메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 18, Issue 1, 2005, Pages 1-30

Challenging the Role of Judges in Slaughter's Liberal Theory of International Law

Author keywords

globalization; international courts and tribunals; international relations; liberal theory

Indexed keywords


EID: 34248039721     PISSN: 09221565     EISSN: 14789698     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/S0922156504002328     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (23)

References (108)
  • 2
    • 85022374532 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (1999) 31 (4) The New York University Journal of International Law and Politics (special issue); T. Buergenthal, ‘Proliferation of International Courts and Tribunals: Is It Good or Bad?’, (2001) 14 LJIL 267; P. Sands, R.Mackenzie, and Y. Shany (eds.),Manual on International Courts and Tribunals
    • See in particular (1999) 31 (4) The New York University Journal of International Law and Politics (special issue); T. Buergenthal, ‘Proliferation of International Courts and Tribunals: Is It Good or Bad?’, (2001) 14 LJIL 267; P. Sands, R.Mackenzie, and Y. Shany (eds.),Manual on International Courts and Tribunals (1999).
    • (1999) particular
  • 3
    • 84904510370 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (1998) 271 Recueil des cours 115; idem, ‘The Impact on the International Legal System of the Growth of International Courts and Tribunals’, 31 New York University Journal of International Law and Politics 697 (concluding that there is no evidence of any substantial fragmentation of international law).
    • J. I. Charney, ‘International Law andMultiple International Tribunals’, (1998) 271 Recueil des cours 115; idem, ‘The Impact on the International Legal System of the Growth of International Courts and Tribunals’, (1999) 31 New York University Journal of International Law and Politics 697 (concluding that there is no evidence of any substantial fragmentation of international law).
    • (1999) International Law andMultiple International Tribunals
    • Charney, J.I.1
  • 4
    • 33748098195 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (2003); and V. Lowe, ‘Overlapping Jurisdiction in International Tribunals’, 20 Australian Yearbook of International Law
    • Y. Shany, The Competing Jurisdictions of International Courts and Tribunals (2003); and V. Lowe, ‘Overlapping Jurisdiction in International Tribunals’, (1999) 20 Australian Yearbook of International Law 191.
    • (1999) The Competing Jurisdictions of International Courts and Tribunals , pp. 191
    • Shany, Y.1
  • 7
    • 85022442481 scopus 로고
    • That honour belonged to the Central American Arbitral Tribunal (CAAT), established in 1902 by the Corinto Convention (Convention of Peace and Arbitration, opened for signature 20 Jan. 1902 (-1902 Parry's TS 357).
    • Although it was the world's first permanent international court it was not the first permanent international court in the world. That honour belonged to the Central American Arbitral Tribunal (CAAT), established in 1902 by the Corinto Convention (Convention of Peace and Arbitration, opened for signature 20 Jan. 1902 (1901-1902 Parry's TS 357).
    • (1901) Although it was the world's first permanent international court it was not the first permanent international court in the world
  • 8
    • 85022453076 scopus 로고
    • For instance,Wilson (in contrast to his immediate predecessor,William Taft) was strongly anti-legalist and was opposed to the proposed PCIJ (at one stage in the drafting of the Covenant of the LeagueWilson removed the draft article which provided for its establishment): see J.W. Wheeler-Bennett and M. Fanshawe, Information on theWorld Court 1918-1928 (1929), 1-21, 147; A. Zimmern, The League of Nations and the Rule of Law 1918-1935 (1936). For an extensive discussion of the politics of the United States’ relationship with the PCIJ see M. Dunne, The United States and theWorld Court
    • The lasting association of Wilson with liberal idealism should not be taken to imply that Wilson himself held all the views associated with that paradigmatic approach to international relations. For instance,Wilson (in contrast to his immediate predecessor,William Taft) was strongly anti-legalist and was opposed to the proposed PCIJ (at one stage in the drafting of the Covenant of the LeagueWilson removed the draft article which provided for its establishment): see J.W. Wheeler-Bennett and M. Fanshawe, Information on theWorld Court 1918-1928 (1929), 1-21, 147; A. Zimmern, The League of Nations and the Rule of Law 1918-1935 (1936). For an extensive discussion of the politics of the United States’ relationship with the PCIJ see M. Dunne, The United States and theWorld Court 1920-1935 (1988).
