메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 34, Issue 4, 2006, Pages 313-351

The benefits of cooperation

(1)  Heath, Joseph a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 33748938739     PISSN: 00483915     EISSN: 10884963     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1088-4963.2006.00073.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (72)

References (90)
  • 1
    • 0004274311 scopus 로고
    • One can see this idea most clearly in the work of (Oxford: Clarendon), or Andrew Schotter, The Economic Theory of Social Institutions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980)
    • One can see this idea most clearly in the work of David Gauthier, Morals by Agreement (Oxford: Clarendon, 1986), or Andrew Schotter, The Economic Theory of Social Institutions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980).
    • (1986) Morals By Agreement
    • Gauthier, D.1
  • 2
    • 33748934290 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The dominant opposition to this view stems from those who consider "conflict"to be a more important determinant of the structure of social institutions than the "consensus"that Pareto-efficiency supposedly creates. As we shall see, the version of the "consensus"approach used here predicts much higher levels of social conflict than the more traditional versions, and thus goes a long way toward undermining the force of the "conflict"objection.
  • 3
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2d ed. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press) When he does go on to discuss more concrete institutional proposals, his analysis suffers from the catallactic bias diagnosed below (especially his proposal for an "exchange branch"of the state to handle efficiency issues, pp. 249-50)
    • John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 2d ed. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999), p. 4. When he does go on to discuss more concrete institutional proposals, his analysis suffers from the catallactic bias diagnosed below (especially his proposal for an "exchange branch"of the state to handle efficiency issues, pp. 249-50).
    • (1999) A Theory of Justice , pp. 4
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 4
    • 0004272517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (New York: Simon & Schuster) James Coleman, who introduced the concept, writes, "Social capital is defined by its function. It is not a single entity but a variety of different entities, with two elements in common: they all consist of some aspect of social structures, and they facilitate certain actions of actors-whether persons or corporate actors-within the structure. Like other forms of capital, social capital is productive, making possible the achievements of certain ends that in its absence would not be possible"("Social Capital in the Creation of Human Capital,"American Journal of Sociology 94 supp. [1988]: S95-S120, at S98)
    • Robert Putnam, Bowling Alone (New York: Simon & Schuster, 2000), pp. 19-26. James Coleman, who introduced the concept, writes, "Social capital is defined by its function. It is not a single entity but a variety of different entities, with two elements in common: They all consist of some aspect of social structures, and they facilitate certain actions of actors-whether persons or corporate actors-within the structure. Like other forms of capital, social capital is productive, making possible the achievements of certain ends that in its absence would not be possible"("Social Capital in the Creation of Human Capital,"American Journal of Sociology 94 supp. [1988]: S95-S120, at S98).
    • (2000) Bowling Alone , pp. 19-26
    • Putnam, R.1
  • 5
    • 0004272517 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See and also Francis Fukuyama, Trust (London: Penguin, 1995), p. 27
    • See Putnam, Bowling Alone, p. 21, and also Francis Fukuyama, Trust (London: Penguin, 1995), p. 27.
    • Bowling Alone , pp. 21
    • Putnam, R.1
  • 6
    • 0004224103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an example of an analysis based upon a list of goods, rather than mechanisms, see (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press) When he does specify mechanisms (p. 25), he presents only one: gains from trade, along with two abstract categories-gains from cooperation, and gains from coordination
    • For an example of an analysis based upon a list of goods, rather than mechanisms, see Jack Knight, Institutions and Social Conflict (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), pp. 22-24. When he does specify mechanisms (p. 25), he presents only one: Gains from trade, along with two abstract categories-gains from cooperation, and gains from coordination.
    • (1992) Institutions and Social Conflict , pp. 22-24
    • Knight, J.1
  • 7
    • 0003701935 scopus 로고
    • The term "catallaxy"was introduced by as a way of referring to a system of order established through exchange. See his (Chicago: University of Chicago Press). The highest expression of this catallactic perspective can be found in the work of James M. Buchanan, who essentially redefines efficiency in such a way that only gains from trade count as efficiency-promoting. See "Rights, Efficiency, and Exchange: The Irrelevance of Transaction Costs,"in his Liberty, Market and State (Brighton: Harvester, 1986), pp. 92-107
    • The term "catallaxy"was introduced by Friedrich A. Hayek as a way of referring to a system of order established through exchange. See his Law, Legislation and Liberty, Vol. 2 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1977). The highest expression of this catallactic perspective can be found in the work of James M. Buchanan, who essentially redefines efficiency in such a way that only gains from trade count as efficiency-promoting. See "Rights, Efficiency, and Exchange: The Irrelevance of Transaction Costs,"in his Liberty, Market and State (Brighton: Harvester, 1986), pp. 92-107.
