal Duty and Obligation', above n 14 at 159-160.
  • 77
    • 34548473734 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Commands and Authoritative Reasons', above n 46 at 267.
    • 'Commands and Authoritative Reasons', above n 46 at 267.
  • 78
    • 34548484031 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Ibid at 268.
  • 79
    • 34548514749 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hart's explicit characterization of acceptance in the postscript to The Concept of Law can be read to convey this deflated conception of acceptance: '[Acceptance] consists in the standing disposition of individuals to take [some] patterns of conduct both as guides to their own future conduct and as standards of criticism which may legitimate demands and various forms of pressure for conformity'. The Concept of Law, above n 1 at 255.
    • Hart's explicit characterization of acceptance in the postscript to The Concept of Law can be read to convey this deflated conception of acceptance: '[Acceptance] consists in the standing disposition of individuals to take [some] patterns of conduct both as guides to their own future conduct and as standards of criticism which may legitimate demands and various forms of pressure for conformity'. The Concept of Law, above n 1 at 255.
  • 80
    • 34548503558 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz may respond by pointing out that such statements are not normally formulated in deontic predicates, whereas legal statements are. Several sentences in the above-quoted passage from 'The Purity of the Pure Theory, especially the last sentence, indicate that Raz saw a special need to explain uses of deontic predicates in legal discourse
    • Raz may respond by pointing out that such statements are not normally formulated in deontic predicates, whereas legal statements are. Several sentences in the above-quoted passage from 'The Purity of the Pure Theory', especially the last sentence, indicate that Raz saw a special need to explain uses of deontic predicates in legal discourse.
  • 81
    • 34548502366 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See also Raz, Practical Reason and Norms, above n 12 at 154-6, 163, 169-70;
    • See also Raz, Practical Reason and Norms, above n 12 at 154-6, 163, 169-70;
  • 83
    • 34548482177 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Sources, Normativity, and Individuation', above n 12 at 230, 234-5;
    • 'Sources, Normativity, and Individuation', above n 12 at 230, 234-5;
  • 84
    • 34548471897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Hart on Moral Rights and Legal Duties', above n 38 at 129-31;
    • 'Hart on Moral Rights and Legal Duties', above n 38 at 129-31;
  • 86
    • 34548477576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Legal Duty and Obligation', above n 14. Raz's point may be that all deontically-formulated objective- or categorical-reason-giving statements are moral statements. This counter-response, however, would run up against Hart's very plausible theses that the original and natural home of deontic concepts like 'obligation' and 'right' is law, not morality, and that the wholesale deployment of such concepts in internal moral discussions may be inappropriate and even blinding.
    • 'Legal Duty and Obligation', above n 14. Raz's point may be that all deontically-formulated objective- or categorical-reason-giving statements are moral statements. This counter-response, however, would run up against Hart's very plausible theses that the original and natural home of deontic concepts like 'obligation' and 'right' is law, not morality, and that the wholesale deployment of such concepts in internal moral discussions may be inappropriate and even blinding.
  • 87
    • 0003364390 scopus 로고
    • Legal and Moral Obligation
    • See, A.I. Melden ed, Seattle: University of Washington Press
    • See Hart, 'Legal and Moral Obligation' in A.I. Melden (ed.), Essays in Moral Philosophy (Seattle: University of Washington Press 1958).
    • (1958) Essays in Moral Philosophy
    • Hart1
  • 88
    • 34548494067 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Thanks to Grant Lamond for urging me to address the relevant passages of 'Legal Duty and Obligation'.
    • Thanks to Grant Lamond for urging me to address the relevant passages of 'Legal Duty and Obligation'.
  • 89
    • 34548496186 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Legal Duty and Obligation', above n 14 at 156.
    • 'Legal Duty and Obligation', above n 14 at 156.
  • 90
    • 34548479867 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Ibid at 159-60.
