-
1
-
-
84861979919
-
See David Hume's that ‘there is no such passion in human minds, as the love of mankind, merely as such
-
Harmondsworth: Penguin
-
See David Hume's that ‘there is no such passion in human minds, as the love of mankind, merely as such’, in A Treatise of Human Nature (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1969), p. 533.
-
(1969)
A Treatise of Human Nature
, pp. 533
-
-
-
2
-
-
0742292339
-
Spheres of Affection
-
and the reservations about cosmopolitan motivation in Boston, MA: Beacon Press
-
and the reservations about cosmopolitan motivation in Michael Walzer, ‘Spheres of Affection’, in Martha Nussbaum, For Love of Country? (Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 2002).
-
(2002)
Martha Nussbaum, For Love of Country?
-
-
Walzer, M.1
-
4
-
-
84994998617
-
Critical Notice
-
See and the discussion in Gaita, Common Humanity
-
See Raimond Gaita, ‘Critical Notice’, Philosophical Investigations, 17 (1994), pp. 616ff, and the discussion in Gaita, Common Humanity.
-
(1994)
Philosophical Investigations
, vol.17
, pp. 616ff
-
-
Gaita, R.1
-
5
-
-
0038413548
-
-
Similar sentiments are present in the claim that: ‘To no matter whom the question may be put in general terms, nobody is of the opinion that any man is innocent if, possessing food himself in abundance and finding someone on his doorstep three parts dead from hunger, he brushes past without giving him anything’. See London: Routledge and Kegan Paul
-
Similar sentiments are present in the claim that: ‘To no matter whom the question may be put in general terms, nobody is of the opinion that any man is innocent if, possessing food himself in abundance and finding someone on his doorstep three parts dead from hunger, he brushes past without giving him anything’. See Simone Weil, The Need for Roots: Prelude to a Declaration of Duties Towards Mankind (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1952), p. 6.
-
(1952)
The Need for Roots: Prelude to a Declaration of Duties Towards Mankind
, pp. 6
-
-
Weil, S.1
-
6
-
-
0038413548
-
-
where she describes this obligation as ‘eternal’
-
Weil, Need for Roots, p. 6 where she describes this obligation as ‘eternal’.
-
Need for Roots
, pp. 6
-
-
Weil1
-
8
-
-
0003411222
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Martha Nussbaum maintains that ‘biology and common circumstances … make it extremely unlikely that the emotional repertoires of two societies will be entirely opaque to one another’
-
In Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), p. 169, Martha Nussbaum maintains that ‘biology and common circumstances … make it extremely unlikely that the emotional repertoires of two societies will be entirely opaque to one another’.
-
(2001)
In Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions
, pp. 169
-
-
-
10
-
-
0038075132
-
-
notes that a slave-owner might assist a slave in desperate circumstances, but in this case assistance does not rest on a doctrine of equal rights. The desire to protect another slave-owners’ property, rather than human solidarity, may prompt an act of rescue
-
Gaita, Common Humanity, p. 276 notes that a slave-owner might assist a slave in desperate circumstances, but in this case assistance does not rest on a doctrine of equal rights. The desire to protect another slave-owners’ property, rather than human solidarity, may prompt an act of rescue.
-
Common Humanity
, pp. 276
-
-
Gaita1
-
12
-
-
0008302074
-
Universality in Culture
-
The idea of a form of universality that requires a complex labour of translation can be found in
-
The idea of a form of universality that requires a complex labour of translation can be found in Judith Butler, ‘Universality in Culture’, in Nussbaum, Love of Country.
-
Nussbaum, Love of Country
-
-
Butler, J.1
-
13
-
-
85022872159
-
-
Reason and the Rationalisation of Society For Occidental rationalism and societial rationalisation, see Boston, MA: Beacon Press
-
For Occidental rationalism and societial rationalisation, see Jurgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action, vol. 1: Reason and the Rationalisation of Society (Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 1984).
-
(1984)
The Theory of Communicative Action
, vol.1
-
-
Habermas, J.1
-
14
-
-
0003837530
-
-
London: William Heinemann Book 1.13
-
Aristotle, The ‘Art’ of Rhetoric (London: William Heinemann, 1959), Book 1.13.
-
(1959)
The ‘Art’ of Rhetoric
-
-
-
16
-
-
33845745801
-
Distant Suffering and Cosmopolitan Obligations
-
See my
-
See my ‘Distant Suffering and Cosmopolitan Obligations’, International Politics, 44:1 (2007), pp. 19-36.
