-
1
-
-
84997866335
-
Bindingen als voorwaarden voor de voorwaarde van het goede leven? Een kritiek op Will Kymlicka's morele monisme
-
This article is a substantially revised version of
-
This article is a substantially revised version of Bart van Leeuwen, ‘Bindingen als voorwaarden voor de voorwaarde van het goede leven? Een kritiek op Will Kymlicka's morele monisme’, Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Rechtsfilosofie en Rechtstheorie 31(3) (2002): 235–50.
-
(2002)
Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Rechtsfilosofie en Rechtstheorie
, vol.31
, Issue.3
, pp. 235-250
-
-
van Leeuwen, B.1
-
3
-
-
0001778197
-
The Politics of Recognition
-
in Amy Gutmann (ed.), Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
-
Charles Taylor, ‘The Politics of Recognition’, in Amy Gutmann (ed.) Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1994), pp. 25–73.
-
(1994)
Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition
, pp. 25-73
-
-
Taylor, C.1
-
4
-
-
0003985193
-
-
When concepts such as ‘culture’, ‘social attachment’ or ‘sense of belonging’ are being used in this study, they should be interpreted in a non-essentialist manner. That implies first a rejection of the idea that cultural diversity should be understood as a ‘mosaic’: a collection of internally homogeneous and hard-edged pieces, which are neatly positioned against one another. Instead, cultures are internally mixed, often overlapping, while cultural and sub-cultural boundaries are by their nature more often blurred than clear, New York: Columbia University Press, Secondly, cultural belonging or social attachments do not imply that people are dominated unilaterally by a homogeneous sphere of meanings that is supposed to exist independently from daily meaning-generating practices. Culture is neither a static ‘structure’ nor a collection of cerebral ‘ideas of the good’, but it should be understood as a relatively coherent set of practices and institutions, which embody particular norms and values of a social group. ‘Embodiment’ means that these norms and values exist in the changing and plural cultural expression itself. Moreover, social groups do not simply execute cultural practices; they also reflect on and in consequence shape these practices
-
When concepts such as ‘culture’, ‘social attachment’ or ‘sense of belonging’ are being used in this study, they should be interpreted in a non-essentialist manner. That implies first a rejection of the idea that cultural diversity should be understood as a ‘mosaic’: a collection of internally homogeneous and hard-edged pieces, which are neatly positioned against one another. Instead, cultures are internally mixed, often overlapping, while cultural and sub-cultural boundaries are by their nature more often blurred than clear. See Ulf Hannerz, Cultural Complexity: Studies in the Social Organization of Meaning (New York: Columbia University Press, 1992). Secondly, cultural belonging or social attachments do not imply that people are dominated unilaterally by a homogeneous sphere of meanings that is supposed to exist independently from daily meaning-generating practices. Culture is neither a static ‘structure’ nor a collection of cerebral ‘ideas of the good’, but it should be understood as a relatively coherent set of practices and institutions, which embody particular norms and values of a social group. ‘Embodiment’ means that these norms and values exist in the changing and plural cultural expression itself. Moreover, social groups do not simply execute cultural practices; they also reflect on and in consequence shape these practices.
-
(1992)
Cultural Complexity: Studies in the Social Organization of Meaning
-
-
Hannerz, U.1
-
6
-
-
0040783984
-
Multiculturalism
-
Joseph Raz formulates the theoretical challenge of multiculturalism in a similar way: ‘One of the theoretical — rather than merely political — challenges multiculturalism gives rise to is how to combine the truth of universalism with the truth in particularism.’
-
Joseph Raz formulates the theoretical challenge of multiculturalism in a similar way: ‘One of the theoretical — rather than merely political — challenges multiculturalism gives rise to is how to combine the truth of universalism with the truth in particularism.’ See Joseph Raz, ‘Multiculturalism’, Ratio Juris 11(3) (1998): 193–205 (194).