    • Hart1
  • 91
    • 34548488137 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I have already pointed out and criticized Raz's assumption that (i) is also equivalent to or largely overlaps with a third distinction, namely, the distinction between moral statements and expressions of subjective interests or preferences. What Hart says at the beginning of the second long passage from 'Legal Duty and Obligation' that I quoted above suggests that Hart himself did not make this particular mistaken assumption. But there are some passages in his writings that point in the other direction. For instance, in the following passage in 'Commands and Authoritative Legal Reasons, 266-7, Hart seems to run all three distinctions together: Of course if it were the case, as a cognitive account of duty would hold it to be, that the statement that the subject has a legal duty to act in a way contrary to his interests and inclination entails, the statement that there exist reasons which are 'external' or objective, in the sense that they exist independently of his subjective motivati
    • I have already pointed out and criticized Raz's assumption that (i) is also equivalent to or largely overlaps with a third distinction - namely, the distinction between moral statements and expressions of subjective interests or preferences. What Hart says at the beginning of the second long passage from 'Legal Duty and Obligation' that I quoted above suggests that Hart himself did not make this particular mistaken assumption. But there are some passages in his writings that point in the other direction. For instance, in the following passage in 'Commands and Authoritative Legal Reasons', 266-7, Hart seems to run all three distinctions together: Of course if it were the case, as a cognitive account of duty would hold it to be, that the statement that the subject has a legal duty to act in a way contrary to his interests and inclination entails, the statement that there exist reasons which are 'external' or objective, in the sense that they exist independently of his subjective motivation, it would be difficult to deny that legal duty is a form of moral duty. At least this would be so if it is assumed that ordinary non-legal moral judgements of duty are also statements of such objective reasons for action. For in that case, to hold that legal and moral duties were conceptually independent would involve the extravagant hypothesis that there were two independent 'worlds' or sets of objective reasons, one legal and the other moral.
  • 92
    • 34548477818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • There is some indication that Hart was more open to the 'extravagant hypothesis' in his earlier years. See 'Kelsen's Doctrine of the Unity of Law', above n 14 at 322.
    • There is some indication that Hart was more open to the 'extravagant hypothesis' in his earlier years. See 'Kelsen's Doctrine of the Unity of Law', above n 14 at 322.
  • 93
    • 0040904042 scopus 로고
    • Errors and the Phenomenology of Value' (1985) in Blackburn
    • See, Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • See Simon Blackburn, 'Errors and the Phenomenology of Value' (1985) in Blackburn, Essays in Quasi-Realism (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1993).
    • (1993) Essays in Quasi-Realism
    • Blackburn, S.1
  • 94
    • 34548472564 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See ibid;
    • See ibid;
  • 95
    • 34548488844 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings, above n 27 at ch 8.
    • Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings, above n 27 at ch 8.
  • 96
    • 34548493827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See e.g. The Concept of Law, above n 1 at 203, 231-2;
    • See e.g. The Concept of Law, above n 1 at 203, 231-2;
  • 97
    • 34548483581 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Commands and Authoritative Reasons', above n 46.
    • 'Commands and Authoritative Reasons', above n 46.
  • 98
    • 34548478262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Both John Finnis and John Gardner pressed me to address this objection. Their questions also made me realize that some worries that Les Green raised about an earlier draft of my 'Hart's Expressivism and His Benthamite Project' were motivated by the same objection. I tried to address Green's worries in s V of that article, but now realize that I may not have done so satisfactorily. I hope that what I say in the text will be a more adequate treatment.
    • Both John Finnis and John Gardner pressed me to address this objection. Their questions also made me realize that some worries that Les Green raised about an earlier draft of my 'Hart's Expressivism and His Benthamite Project' were motivated by the same objection. I tried to address Green's worries in s V of that article, but now realize that I may not have done so satisfactorily. I hope that what I say in the text will be a more adequate treatment.
  • 100
    • 34548490017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Practical Reason and Norms, above n 12 at 211;
    • See Practical Reason and Norms, above n 12 at 211;
  • 101
    • 34548489087 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Legal Validity', above n 12 at 155.
    • 'Legal Validity', above n 12 at 155.