-
(2007)
International Politics
, vol.44
, Issue.1
, pp. 19-36
-
-
-
17
-
-
16344386122
-
-
maintains that a person may be unable to sleep at night knowing that his or her small finger will be removed the following day, but the same person will sleep peacefully even though s/he knows that countless distant strangers face the most awful calamities -- presuming, Smith added, that the person ‘never sees them’. For further reflections on these matters, see my Distant Suffering
-
Adam Smith, Moral Sentiments, pp. 136-137 maintains that a person may be unable to sleep at night knowing that his or her small finger will be removed the following day, but the same person will sleep peacefully even though s/he knows that countless distant strangers face the most awful calamities -- presuming, Smith added, that the person ‘never sees them’. For further reflections on these matters, see my Distant Suffering.
-
Moral Sentiments
, pp. 136-137
-
-
Smith, A.1
-
19
-
-
0004251932
-
-
Oxford: Basil Blackwell Section 4. See also the discussion in Gaita, Common Humanity, pp. 259ff
-
Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1974), Part II, Section 4. See also the discussion in Gaita, Common Humanity, pp. 259ff.
-
(1974)
Philosophical Investigations
-
-
Wittgenstein, L.1
-
23
-
-
1642401428
-
Norbert Elias, the “Civilizing Process” and International Relations
-
These were crucial themes in the writings of Norbert Elias. For a summary of their significance for International Relations, see my
-
These were crucial themes in the writings of Norbert Elias. For a summary of their significance for International Relations, see my ‘Norbert Elias, the “Civilizing Process” and International Relations’, International Politics, 41 (2004), pp. 3-35.
-
(2004)
International Politics
, vol.41
, pp. 3-35
-
-
-
24
-
-
33846498880
-
-
Kant denied that an ethic could be grounded in the emotions, and indeed he expressed a preference for ‘cold-blooded goodness’ over the ‘warmth of affection’ precisely because the former was ‘more reliable’. See Berkeley, CA: University of California Press
-
Kant denied that an ethic could be grounded in the emotions, and indeed he expressed a preference for ‘cold-blooded goodness’ over the ‘warmth of affection’ precisely because the former was ‘more reliable’. See Anthony Cunningham, The Heart of What Matters: The Role for Literature in Moral Philosophy (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 2001), p. 222.
-
(2001)
The Heart of What Matters: The Role for Literature in Moral Philosophy
, pp. 222
-
-
Cunningham, A.1
-
25
-
-
0003942144
-
-
London: Routledge stresses that recent Kantians have been less cautious about emotions such as compassion because of their importance for developing a sense of ‘connectedness’ with other persons. Not that this theme was wholly alien to Kant, as we have seen. Exposure to the poor, the sick and imprisoned could produce ‘the pain of compassion’, an impulse which had been created by Nature ‘for effecting what the representation of duty might not accomplish by itself’ (quoted in Cunningham, Heart of What Matters, p. 77 and p. 213)
-
Justin Oakley, Morality and the Emotions (London: Routledge 1992), pp. 109ff, stresses that recent Kantians have been less cautious about emotions such as compassion because of their importance for developing a sense of ‘connectedness’ with other persons. Not that this theme was wholly alien to Kant, as we have seen. Exposure to the poor, the sick and imprisoned could produce ‘the pain of compassion’, an impulse which had been created by Nature ‘for effecting what the representation of duty might not accomplish by itself’ (quoted in Cunningham, Heart of What Matters, p. 77 and p. 213).
-
(1992)
Morality and the Emotions
, pp. 109ff
-
-
Oakley, J.1
-
26
-
-
11844253575
-
Introduction: Why Emotions are Crucial
-
See in Jack Barbalet (ed.) Oxford: Blackwell
-
See Jack Barbalet, ‘Introduction: Why Emotions are Crucial’ in Jack Barbalet (ed.), Emotions and Sociology (Oxford: Blackwell, 2002).
-
(2002)
Emotions and Sociology
-
-
Barbalet, J.1
-
27
-
-
0003664669
-
-
Interesting issues are raised here about how the emotions mark the point where the ‘cultural’ and the ‘somatic’ intersect. See London: Sage Introduction
-
Interesting issues are raised here about how the emotions mark the point where the ‘cultural’ and the ‘somatic’ intersect. See Rom Harre and W. Gerrod Parrott, (eds.), The Emotions: Social, Cultural and Biological Dimensions (London: Sage, 1996), Introduction.