    • (1988) The lasting association of Wilson with liberal idealism should not be taken to imply that Wilson himself held all the views associated with that paradigmatic approach to international relations , pp. 1920-1935
  • 9
    • 27144482699 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (2000) 54 International Organization 457 (using a liberal approach to understand the differing political dynamics of inter-state and transnational adjudication) 458, 469 (transnational dispute resolution involves individual/individual and individual/state cases across national boundaries adjudicated by an overarchingtribunal that isindependentandrenders decisionsimplementeddirectlybynational judiciaries). Of course these scholars are not alone in their attempts to understand transnational life: seeH.Koh, ‘WhyDo Nations Obey International Law?’, (1995) 106 Yale Law Journal 2599; and idem, ‘Transnational Legal Process’, 75 Nebraska Law Review
    • See R. O. Keohane, A. Moravcsik, and A.-M. Slaughter, ‘Legalized Dispute Resolution: Interstate and Transnational’, (2000) 54 International Organization 457 (using a liberal approach to understand the differing political dynamics of inter-state and transnational adjudication) 458, 469 (transnational dispute resolution involves individual/individual and individual/state cases across national boundaries adjudicated by an overarchingtribunal that isindependentandrenders decisionsimplementeddirectlybynational judiciaries). Of course these scholars are not alone in their attempts to understand transnational life: seeH.Koh, ‘WhyDo Nations Obey International Law?’, (1995) 106 Yale Law Journal 2599; and idem, ‘Transnational Legal Process’, (1996) 75 Nebraska Law Review 181.
    • (1996) Legalized Dispute Resolution: Interstate and Transnational , pp. 181
    • Keohane, R.O.1    Moravcsik, A.2    Slaughter, A.-M.3
  • 11
    • 85022351582 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a concise summary of the realism of Carr and Morgenthau see S. Burchill, in S. Burchill, R. Devetak, A. Linklater, M. Paterson, C. Reus-Smit, and J. True, Theories of International Relations, 70-102, at
    • For a concise summary of the realism of Carr and Morgenthau see S. Burchill, ‘Liberalism’, in S. Burchill, R. Devetak, A. Linklater, M. Paterson, C. Reus-Smit, and J. True, Theories of International Relations (2001), 70-102, at 71-83.
    • (2001) Liberalism , pp. 71-83
  • 13
    • 85022379613 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Domestic Analogy andWorld Order Proposals note 14, ch.
    • Carr, The Domestic Analogy andWorld Order Proposals note 14, ch. 12.
    • Carr , pp. 12
  • 14
    • 85022427782 scopus 로고
    • at 249. In saying this Carr was echoing the views of Emerich de Vattel (1714-67), who originated the notion of non-justiciable disputes and insisted that while an arbitrated resolution to a dispute should be attempted, where a nation's ‘essential rights’ were threatened, ‘the Nation will take counsel only of its courage’, E. de Vattel, The Law of Nations or the Principles of Natural Law: Applied to the Conduct and to the Affairs of Nations and of Sovereign, trans. G. Fenwick ( [1758]), bk II, ch. XVIII, para.
    • Carr., at 249. In saying this Carr was echoing the views of Emerich de Vattel (1714-67), who originated the notion of non-justiciable disputes and insisted that while an arbitrated resolution to a dispute should be attempted, where a nation's ‘essential rights’ were threatened, ‘the Nation will take counsel only of its courage’, E. de Vattel, The Law of Nations or the Principles of Natural Law: Applied to the Conduct and to the Affairs of Nations and of Sovereign, trans. G. Fenwick (1916 [1758]), bk II, ch. XVIII, para. 331.
    • (1916) Carr , pp. 331
  • 15
    • 85022407588 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Carr note 14, at 253-4. There is a striking parallel here with Slaughter's acknowledgement that an effective transjudicial community will need to be constructed upon shared norms and commitments: see infra n.
    • Carr, Carr note 14, at 253-4. There is a striking parallel here with Slaughter's acknowledgement that an effective transjudicial community will need to be constructed upon shared norms and commitments: see infra n. 89.
    • Carr , pp. 89
  • 16
    • 85022420869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Carr note 14, at
    • Carr, Carr note 14, at 258.