    • (1977) Law, Legislation and Liberty, Vol. 2
    • Hayek, F.A.1
  • 8
    • 33748922671 scopus 로고
    • 4th ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press) Also known as the "first theorem"or "first fundamental theorem"of welfare economics, e.g., see Gareth D. Myles, Public Economics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), pp. 37-40
    • Mark Blaug, Economic Theory in Retrospect, 4th ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), pp. 585-97. Also known as the "first theorem"or "first fundamental theorem"of welfare economics, e.g., see Gareth D. Myles, Public Economics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), pp. 37-40.
    • (1985) Economic Theory in Retrospect , pp. 585-597
    • Blaug, M.1
  • 9
    • 33748943391 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The extent to which these limitations prevent one from drawing normative conclusions is often not fully appreciated, however. In particular, there is a widespread failure to recognize the significance of the "second best theorem."See
  • 11
    • 33748939655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Of course, the exclusion of economies of scale is explicit. However, the significance of the assumptions made about information, uncertainty, and preferences is less obvious. Sophisticated economists have long understood these limitations (e.g., see
  • 12
    • 0002379704 scopus 로고
    • "Limited Knowledge and Economic Analysis"
    • Kenneth Arrow, "Limited Knowledge and Economic Analysis,"American Economic Review 64 [1974]: 1-10
    • (1974) American Economic Review , vol.64 , pp. 1-10
    • Arrow, K.1
  • 13
    • 5444221773 scopus 로고
    • "No Need for Morality: The Case of the Competitive Market"
    • David Gauthier's "No Need for Morality: The Case of the Competitive Market,"Philosophic Exchange 3 (1982): 41-54.
    • (1982) Philosophic Exchange , vol.3 , pp. 41-54
    • Gauthier's, D.1
  • 14
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Perhaps the most important example of this in contemporary political philosophy is For a more explicit version, see Nicholas Barr, The Economics of the Welfare State, 3d ed. (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998), chap. 4. Adam Przeworski, States and Markets (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), describes this as the "markets whenever possible, the state whenever necessary"view, p. 40
    • Perhaps the most important example of this in contemporary political philosophy is Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 242-51. For a more explicit version, see Nicholas Barr, The Economics of the Welfare State, 3d ed. (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998), chap. 4. Adam Przeworski, States and Markets (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), describes this as the "markets whenever possible, the state whenever necessary"view, p. 40.
    • A Theory of Justice , pp. 242-251
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 15
    • 33748942897 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This broader way of speaking of externalities, not as an effect on a third party, but merely as an effect upon another, is one that I find very helpful. It is used in this way by Gauthier, in Morals by Agreement, p. 96 and passim.
  • 16
    • 0001742381 scopus 로고
    • "The Evolution of Altruistic Behavior"
    • W. D. Hamilton, "The Evolution of Altruistic Behavior,"The American Naturalist 97 (1963): 354-56
    • (1963) The American Naturalist , vol.97 , pp. 354-356
    • Hamilton, W.D.1
  • 17
    • 0000841452 scopus 로고
    • "Group Selection and Kin Selection"
    • J. Maynard Smith, "Group Selection and Kin Selection,"Nature 201 (1964): 1145-47.
    • (1964) Nature , vol.201 , pp. 1145-1147
    • Smith, J.M.1
  • 18
    • 0000139691 scopus 로고
    • "Moral Hazard and Observability"
    • Bengt Holmstrom, "Moral Hazard and Observability,"Bell Journal of Economics 10 (1979): 74-91.
    • (1979) Bell Journal of Economics , vol.10 , pp. 74-91
    • Holmstrom, B.1
  • 19
    • 0003411497 scopus 로고
    • 3 vols., ed. E. G. Wakefield (London: C. Knight) 1:26. John Stuart Mill saw fit to reproduce lengthy segments of this discussion in his Principles of Political Economy (Amherst: Prometheus, 2004), p. 134
    • Adam Smith, Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, 3 vols., ed. E. G. Wakefield (London: C. Knight, 1835-36), 1:26. John Stuart Mill saw fit to reproduce lengthy segments of this discussion in his Principles of Political Economy (Amherst: Prometheus, 2004), p. 134.