-
(1996)
The Emotions: Social, Cultural and Biological Dimensions
-
-
Harre, R.1
Gerrod Parrott, W.2
-
28
-
-
0034417139
-
The Passions of World Politics: Propositions on Emotions and Emotional Relationships
-
Neta Crawford, ‘The Passions of World Politics: Propositions on Emotions and Emotional Relationships’, International Security, 24 (2001), pp. 116-156.
-
(2001)
International Security
, vol.24
, pp. 116-156
-
-
Crawford, N.1
-
30
-
-
85022864509
-
-
Embodiment was central to Elias's analysis of the civilising process which was first set out in the 1930s. Its significance for the Frankfurt School and for the critical sociology of world politics is considered on pp.
-
Embodiment was central to Elias's analysis of the civilising process which was first set out in the 1930s. Its significance for the Frankfurt School and for the critical sociology of world politics is considered on pp. 147ff.
-
-
-
-
31
-
-
34248247289
-
Outline of a Theory of Human Rights
-
Bryan S. Turner, ‘Outline of a Theory of Human Rights’, Sociology, 27 (1993), pp 489-512.
-
(1993)
Sociology
, vol.27
, pp. 489-512
-
-
Turner, B.S.1
-
32
-
-
0004292742
-
-
See respectively London: Routledge and
-
See respectively Theodor Adorno, Negative Dialectics (London: Routledge, 1990), pp. 17-18, and.
-
(1990)
Negative Dialectics
, pp. 17-18
-
-
Adorno, T.1
-
35
-
-
0003772397
-
-
and Stephen Oxford: Blackwell on the importance of such themes in Frankfurt School theory more generally
-
and Stephen. E. Bronner, Of Critical Theory and its Theorists (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), pp. 332-335 on the importance of such themes in Frankfurt School theory more generally.
-
(1994)
Of Critical Theory and its Theorists
, pp. 332-335
-
-
Bronner, E.1
-
36
-
-
52549108883
-
-
Horkheimer, quoted in Hemel Hempstead: Harvester Wheatsheaf
-
Horkheimer, quoted in Peter M. Stirk, Max Horkheimer: A New Interpretation (Hemel Hempstead: Harvester Wheatsheaf, 1992), p. 178.
-
(1992)
Max Horkheimer: A New Interpretation
, pp. 178
-
-
Stirk, P.M.1
-
37
-
-
34547254493
-
Schopenhauer Today
-
Vulnerability did not merely underpin solidarity with ‘the community of men lost in the universe’ -- see New York: Seabury Schopenhauer's defence of a post-anthropocentric ethic was reflected in Horkheimer's additional claim that the idea of vulnerability should underpin compassion for all sentient creatures and ‘solidarity with life in general’ (Horkheimer, Materialism, p. 36; see also Schopenhauer, Basis of Morality, pp. 175ff)
-
Vulnerability did not merely underpin solidarity with ‘the community of men lost in the universe’ -- see Max Horkheimer, ‘Schopenhauer Today’ in Max Horkheimer, Critique of Instrumental Reason (New York: Seabury 1974), p. 75. Schopenhauer's defence of a post-anthropocentric ethic was reflected in Horkheimer's additional claim that the idea of vulnerability should underpin compassion for all sentient creatures and ‘solidarity with life in general’ (Horkheimer, Materialism, p. 36; see also Schopenhauer, Basis of Morality, pp. 175ff).
-
(1974)
Max Horkheimer, Critique of Instrumental Reason
, pp. 75
-
-
Horkheimer, M.1
-
38
-
-
34547335012
-
-
For broadly similar views, see on the insights that can be learnt from Schopenhauer's ‘crankiness’
-
For broadly similar views, see Adorno, Problems, p. 145 on the insights that can be learnt from Schopenhauer's ‘crankiness’.
-
Problems
, pp. 145
-
-
Adorno1
-
39
-
-
84917171903
-
After Auschwitz: Trauma and the Grammar of Ethics
-
The expression is used by in Robert Fine and Charles Turner (eds.) Liverpool: Liverpool University Press
-
The expression is used by J. M. Bernstein in ‘After Auschwitz: Trauma and the Grammar of Ethics’, in Robert Fine and Charles Turner (eds.), Social Theory after the Holocaust (Liverpool: Liverpool University Press, 2000), p. 122.