  • 102
    • 34548513908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I have not sought in the following pages to go beyond Raz's characterizations of Kelsen's views. My acquaintance with Kelsen's vast oeuvre is rather limited, and so far has been filtered largely through Raz's interpretations. Moreover, some Kelsen scholars have disputed Raz's interpretations of Kelsen's views. See Bulygin, 'Enunciados Juridicos y Positivismo', above n 18;
    • I have not sought in the following pages to go beyond Raz's characterizations of Kelsen's views. My acquaintance with Kelsen's vast oeuvre is rather limited, and so far has been filtered largely through Raz's interpretations. Moreover, some Kelsen scholars have disputed Raz's interpretations of Kelsen's views. See Bulygin, 'Enunciados Juridicos y Positivismo', above n 18;
  • 103
    • 0041580320 scopus 로고
    • Kelsen's Rechtssätze as Detached Statements
    • Richard Tur and William Twining eds, Oxford: Clarendon Press, For these reasons, what I refer to in the following paragraphs as Kelsen's views should be taken as a shorthand for Kelsen's views as Raz construes them
    • Roberto J. Vernengo, 'Kelsen's Rechtssätze as Detached Statements' in Richard Tur and William Twining (eds), Essays on Kelsen (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1986). For these reasons, what I refer to in the following paragraphs as Kelsen's views should be taken as a shorthand for Kelsen's views as Raz construes them.
    • (1986) Essays on Kelsen
    • Vernengo, R.J.1
  • 104
    • 34548480858 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Practical Reason and Norms, above n 12 at 154-5, 163. In many places, Raz also says that the problem of the normativity of law has to do with explaining why normative language is used in legal discourse.
    • Practical Reason and Norms, above n 12 at 154-5, 163. In many places, Raz also says that the problem of the normativity of law has to do with explaining why normative language is used in legal discourse.
  • 105
    • 34548504022 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See e.g. ibid, at 154-6, 163, 169-70;
    • See e.g. ibid, at 154-6, 163, 169-70;
  • 107
    • 34548496428 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Sources, Normativity, and Individuation', above n 12, at 230, 234-5. I believe that this is largely a red herring, resulting most likely from: (i) the unwarranted assumption that the true home of normative language is morality; and (ii) the perennial concern of legal philosophers to spot any non-contingent connection between law and morality.
    • 'Sources, Normativity, and Individuation', above n 12, at 230, 234-5. I believe that this is largely a red herring, resulting most likely from: (i) the unwarranted assumption that the true home of normative language is morality; and (ii) the perennial concern of legal philosophers to spot any non-contingent connection between law and morality.
  • 108
    • 34548510491 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', above n 14 at 134;
    • See 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', above n 14 at 134;
  • 109
    • 34548499243 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf 'Legal Validity', above n 12 at 150.
    • cf 'Legal Validity', above n 12 at 150.
  • 110
    • 34548505180 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Practical Reason and Norms, above n 12 at 170.
    • See Practical Reason and Norms, above n 12 at 170.
  • 111
    • 34548514971 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Raz, 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', above n 14 at 134;
    • See Raz, 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', above n 14 at 134;
  • 113
    • 34548480859 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Ibid at 154 70;
  • 115
    • 34548502119 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Raz has had a varied and complex history with the two approaches. In a 1974 article, Raz enumerates Kelsen's reasons for adopting the justificatory approach, and says that Kelsen's legal theory is the best existing theory following the justificatory approach. 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', above n 14 at 145.
    • Raz has had a varied and complex history with the two approaches. In a 1974 article, Raz enumerates Kelsen's reasons for adopting the justificatory approach, and says that Kelsen's legal theory is the best existing theory following the justificatory approach. 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', above n 14 at 145.
  • 116
    • 34548514748 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the same article, Raz says that Hart's The Concept of Law provides the most successful deployment of the explanatory approach in explaining the normativity of law: Ibid at 134.
    • In the same article, Raz says that Hart's The Concept of Law provides the most successful deployment of the explanatory approach in explaining the normativity of law: Ibid at 134.
  • 117
    • 34548490234 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In his 1975 book, Practical Reason and Norms, Raz says that explanations following the explanatory approach 'come nearer the truth' than those following the justificatory approach: Above n 12 at 170.
    • In his 1975 book, Practical Reason and Norms, Raz says that explanations following the explanatory approach 'come nearer the truth' than those following the justificatory approach: Above n 12 at 170.
