-
1
-
-
84992915869
-
Equality of Welfare
-
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
See Ronald Dworkin, ‘Equality of Welfare’ and ‘Equality of Resources’, in Sovereign Virtue (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001).
-
(2001)
‘Equality of Resources’, in Sovereign Virtue
-
-
Ronald, D.1
-
2
-
-
0032647108
-
network externalities
-
Will Kymlicka's use of Dworkin's auction thought experiment to justify minority rights is based on a flawed interpretation, as it assumes the presence of uninternalized associated with language and cultural practices. See Will Kymlicka, Liberalism, Community and Culture (Oxford: Clarendon, 1989). Similarly, Elizabeth Anderson's recent reappraisal of the ‘point’ of egalitarianism takes Dworkin's interpretation of the auction at face value, which allows her then to accuse resource egalitarianism of harboring a ‘Poor Law’ mentality. See Elizabeth Anderson, ‘What is the Point of Equality?’ Ethics 109
-
For example, Will Kymlicka's use of Dworkin's auction thought experiment to justify minority rights is based on a flawed interpretation, as it assumes the presence of uninternalized ‘network externalities’ associated with language and cultural practices. See Will Kymlicka, Liberalism, Community and Culture (Oxford: Clarendon, 1989). Similarly, Elizabeth Anderson's recent reappraisal of the ‘point’ of egalitarianism takes Dworkin's interpretation of the auction at face value, which allows her then to accuse resource egalitarianism of harboring a ‘Poor Law’ mentality. See Elizabeth Anderson, ‘What is the Point of Equality?’ Ethics 109 (1999): 287-337.
-
(1999)
For example
, pp. 287-337
-
-
-
4
-
-
0002912233
-
Resource Allocation in the Public Sector
-
‘Equity, Envy and Efficiency’, Journal of Economic Theory 9 (1974): 63-91; William J. Baumol, Superfairness (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986); Serge-Christophe Kolm, Justice and Equity, trans. Harold F. See (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997).
-
The following is an incomplete list: Duncan Foley, ‘Resource Allocation in the Public Sector’, Yale Economic Essays 7 (1967): 45-98; Hal Varian, ‘Equity, Envy and Efficiency’, Journal of Economic Theory 9 (1974): 63-91; William J. Baumol, Superfairness (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1986); Serge-Christophe Kolm, Justice and Equity, trans. Harold F. See (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997).
-
(1967)
The following is an incomplete list: Duncan Foley, Yale Economic Essays 7
, pp. 45-98
-
-
Varian, H.1
-
5
-
-
84992801499
-
-
edited by Richard Tuck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
-
Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, edited by Richard Tuck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 87.
-
(1991)
Leviathan
, pp. 87
-
-
Thomas, H.1
-
7
-
-
84992795517
-
-
4th edn. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,).
-
See Mark Blaug, Economic Theory in Retrospect, 4th edn. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), Ch. 13.
-
(1985)
Economic Theory in Retrospect
, Issue.13
-
-
Mark, B.1
-
8
-
-
0001131558
-
A Difficulty in the Concept of Fairness
-
The example above is of a pure exchange economy, without production. Adding production into the mix complicates things, because it introduces a variety of problems pertaining to the distribution of leisure. See Elisha A. Pazner and David Schmeidler, Review of Economic Studies 41
-
There is one noteworthy restriction to this claim. The example above is of a pure exchange economy, without production. Adding production into the mix complicates things, because it introduces a variety of problems pertaining to the distribution of leisure. See Elisha A. Pazner and David Schmeidler, ‘A Difficulty in the Concept of Fairness’, Review of Economic Studies 41 (1974): 441-3.
-
(1974)
There is one noteworthy restriction to this claim
, pp. 441-443
-
-
-
9
-
-
84992858667
-
-
(SV: 72) claims, erroneously, that the envy-freeness standard alone can be used to rank distributions as more or less equal.
-
Note that Dworkin (SV: 72) claims, erroneously, that the envy-freeness standard alone can be used to rank distributions as more or less equal.
-
Note that Dworkin
-
-
-
12
-
-
84992815390
-
Ethics and Markets
-
See, for example, Philosophy and Public Affairs 14
-
This has been noted elsewhere. See, for example, John G. Bennett, ‘Ethics and Markets’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 14 (1985): 197.
-
(1985)
This has been noted elsewhere
, pp. 197
-
-
Bennett, J.G.1
-
13
-
-
84992858675
-
The Place of Liberty
-
See in Sovereign Virtue (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,), Again, he fails to notice that the auction does no such thing. Aggregate opportunity costs are already equalized by the initial allocation (since the bundles are identical, aggregate opportunity costs must be the same). The auction simply preserves the equality of these aggregate opportunity costs, while selecting a more efficient allocation.