-
(1998)
Ratio Juris
, vol.11
, Issue.3
, pp. 193-205
-
-
Raz, J.1
-
9
-
-
80052527400
-
Official-Language Rights: Intrinsic Value and the Protection of Difference
-
Denise Réaume is one example: ‘On this [Kymlicka's] account, planning one's own life is not valuable merely because it promotes some further valuable end, but rather is good in itself. It does not derive its value from its contribution to some other end, but rather itself accounts for the value of a particular life. In other words, the self-directioned life is intrinsically good.’, Will Kymlicka and Wayne Norman (eds), Oxford: Oxford University Press, Réaume ignores in her article the fact that self-direction, or personal autonomy, according to Kymlicka, is not so much an end in itself but rather a necessary condition to liberalism's supreme value: living the good life. Kymlicka is quite explicit about this: ‘Liberals aren't saying that we should have the freedom to select our projects for its own sake, because freedom is the most valuable thing in the world. Rather, it is our projects and tasks that are the most important things in our lives, and it is because they are so important that we should be free to revise and reject them…. Freedom of choice, then, isn't pursued for its own sake, but as a precondition for pursuing those projects and practices that are valued for their own sake.’
-
Denise Réaume is one example: ‘On this [Kymlicka's] account, planning one's own life is not valuable merely because it promotes some further valuable end, but rather is good in itself. It does not derive its value from its contribution to some other end, but rather itself accounts for the value of a particular life. In other words, the self-directioned life is intrinsically good.’ Denise Réaume, ‘Official-Language Rights: Intrinsic Value and the Protection of Difference’, in Will Kymlicka and Wayne Norman (eds) Citizenship in Diverse Societies (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), pp. 245–72 (246). Réaume ignores in her article the fact that self-direction, or personal autonomy, according to Kymlicka, is not so much an end in itself but rather a necessary condition to liberalism's supreme value: living the good life. Kymlicka is quite explicit about this: ‘Liberals aren't saying that we should have the freedom to select our projects for its own sake, because freedom is the most valuable thing in the world. Rather, it is our projects and tasks that are the most important things in our lives, and it is because they are so important that we should be free to revise and reject them…. Freedom of choice, then, isn't pursued for its own sake, but as a precondition for pursuing those projects and practices that are valued for their own sake.’
-
(2000)
Citizenship in Diverse Societies
, pp. 245-272
-
-
Réaume, D.1
-
10
-
-
84970789439
-
-
I shall come back to Réaume's article later on
-
See Kymlicka, Liberalism, Community and Culture, p. 48. I shall come back to Réaume's article later on.
-
Liberalism, Community and Culture
, pp. 48
-
-
Kymlicka1
-
13
-
-
33751317295
-
The Nature and Value of Rights
-
For the interpretation of rights in terms of ‘claims’, It is furthermore important for our argument to recognize that a concept of rights implies, implicitly or more explicitly, a concept of individual well-being
-
For the interpretation of rights in terms of ‘claims’, see Joel Feinberg, ‘The Nature and Value of Rights’, Journal of Value Inquiry 4 (1969): 243–57. It is furthermore important for our argument to recognize that a concept of rights implies, implicitly or more explicitly, a concept of individual well-being.
-
(1969)
Journal of Value Inquiry
, vol.4
, pp. 243-257
-
-
Feinberg, J.1
-
14
-
-
0009430406
-
Rights and Individual Well-Being
-
defends this view in a number of his works; for instance, in, Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
Joseph Raz defends this view in a number of his works; for instance, in ‘Rights and Individual Well-Being’, in Joseph Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain: Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994), pp. 29–44.
-
(1994)
Ethics in the Public Domain: Essays in the Morality of Law and Politics
, pp. 29-44
-
-
Raz, J.1
-
15
-
-
60949382427
-
The Importance of Autonomy
-
in Thomas Hill, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
Thomas Hill, ‘The Importance of Autonomy’, in Thomas Hill, Autonomy and Self-Respect (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 43–51.
-
(1991)
Autonomy and Self-Respect
, pp. 43-51
-
-
Hill, T.1
-
16
-
-
84970789439
-
-
For this crucial argument in Kymlicka's theory of minority rights, see
-
For this crucial argument in Kymlicka's theory of minority rights, see Kymlicka, Liberalism, Community and Culture, pp. 162–72;
-
Liberalism, Community and Culture
, pp. 162-172
-
-
Kymlicka1
-
17
-
-
0004022577
-
-
§5.3, ‘Societal Cultures as Context of Choice’
-
Kymlicka, Multicultural Citizenship, §5.3, ‘Societal Cultures as Context of Choice’
-
Multicultural Citizenship
-
-
Kymlicka1
-
22
-
-
38949210433
-
Citizenship in Culturally Diverse Societies: Issues, Contexts, Concepts
-
in Kymlicka and Norman (eds), 18ff
-
Will Kymlicka and Wayne Norman, ‘Citizenship in Culturally Diverse Societies: Issues, Contexts, Concepts’, in Kymlicka and Norman (eds) Citizenship in Diverse Societies, pp. 1–41, 18ff.