    • (1835) Inquiry Into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations
    • Smith, A.1
  • 20
    • 0004252421 scopus 로고
    • With regard to the former, see (Indianapolis: Liberty Books), and on the latter, see Gauthier, Morals by Agreement, p. 84
    • With regard to the former, see Friedrich A. Hayek, The Counter-Revolution of Science (Indianapolis: Liberty Books, 1979), and on the latter, see Gauthier, Morals by Agreement, p. 84.
    • (1979) The Counter-Revolution of Science
    • Hayek, F.A.1
  • 23
    • 0010113702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The standard deviation is 0.4 tons. See (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press)
    • The standard deviation is 0.4 tons. See David A. Moss, When All Else Fails (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2002), pp. 28-31.
    • (2002) When All Else Fails , pp. 28-31
    • Moss, D.A.1
  • 24
    • 8644278856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The law of large numbers is also at the root of the "wisdom of crowds"phenomenon: the fact that two heads are generally better than one, even in the absence of complementarities. This connection is stated most explicitly in the Condorcet Jury Theorem, but see also (New York: Anchor)
    • The law of large numbers is also at the root of the "wisdom of crowds"phenomenon: The fact that two heads are generally better than one, even in the absence of complementarities. This connection is stated most explicitly in the Condorcet Jury Theorem, but see also James Surowiecki, The Wisdom of Crowds (New York: Anchor, 2005).
    • (2005) The Wisdom of Crowds
    • Surowiecki, J.1
  • 25
    • 0004023255 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an example of a discussion that unhelpfully blurs the distinction between the two mechanisms, see or Frank H. Easterbrook and Daniel R. Fischel, The Economic Structure of Corporate Law (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1991), p. 53
    • For an example of a discussion that unhelpfully blurs the distinction between the two mechanisms, see Barr, The Economics of the Welfare State, pp. 111-12, or Frank H. Easterbrook and Daniel R. Fischel, The Economic Structure of Corporate Law (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1991), p. 53.
    • The Economics of the Welfare State , pp. 111-112
    • Barr1
  • 26
    • 84967211836 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Risk and Dirt"
    • in ed. Richard V. Ericson and Aaron Doyle (Toronto: University of Toronto Press), refers to the former as the "Lloyd's of London"model of insurance. The mutual society model, on the other hand, which involves symmetry in the relation between all policyholders, is the arrangement that predominates in the standard categories of health, life, home, and automobile insurance
    • Ian Hacking, "Risk and Dirt,"in Risk and Morality, ed. Richard V. Ericson and Aaron Doyle (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2003), refers to the former as the "Lloyd's of London"model of insurance. The mutual society model, on the other hand, which involves symmetry in the relation between all policyholders, is the arrangement that predominates in the standard categories of health, life, home, and automobile insurance.
    • (2003) Risk and Morality
    • Hacking, I.1
  • 28
    • 0003934109 scopus 로고
    • See (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). See also Howard Rachlin, The Science of Self-Control (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000)
    • See George Ainslie, Picoeconomics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992). See also Howard Rachlin, The Science of Self-Control (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000).
    • (1992) Picoeconomics
    • Ainslie, G.1
  • 29
    • 0004245883 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • George Ainslie, Breakdown of Will (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), p. 33.
    • (2001) Breakdown of Will , pp. 33
    • Ainslie, G.1
  • 30
    • 0004192988 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jon Elster provides an extreme formulation of this thesis. Following Henry Sidgwick, he regards zero discounting as the only "rational"preference, and thus treats all time preference as a symptom of irrationality. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • Jon Elster provides an extreme formulation of this thesis. Following Henry Sidgwick, he regards zero discounting as the only "rational"preference, and thus treats all time preference as a symptom of irrationality. Jon Elster, Ulysses and the Sirens (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979), p. 66.
    • (1979) Ulysses and the Sirens , pp. 66
    • Elster, J.1
  • 31
    • 0004206723 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jon Elster, Ulysses Unbound (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), pp. 76-77
    • Rachlin, Science of Self-Control, p. 89. Jon Elster, Ulysses Unbound (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), pp. 76-77.
    • Science of Self-Control , pp. 89
    • Rachlin1
  • 33
    • 33748937933 scopus 로고
    • 2d. ed., ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon)
    • David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, 2d. ed., ed. P. H. Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon, 1978), p. 537.
