메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 21, Issue 1, 2007, Pages 32-40

Death and transplantation: Let's try to get things methodologically straight

Author keywords

Death; Definition; Explantability window; Methodology; Transplantation

Indexed keywords

ARTICLE; BIOETHICS; BRAIN; DEATH; HEART; HUMAN; METHODOLOGY; ORGAN TRANSPLANTATION; PROBLEM IDENTIFICATION; TRANSPLANTATION;

EID: 33845667022     PISSN: 02699702     EISSN: 14678519     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-8519.2007.00521.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (10)

References (46)
  • 1
    • 33845611183 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Notice that I differentiate in a classical way 'ontology' from 'metaphysics'. The former concerns what a given theory speaks about. The latter has to do with our commitment on the status of 'what a given theory speaks about' is.
  • 2
    • 33845618677 scopus 로고
    • The Beginning of Full Moral Status
    • F.K. Beller & R.F. Weir, eds. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Press
    • R.M. Veatch. 1994. The Beginning of Full Moral Status. In The Beginning of Human Life. F.K. Beller & R.F. Weir, eds. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Press: 22-24.
    • (1994) The Beginning of Human Life , pp. 22-24
    • Veatch, R.M.1
  • 3
    • 0034841151 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Recommendations for Nonheart-beating Organ Donation
    • Cf. Ethics Committee, American College of Critical Care Medicine, Society of Critical Care Medicine
    • Cf. Ethics Committee, American College of Critical Care Medicine, Society of Critical Care Medicine. Recommendations For Nonheart-beating Organ Donation. Crit Care Med 2002; 29: 1826-1831. Here there is a relevant question upon which we cannot dwell: the difference between spontaneous recovering and artificial recovering.
    • (2002) Crit Care Med , vol.29 , pp. 1826-1831
  • 4
    • 0033217249 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • When is Dead?
    • S.J. Youngner et al. When is Dead? Hastings Cent Rep 1999; 29: 14-21. It should be noted that the authors point out that their data are no so good as it could appear and therefore that they have to be considered as 'the weakest possible evidence for a recommendation'.
    • (1999) Hastings Cent Rep , vol.29 , pp. 14-21
    • Youngner, S.J.1
  • 5
    • 0027537132 scopus 로고
    • Restoration of Spontaneous Circulation after Cessation of Cardiopulmonary Resuscitation
    • Cf.
    • Cf. a) P. Mertens et al. Restoration of Spontaneous Circulation After Cessation of Cardiopulmonary Resuscitation. Lancet. 1993; 341: 841.
    • (1993) Lancet , vol.341 , pp. 841
    • Mertens, P.1
  • 6
    • 0027931713 scopus 로고
    • Prolonged Asystolic Hypercalemic Cardiac Arrest with No Neurologic Sequelae
    • b) G. Quick et al. Prolonged Asystolic Hypercalemic Cardiac Arrest With No Neurologic Sequelae. Ann Emerg Med 1994; 24: 305-311.
    • (1994) Ann Emerg Med , vol.24 , pp. 305-311
    • Quick, G.1
  • 7
    • 0032443886 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unexpected Return of Spontaneous Circulation after Cessation of Resuscitation (Lazarus Phenomenon)
    • c) W.H. Maleck et al. Unexpected Return of Spontaneous Circulation After Cessation of Resuscitation (Lazarus Phenomenon). Resuscitation 1998; 39: 125-128.
    • (1998) Resuscitation , vol.39 , pp. 125-128
    • Maleck, W.H.1
  • 8
    • 0007816978 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Lazarus Phenomenon Revisited
    • d) J.G. Bray. The Lazarus Phenomenon Revisited. Anesthesiology 1999; 78: 991.
    • (1999) Anesthesiology , vol.78 , pp. 991
    • Bray, J.G.1
  • 9
    • 0037173121 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Death Following Spontaneous Recovery from Cardiopulmonary Arrest in a Hospital Mortuary: 'Lazarus Phenomenon' in a Case of Alleged Medical Negligence
    • e) H. Maeda et al. Death Following Spontaneous Recovery From Cardiopulmonary Arrest in a Hospital Mortuary: 'Lazarus Phenomenon' in a Case of Alleged Medical Negligence. Forensic Sci Int 2002; 127: 82-87. Note that W.H. Maleck et al. quote more than twenty cases reported between 1982 and 1998. They also emphasise how the phenomenon is underestimated due to the possible medical-legal consequences.