-
Citizenship in Diverse Societies
, pp. 1-41
-
-
Kymlicka, W.1
Norman, W.2
-
23
-
-
84910028206
-
Do We Need a Liberal Theory of Minority Rights?
-
Will Kymlicka, ‘Do We Need a Liberal Theory of Minority Rights?’, Constellations 4(1) (1997): 72–87 (73–4).
-
(1997)
Constellations
, vol.4
, Issue.1
, pp. 72-87
-
-
Kymlicka, W.1
-
28
-
-
84937268797
-
Dilemmas of a Multicultural Theory of Citizenship
-
Bhikhu Parekh, ‘Dilemmas of a Multicultural Theory of Citizenship’, Constellations 4(1) (1997): 54–62;
-
(1997)
Constellations
, vol.4
, Issue.1
, pp. 54-62
-
-
Parekh, B.1
-
29
-
-
0039165825
-
Plural Cultures, Contested Territories: a Critique of Kymlicka
-
Brian Walker, ‘Plural Cultures, Contested Territories: a Critique of Kymlicka’, Canadian Journal of Political Science 30(2) (1997): 211–34;
-
(1997)
Canadian Journal of Political Science
, vol.30
, Issue.2
, pp. 211-234
-
-
Walker, B.1
-
30
-
-
0002782474
-
Minority Cultures and the Cosmopolitan Alternative
-
in W. Kymlicka (ed.), Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Jeremy Waldron, ‘Minority Cultures and the Cosmopolitan Alternative’, in W. Kymlicka (ed.) The Rights of Minority Cultures (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995), pp. 93–119;
-
(1995)
The Rights of Minority Cultures
, pp. 93-119
-
-
Waldron, J.1
-
34
-
-
84910064243
-
A Multicultural Continuum: a Critique of Will Kymlicka's Ethnic-Nation Dichotomy
-
Iris Marion Young, ‘A Multicultural Continuum: a Critique of Will Kymlicka's Ethnic-Nation Dichotomy’, Constellations 4(1) (1997): 48–53;
-
(1997)
Constellations
, vol.4
, Issue.1
, pp. 48-53
-
-
Young, I.M.1
-
36
-
-
0004323817
-
-
Others have made the same point, though in more general terms
-
Barry, Culture and Equality. Others have made the same point, though in more general terms.
-
Culture and Equality
-
-
Barry1
-
37
-
-
0002367489
-
The Multicultural Misunderstanding
-
See Kwame Anthony Appiah, ‘The Multicultural Misunderstanding’, The New York Review of Books 44(15) (1997): 30–6;
-
(1997)
The New York Review of Books
, vol.44
, Issue.15
, pp. 30-36
-
-
Appiah, K.A.1
-
40
-
-
23044466518
-
Intrinsic Value as a Reason for the Preservation of Minority Cultures
-
Albert Musschenga, ‘Intrinsic Value as a Reason for the Preservation of Minority Cultures’, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 1(2) (1998): 201–25;
-
(1998)
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice
, vol.1
, Issue.2
, pp. 201-225
-
-
Musschenga, A.1
-
41
-
-
84998034551
-
The Intrinsic Value of Cultures
-
Neil Levy, ‘The Intrinsic Value of Cultures’, Philosophy in the Contemporary World 9(2) (2002): 49–57;
-
(2002)
Philosophy in the Contemporary World
, vol.9
, Issue.2
, pp. 49-57
-
-
Levy, N.1
-
43
-
-
8144226181
-
Beyond Personality: the Territorial and Personal Principles of Language Policy Reconsidered
-
in Will Kymlicka and Alan Patten (eds), Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Denise Réaume, ‘Beyond Personality: the Territorial and Personal Principles of Language Policy Reconsidered’, in Will Kymlicka and Alan Patten (eds) Language Rights and Political Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003), pp. 271–95;
-
(2003)
Language Rights and Political Theory
, pp. 271-295
-
-
Réaume, D.1
-
44
-
-
84937316154
-
Can Liberalism be Communitarian?