    • (1978) A Treatise of Human Nature , pp. 537
    • Hume, D.1
  • 34
    • 0004088235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Incidentally, it is sometimes thought that Hume's argument relies merely upon our tendency to privilege our "short-term"over our "long-term"interests. Yet this alone is not enough to explain the phenomenon of self-binding (and thus the reasons we have for enlisting the assistance of others). A person who merely privileges his short-term over his long-term interests has no reason to take preemptive action to constrain his own future choices, since the lesser, nearer good will always appear superior to him. What Hume's argument relies upon is the preference reversal that occurs as the lesser good becomes nearer. The anticipation of such reversals is what motivates precommitment, and such reversals occur not merely through impatience, but rather through heightened impatience in the near term. It is only this specific sort of infirmity that is capable of becoming "a remedy to itself."
    • Hume, Treatise of Human Nature, p. 536. Incidentally, it is sometimes thought that Hume's argument relies merely upon our tendency to privilege our "short-term"over our "long-term"interests. Yet this alone is not enough to explain the phenomenon of self-binding (and thus the reasons we have for enlisting the assistance of others). A person who merely privileges his short-term over his long-term interests has no reason to take preemptive action to constrain his own future choices, since the lesser, nearer good will always appear superior to him. What Hume's argument relies upon is the preference reversal that occurs as the lesser good becomes nearer. The anticipation of such reversals is what motivates precommitment, and such reversals occur not merely through impatience, but rather through heightened impatience in the near term. It is only this specific sort of infirmity that is capable of becoming "a remedy to itself."
    • Treatise of Human Nature , pp. 536
    • Hume, D.1
  • 35
    • 33748931071 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Tho' we may be fully convinc'd, that the latter object excels the former, we are not able to regulate our actions by this judgment; but yield to the solicitations of our passions, which always plead in favour of whatever is near and contiguous"
    • writes
    • Hume writes, "Tho' we may be fully convinc'd, that the latter object excels the former, we are not able to regulate our actions by this judgment; but yield to the solicitations of our passions, which always plead in favour of whatever is near and contiguous,"Treatise of Human Nature, p. 535.
    • Treatise of Human Nature , pp. 535
    • Hume, D.1
  • 37
    • 0012766806 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press)
    • Lee Dugatkin, Cheating Monkeys and Citizen Bees (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999), pp. 17-20.
    • (1999) Cheating Monkeys and Citizen Bees , pp. 17-20
    • Dugatkin, L.1
  • 38
    • 0038787366 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press) and Robert Brandom, Making It Explicit (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1994), pp. 3-66. The role of cooperation in transmitting information is typically underemphasized in the so-called memetics literature, with the central role assigned to imitation. See, e.g., Daniel Dennett, Darwin's Dangerous Idea (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1995), pp. 342-69
    • See Joseph Heath, Communicative Action and Rational Choice (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2001), pp. 86-107, and Robert Brandom, Making It Explicit (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1994), pp. 3-66. The role of cooperation in transmitting information is typically underemphasized in the so-called memetics literature, with the central role assigned to imitation. See, e.g., Daniel Dennett, Darwin's Dangerous Idea (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1995), pp. 342-69.
    • (2001) Communicative Action and Rational Choice , pp. 86-107
    • Heath, J.1
  • 39
    • 0003651494 scopus 로고
    • trans. Thomas McCarthy (Boston: Beacon Press) Habermas himself is loath to accept the "contractualist"label, for reasons that are somewhat beside the point here. Reasons for including him in this camp can be found in
    • Jürgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action, trans. Thomas McCarthy (Boston: Beacon Press, 1986), pp. 77-92. Habermas himself is loath to accept the "contractualist"label, for reasons that are somewhat beside the point here. Reasons for including him in this camp can be found in
    • (1986) The Theory of Communicative Action , pp. 77-92
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 40
    • 84930561211 scopus 로고
    • "Reason and Agreement in Social Contract Views"
    • Samuel Freeman, "Reason and Agreement in Social Contract Views,"Philosophy & Public Affairs 19 (1990): 122-57.
    • (1990) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.19 , pp. 122-157
    • Freeman, S.1
  • 41
    • 3042744640 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Social Justice in the Age of Identity Politics: Redistribution, Recognition and Participation"
    • For an analysis of the "politics of recognition"in terms of status, see in (London: Verso)
    • For an analysis of the "politics of recognition"in terms of status, see Nancy Fraser, "Social Justice in the Age of Identity Politics: Redistribution, Recognition and Participation,"in Nancy Fraser and Axel Honneth, Redistribution or Recognition? (London: Verso, 2003).