    • Carr , pp. 258
  • 17
    • 85022427336 scopus 로고
    • However, it was for this reason also less cohesive. Although Morgenthau had been transformed from legalist to realist, there is a major tension in Politics among Nations between his largely positive and positivist discussion of the formal legal issues connected with the judicial function (219-28) and his forceful critique of the value of international courts (341-9). Morgenthau had trained as an international lawyer in Germany before emigrating to the United States in 1937 and beginning a new career as a founder of the realist school of international relations. His 1929 doctoral dissertation submitted to the University of Frankfurt Faculty of Law and later published was entitled Die internationale Rechtspflege, ihr Wesen und ihre Grenzen (1929). The work was reviewed by Hersch Lauterpacht in 12 British Yearbook of International Law 229. Demonstrating some prescience, Lauterpacht described the thesis as a ‘most scholarly, although somewhat negative, contribution’. For an overview ofMorgenthau's life and work seeM. Koskenniemi, The Gentle Civilizer of Nations: The Rise and Fall of International Law 1870-1960 (2001), ch. 6. Suganami suggests that parts of Politics among Nations dealing with judicial settlement were largely based onMorgenthau's doctorate: Suganami, Carr note 16, at
    • H.Morgenthau, Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace (1951). However, it was for this reason also less cohesive. Although Morgenthau had been transformed from legalist to realist, there is a major tension in Politics among Nations between his largely positive and positivist discussion of the formal legal issues connected with the judicial function (219-28) and his forceful critique of the value of international courts (341-9). Morgenthau had trained as an international lawyer in Germany before emigrating to the United States in 1937 and beginning a new career as a founder of the realist school of international relations. His 1929 doctoral dissertation submitted to the University of Frankfurt Faculty of Law and later published was entitled Die internationale Rechtspflege, ihr Wesen und ihre Grenzen (1929). The work was reviewed by Hersch Lauterpacht in (1931) 12 British Yearbook of International Law 229. Demonstrating some prescience, Lauterpacht described the thesis as a ‘most scholarly, although somewhat negative, contribution’. For an overview ofMorgenthau's life and work seeM. Koskenniemi, The Gentle Civilizer of Nations: The Rise and Fall of International Law 1870-1960 (2001), ch. 6. Suganami suggests that parts of Politics among Nations dealing with judicial settlement were largely based onMorgenthau's doctorate: Suganami, Carr note 16, at 99.
    • (1931) Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace , pp. 99
    • Morgenthau, H.1
  • 18
    • 84873840682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace note 21, at
    • Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace note 21, at 219.
    • Politics among Nations , pp. 219
    • Morgenthau1
  • 25
    • 85022428656 scopus 로고
    • M. Doyle, ‘Kant, Liberal Legacies and Foreign Affairs’, (1983) 12 Philosophy and Public Affairs 205 (Part 1), 323 (Part 2). See also F. R. Tesó n, A Philosophy of International Law (1998), 11; idem, ‘The Kantian Theory of International Law’, 92 Columbia Law Review
    • In this respect Slaughter relies heavily on the work of Michael Doyle, who examined inter-state wars from 1817 onwards: M. Doyle, ‘Kant, Liberal Legacies and Foreign Affairs’, (1983) 12 Philosophy and Public Affairs 205 (Part 1), 323 (Part 2). See also F. R. Tesó n, A Philosophy of International Law (1998), 11; idem, ‘The Kantian Theory of International Law’, (1992) 92 Columbia Law Review 53.
    • (1992) this respect Slaughter relies heavily on the work of Michael Doyle, who examined inter-state wars from 1817 onwards , pp. 53
  • 26
    • 70449435396 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • this respect Slaughter relies heavily on the work of Michael Doyle, who examined inter-state wars from 1817 onwards note 11, at 509. See I. Kant, Perpetual Peace ( [1795])
    • Slaughter, ‘International Law in aWorld of Liberal States’, this respect Slaughter relies heavily on the work of Michael Doyle, who examined inter-state wars from 1817 onwards note 11, at 509. See I. Kant, Perpetual Peace (1957 [1795]), 12-13.
    • (1957) International Law in aWorld of Liberal States , pp. 12-13
    • Slaughter1
  • 27
    • 70449435396 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘International Law in aWorld of Liberal States’ note 11, at 511. For a critique of this notion of democracy as overly narrow see S. Marks, ‘The End of History? Reflections on Some International Legal Theses’, 3 EJIL
    • Slaughter, ‘International Law in aWorld of Liberal States’, ‘International Law in aWorld of Liberal States’ note 11, at 511. For a critique of this notion of democracy as overly narrow see S. Marks, ‘The End of History? Reflections on Some International Legal Theses’, (1997) 3 EJIL 449.
    • (1997) International Law in aWorld of Liberal States , pp. 449
    • Slaughter1
  • 28
    • 0043236447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 51 International Organization 513.Moravcsik's approach, and Slaughter's development of it, are analysed as a purely empirical project in C. Reus-Smit, ‘The Strange Death of Liberal International Theory’, (2001) 12 EJIL 573, at 583, but we argue to the contrary in section 5 below.