-
Charles Taylor, ‘Can Liberalism be Communitarian?’, Critical Review 8(2) (1994): 257–62;
-
(1994)
Critical Review
, vol.8
, Issue.2
, pp. 257-262
-
-
Taylor, C.1
-
46
-
-
84976069232
-
The Value of Cultural Belonging: Expanding Kymlicka's Theory
-
James Nickel, ‘The Value of Cultural Belonging: Expanding Kymlicka's Theory’, Dialogue 33(4) (1994): 635–42;
-
(1994)
Dialogue
, vol.33
, Issue.4
, pp. 635-642
-
-
Nickel, J.1
-
47
-
-
79952378956
-
Liberalism and the Right to Culture
-
Avishai Margalit and Moshe Halbertal, ‘Liberalism and the Right to Culture’, Social Research 61(3) (1994): 491–510.
-
(1994)
Social Research
, vol.61
, Issue.3
, pp. 491-510
-
-
Margalit, A.1
Halbertal, M.2
-
50
-
-
0007338326
-
-
emphasis added. Because Kymlicka is unable or unwilling to recognize value pluralism, his work is full of examples of instrumental reductionism: ‘Justice is an intrinsic value, and the most basic obligation of the State. Civic virtue, by contrast, is only an instrumental value. Indeed, the main reason to be concerned about the erosion of civic virtue is that it may over time diminish the ability of the State to secure justice.’ Kymlicka goes on to say that it would be a profound mistake to privilege the promotion of civic virtue over the remedying of injustice. But to me it seems an equally profound mistake to understand civic virtue only as a means for ‘the State to secure justice’
-
Kymlicka, ‘Do We Need a Liberal Theory of Minority Rights?’, p. 83; emphasis added. Because Kymlicka is unable or unwilling to recognize value pluralism, his work is full of examples of instrumental reductionism: ‘Justice is an intrinsic value, and the most basic obligation of the State. Civic virtue, by contrast, is only an instrumental value. Indeed, the main reason to be concerned about the erosion of civic virtue is that it may over time diminish the ability of the State to secure justice.’ Kymlicka goes on to say that it would be a profound mistake to privilege the promotion of civic virtue over the remedying of injustice. But to me it seems an equally profound mistake to understand civic virtue only as a means for ‘the State to secure justice’.
-
Do We Need a Liberal Theory of Minority Rights?
, pp. 83
-
-
Kymlicka1
-
51
-
-
0037548747
-
Comments on Shachar and Spinner-Halev: an Update from the Multiculturalism Wars
-
Christian Joppke and Steven Lukes (eds), Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
Will Kymlicka, ‘Comments on Shachar and Spinner-Halev: an Update from the Multiculturalism Wars’, in Christian Joppke and Steven Lukes (eds) Multicultural Questions (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), pp. 112–29 (126).
-
(1999)
Multicultural Questions
, pp. 112-129
-
-
Kymlicka, W.1
-
55
-
-
84998011302
-
-
Neil Levy uses the idea of an assimilation machine in a similar manner; however, he remains trapped within the opposition between the intrinsic value and the instrumental value of culture (or language). See, For reasons that I shall explain later this opposition is extremely misleading
-
Neil Levy uses the idea of an assimilation machine in a similar manner; however, he remains trapped within the opposition between the intrinsic value and the instrumental value of culture (or language). See Levy, ‘The Intrinsic Value of Cultures’. For reasons that I shall explain later this opposition is extremely misleading.