    • (2003) Nancy Fraser and Axel Honneth, Redistribution or Recognition?
    • Fraser, N.1
  • 43
    • 84967417109 scopus 로고
    • See (New York: John Wiley & Sons)
    • See James G. March and Herbert A. Simon, Organizations (New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1958), pp. 59-70.
    • (1958) Organizations , pp. 59-70
    • March, J.G.1    Simon, H.A.2
  • 45
    • 0000589044 scopus 로고
    • "Production, Information Costs, and Economic Organization"
    • Armen A. Alcian and Harold Demsetz, "Production, Information Costs, and Economic Organization,"American Economic Review 63 (1972): 777-95
    • (1972) American Economic Review , vol.63 , pp. 777-795
    • Alcian, A.A.1    Demsetz, H.2
  • 46
    • 3142775111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See (Toronto: Penguin)
    • See Joseph Heath, The Efficient Society (Toronto: Penguin, 2001), pp. 151-59.
    • (2001) The Efficient Society , pp. 151-159
    • Heath, J.1
  • 47
    • 0141640433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The availability of free-rider strategies in this context is consistently downplayed, both by Humeans who emphasize the "conventional"nature of property arrangements, and by proponents of "spontaneous order,"who for ideological reasons want the market to be conceptually prior to any formal systems of constraint, such as the law. See
    • The availability of free-rider strategies in this context is consistently downplayed, both by Humeans who emphasize the "conventional"nature of property arrangements, and by proponents of "spontaneous order,"who for ideological reasons want the market to be conceptually prior to any formal systems of constraint, such as the law. See Schultz, Moral Conditions of Economic Efficiency, pp. 60-70.
    • Moral Conditions of Economic Efficiency , pp. 60-70
    • Schultz, W.J.1
  • 48
    • 0348148359 scopus 로고
    • (New York: Basic Books)
    • Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), p. 280.
    • (1974) State and Utopia , pp. 280
    • Anarchy, R.N.1
  • 49
    • 0003631618 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 3d ed. (Cambridge, Mass.: Blackwell)
    • Eric Rasmusen, Games and Information, 3d ed. (Cambridge, Mass.: Blackwell, 1989), pp. 165-69.
    • (1989) Games and Information , pp. 165-169
    • Rasmusen, E.1
  • 50
  • 51
    • 0004327857 scopus 로고
    • For example, see (Boston: Beacon Press)
    • For example, see Karl Polanyi, The Great Transformation (Boston: Beacon Press, 1957), p. 49.
    • (1957) The Great Transformation , pp. 49
    • Polanyi, K.1
  • 52
    • 0000922534 scopus 로고
    • "Risk, Foraging and Food Sharing among the Aché"
    • See in ed. Elizabeth Cashdan (Boulder: Westview Press)
    • See Hillard Kaplan, Kim Hill, and A. Magdalena Hurtado, "Risk, Foraging and Food Sharing among the Aché,"in Risk and Uncertainty in Tribal and Peasant Economies, ed. Elizabeth Cashdan (Boulder: Westview Press, 1990).
    • (1990) Risk and Uncertainty in Tribal and Peasant Economies
    • Kaplan, H.1    Hill, K.2    Hurtado, A.M.3
  • 53
    • 33748936586 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Risk, Foraging and Food Sharing among the Aché"
    • Kaplan, Hill, and Hurtado, "Risk, Foraging and Food Sharing among the Aché,"p. 129.
    • Kaplan, H.1    Hill, K.2    Hurtado, M.A.3
  • 57
    • 0004277776 scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press) For further discussion, see Gøsta Esping-Anderson, The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1990), pp. 88-92
    • Ian Hacking, The Taming of Chance (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), p. 48. For further discussion, see Gøsta Esping-Anderson, The Three Worlds of Welfare Capitalism (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1990), pp. 88-92.