    • A.Moravcsik, ‘Taking Preferences Seriously:ALiberal Theory of International Politics’, (1997) 51 International Organization 513.Moravcsik's approach, and Slaughter's development of it, are analysed as a purely empirical project in C. Reus-Smit, ‘The Strange Death of Liberal International Theory’, (2001) 12 EJIL 573, at 583, but we argue to the contrary in section 5 below.
    • (1997) Taking Preferences Seriously:ALiberal Theory of International Politics
    • Moravcsik, A.1
  • 29
    • 70449435396 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘Taking Preferences Seriously:ALiberal Theory of International Politics’ note 11, at
    • Slaughter, ‘International Law in aWorld of Liberal States’, ‘Taking Preferences Seriously:ALiberal Theory of International Politics’ note 11, at 509.
    • International Law in aWorld of Liberal States , pp. 509
    • Slaughter1
  • 31
    • 85022362064 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘International Law in aWorld of Liberal States’ note 11, at
    • Slaughter, ‘The Liberal Agenda for Peace’, ‘International Law in aWorld of Liberal States’ note 11, at 392.
    • The Liberal Agenda for Peace , pp. 392
    • Slaughter1
  • 34
    • 85022439481 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (1795), repr. in C. Brown, T. Nardin, and N. Rengger, International Relations in Political Thought: Texts from the Ancient Greeks to the FirstWorldWar
    • I. Kant, Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch (1795), repr. in C. Brown, T. Nardin, and N. Rengger, International Relations in Political Thought: Texts from the Ancient Greeks to the FirstWorldWar (2002), 445.
    • (2002) Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch , pp. 445
    • Kant, I.1
  • 35
    • 85022404611 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Slaughter does notmake this assumption; indeed, she suggests that given that relations between some non-liberal and liberal states might conform to the attributes of her hypothetical construct, it may be appropriate to devise some universal norms for all states, regardless of their democratic credentials: Slaughter, ‘International Law in aWorld of Liberal States’, Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch note 11, at
    • Logically there would also seem to be a need for a body of law governing relations between non-liberal states, unless it is assumed that such relations are anomic. Slaughter does notmake this assumption; indeed, she suggests that given that relations between some non-liberal and liberal states might conform to the attributes of her hypothetical construct, it may be appropriate to devise some universal norms for all states, regardless of their democratic credentials: Slaughter, ‘International Law in aWorld of Liberal States’, Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch note 11, at 511.
    • Logically there would also seem to be a need for a body of law governing relations between non-liberal states, unless it is assumed that such relations are anomic , pp. 511
  • 36
    • 85022365767 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In doing so, she risks neglecting both the potential role of diverse national public policy interventions in restricting that choice, and the range of non-contractual private international interactions, for example tort, delict, or restitution claims. However, Slaughter's vulnerability to this criticism is somewhat mitigated, given her acknowledgement of the importance of these factors in her second level of international law.
    • Unsurprisingly, Slaughter concentrates on those types of transnational interactions which exemplify the liberal paradigm-choice as expressed through contract. In doing so, she risks neglecting both the potential role of diverse national public policy interventions in restricting that choice, and the range of non-contractual private international interactions, for example tort, delict, or restitution claims. However, Slaughter's vulnerability to this criticism is somewhat mitigated, given her acknowledgement of the importance of these factors in her second level of international law.
    • Unsurprisingly, Slaughter concentrates on those types of transnational interactions which exemplify the liberal paradigm-choice as expressed through contract
  • 37
    • 85022379932 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It has been argued that international commercial arbitration, at least in certain circumstances (e.g. in industries based on trust or iterated transactions), has gained the status of an independent system of dispute resolution: see, e.g., R. Banakar, ‘Reflexive Legitimacy in International Arbitration’, in V. Gessner and A. C. Budak, Emerging Legal Certainty: Empirical Studies on the Globalization of Law (1998); T. Carbonneau, LexMercatoria and Arbitration: A Discussion of the New LawMerchant
    • See the 1958 New York Convention. It has been argued that international commercial arbitration, at least in certain circumstances (e.g. in industries based on trust or iterated transactions), has gained the status of an independent system of dispute resolution: see, e.g., R. Banakar, ‘Reflexive Legitimacy in International Arbitration’, in V. Gessner and A. C. Budak, Emerging Legal Certainty: Empirical Studies on the Globalization of Law (1998); T. Carbonneau, LexMercatoria and Arbitration: A Discussion of the New LawMerchant (1998).