-
The Intrinsic Value of Cultures
-
-
Levy1
-
58
-
-
84970789439
-
-
See §2. Therefore it is not sufficient to defend Kymlicka against my critique by lifting his theory to a political level that is subsequently detached from anthropological or social-philosophical concerns. Kymlicka's political philosophy rightly takes as its point of departure certain anthropological assumptions on the formal conditions of the good life. Politics ought to be evaluated accordingly. Therefore some of the discussions that Kymlicka is engaged in, as with Michael Sandel, take place on this level (cf., ch. 4). Incidentally, what is at stake in my discussion with Kymlicka is very different from what is at stake in his discussion with Sandel. My thesis is not that some goals constitute the subject unilaterally and are in that sense beyond the reach of individual reevaluation, as Sandel appears to suggest. Although a social attachment to a cultural or religious group is always to some degree beyond direct personal understanding or control, it is never unavoidable like a fate. People are always capable of reconsidering collective goals and their ties to a social group, however important this belonging has been for the identity of the persons in question. My point is, however, that Kymlicka's moral justification of minority rights implies an untenable social-philosophical presupposition, namely that autonomy is the only structural condition of the good life and that social attachments are important to people only insofar as they make individual freedom of choice possible. However, the fact that people are capable of reconsidering their social attachments does not imply that these attachments have only an instrumental meaning for them
-
See §2. Therefore it is not sufficient to defend Kymlicka against my critique by lifting his theory to a political level that is subsequently detached from anthropological or social-philosophical concerns. Kymlicka's political philosophy rightly takes as its point of departure certain anthropological assumptions on the formal conditions of the good life. Politics ought to be evaluated accordingly. Therefore some of the discussions that Kymlicka is engaged in, as with Michael Sandel, take place on this level (cf. Kymlicka, Liberalism, Community and Culture, ch. 4). Incidentally, what is at stake in my discussion with Kymlicka is very different from what is at stake in his discussion with Sandel. My thesis is not that some goals constitute the subject unilaterally and are in that sense beyond the reach of individual reevaluation, as Sandel appears to suggest. Although a social attachment to a cultural or religious group is always to some degree beyond direct personal understanding or control, it is never unavoidable like a fate. People are always capable of reconsidering collective goals and their ties to a social group, however important this belonging has been for the identity of the persons in question. My point is, however, that Kymlicka's moral justification of minority rights implies an untenable social-philosophical presupposition, namely that autonomy is the only structural condition of the good life and that social attachments are important to people only insofar as they make individual freedom of choice possible. However, the fact that people are capable of reconsidering their social attachments does not imply that these attachments have only an instrumental meaning for them.
-
Liberalism, Community and Culture
-
-
Kymlicka1
-
61
-
-
1542282134
-
The Crooked Timber of Nationalism
-
in Mark Lilla et al. (eds), New York: New York Review Books
-
Cf. Avishai Margalit, ‘The Crooked Timber of Nationalism’, in Mark Lilla et al. (eds) The Legacy of Isaiah Berlin (New York: New York Review Books, 2001), pp. 147–59.
-
(2001)
The Legacy of Isaiah Berlin
, pp. 147-159
-
-
Margalit, A.1
-
62
-
-
0004292576
-
-
For this aspect of social attachments, see also the description of ‘encompassing groups’ — especially characterization number 5 — in, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
For this aspect of social attachments, see also the description of ‘encompassing groups’ — especially characterization number 5 — in Avishai Margalit, The Decent Society (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996), pp. 139–40.
-
(1996)
The Decent Society
, pp. 139-140
-
-
Margalit, A.1
-
64
-
-
0004184760
-
-
That the human mind is structured dialogically means, in Taylor's vocabulary, that it is in need of external confirmation, in terms not only of expression but also of recognition from others. This notion is closely related to the concept of ‘embodiment’ that is so central to Taylor's interpretation of Hegel's work, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
That the human mind is structured dialogically means, in Taylor's vocabulary, that it is in need of external confirmation, in terms not only of expression but also of recognition from others. This notion is closely related to the concept of ‘embodiment’ that is so central to Taylor's interpretation of Hegel's work. See Charles Taylor, Hegel and Modern Society (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), ch. 1.
-
(1979)
Hegel and Modern Society
-
-
Taylor, C.1
-
65
-
-
0002636259
-
The Dialogical Self
-
in David Hiley et al. (eds), Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
-
See also Charles Taylor, ‘The Dialogical Self’, in David Hiley et al. (eds) The Interpretive Turn: Philosophy, Science, Culture (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991), pp. 304–14.
-
(1991)
The Interpretive Turn: Philosophy, Science, Culture
, pp. 304-314
-
-
Taylor, C.1
-
67
-
-
10044288778
-
-
This seems to be the position Honneth hints at in one of his later publications. In, he argues that the overwhelming majority of claims for recognition by social minorities is ‘essentially determined by the recognition principle of legal equality’ (p. 169). Within Honneth's tripartite division, this seems to imply that, just like social and political rights in his theory, cultural rights are safeguarding the conditions for personal autonomy. It must, however, be said that Honneth is very unclear about this, for he does not explain in what way culture should be incorporated in the sphere of equal respect for autonomy. He argues only that most of the claims of minority groups ‘can usually be understood as an innovative application of the equality principal’ (p. 169). Yet, it remains unclear how he himself sees this ‘innovation’
-
This seems to be the position Honneth hints at in one of his later publications. In Fraser and Honneth, Redistribution or Recognition?, he argues that the overwhelming majority of claims for recognition by social minorities is ‘essentially determined by the recognition principle of legal equality’ (p. 169). Within Honneth's tripartite division, this seems to imply that, just like social and political rights in his theory, cultural rights are safeguarding the conditions for personal autonomy. It must, however, be said that Honneth is very unclear about this, for he does not explain in what way culture should be incorporated in the sphere of equal respect for autonomy. He argues only that most of the claims of minority groups ‘can usually be understood as an innovative application of the equality principal’ (p. 169). Yet, it remains unclear how he himself sees this ‘innovation’.