    • (2002) Forensic Sci Int , vol.127 , pp. 82-87
    • Maeda, H.1
  • 10
    • 0037306127 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Problematic Role of 'Irreversibility' in the Definition of Death
    • With reference to the difficulties concerning the notion of 'irreversibility', cf. D. Hershenov. The Problematic Role of 'Irreversibility' in the Definition of Death. Bioethics 2003; 17: 89-100.
    • (2003) Bioethics , vol.17 , pp. 89-100
    • Hershenov, D.1
  • 11
    • 0000473553 scopus 로고
    • Ad hoc Committee of the Harvard Medical School to Examine the Definition of Brain Death
    • Cf.
    • Cf. Ad hoc Committee of The Harvard Medical School to Examine the Definition of Brain Death. JAMA 1968; 205: 85-88.
    • (1968) JAMA , vol.205 , pp. 85-88
  • 12
    • 0019539808 scopus 로고
    • On the Definition and Criterion of Death
    • J.L. Bernat et al. On the Definition and Criterion of Death. Ann Intern Med 1981; 94: 390-391.
    • (1981) Ann Intern Med , vol.94 , pp. 390-391
    • Bernat, J.L.1
  • 13
    • 33845663252 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Actually, they also discussed the heart approach characterised by the criterion of the permanent loss of cardiopulmonary functioning and the tests related to such a loss. Nevertheless, they criticised this approach and supported the brain one.
  • 14
    • 0003649562 scopus 로고
    • Washington D.C. U.S. Government Printing Office
    • 'The Uniform Determination of Death Act' proposed by the 'President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioural Research' in their: 1981. Defining Death: A Report on the Medical, Legal, and Ethical Issues in the Determination of Death. Washington D.C. U.S. Government Printing Office: 73. Let us recall the following passage: 'On this view, the heart and lungs are not important as basic prerequisites to continue life but rather because the irreversible cessation of their functions shows that the brain had ceased functioning. [. . .]. The "primary organ" view would be satisfied with a statute that contained only a single standard - the irreversible cessation of all functions of the entire brain. Nevertheless, as a practical matter, the view is also compatible with a statute establishing irreversible cessation of respiration and circulation as an alternative standard, since it is inherent in this view that the loss of spontaneous breathing and heartbeat are surrogates for the loss of brain function.'
    • (1981) Defining Death: A Report on the Medical, Legal, and Ethical Issues in the Determination of Death , pp. 73
  • 15
    • 33845600896 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Actually Bernat et al. (op. cit. note 8) proposed a justification: 'What we call tests have sometimes themselves been called "criteria", but it is important to distinguish these second-level criteria from the first-level criteria. While the first-level criteria determining the death of an organism must be understood by the layman, the second-level criteria or test determining permanent loss of functioning of the whole brain need not to be understood by anyone except qualified clinicians' (p. 392). From the methodological point of view, this distinction appears to be extremely weak. Moreover, from a sociological point of view it appears also a little bit unfair. It should be noted that the authors seem to have some difficulties in supporting this distinction; they themselves write that 'test' has to be understood as 'criterion', even if a second-level one.
  • 16
    • 0026833539 scopus 로고
    • How Much of the Brain Must Die in Brain Death?
    • For example, Bernat himself, in a subsequent paper (J.L Bernat. How Much of the Brain Must Die in Brain Death? J Clin Ethics 1992; 3: 21-26), acknowledged that some brain functions can be retained in brain death, and that 'the designation "whole brain" death is an approximation'. Therefore he suggested identifying brain death with the destruction of a theoretically determinable critical neuronal population. Yet, he could not specify how much of the brain must die.