-
(2000)
Social Theory after the Holocaust
, pp. 122
-
-
Bernstein, J.M.1
-
42
-
-
33747039593
-
The Harm Principle and Global Ethics
-
Whether Adorno overwrote this ethical argument is a question that goes beyond this discussion. Suffice it to add that his comments about an ethic which starts with the conditions of frailty and vulnerability find sympathy in many different areas of philosophical analysis. For comments on parallel themes in recent moral and political theory, see my
-
Whether Adorno overwrote this ethical argument is a question that goes beyond this discussion. Suffice it to add that his comments about an ethic which starts with the conditions of frailty and vulnerability find sympathy in many different areas of philosophical analysis. For comments on parallel themes in recent moral and political theory, see my ‘The Harm Principle and Global Ethics’, Global Society, 20 (2006), pp. 329-343.
-
(2006)
Global Society
, vol.20
, pp. 329-343
-
-
-
43
-
-
0003940096
-
-
The rejection of what Cambridge: Cambridge University Press calls the practice of placing ‘the principle of injury’ at the centre of social life can be traced back to the European Enlightenment
-
The rejection of what Onora O'Neill, Towards Justice and Virtue: A Constructive Account of Practical Reason (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), pp. 165-166 calls the practice of placing ‘the principle of injury’ at the centre of social life can be traced back to the European Enlightenment.
-
(1996)
Towards Justice and Virtue: A Constructive Account of Practical Reason
, pp. 165-166
-
-
O'Neill, O.1
-
44
-
-
84936526484
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press situates this within the broad cultural shift which supported ‘the affirmation of ordinary life’ and the parallel rejection of sacred suffering
-
Charles Taylor, Sources of the Self: The Making of Modernity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989) situates this within the broad cultural shift which supported ‘the affirmation of ordinary life’ and the parallel rejection of sacred suffering.
-
(1989)
Sources of the Self: The Making of Modernity
-
-
Taylor, C.1
-
45
-
-
30744451390
-
-
Horkheimer's later reflections on theology and suffering (see in Benhabib, On Max Horkheimer, ch. 3) invite the comment that several major faith traditions have regarded the capacity for suffering, and the potential for sympathy with the distressed, as the most natural point of solidarity between strangers
-
Horkheimer's later reflections on theology and suffering (see Jurgen Habermas, ‘Reflections on the Development of Horkheimer's Work’, in Benhabib, On Max Horkheimer, ch. 3) invite the comment that several major faith traditions have regarded the capacity for suffering, and the potential for sympathy with the distressed, as the most natural point of solidarity between strangers.
-
Reflections on the Development of Horkheimer's Work
-
-
Habermas, J.1
-
48
-
-
12944292941
-
The Frankfurt School and International Relations: On the Centrality of Recognition
-
Jurgen Hacke, ‘The Frankfurt School and International Relations: On the Centrality of Recognition’, Review of International Studies, 31 (2005), pp. 181-194.
-
(2005)
Review of International Studies
, vol.31
, pp. 181-194
-
-
Hacke, J.1
-
49
-
-
84917171882
-
-
See also at: ?www.unesco.or.kr/kor/ science_s/project/universal_ethics/asianvalues/honneth.htm?
-
See also Axel Honneth, ‘Mutual Recognition as a Key for a Universal Ethics’, at: ?www.unesco.or.kr/kor/ science_s/project/universal_ethics/asianvalues/honneth.htm?.
-
Mutual Recognition as a Key for a Universal Ethics
-
-
Honneth, A.1
-
50
-
-
0003527892
-
-
With respect to exploitation Boston, MA: Beacon Press distinguishes between ‘bodily harm (hunger, exhaustion, illness), personal injury (degradation, servitude, fear), and finally spiritual desperation (loneliness, emptiness) -- to which in turn there correspond various hopes -- for well-being and security, freedom and dignity, happiness and fulfillment’
-
With respect to exploitation, Jurgen Habermas, Communication and the Evolution of Society (Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 1979), p. 164, distinguishes between ‘bodily harm (hunger, exhaustion, illness), personal injury (degradation, servitude, fear), and finally spiritual desperation (loneliness, emptiness) -- to which in turn there correspond various hopes -- for well-being and security, freedom and dignity, happiness and fulfillment’.
-
(1979)
Communication and the Evolution of Society
, pp. 164
-
-
Habermas, J.1
-
52
-
-
0036555375
-
The Problem of Harm in World Politics: Implications for the Sociology of States-Systems
-
See my and Linklater, Norbert Elias
-
See my ‘The Problem of Harm in World Politics: Implications for the Sociology of States-Systems’, International Affairs, 78 (2002), pp. 319-338 and Linklater, Norbert Elias.