-
Redistribution or Recognition?
-
-
Fraser1
Honneth2
-
69
-
-
10844226357
-
The Struggle for Recognition in the Philosophy of Axel Honneth, Applied to the Current South African Situation and its Call for an African Renaissance
-
Gail Presbey, ‘The Struggle for Recognition in the Philosophy of Axel Honneth, Applied to the Current South African Situation and its Call for an African Renaissance’, Philosophy & Social Criticism 29(5) (2003): 537–61.
-
(2003)
Philosophy & Social Criticism
, vol.29
, Issue.5
, pp. 537-561
-
-
Presbey, G.1
-
70
-
-
0039217876
-
Recognition, Value, and Equality: a Critique of Charles Taylor's and Nancy Fraser's Accounts of Multiculturalism
-
Cynthia Willett (ed.), Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers, 1998
-
Cf. Lawrence Blum (1998), ‘Recognition, Value, and Equality: a Critique of Charles Taylor's and Nancy Fraser's Accounts of Multiculturalism’, in Cynthia Willett (ed.) Theorizing Multiculturalism: A Guide to the Current Debate (Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers, 1998), pp. 73–99.
-
(1998)
Theorizing Multiculturalism: A Guide to the Current Debate
, pp. 73-99
-
-
Blum, L.1
-
71
-
-
0004351763
-
Official-Language Rights
-
also pp. 251, 252, 258
-
Réaume, ‘Official-Language Rights’, p. 250, also pp. 251, 252, 258.
-
-
-
Réaume1
-
72
-
-
58849092816
-
The Antinomy of Language Policy
-
For such a critical interpretation of Réaume's point of view:, in Kymlicka and Patten (eds)
-
For such a critical interpretation of Réaume's point of view: Daniel Weinstock, ‘The Antinomy of Language Policy’, in Kymlicka and Patten (eds) Language Rights and Political Theory, pp. 250–70;
-
Language Rights and Political Theory
, pp. 250-270
-
-
Weinstock, D.1
-
73
-
-
84861990125
-
Global Linguistic Diversity, Public Goods, and the Principle of Fairness
-
Kymlicka and Patten (eds), especially pp. 207–9
-
see also Idil Boran, ‘Global Linguistic Diversity, Public Goods, and the Principle of Fairness’, in Kymlicka and Patten (eds) Language Rights and Political Theory, pp. 189–209, especially pp. 207–9.
-
Language Rights and Political Theory
, pp. 189-209
-
-
Boran, I.1
-
75
-
-
0038562763
-
Francophonia for Ever: the Contradiction in Charles Taylor's “Politics of Recognition”
-
23 July
-
Andy Lamey, ‘Francophonia for Ever: the Contradiction in Charles Taylor's “Politics of Recognition”’, The Times Literary Supplement, 23 July 1999, pp. 12–15 (14).
-
(1999)
The Times Literary Supplement
, pp. 12-15
-
-
Lamey, A.1
-
76
-
-
0033474432
-
Negative Freedom and Cultural Belonging; an Unhealthy Tension in the Political Philosophy of Isaiah Berlin
-
Honneth reduces, for example, the possibilities for the justification of difference-respect to these choices in his article on Isaiah Berlin
-
Honneth reduces, for example, the possibilities for the justification of difference-respect to these choices in his article on Isaiah Berlin: Axel Honneth, ‘Negative Freedom and Cultural Belonging; an Unhealthy Tension in the Political Philosophy of Isaiah Berlin’, Social Research 66(4) (1999): 1063–77.