    • (1992) J Clin Ethics , vol.3 , pp. 21-26
    • Bernat, J.L.1
  • 17
    • 0344106872 scopus 로고
    • London: Allen and Unwin
    • B. Russell. 1910. Philosophical Essays. London: Allen and Unwin. By the way, this is the idea underlying 1931 A. Tarski's theory of truth. This proposal contained a definition of truth but not a criterion of truth. That is, Tarski's theory allows us to know the meaning of the locution 'truth', but not when a statement is true.
    • (1910) Philosophical Essays
    • Russell, B.1
  • 18
    • 0004237431 scopus 로고
    • cf. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • With reference to the differences between definition of truth and criterion of truth, also in relation to A. Tarski, cf. S. Haack. 1978. Philosophies of Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • (1978) Philosophies of Logic
    • Tarski, A.1    Haack, S.2
  • 19
    • 33845607292 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Of course, by 'tests' I mean 'empirical tests', that is, the tests which are relevant for our biomedical context.
  • 20
    • 33845629062 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Note that we are using the terms 'truth', 'falsity' and the derived ones in a very loose way, that is, without philosophical accuracy. Nevertheless, such accuracy is not required here.
  • 21
    • 0030959447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Change of Heart and a Change of Mind? Technology and the Redefinition of Death in 1968
    • For example
    • For example, a) M. Giacomini. A Change of Heart and a Change of Mind? Technology and the Redefinition of Death in 1968. Soc Sci Med 1997; 44: 1465-1482.
    • (1997) Soc Sci Med , vol.44 , pp. 1465-1482
    • Giacomini, M.1
  • 22
    • 0027620181 scopus 로고
    • The Dead Donor Rule: Should we Stretch tt, Bend it or Abandon it?
    • b) R.M. Arnold et al. The Dead Donor Rule: Should we Stretch tt, Bend it or Abandon it? Kennedy Inst Ethics J 1993; 3: 263-278.
    • (1993) Kennedy Inst Ethics J , vol.3 , pp. 263-278
    • Arnold, R.M.1
  • 24
    • 0031061254 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Recovery from 'Brain Death': A Neurologist's Apologia
    • b) D.A. Shewmon. Recovery from 'Brain Death': A Neurologist's Apologia. Linacre Q 1997; 64: 30-96.
    • (1997) Linacre Q , vol.64 , pp. 30-96
    • Shewmon, D.A.1
  • 25
    • 0031702524 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Chronic 'Brain Death'. Meta-Analysis and Conceptual Consequences
    • Cf.
    • Cf. a) D.A. Shewmon. Chronic 'Brain Death'. Meta-Analysis and Conceptual Consequences. Neurology 1998; 51: 1538-1545.
    • (1998) Neurology , vol.51 , pp. 1538-1545
    • Shewmon, D.A.1
  • 27
    • 0035183576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Brain and Somatic Integration: Insights into the Standard Biological Rationale for Equating 'Brain Death' with Death
    • Cf.
    • Cf. D.A. Shewmon. The Brain and Somatic Integration: Insights into the Standard Biological Rationale for Equating 'Brain Death' with Death. J Med Philos 2001; 26: 457-478.
    • (2001) J Med Philos , vol.26 , pp. 457-478
    • Shewmon, D.A.1
  • 28
    • 0026452449 scopus 로고
    • Rethinking Brain Death
    • Cf.
    • Cf. a) R.D. Truog et al. Rethinking Brain Death. Crit Care Med 1992; 20: 1705-1713.
    • (1992) Crit Care Med , vol.20 , pp. 1705-1713
    • Truog, R.D.1
  • 29
    • 0027635952 scopus 로고
    • The Impending Collapse of the Whole-Brain Death Definition of Death
    • b) R.M. Veatch. The Impending Collapse of the Whole-Brain Death Definition of Death. Hastings Cent Rep 1993; 23: 18-24.
    • (1993) Hastings Cent Rep , vol.23 , pp. 18-24
    • Veatch, R.M.1
  • 30
    • 0030639398 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Is it Time to Abandon Brain Death?
    • c) R.D. Truog. Is it Time to Abandon Brain Death? Hastings Cent Rep 1997; 21: 29-37.
    • (1997) Hastings Cent Rep , vol.21 , pp. 29-37
    • Truog, R.D.1
  • 31
    • 33845618131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • D. Graff, T. Williamson (eds.). Ashgate: Aldershot
