-
1
-
-
79956602215
-
-
Stuttgart:, esp 270-275
-
In many respects, contemporary philosophers move objections to Kant's moral psychology which are similar to the ones formulated by his first critics, Schiller and Hegel; see F. Schiller, Uber Anmut und Wurde, Schillers Werke (Stuttgart: 1867) 238-96, esp. 270-5;
-
(1867)
Uber Anmut und Wurde, Schillers Werke
, pp. 238-296
-
-
Schiller, F.1
-
2
-
-
0004260323
-
-
Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
F. Hegel, Philosophy of Right (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1942), 90;
-
(1942)
Philosophy of Right
, pp. 90
-
-
Hegel, F.1
-
3
-
-
0004070203
-
-
386, Oxford: Oxford University Press
-
F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1979), 260-2, 386.
-
(1979)
Phenomenology of Spirit
, pp. 260-262
-
-
Hegel, F.1
-
4
-
-
0004123369
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
The literature on the subject is extensive, but see e.g. H. Allison, Kant's Theory of Freedom (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1990), 180-98;
-
(1990)
Kant's Theory of Freedom
, pp. 180-198
-
-
Allison, H.1
-
5
-
-
79956493556
-
The Hegelian Critique of Kantian Morality
-
B. den Ouden and M. Moen, eds, New York: Peter Lang
-
K. Ameriks, 'The Hegelian Critique of Kantian Morality,' in New Essays on Kant, B. den Ouden and M. Moen, eds. (New York: Peter Lang 1987) 155-78;
-
(1987)
New Essays on Kant
, pp. 155-178
-
-
Ameriks, K.1
-
6
-
-
80053253755
-
Der Begriff der sittlichen Einsight und Kants Lehre vom Faktum der Vernunft
-
G. Prauss, ed, Koln: Kiepernheuer & Witsch
-
D. Henrich, 'Der Begriff der sittlichen Einsight und Kants Lehre vom Faktum der Vernunft,' in Kant: Zur Deutung seiner Theorie von Erkennen und Handeln, G. Prauss, ed. (Koln: Kiepernheuer & Witsch 1973) 77-115;
-
(1973)
Kant: Zur Deutung seiner Theorie von Erkennen und Handeln
, pp. 77-115
-
-
Henrich, D.1
-
7
-
-
84948850596
-
Kant on Moral Feeling
-
A. McBeath, 'Kant on Moral Feeling,' Kant Studien 64 (1973) 283-314;
-
(1973)
Kant Studien
, vol.64
, pp. 283-314
-
-
McBeath, A.1
-
9
-
-
0040133993
-
On the Relation of Pure Reason to Content: A Reply to Hegel's Critique of Formalism in Kant's Ethics
-
S. Sedgwick, 'On the Relation of Pure Reason to Content: A Reply to Hegel's Critique of Formalism in Kant's Ethics,' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 49 (1988) 59-80;
-
(1988)
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
, vol.49
, pp. 59-80
-
-
Sedgwick, S.1
-
10
-
-
0009993153
-
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
A. Wood, Kant's Ethical Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1999), 40-49.
-
(1999)
Kant's Ethical Thought
, pp. 40-49
-
-
Wood, A.1
-
11
-
-
0001343580
-
Moral Perception and Particularity
-
See, e.g., L. Blum, 'Moral Perception and Particularity,' Ethics 101 (1991) 701-25;
-
(1991)
Ethics
, vol.101
, pp. 701-725
-
-
Blum, L.1
-
13
-
-
79956626870
-
Persons and Others
-
J. Genova, ed, Edmonton: Academic Printing and Publishing
-
L. Code, 'Persons and Others,' in Power, Gender, and Values, J. Genova, ed. (Edmonton: Academic Printing and Publishing 1987) 143-61;
-
(1987)
Power, Gender, and Values
, pp. 143-161
-
-
Code, L.1
-
14
-
-
34248347606
-
On Respecting Human Beings as Persons
-
C. Cranor, 'On Respecting Human Beings as Persons,' Journal of Value Inquiry 17 (1983) 103-17;
-
(1983)
Journal of Value Inquiry
, vol.17
, pp. 103-117
-
-
Cranor, C.1
-
15
-
-
84954636040
-
Respect and Care: Toward Moral Integration
-
R. Dillon, 'Respect and Care: Toward Moral Integration,' Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (1999) 105-32;
-
(1999)
Canadian Journal of Philosophy
, vol.22
, pp. 105-132
-
-
Dillon, R.1
-
16
-
-
33748676820
-
Did Kant Respect Persons?
-
M. Newman, 'Did Kant Respect Persons?' Res Publica 6 (2000) 285-99;
-
(2000)
Res Publica
, vol.6
, pp. 285-299
-
-
Newman, M.1
-
17
-
-
80053663986
-
Kant, Respect, and Particular Persons
-
at 452-456
-
R. Noggle, 'Kant, Respect, and Particular Persons,' Canadian Journal of Philosophy 29 (1999) 449-78, at 452-6;
-
(1999)
Canadian Journal of Philosophy
, vol.29
, pp. 449-478
-
-
Noggle, R.1
-
18
-
-
84925911311
-
On Treating Persons as Persons
-
E. Spelman, 'On Treating Persons as Persons,' Ethics 88 (1977) 150-61;
-
(1977)
Ethics
, vol.88
, pp. 150-161
-
-
Spelman, E.1
-
19
-
-
0002211902
-
Persons, Character, and Morality
-
reprinted in, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
-
B. Williams, 'Persons, Character, and Morality,' reprinted in Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1981) 1-19.