    • (1990) The Taming of Chance , pp. 48
    • Hacking, I.1
  • 58
    • 33748948637 scopus 로고
    • The former observation was apparent to nineteenth-century commentators as well, e.g., see (London: Baldwin and Cradock) On the persistence of "level premium"societies into the twentieth century, see
    • The former observation was apparent to nineteenth-century commentators as well, e.g., see Charles Ansell, A Treatise on Friendly Societies (London: Baldwin and Cradock, 1835), p. 4. On the persistence of "level premium"societies into the twentieth century, see
    • (1835) A Treatise on Friendly Societies , pp. 4
    • Ansell, C.1
  • 59
    • 0030118258 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Risky Business? Nonactuarial Pricing Practices and the Financial Viability of Fraternal Sickness Insurers"
    • J.C.H. Emery, "Risky Business? Nonactuarial Pricing Practices and the Financial Viability of Fraternal Sickness Insurers,"Explorations in Economic History 33 (1996): 195-226.
    • (1996) Explorations in Economic History , vol.33 , pp. 195-226
    • Emery, J.C.H.1
  • 62
    • 0004015171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Elster notes certain disanalogies, however, since constitutions bind collectivities (i.e., legislatures) and individuals only indirectly
    • Elster, Ulysses Unbound, pp. 88-89. Elster notes certain disanalogies, however, since constitutions bind collectivities (i.e., legislatures) and individuals only indirectly.
    • Ulysses Unbound , pp. 88-89
    • Elster, J.1
  • 63
    • 3142775111 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Kenneth Galbraith's discussion, in The New Industrial State, pp. 85-97, pays due regard to the diversity of functions the modern corporation serves. For reasons of his own, however, Galbraith chooses to subordinate all of these various mechanisms of cooperative benefit under the general rubric of "planning."
    • Heath, The Efficient Society, pp. 160-61. John Kenneth Galbraith's discussion, in The New Industrial State, pp. 85-97, pays due regard to the diversity of functions the modern corporation serves. For reasons of his own, however, Galbraith chooses to subordinate all of these various mechanisms of cooperative benefit under the general rubric of "planning."
    • The Efficient Society , pp. 160-161
    • Heath, J.1
  • 65
    • 33748932776 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See see also Blaug, Economic Theory in Retrospect, pp. 592-95; Gareth D. Myles, Public Economics, chap. 2
    • See Barr, The Economics of the Welfare State, p. 78; see also Blaug, Economic Theory in Retrospect, pp. 592-95; Gareth D. Myles, Public Economics, chap. 2.
    • The Economics of the Welfare State , pp. 78
    • Barr1
  • 66
    • 0004084396 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge, Mass.: Houghton Mifflin)
    • John Kenneth Galbraith, American Capitalism (Cambridge, Mass.: Houghton Mifflin, 1952), p. 110.
    • (1952) American Capitalism , pp. 110
    • Galbraith, J.K.1
  • 67
    • 33748932599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This example of course draws its force from the elimination of a collective action problem that arises through negative externalities, whereas in this article I am only considering arrangements that resolve collective action problems involving the failure to produce positive externalities. However, it would be quite easy to vary the example to provide the correct illustration. The Jamestown bowling story, for example (in which no one is willing to work the fields, because the crops are divided up equally among all, regardless of work effort), would suffice. See
  • 68
    • 33947542912 scopus 로고
    • "Property in Land"
    • Robert C. Ellickson, "Property in Land,"Yale Law Journal 102 (1993): 1315-400.
    • (1993) Yale Law Journal , vol.102 , pp. 1315-1400
    • Ellickson, R.C.1
  • 69
    • 0003115488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Open Field, Common Pot: Harvest Variability and Risk Avoidance in Agricultural and Foraging Societies"
    • This fact has been noted by anthropologists (e.g., see in ed. Cashdan), but the impact of the observation has not been widely felt in normative economics and political philosophy. The "tragedy of the commons"argument for property rights is still typically presented as a straightforward efficiency gain
    • This fact has been noted by anthropologists (e.g., see Bruce Winterhalder, "Open Field, Common Pot: Harvest Variability and Risk Avoidance in Agricultural and Foraging Societies,"in Risk and Uncertainty in Tribal and Peasant Economies, ed. Cashdan, pp. 68-70), but the impact of the observation has not been widely felt in normative economics and political philosophy. The "tragedy of the commons"argument for property rights is still typically presented as a straightforward efficiency gain.
    • Risk and Uncertainty in Tribal and Peasant Economies , pp. 68-70
    • Winterhalder, B.1
  • 70
    • 33748941490 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Rasmusen, Games and Information, presents a simple model of an insurance arrangement in which "there is a trade-off between efficient effort and efficient risk allocation,"p. 187. The fact that this trade-off arises from a conflict between two different mechanisms of cooperative benefit is obscured, however, by the fact that Rasmusen analyzes insurance contracts as a trade between a risk-neutral insurance company ("perhaps because it is owned by diversified shareholders") and a risk-averse individual (p. 183). This treats the central mechanism as a gain from trade, obscuring the role played by the law of large numbers.