    • (1998) the 1958 New York Convention
  • 39
    • 85022434592 scopus 로고
    • 89 American Society of International Law Proceedings 79, at
    • A.-M. Slaughter and A. Stone, ‘Assessing the Effectiveness of International Adjudication’, (1995) 89 American Society of International Law Proceedings 79, at 91.
    • (1995) Assessing the Effectiveness of International Adjudication , pp. 91
  • 40
  • 41
    • 85022362064 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘Toward an Age of Liberal Nations’ note 11, at 400 (emphasis added).
    • Slaughter, ‘The Liberal Agenda for Peace’, ‘Toward an Age of Liberal Nations’ note 11, at 400 (emphasis added).
    • The Liberal Agenda for Peace
    • Slaughter1
  • 43
    • 85022442473 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 94 American Society of International Law Proceedings 240, at
    • A.-M. Slaughter, ‘A Liberal Theory of International Law’, (2000) 94 American Society of International Law Proceedings 240, at 246.
    • (2000) A Liberal Theory of International Law , pp. 246
    • Slaughter, A.-M.1
  • 44
    • 85022388318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘A Liberal Theory of International Law’ note
    • But see comments above, ‘A Liberal Theory of International Law’ note 43.
    • But see comments above , pp. 43
  • 48
    • 85022430411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘International Law in aWorld of Liberal States’ note 6, at
    • Helfer and Slaughter, ‘International Law in aWorld of Liberal States’ note 6, at 387.
    • Helfer and Slaughter , pp. 387
  • 49
    • 70449435396 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Helfer and Slaughter note 11, at 532. E.g., on the issue of the Israeli-PalestinianWall, Slaughter's theory would seek to contrast the binding decision of the High Court of Israel (Beit Sourik v. Israel, HCJ 2056/04) with the Advisory Opinion of the ICJ in the Legal Consequences of the Construction of aWall in the Occupied Palestinian Territory (http://www.icj-cij.org/icjwww/icjhome.htm) (14 July 2004). An analysis of the High Court decision suggests that such a distinction would be less vulnerable to the criticism previously raised in J. E. Alvarez ('Do Liberal States Behave Better? A Critique of Slaughter's Liberal Theory’, 12 EJIL 183, at 215) in respect of Slaughter's reliance on an earlier decision (Public Committee Against Torture in Israel v. Israel,HCJ 51000/94) as evidence of transjudicial communication among judges of liberal states.
    • Slaughter, ‘International Law in a World of Liberal States’, Helfer and Slaughter note 11, at 532. E.g., on the issue of the Israeli-PalestinianWall, Slaughter's theory would seek to contrast the binding decision of the High Court of Israel (Beit Sourik v. Israel, HCJ 2056/04) with the Advisory Opinion of the ICJ in the Legal Consequences of the Construction of aWall in the Occupied Palestinian Territory (http://www.icj-cij.org/icjwww/icjhome.htm) (14 July 2004). An analysis of the High Court decision suggests that such a distinction would be less vulnerable to the criticism previously raised in J. E. Alvarez ('Do Liberal States Behave Better? A Critique of Slaughter's Liberal Theory’, (2001) 12 EJIL 183, at 215) in respect of Slaughter's reliance on an earlier decision (Public Committee Against Torture in Israel v. Israel,HCJ 51000/94) as evidence of transjudicial communication among judges of liberal states.
    • (2001) International Law in a World of Liberal States
    • Slaughter1
  • 50
    • 70449435396 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘International Law in a World of Liberal States’ note 11, at 532 (emphasis added).
    • Slaughter, ‘International Law in aWorld of Liberal States’, ‘International Law in a World of Liberal States’ note 11, at 532 (emphasis added).
    • International Law in aWorld of Liberal States
    • Slaughter1
  • 51
    • 70449435396 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at 533. This may be an implicit acknowledgement of the philosophical problems in achieving genuine communication or agreement between holders of different value systems, an issue discussedmore generally in section
    • ‘International Law in aWorld of Liberal States’., at 533. This may be an implicit acknowledgement of the philosophical problems in achieving genuine communication or agreement between holders of different value systems, an issue discussedmore generally in section 4.
    • International Law in aWorld of Liberal States , pp. 4
  • 52
    • 85022432335 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moravcsik,andSlaughter, supranote 10, at478('themorefirmlyembeddedaninternational commitment is in domestic law, the more likely is compliance with judgments to enforce it').
    • See alsoKeohane,Moravcsik,andSlaughter, supranote 10, at478('themorefirmlyembeddedaninternational commitment is in domestic law, the more likely is compliance with judgments to enforce it').