  • 118
    • 34548472332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Between 1975 and 1977, Raz seems to have abandoned the explanatory approach and adopted something like Kelsen's account. In a 1977 article, 'Legal Validity', Raz adopts the justificatory approach without explicitly endorsing Kelsen's reasons or giving independent reasons: above n 12.
    • Between 1975 and 1977, Raz seems to have abandoned the explanatory approach and adopted something like Kelsen's account. In a 1977 article, 'Legal Validity', Raz adopts the justificatory approach without explicitly endorsing Kelsen's reasons or giving independent reasons: above n 12.
  • 119
    • 34548507407 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The 1974 and 1977 articles are reprinted in Raz's 1979 book The Authority of Law as essays 7 and 8, respectively: Above n 12.
    • The 1974 and 1977 articles are reprinted in Raz's 1979 book The Authority of Law as essays 7 and 8, respectively: Above n 12.
  • 120
    • 34548511012 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the preface to that book, Raz says: The best positivist explanation of the use of normative language in law was suggested by Kelsen...'; ibid at vii. I am inferring from this history that Raz largely endorses Kelsen's reasons for favouring the justificatory approach.
    • In the preface to that book, Raz says: The best positivist explanation of the use of normative language in law was suggested by Kelsen...'; ibid at vii. I am inferring from this history that Raz largely endorses Kelsen's reasons for favouring the justificatory approach.
  • 121
    • 34548513457 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Pure Theory of Law (Berkely and Los Angeles: University of California Press 2nd edn, Max Knight trans., 1967) at 19,
    • The Pure Theory of Law (Berkely and Los Angeles: University of California Press 2nd edn, Max Knight trans., 1967) at 19,
  • 122
    • 34548498535 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • quoted in Raz, 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', above n 14 at 135.
    • quoted in Raz, 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', above n 14 at 135.
  • 123
    • 34548478723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Pure Theory of Law, ibid at 19-20.
    • The Pure Theory of Law, ibid at 19-20.
  • 124
    • 34548501897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', above n 14 at 135.
    • 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', above n 14 at 135.
  • 125
    • 34548473733 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Pure Theory of Law, above n 68 at 218,
    • The Pure Theory of Law, above n 68 at 218,
  • 126
    • 34548500721 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • quoted in 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', ibid at 136.
    • quoted in 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', ibid at 136.
  • 127
    • 34548487065 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', above n 14 at 136;
    • 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', above n 14 at 136;
  • 128
    • 34548508347 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • cf 'The Purity of the Pure Theory', above n 8 at 451.
    • cf 'The Purity of the Pure Theory', above n 8 at 451.
  • 129
    • 34548474457 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', ibid at 137.
    • Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', ibid at 137.
  • 130
    • 34548488375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', ibid at 141;
    • See 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', ibid at 141;
  • 132
    • 34548480857 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Sources, Normativity, and Individuation', above n 12 at 237.
    • 'Sources, Normativity, and Individuation', above n 12 at 237.
  • 133
    • 34548481452 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Raz, 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', above n 14 at 135, 143, 145.
    • See Raz, 'Kelsen's Theory of the Basic Norm', above n 14 at 135, 143, 145.
  • 134
    • 34548486395 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Legal Duty and Obligation', above n 14 at 144.
    • 'Legal Duty and Obligation', above n 14 at 144.
  • 137
    • 34548504485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This attitude seems to offer an explanation of a rather amusing aside in Hart's account of his public meeting with Kelsen: I should like to record the fact that our discussion had its entertaining moments, The second was towards the end of our debate, when upon Kelsen emphasizing in stentorian tones, so remarkable in an octogenarian (or in any one, that 'Norm was Norm' and not something else, I was so startled that I (literally) fell over backwards in my chair, Kelsen Visited, 1963) in Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy, above n 5 at 287. Hart does not explain what comments of his occasioned this emphasis by Kelsen
    • This attitude seems to offer an explanation of a rather amusing aside in Hart's account of his public meeting with Kelsen: I should like to record the fact that our discussion had its entertaining moments... The second was towards the end of our debate, when upon Kelsen emphasizing in stentorian tones, so remarkable in an octogenarian (or in any one), that 'Norm was Norm' and not something else, I was so startled that I (literally) fell over backwards in my chair. 'Kelsen Visited' (1963) in Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy, above n 5 at 287. Hart does not explain what comments of his occasioned this emphasis by Kelsen.