    • With reference to the problem of vagueness, cf. D. Graff, T. Williamson (eds.). 2001. Vagueness. Ashgate: Aldershot;
    • (2001) Vagueness
  • 33
    • 33845602257 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • R. Keefe. 2000. Theory of Vagueness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press;
    • (2000) Theory of Vagueness
    • Keefe, R.1
  • 34
    • 14544287908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Varieties of Vagueness
    • T. Merricks. Varieties of Vagueness. Philos Phenomenol Res 2001; LXII: 145-157;
    • (2001) Philos Phenomenol Res , vol.62 , pp. 145-157
    • Merricks, T.1
  • 36
    • 33845653232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What Makes it a Heap?
    • T. Williamson. What Makes it a Heap? Erkenntnis 1996; 44: 327-339;
    • (1996) Erkenntnis , vol.44 , pp. 327-339
    • Williamson, T.1
  • 37
  • 38
    • 33845619134 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • A definition can be implicit or explicit. The definiens of a term is given 'implicitly' when the statement in which it occurs belongs to a set of statements where there are other terms capable of implicitly specifying its meaning. It is used in some formal axiomatisations, and this is not our case.
  • 39
    • 33845611182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Differently from a linguistic definition, by means of which we modify the language by enlarging it with a new term, in the metalinguistic definition, we do not modify a given language and we settle on a particular locution. For example, when we say '. . . 'man' is an animal belonging to the species Homo sapiens' we do not enlarge the language containing the terms 'animal' and 'Homo sapiens' and we settle, by resorting to a metalanguage, on the fact that the locution 'animal belonging to the species Homo sapiens' has to be termed 'man'. By choosing this latter view, I am implicitly affirming that the biomedical language has already the right terms to permit us to speak about that particular state of human being that we want to identify with a certain term.
  • 40
    • 33845604692 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It is worth noting that we could introduce a definition per genus et differentiam without committing ourselves in giving an essentialistic value to the definiens.
  • 41
    • 33845628183 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Also the ostensive definition is denotative. Of course we must reject such a possibility. For we could simply indicate a dead body and say: 'Death is the state of this body'. Unfortunately in doing so we should have decided in advance when a body is a dead one.
  • 42
    • 33845633968 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Ontogenesis of Human Identity
    • Biology, Philosophy, and Life. A. O'Hear ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Someone could object that I am using the term 'human being' when before I said it is vague. Actually, by taking into account the pragmatic taste of my pars construens, this is not a serious objection. However, I assume, without any bad consequence for my analysis, that a human being is any individual belonging to the species Homo sapiens. For a more detailed discussion, cf. G. Boniolo. The Ontogenesis of Human Identity. In Biology, Philosophy, and Life. A. O'Hear ed. Supplement to Philosophy 2005; 56: 49-82. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    • (2005) Philosophy , vol.56 , Issue.SUPPL. , pp. 49-82
    • Boniolo, G.1
  • 46
    • 33845638405 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • n considering the tests which, in that particular technological situation, allow us to fix, and therefore define, the neurological explantability window. The problem, as seen, is to fix the first extreme of the explantability window. From what discussed in § 2, I believe that it should concern a devastating and irreversible cerebral lesion (as in the brain dead donors protocols), or a resuscitation period sufficiently long (in case of uncontrolled non-beating-heart donors), or an acceptable refusal of resuscitation (in case of controlled non-beating-heart donors).


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.