    • alsoKeohane
  • 53
  • 54
    • 85022430411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Helfer and Slaughter note 6, at
    • Helfer and Slaughter, Helfer and Slaughter note 6, at 336.
    • Helfer and Slaughter , pp. 336
  • 56
    • 85022430411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an exhaustive discussion of the politics of transnational and supranational adjudication see Keohane note 6, at 369. The level to which law is or ought to be insulated from politics is of course a point of some controversy to theorists who are not committed to procedural and institutional definitions of democracy.
    • Helfer and Slaughter, For an exhaustive discussion of the politics of transnational and supranational adjudication see Keohane note 6, at 369. The level to which law is or ought to be insulated from politics is of course a point of some controversy to theorists who are not committed to procedural and institutional definitions of democracy.
    • Helfer and Slaughter
  • 59
    • 85022414370 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Helfer and Slaughter note 60;Mattli and Slaughter, ‘Revisiting the European Court of Justice’, Helfer and Slaughter note
    • Burley andMattli, Helfer and Slaughter note 60;Mattli and Slaughter, ‘Revisiting the European Court of Justice’, Helfer and Slaughter note 60.
    • Burley andMattli , pp. 60
  • 60
    • 85022430411 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Burley andMattli note 6, at
    • Helfer and Slaughter, Burley andMattli note 6, at 373.
    • Helfer and Slaughter , pp. 373
  • 64
    • 70449435396 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Health of Nations: Society and Law Beyond the State note 11, at
    • Slaughter, ‘International Law in aWorld of Liberal States’, The Health of Nations: Society and Law Beyond the State note 11, at 535.
    • International Law in aWorld of Liberal States , pp. 535
    • Slaughter1
  • 65
    • 85022381116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moravcsik, and Slaughter, ‘International Law in aWorld of Liberal States’ note 10, at
    • Keohane,Moravcsik, and Slaughter, ‘International Law in aWorld of Liberal States’ note 10, at 466.
    • Keohane , pp. 466
  • 66
    • 85022354428 scopus 로고
    • at 479. See alsoD.S.Sullivan, ‘Effective InternationalDisputeSettlementMechanismsandtheNecessary Condition of Liberal Peace’, 81 Georgetown Law Journal 2369 (liberal democracy is a necessary but not always sufficient condition for the creation of an effective, far-reaching international dispute settlement mechanism).
    • Keohane., at 479. See alsoD.S.Sullivan, ‘Effective InternationalDisputeSettlementMechanismsandtheNecessary Condition of Liberal Peace’, (1993) 81 Georgetown Law Journal 2369 (liberal democracy is a necessary but not always sufficient condition for the creation of an effective, far-reaching international dispute settlement mechanism).
    • (1993) Keohane
  • 68
    • 85022445362 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘ACF Position on Australia-United States Free Trade Agreement’, Oct. 2003, at http://www.acfonline.org.au/docs/general/00493.pdf (22 Dec. 2004). It appears that partly as a result of such criticism an equivalent to Chapter 11 of the North American Free Trade Agreement was omitted from the US-Australia Free Trade Agreement, [2004] ATNIF 6 (to enter into force 1 Jan. ).
    • See, e.g., Australian Conservation Foundation, ‘ACF Position on Australia-United States Free Trade Agreement’, Oct. 2003, at http://www.acfonline.org.au/docs/general/00493.pdf (22 Dec. 2004). It appears that partly as a result of such criticism an equivalent to Chapter 11 of the North American Free Trade Agreement was omitted from the US-Australia Free Trade Agreement, [2004] ATNIF 6 (to enter into force 1 Jan. 2005).
    • (2005) Australian Conservation Foundation
  • 71
    • 85022379534 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘Symposium: Globalization, Accountability, and the Future of Administrative Law: The Accountability of Government Networks’ note 76, at 90 (emphasis in original).
    • Marks, ‘Symposium: Globalization, Accountability, and the Future of Administrative Law: The Accountability of Government Networks’ note 76, at 90 (emphasis in original).
    • Marks
  • 76
    • 85022388071 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • in R. French, G. Lindell, and C. Saunders (eds.), Reflections on the Australian Constitution
    • B. Opeskin, ‘Globalisation and Constitutional Law’, in R. French, G. Lindell, and C. Saunders (eds.), Reflections on the Australian Constitution (2003).