-
(1999)
Social Research
, vol.66
, Issue.4
, pp. 1063-1077
-
-
Honneth, A.1
-
81
-
-
84923980017
-
Associative Democracy and Minorities Within Minorities
-
As Veit Bader puts it sharply: ‘Practices of slavery, caste, bondage, or of an unequal civil and political status for ascriptive minorities, are incompatible with the most minimalist interpretation of modern freedom and equality. Practices like sati, domestic violence, stranger-rape, marital rape, sexual abuse, genital mutilation, honor killing, forced collective suicide are surely incompatible with the most minimalist interpretations of basic rights to life and bodily integrity. Group autonomy should not be allowed to shield these practices. Public opinion and liberal-democratic polities must try to convince minorities to change these practices, and jurisdictions must prosecute and punish perpetrators.’, in Avigail Eisenberg and Jeff Spinner-Halev (eds), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
As Veit Bader puts it sharply: ‘Practices of slavery, caste, bondage, or of an unequal civil and political status for ascriptive minorities, are incompatible with the most minimalist interpretation of modern freedom and equality. Practices like sati, domestic violence, stranger-rape, marital rape, sexual abuse, genital mutilation, honor killing, forced collective suicide are surely incompatible with the most minimalist interpretations of basic rights to life and bodily integrity. Group autonomy should not be allowed to shield these practices. Public opinion and liberal-democratic polities must try to convince minorities to change these practices, and jurisdictions must prosecute and punish perpetrators.’ Veit Bader, ‘Associative Democracy and Minorities Within Minorities’, in Avigail Eisenberg and Jeff Spinner-Halev (eds) Minorities within Minorities: Equality, Rights and Diversity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), pp. 319–39 (p. 328).
-
(2005)
Minorities within Minorities: Equality, Rights and Diversity
, pp. 319-339
-
-
Bader, V.1
-
82
-
-
84923010855
-
Attachment and Uniqueness
-
Joseph Raz, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
See Joseph Raz, ‘Attachment and Uniqueness’, in Joseph Raz, Value, Respect and Attachment (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), pp. 10–40.
-
(2001)
Value, Respect and Attachment
, pp. 10-40
-
-
Raz, J.1
-
83
-
-
84998011140
-
Voorschoolse en buitenschoolse opvoeding
-
in Rinus Penninx et al. (eds), Groningen: Wolters-Noordhoff, 604ff
-
Trees Pels, ‘Voorschoolse en buitenschoolse opvoeding’, in Rinus Penninx et al. (eds) Etnische minderheden en de multiculturele samenleving (Groningen: Wolters-Noordhoff, 1998), pp. 585–611, 604ff.
-
(1998)
Etnische minderheden en de multiculturele samenleving
, pp. 585-611
-
-
Pels, T.1
-
84
-
-
84890484425
-
-
Assen: Van Gorcum, ‘Parents … are rather being treated as an instrument to enhance the development of their children than to provide them with support in their role as educators’ (p. 222; my translation)
-
Trees Pels (ed.) Opvoeding en integratie (Assen: Van Gorcum, 2000): ‘Parents … are rather being treated as an instrument to enhance the development of their children than to provide them with support in their role as educators’ (p. 222; my translation).
-
(2000)
Opvoeding en integratie
-
-
Pels, T.1
-
85
-
-
84997906557
-
Voorschoolse en buitenschoolse opvoeding
-
Pels, ‘Voorschoolse en buitenschoolse opvoeding’, pp. 597ff;
-
-
-
Pels1
-
88
-
-
2942672178
-
Liberale moraal en preventieve gezinsinterventie
-
Government intervention on an involuntary basis has been proposed in the United States as in other countries (both in academic circles and by political parties) in order to prevent criminal behaviour by children from so-called high-risk families. This category of families is being determined on the basis of a combination of risk factors such as unemployment, young single parenthood, behavioural dysfunctions or low IQ of the children and belonging to certain minority groups, in Hans de Frankrijer et al. (eds), Amsterdam: SWP
-
Government intervention on an involuntary basis has been proposed in the United States as in other countries (both in academic circles and by political parties) in order to prevent criminal behaviour by children from so-called high-risk families. This category of families is being determined on the basis of a combination of risk factors such as unemployment, young single parenthood, behavioural dysfunctions or low IQ of the children and belonging to certain minority groups. Ger Snik and Wouter van Haaften, ‘Liberale moraal en preventieve gezinsinterventie’, in Hans de Frankrijer et al. (eds) Gezin, morele opvoeding en antisociaal gedrag (Amsterdam: SWP, 2000), pp. 10–18 (10–12).