-
(2002)
International Affairs
, vol.78
, pp. 319-338
-
-
-
56
-
-
85022820375
-
-
See the discussion of psychoanalytical theory in Habermas, Knowledge, chs. 10--12 and the References to ‘cognitive developmental psychology’ in see also ch. 2 entitled ‘Moral Development and Ego Identity’
-
See the discussion of psychoanalytical theory in Habermas, Knowledge, chs. 10--12 and the References to ‘cognitive developmental psychology’ in Habermas, Communication, p. 100; see also ch. 2 entitled ‘Moral Development and Ego Identity’.
-
Communication
, pp. 100
-
-
Habermas1
-
57
-
-
0002115863
-
Emotion and Communicative Action: Habermas, Linguistic Philosophy and Existentialism
-
Some critics regard this oversight as a weakness in Habermas's position, but not one that his approach is incapable of correcting. See in Gillian Bendelow and Simon. J. Williams (eds.) London: Routledge
-
Some critics regard this oversight as a weakness in Habermas's position, but not one that his approach is incapable of correcting. See Nick Crossley, ‘Emotion and Communicative Action: Habermas, Linguistic Philosophy and Existentialism’, in Gillian Bendelow and Simon. J. Williams (eds.), Emotions in Social Life: Critical Themes and Contemporary Issues (London: Routledge, 1998).
-
(1998)
Emotions in Social Life: Critical Themes and Contemporary Issues
-
-
Crossley, N.1
-
58
-
-
85022858847
-
-
ch. 3. See also the References to the significance of ‘affective expressions’ in the evolutionary movement from primates to hominids on and the more central concern with the development of ‘structures of thought’ which is expressed on p. 149
-
Habermas, Communication, ch. 3. See also the References to the significance of ‘affective expressions’ in the evolutionary movement from primates to hominids on p. 134, and the more central concern with the development of ‘structures of thought’ which is expressed on p. 149.
-
Communication
, pp. 134
-
-
Habermas1
-
59
-
-
0039021405
-
Fantasy and Critique: Some Thoughts on Freud and the Frankfurt School
-
in David. M. Rasmussen (ed.) Oxford: Blackwell
-
Joel Whitebook, ‘Fantasy and Critique: Some Thoughts on Freud and the Frankfurt School’, in David. M. Rasmussen (ed.), The Handbook of Critical Theory (Oxford: Blackwell, 1996), p. 300.
-
(1996)
The Handbook of Critical Theory
, pp. 300
-
-
Whitebook, J.1
-
61
-
-
0003842838
-
-
What has been lost, it might be argued, is the ‘underground history’ which concerns the body and ‘the fate of the human instincts and passions which are displaced and distorted by civilization’: see London: Verso
-
What has been lost, it might be argued, is the ‘underground history’ which concerns the body and ‘the fate of the human instincts and passions which are displaced and distorted by civilization’: see Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer, Dialectic of Enlightenment (London: Verso 1972), p. 231.
-
(1972)
Dialectic of Enlightenment
, pp. 231
-
-
Adorno, T.1
Horkheimer, M.2
-
62
-
-
0039289698
-
-
See, for example, the following claim in ‘In living, the organisms themselves make an evaluation to the effect that self-maintenance is preferable to the destruction of the system, reproduction of life to death, health to the risks of sickness’. But from the ‘descriptive statement that living systems prefer certain states to others’ nothing follows ethically from the standpoint of observers
-
See, for example, the following claim in Habermas, Communication, p. 176: ‘In living, the organisms themselves make an evaluation to the effect that self-maintenance is preferable to the destruction of the system, reproduction of life to death, health to the risks of sickness’. But from the ‘descriptive statement that living systems prefer certain states to others’ nothing follows ethically from the standpoint of observers.
-
Communication
, pp. 176
-
-
Habermas1
-
63
-
-
0039289698
-
-
See the following claim in ‘For a living being that maintains itself in the structures of ordinary language communication, the validity basis of speech has the binding force of universal and unavoidable -- in this sense transcendental -- presuppositions. The theoretician does not have the same possibility of choice in relation to the validity claims immanent in speech as he does in relation to the basic biological value of health’ (italics in original)
-
See the following claim in Habermas, Communication, p. 177): ‘For a living being that maintains itself in the structures of ordinary language communication, the validity basis of speech has the binding force of universal and unavoidable -- in this sense transcendental -- presuppositions. The theoretician does not have the same possibility of choice in relation to the validity claims immanent in speech as he does in relation to the basic biological value of health’ (italics in original).