-
Elsewhere, Dworkin describes the function of the auction as equalizing aggregate opportunity costs. See Ronald Dworkin, ‘The Place of Liberty’, in Sovereign Virtue (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001), p. 149. Again, he fails to notice that the auction does no such thing. Aggregate opportunity costs are already equalized by the initial allocation (since the bundles are identical, aggregate opportunity costs must be the same). The auction simply preserves the equality of these aggregate opportunity costs, while selecting a more efficient allocation.
-
(2001)
Elsewhere, Dworkin describes the function of the auction as equalizing aggregate opportunity costs
, pp. 149
-
-
Dworkin, R.1
-
15
-
-
84992858678
-
The Place of Liberty
-
See Dworkin, ‘The Place of Liberty’, Sovereign Virtue, pp. 150–1.
-
Sovereign Virtue
, pp. 150-151
-
-
-
16
-
-
84992899706
-
no aid to those it labels irresponsible, and humiliating aid to those it labels innately inferior. It gives us the cramped vision of the Poor Laws, where unfortunates breathe words of supplication and submit to the humiliating moral judgments of the state
-
See Anderson, ‘What is the Point of Equality?’
-
Anderson suggests that the market offers ‘no aid to those it labels irresponsible, and humiliating aid to those it labels innately inferior. It gives us the cramped vision of the Poor Laws, where unfortunates breathe words of supplication and submit to the humiliating moral judgments of the state’. See Anderson, ‘What is the Point of Equality?’, p. 308.
-
Anderson suggests that the market offers
, pp. 308
-
-
-
17
-
-
84992875728
-
Why Efficiency?
-
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,), Elsewhere in the same volume, he says that the price system is needed to achieve equality because ‘it fixes the true cost to the community of meeting [each individual's] own preferences for goods and activities’. See Ronald Dworkin, ‘Liberalism’, in A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985), p. 194.
-
Ronald Dworkin, ‘Why Efficiency?’ in A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985), p. 270. Elsewhere in the same volume, he says that the price system is needed to achieve equality because ‘it fixes the true cost to the community of meeting [each individual's] own preferences for goods and activities’. See Ronald Dworkin, ‘Liberalism’, in A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985), p. 194.
-
(1985)
A Matter of Principle
, pp. 270
-
-
Ronald, D.1
-
19
-
-
84992915879
-
-
The difference principle favors perfect equality (according to some index of primary goods), unless it is possible to make Paretoefficiency gains that increase inequality. When that occurs, it recommends choosing the Pareto improvement that maximizes the allocation of the worst-off. See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Belknap: Harvard University Press,), Rawls must assume that the question of trade-offs between the two principles will arise in the normative component of his theory in part because he does not adopt the idealizing framework of welfare economics that structures Dworkin's discussion.
-
This is sometimes overlooked. The difference principle favors perfect equality (according to some index of primary goods), unless it is possible to make Paretoefficiency gains that increase inequality. When that occurs, it recommends choosing the Pareto improvement that maximizes the allocation of the worst-off. See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Belknap: Harvard University Press, 1971), p. 76. Rawls must assume that the question of trade-offs between the two principles will arise in the normative component of his theory in part because he does not adopt the idealizing framework of welfare economics that structures Dworkin's discussion.
-
(1971)
This is sometimes overlooked
, pp. 76
-
-
-
21
-
-
84992822391
-
-
2nd edn. (Bombay: Asian Publishing House,); Oskar Lange and Fred M. Taylor, On the Economic Theory of Socialism (New York: McGraw Hill, 1964); Abba P. Lerner, The Economics of Control (New York: Macmillan, 1944).
-
Oskar Lange, Essays on Economic Planning, 2nd edn. (Bombay: Asian Publishing House, 1967); Oskar Lange and Fred M. Taylor, On the Economic Theory of Socialism (New York: McGraw Hill, 1964); Abba P. Lerner, The Economics of Control (New York: Macmillan, 1944).
-
(1967)
Essays on Economic Planning
-
-
Oskar, L.1
-
24
-
-
84877687576
-
-
Dworkin's remarks at the top of, Sovereign Virtue.
-
See, for example, Dworkin's remarks at the top of p. 70, Sovereign Virtue.
-
for example
, pp. 70
-
-
-
25
-
-
0004282258
-
-
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)
-
See John Roemer, Theories of Distributive Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996), p. 256.
-
(1996)
Theories of Distributive Justice
, pp. 256
-
-
John, R.1
|