-
(2000)
Gezin, morele opvoeding en antisociaal gedrag
, pp. 10-18
-
-
Snik, G.1
van Haaften, W.2
-
89
-
-
60949537683
-
-
European colonists in Canada, who wanted to assimilate the natives, were also familiar with this technical possibility: ‘they have tried to culturally assimilate the youth in a deliberate and planned manner, especially by lodging them into boarding schools. There, they were forbidden to speak their own language and their culture was systematically devalued and run down.’, Leuven: Acco, (my translation)
-
European colonists in Canada, who wanted to assimilate the natives, were also familiar with this technical possibility: ‘they have tried to culturally assimilate the youth in a deliberate and planned manner, especially by lodging them into boarding schools. There, they were forbidden to speak their own language and their culture was systematically devalued and run down.’ Eugeen Roosens, Eigen grond eerst? Primordiale autochtonie: dilemma van de multiculturele samenleving (Leuven: Acco, 1998), p. 77 (my translation).
-
(1998)
Eigen grond eerst? Primordiale autochtonie: dilemma van de multiculturele samenleving
, pp. 77
-
-
Roosens, E.1
-
91
-
-
0003264086
-
Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women?
-
The pedagogical dialectic takes place against the background of certain non-negotiable norms that are given with the liberal democratic state, such as the equality between male and female. As I said, internal restrictions cannot be tolerated. It seems to me that the basic conceptual distinction between external protections and internal restrictions is one of the great achievements of Kymlicka's theory. In his reply to Susan Moller Okin's charge that ‘group rights are potentially, and in many cases actually, antifeminist’ (see her, in Joshua Cohen et al. (eds), Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, Kymlicka rightly refers to this distinction and questions Okin's antagonistic strategy of opposing feminism and multiculturalism, since these movements both are challenging the traditional liberal assumption that equality requires identical treatment
-
The pedagogical dialectic takes place against the background of certain non-negotiable norms that are given with the liberal democratic state, such as the equality between male and female. As I said, internal restrictions cannot be tolerated. It seems to me that the basic conceptual distinction between external protections and internal restrictions is one of the great achievements of Kymlicka's theory. In his reply to Susan Moller Okin's charge that ‘group rights are potentially, and in many cases actually, antifeminist’ (see her ‘Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women?’, in Joshua Cohen et al. (eds) Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women? [Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1999], pp. 7–24 [12]), Kymlicka rightly refers to this distinction and questions Okin's antagonistic strategy of opposing feminism and multiculturalism, since these movements both are challenging the traditional liberal assumption that equality requires identical treatment
-
(1999)
Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women?
, pp. 7-24
-
-
-
93
-
-
0039129703
-
-
However, Kymlicka does admit that the distinction itself needs to be further refined. For an excellent account of such an attempt, see, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
However, Kymlicka does admit that the distinction itself needs to be further refined. For an excellent account of such an attempt, see Ayelet Shachar, Multicultural Jurisdictions: Cultural Differences and Women's Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001).
-
(2001)
Multicultural Jurisdictions: Cultural Differences and Women's Rights
-
-
Shachar, A.1
-
94
-
-
84997906557
-
Voorschoolse en buitenschoolse opvoeding
-
Pels, ‘Voorschoolse en buitenschoolse opvoeding’, pp. 607–8;
-
-
-
Pels1
-
95
-
-
78650098203
-
Minderheden en schoolsucces
-
in C. H. M. Geuijen (ed.), Utrecht: Lemma
-
cf. Karen Phalet, ‘Minderheden en schoolsucces’, in C. H. M. Geuijen (ed.) Multiculturalisme (Utrecht: Lemma, 1998), pp. 97–114 (p. 113).
-
(1998)
Multiculturalisme
, pp. 97-114
-
-
Phalet, K.1
-
97
-
-
0004351763
-
-
However, as I said earlier, she often confuses intrinsic value of a language or culture ‘as such’ with the intrinsic value of a language or culture for the members of the minority group in question. Incidentally, I do agree with the parallel she draws between language and culture in these debates about intrinsic vs instrumental value:, 256, 264, 271
-
However, as I said earlier, she often confuses intrinsic value of a language or culture ‘as such’ with the intrinsic value of a language or culture for the members of the minority group in question. Incidentally, I do agree with the parallel she draws between language and culture in these debates about intrinsic vs instrumental value: Réaume, ‘Official-Language Rights’, p. 246, 256, 264, 271.
-
Official-Language Rights
, pp. 246
-
-
Réaume1
-
101
-
-
0004323817
-
-
Two recent publications are indicative of this new trend
-
Two recent publications are indicative of this new trend: Barry, Culture and Equality;
-
Culture and Equality
-
-
Barry1
|