    • (2003) Globalisation and Constitutional Law
    • Opeskin, B.1
  • 80
    • 85022378906 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Here the judges themselves might be hard pressed; each can testify to his or her individual experience but would have difficulty seeing the larger vision. As an academic observer, Iwould offer the following candidates as precepts of an emerging global community of courts.’ Slaughter, text accompanying note 67 The Rule of the Many: Fundamental Issues in Democratic Theory note 60, at
    • ‘A full-fledged community, however, requires norms and principles that are recognized by its members-shared precepts that bindthemas a community, rather thanmerely as a collective.Here the judges themselves might be hard pressed; each can testify to his or her individual experience but would have difficulty seeing the larger vision. As an academic observer, Iwould offer the following candidates as precepts of an emerging global community of courts.’ Slaughter, text accompanying note 67 The Rule of the Many: Fundamental Issues in Democratic Theory note 60, at 217.
    • ‘A full-fledged community, however, requires norms and principles that are recognized by its members-shared precepts that bindthemas a community, rather thanmerely as a collective , pp. 217
  • 81
    • 85022423241 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘A full-fledged community, however, requires norms and principles that are recognized by its members-shared precepts that bindthemas a community, rather thanmerely as a collective note 32, at
    • Marks, ‘A full-fledged community, however, requires norms and principles that are recognized by its members-shared precepts that bindthemas a community, rather thanmerely as a collective note 32, at 470.
    • Marks , pp. 470
  • 82
    • 85022445036 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For such an approach see E.-U. Petersmann, (1998) 20 Michigan Journal of International Law 1; idem, ‘Constitutionalism and International Adjudication: How to Constitutionalize the UN Dispute Settlement System?’, 31 New York University Journal of International Law and Politics
    • For such an approach see E.-U. Petersmann, ‘How to Constitutionalize International Law and Foreign Policy for the Benefit of Civil Society’, (1998) 20 Michigan Journal of International Law 1; idem, ‘Constitutionalism and International Adjudication: How to Constitutionalize the UN Dispute Settlement System?’, (1999) 31 New York University Journal of International Law and Politics 753.
    • (1999) How to Constitutionalize International Law and Foreign Policy for the Benefit of Civil Society , pp. 753
  • 85
    • 84920535981 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • for example, has argued that an increased dependence on domestic courts is emerging in the context of international criminal law: Burke-White, Although there are important parallels between Slaughter's liberal internationalism and the distinctive US internationalism of democrats from PresidentWilson onwards note 11, at
    • Burke-White, for example, has argued that an increased dependence on domestic courts is emerging in the context of international criminal law: Burke-White, Although there are important parallels between Slaughter's liberal internationalism and the distinctive US internationalism of democrats from PresidentWilson onwards note 11, at 3.
    • Burke-White , pp. 3
  • 86
    • 0347901898 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Art. 8; International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR), Art. 2(3).
    • Universal Declaration ofHuman Rights, Art. 8; International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR), Art. 2(3).
    • Universal Declaration ofHuman Rights
  • 87
    • 85022365122 scopus 로고
    • (established by the ICCPR and the Optional Protocol (Optional Protocol to the ICCPR, UN GA Res. 2200 A (XXI), GAOR, 21st Session, Supp. No. 16 (A/6316)), the Committee on the Elimination of Racial Discrimination (established by the International Convention for Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination, UN GA Res. 2106A (XX), GAOR, 12th Session, Supp. No. 14 (A/6014) 47, UN Doc. A/CONF 32/4); Committee against Torture (established by the 1984 Convention against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment, (1984) 23 ILM 1027); the Inter-American Court ofHuman Rights (established by the 1969 American Convention onHuman Rights, (1970) 9 ILM673); the African Commission onHuman and Peoples’ Rights (established by the 1981 African Charter onHuman and Peoples’ Rights, 21 ILM 58).
    • These include theHuman Rights Committee (established by the ICCPR and the Optional Protocol (Optional Protocol to the ICCPR, UN GA Res. 2200 A (XXI), GAOR, 21st Session, Supp. No. 16 (A/6316)), the Committee on the Elimination of Racial Discrimination (established by the International Convention for Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination, UN GA Res. 2106A (XX), GAOR, 12th Session, Supp. No. 14 (A/6014) 47, UN Doc. A/CONF 32/4); Committee against Torture (established by the 1984 Convention against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment, (1984) 23 ILM 1027); the Inter-American Court ofHuman Rights (established by the 1969 American Convention onHuman Rights, (1970) 9 ILM673); the African Commission onHuman and Peoples’ Rights (established by the 1981 African Charter onHuman and Peoples’ Rights, (1982) 21 ILM 58).