-
Communication
, pp. 177
-
-
Habermas1
-
64
-
-
0039076709
-
History and Evolution
-
Jurgen Habermas, ‘History and Evolution’, Telos, 39 (1979), pp. 5-44.
-
(1979)
Telos
, vol.39
, pp. 5-44
-
-
Habermas, J.1
-
65
-
-
84895032145
-
-
See and 285
-
See Habermas, Knowledge, pp. 256 and 285.
-
Knowledge
, pp. 256
-
-
Habermas1
-
68
-
-
0346335329
-
Politics and Psychoanalysis
-
and in S. E. Bronner and D. M. Kellner (eds.) London: Routledge
-
and Erich Fromm, ‘Politics and Psychoanalysis’, in S. E. Bronner and D. M. Kellner (eds.), Critical Theory and Society (London: Routledge, 1989), p. 216.
-
(1989)
Critical Theory and Society
, pp. 216
-
-
Fromm, E.1
-
71
-
-
0004217662
-
-
Harmondsworth: Pelican
-
Herbert Marcuse, An Essay on Liberation (Harmondsworth: Pelican, 1972), pp. 29-30.
-
(1972)
An Essay on Liberation
, pp. 29-30
-
-
Marcuse, H.1
-
73
-
-
0039265112
-
-
See also the writings of Lucien Febvre collected in London: Routledge and Kegan Paul
-
See also the writings of Lucien Febvre collected in Peter Burke (ed.), A New Kind of History from the Writing of Lucien Febvre (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1973), p. 24.
-
(1973)
A New Kind of History from the Writing of Lucien Febvre
, pp. 24
-
-
Burke, P.1
-
74
-
-
0022133547
-
Emotionology: Clarifying the History of Emotions and Emotion Standards
-
and See Linklater, Elias for a list of key works in figurational sociology which are also relevant to the argument of this article
-
and Peter N. Stearns and Carol Z. Stearns, ‘Emotionology: Clarifying the History of Emotions and Emotion Standards’, American Historical Review, 90 (1985), pp. 813-836. See Linklater, Elias for a list of key works in figurational sociology which are also relevant to the argument of this article.
-
(1985)
American Historical Review
, vol.90
, pp. 813-836
-
-
Stearns, P.N.1
Stearns, C.Z.2
-
76
-
-
84972793004
-
Elias and the Frankfurt School
-
Elias moved to Frankfurt University when Karl Mannheim was appointed to the Chair of Sociology in 1929. For further details, see and Wiggershaus, Frankfurt School
-
Elias moved to Frankfurt University when Karl Mannheim was appointed to the Chair of Sociology in 1929. For further details, see Artur Bogner, ‘Elias and the Frankfurt School’, Theory, Culture and Society, 4 (1987), pp. 249-285, and Wiggershaus, Frankfurt School.
-
(1987)
Theory, Culture and Society
, vol.4
, pp. 249-285
-
-
Bogner, A.1
-
77
-
-
20744447415
-
An Anatomy of the Leicester School of Sociology: An Interview with Eric Dunning
-
See also
-
See also Chris Rojek, ‘An Anatomy of the Leicester School of Sociology: An Interview with Eric Dunning’, Journal of Classical Sociology, 4 (2004), pp. 337-359.
-
(2004)
Journal of Classical Sociology
, vol.4
, pp. 337-359
-
-
Rojek, C.1
-
79
-
-
0000714928
-
The Formation of We-Images: A Process Theory
-
in Craig Calhoun (ed.) Oxford: Blackwell and
-
Stephen Mennell, ‘The Formation of We-Images: A Process Theory’, in Craig Calhoun (ed.), Social Theory and the Politics of Identity (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994); and.
-
(1994)
Social Theory and the Politics of Identity
-
-
Mennell, S.1
-
80
-
-
84937295072
-
Widening Circles of Identification: Emotional Concerns in Sociogenetic Perspective
-
Abram De Swaan, ‘Widening Circles of Identification: Emotional Concerns in Sociogenetic Perspective’, Theory, Culture and Society, 12 (1995), pp. 25-39.
-
(1995)
Theory, Culture and Society
, vol.12
, pp. 25-39
-
-
De Swaan, A.1
|