  • 138
    • 34548494282 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See The Pure Theory of Law (1st edn, 1934) published as Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, B.L. Paulson and S.L. Paulson trans., 1992) at chs 1, 3;
    • See The Pure Theory of Law (1st edn, 1934) published as Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, B.L. Paulson and S.L. Paulson trans., 1992) at chs 1, 3;
  • 139
    • 34548503557 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • General Theory of Law and State (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, Anders Wedberg trans., 1945) at ch. 12;
    • General Theory of Law and State (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, Anders Wedberg trans., 1945) at ch. 12;
  • 140
    • 34548498292 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Pure Theory of Law, above n 68 at chs 1, 3.
    • The Pure Theory of Law, above n 68 at chs 1, 3.
  • 141
    • 34548476884 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In other words, Kelsen seems to have been unmindful of the distinction between straight and oblique analyses of normative statements that I discussed earlier
    • In other words, Kelsen seems to have been unmindful of the distinction between straight and oblique analyses of normative statements that I discussed earlier.
  • 142
    • 34548503097 scopus 로고
    • The Model of Rules II' (1972) in Dworkin
    • See e.g, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • See e.g. Dworkin, 'The Model of Rules II' (1972) in Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 1977);
    • (1977) Taking Rights Seriously
    • Dworkin1
  • 143
    • 0004166519 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 1986);
    • (1986) Law's Empire
  • 144
    • 0010915611 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Objectivity and Truth: You'd Better Believe It' (1996) 25 Philosophy and Public Affairs.
    • 'Objectivity and Truth: You'd Better Believe It' (1996) 25 Philosophy and Public Affairs.
  • 145
    • 33749350972 scopus 로고
    • Human Purpose and Natural Law
    • See
    • See Fuller, 'Human Purpose and Natural Law' (1956) 53 The Journal of Philosophy;
    • (1956) The Journal of Philosophy , vol.53
    • Fuller1
  • 146
    • 34548489086 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights, above n 12 at ch. 1.
    • Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights, above n 12 at ch. 1.
  • 147
    • 34548491542 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Raz, 'The Problem about the Nature of Law' (1983) in Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain, above n 31 at 192-3;
    • See Raz, 'The Problem about the Nature of Law' (1983) in Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain, above n 31 at 192-3;
  • 148
    • 34548473006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Authority, Law, and Morality' (1985) in Ethics in the Public Domain ibid at 219-21;
    • 'Authority, Law, and Morality' (1985) in Ethics in the Public Domain ibid at 219-21;
  • 149
    • 34548511947 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 'Two Views of the Nature of the Theory of Law: A Partial Comparison' (1998) in Jules Coleman (ed.), Hart's Postscript (Oxford: Clarendon Press 2001) at 21-2.
    • 'Two Views of the Nature of the Theory of Law: A Partial Comparison' (1998) in Jules Coleman (ed.), Hart's Postscript (Oxford: Clarendon Press 2001) at 21-2.
  • 150
    • 34548514601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The following key passage from one of the endnotes to ch. 1 of Finnis's Natural Law and Natural Rights, above n 12 at 21, bears this out: The fact that, as I have argued in this chapter, the descriptive theorist needs the assistance of a general normative theory in developing sufficiently differentiated concepts and reasonable standards of relevance does not eliminate the different uses to which the more or less common stock of theoretical concepts will be put by the normative and the descriptive (historical) theorists, respectively.
    • The following key passage from one of the endnotes to ch. 1 of Finnis's Natural Law and Natural Rights, above n 12 at 21, bears this out: The fact that, as I have argued in this chapter, the descriptive theorist needs the assistance of a general normative theory in developing sufficiently differentiated concepts and reasonable standards of relevance does not eliminate the different uses to which the more or less common stock of theoretical concepts will be put by the normative and the descriptive (historical) theorists, respectively.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.