  • 72
    • 0038969032 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Golden Eggs and Hyperbolic Discounting"
    • David Laibson, "Golden Eggs and Hyperbolic Discounting,"Quarterly Journal of Economics 112 (1997): 443-77.
    • (1997) Quarterly Journal of Economics , vol.112 , pp. 443-477
    • Laibson, D.1
  • 73
    • 33748951636 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • World Bank (Washington, D.C.: World Bank), chap. 4
    • World Bank, Curbing the Epidemic (Washington, D.C.: World Bank, 2000), chap. 4.
    • (2000) Curbing the Epidemic
  • 74
    • 33748920418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am grateful to Patrick Turmel (personal communication) for this formulation of the distinction.
  • 75
    • 79953182438 scopus 로고
    • "Property Rights, Progress, and the Aircraft Patent Agreement"
    • George Bittlingmayer, "Property Rights, Progress, and the Aircraft Patent Agreement,"Journal of Law and Economics 31 (1988): 227-48.
    • (1988) Journal of Law and Economics , vol.31 , pp. 227-248
    • Bittlingmayer, G.1
  • 80
    • 0043081656 scopus 로고
    • For the former, see (New York: Basic Books) and Anthony Downs, An Economic Theory of Democracy (New York: Harper & Row, 1957); for the latter, see Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 240-50
    • For the former, see Gordon Tullock, Private Wants, Public Means (New York: Basic Books, 1970) and Anthony Downs, An Economic Theory of Democracy (New York: Harper & Row, 1957); for the latter, see Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 240-50.
    • (1970) Private Wants, Public Means
    • Tullock, G.1
  • 82
    • 33748947576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Myths and Misinformation about America's Retirement System"
    • in ed. Jeff Madrick (New York: The Century Foundation)
    • Teresa Ghilarducci, "Myths and Misinformation about America's Retirement System,"in Unconventional Wisdom: Alternative Perspectives on the New Economy, ed. Jeff Madrick (New York: The Century Foundation, 2000), pp. 69-92.
    • (2000) Unconventional Wisdom: Alternative Perspectives on the New Economy , pp. 69-92
    • Ghilarducci, T.1
  • 84
    • 0004223708 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press)
    • Ronald Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000), p. 73.
    • (2000) Sovereign Virtue , pp. 73
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 85
    • 84922009321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "A Reply"
    • On the latter, see in ed. Justine Burley (Oxford: Blackwell) Dworkin does state that risk aversion is the basis for the utility gain associated with insurance (Sovereign Virtue, p. 95), but he goes on to elaborate this point in a way that suggests otherwise. For example, he writes, "I buy insurance on my house because the marginal utility loss of an uncompensated fire is so much greater than the utility cost of the premium,"p. 97. It goes without saying that the loss of the house is worse than the payment of the premium, but that fails to explain why anyone buys insurance. People buy insurance because-or more to the point, to the extent that -the expected utility associated with the gamble between losing and not losing one's house is less than the loss of utility associated with paying the premium
    • On the latter, see Ronald Dworkin, "A Reply,"in Dworkin and His Critics, ed. Justine Burley (Oxford: Blackwell, 2004), p. 348. Dworkin does state that risk aversion is the basis for the utility gain associated with insurance (Sovereign Virtue, p. 95), but he goes on to elaborate this point in a way that suggests otherwise. For example, he writes, "I buy insurance on my house because the marginal utility loss of an uncompensated fire is so much greater than the utility cost of the premium,"p. 97. It goes without saying that the loss of the house is worse than the payment of the premium, but that fails to explain why anyone buys insurance. People buy insurance because-or more to the point, to the extent that -the expected utility associated with the gamble between losing and not losing one's house is less than the loss of utility associated with paying the premium.
    • (2004) Dworkin and His Critics , pp. 348
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 88
    • 33748944577 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See
  • 90
    • 0004224103 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This observation has been made before, in different ways (see)
    • This observation has been made before, in different ways (see Knight, Institutions and Social Conflict, pp. 34-37).
    • Institutions and Social Conflict , pp. 34-37
    • Knight, J.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.