    • (1982) These include theHuman Rights Committee
  • 89
    • 85022451055 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ‘The Liberal Agenda for Peace’, Note, for instance, that the jurisdiction of the ICC is only ‘complementary’ to national criminal jurisdictions in the sense that a case can be brought before the ICC only if a state with jurisdiction is unwilling or unable genuinely to investigate or prosecute the case note 11 (highlighting the weaknesses of the dichotomized realist/legalist conceptualization of the United Nations and offering an agenda for its reform based on liberal international relations theory).
    • See in particular Slaughter, ‘The Liberal Agenda for Peace’, Note, for instance, that the jurisdiction of the ICC is only ‘complementary’ to national criminal jurisdictions in the sense that a case can be brought before the ICC only if a state with jurisdiction is unwilling or unable genuinely to investigate or prosecute the case note 11 (highlighting the weaknesses of the dichotomized realist/legalist conceptualization of the United Nations and offering an agenda for its reform based on liberal international relations theory).
    • particular Slaughter
  • 90
  • 92
    • 85022409370 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Admission of a State to the United Nations note 100, at 566. Simpson also suggests (at 566-7) that while Slaughter appears inrecent years to be retreating from an anti-pluralist position, that retreat is incompatible with her use of the distinction in the behaviour of liberal and non-liberal states to generate prescriptions for institutional reform that take these distinctions seriously.
    • Simpson, Admission of a State to the United Nations note 100, at 566. Simpson also suggests (at 566-7) that while Slaughter appears inrecent years to be retreating from an anti-pluralist position, that retreat is incompatible with her use of the distinction in the behaviour of liberal and non-liberal states to generate prescriptions for institutional reform that take these distinctions seriously.
    • Simpson
  • 93
    • 85022363368 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Philosophy, Simpson note 30, at
    • Tesó n, A Philosophy, Simpson note 30, at 21, 25.
    • Tesó n , vol.21 , pp. 25
  • 94
    • 85022373663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Tesó n., at 17.
    • Tesó n , pp. 17
  • 95
    • 85022398376 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • at
    • Tesó n., at 19.
    • Tesó n , pp. 19
  • 98
    • 85022419675 scopus 로고
    • Justice, Legitimacy and Self-Determination:Moral Foundations for International Law note 30; M. Reisman, ‘Sovereignty and Human Rights in Contemporary International Law’ 84 AJIL 866; see also Simpson, Justice, Legitimacy and Self-Determination:Moral Foundations for International Law note 100, at
    • Tesó n, Justice, Legitimacy and Self-Determination:Moral Foundations for International Law note 30; M. Reisman, ‘Sovereignty and Human Rights in Contemporary International Law’ (1990) 84 AJIL 866; see also Simpson, Justice, Legitimacy and Self-Determination:Moral Foundations for International Law note 100, at 558, 563.
    • (1990) Tesó n , vol.558 , pp. 563
  • 101
    • 85022422233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fairness in International Law and Institutions note
    • Reus-Smit, Fairness in International Law and Institutions note 34.
    • Reus-Smit1
  • 104
    • 85022367832 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Reus-Smit does point out that this neutral stance in Slaughter's work is inconsistent with the parts of her work where she advocates a normative agenda, but suggests that her normativity is without foundation rather than (as we suggest) her claim for neutrality note 106 note 55, at 192 et seq.
    • See discussion in Alvarez, Reus-Smit does point out that this neutral stance in Slaughter's work is inconsistent with the parts of her work where she advocates a normative agenda, but suggests that her normativity is without foundation rather than (as we suggest) her claim for neutrality note 106 note 55, at 192 et seq.
    • discussion in Alvarez
  • 106
    • 85022354007 scopus 로고
    • discussion in Alvarez note 76 note 110, at 138. Franck's analysis borrows from Schumpeter's work in the seeMarks, discussion in Alvarez note 76 note 76, at
    • Franck, discussion in Alvarez note 76 note 110, at 138. Franck's analysis borrows from Schumpeter's work in the 1940s-seeMarks, discussion in Alvarez note 76 note 76, at 50.
    • (1940) Franck , pp. 50
  • 107
    • 85022384939 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Franck note 76, at
    • Marks, Franck note 76, at 57.
    • Marks , pp. 57
  • 108
    • 77952256647 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A similar point is made with respect to the possibility of internationalizing a norm of domestic governance in M. Koskenniemi, 37 Harvard International Law Journal
    • A similar point is made with respect to the possibility of internationalizing a norm of domestic governance in M. Koskenniemi, ‘“Intolerant Democracies”: A Reaction’, (1996) 37 Harvard International Law Journal 231.
    • (1996) “Intolerant Democracies”: A Reaction , pp. 231


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.