-
(1981)
Moral Luck
, pp. 1-19
-
-
Williams, B.1
-
20
-
-
0004051088
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
Philosophers more sympathetic to Kantian ethics also show to be sensitive to the kinds of concern raised by Murdoch, and attempt to revise Kant's conception of respect accordingly, see e.g. B. Herman, The Practice of Moral Judgment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 1993);
-
(1993)
The Practice of Moral Judgment
-
-
Herman, B.1
-
24
-
-
0002217636
-
On the Value of Acting for the Motive of Duty
-
at 176ff
-
Compare B. Herman, 'On the Value of Acting for the Motive of Duty,' Philosophical Review 90 (1981) 359-82, at 176ff.;
-
(1981)
Philosophical Review
, vol.90
, pp. 359-382
-
-
Herman, B.1
-
26
-
-
34248392409
-
The Possibility of Categorical Imperative
-
P. Guyer, ed. (New York: Rowman and Littlefield) and 234-9
-
See Guyer, 'The Possibility of Categorical Imperative,' in Kant's Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: Critical Essays, P. Guyer, ed. (New York: Rowman and Littlefield 1998) 215-18 and 234-9. I would like to thank an anonymous referee of this journal for pressing me on this point. I come back to this issue in section V.
-
(1998)
Kant's Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals: Critical Essays
, pp. 215-218
-
-
Guyer1
-
27
-
-
79954281807
-
Vision, Choice, and Existentialism
-
This objection is extended to various forms of contemporary ethics, which Murdoch claims to be Kantian in spirit, see R. Moran, 'Vision, Choice, and Existentialism,' Notizie di Politeia 66 (2002) 88-101.
-
(2002)
Notizie di Politeia
, vol.66
, pp. 88-101
-
-
Moran, R.1
-
28
-
-
0003629344
-
-
Chicago: University of Chicago Press
-
To this extent, respect is the subjective part of the fact of reason. The fact of reason has subjective and objective aspects; see L. Beck, A Commentary on Kant's Critique of Practical Reason (Chicago: University of Chicago Press 1960), 166-75;
-
(1960)
A Commentary on Kant's Critique of Practical Reason
, pp. 166-175
-
-
Beck, L.1
-
30
-
-
61249229955
-
-
Objectively, it establishes the validity of the moral law and thus it proves the autonomy of the will, see Kant, Practical Reason, 55-7.
-
Practical Reason
, pp. 55-57
-
-
Kant1
-
33
-
-
84955870998
-
Kant's Theory of Moral Sensibility
-
295
-
A. Reath, 'Kant's Theory of Moral Sensibility,' Kant Studien 80 (1980) 284-302, at 295;
-
(1980)
Kant Studien
, vol.80
, pp. 284-302
-
-
Reath, A.1
-
34
-
-
33644683482
-
Autonomy, Necessity, and Love
-
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press at 141
-
Frankfurt puts it differently: 'The moral law can influence a person's conduct, Kant believes, only through the mediation of respect' (H. Frankfurt, 'Autonomy, Necessity, and Love,' in The Importance of What We Care About (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1988) 129-41, at 141. This suggests that whether the agent eventually acts for the sake of morality depends on whether respect is sufficiently strong to overcome the competing inclinations. For reasons I provide in this paragraph, Frankfurt's suggestion is misleading.
-
(1988)
The Importance of What We Care About
, pp. 129-141
-
-
Frankfurt, H.1
-
35
-
-
61049203350
-
Love and Respect in the Doctrine of Virtue
-
37-38
-
Rather, I am simply pointing out that Kant is interested in drawing a distinction between external and internal correctness of actions, which is a distinction in the kind of legislation and motivation, see e.g. M. Baron, 'Love and Respect in the Doctrine of Virtue,' Southern Journal of Philosophy 36 (1997) 29-44, at 37-8.
-
(1997)
Southern Journal of Philosophy
, vol.36
, pp. 29-44
-
-
Baron, M.1
-
36
-
-
79956515090
-
Mind and Change in Mind
-
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
-
Not all alterations of mind qualify as a change in mind. To be a change in mind, an alteration must be neither imposed on the agent nor prompted by the circumstances, see A. Baier, 'Mind and Change in Mind,' in Postures of the Mind (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press 1985) 51-73.
-
(1985)
Postures of the Mind
, pp. 51-73
-
-
Baier, A.1
-
37
-
-
79956489016
-
-
P. Guyer, ed.
-
There is scholarly disagreement as to whether dutiful actions always fulfill duties of respect. For example, Baron suggests that lack of respect as a moral feeling not only deprives actions of moral worth, but also makes them wrong; see Baron, and compare A. Wood, 'Humanity as End in Itself,' in P. Guyer, ed., 165-88. I do not address this issue here because it is not the kind of worry that Murdoch raises. My point is simply that the distinction between legality and morality is sufficient to respond to Murdoch's objection about the intelligibility of internal change in Kant's ethics.
-
Humanity as End in Itself
, pp. 165-188
-
-
Baron1
Wood, A.2
-
38
-
-
84875681578
-
-
The claim about the opacity of maxims is pervasive, see Kant, Groundwork, 407;
-
Groundwork
, pp. 407
-
-
Kant1
-
40
-
-
0346232839
-
Kant's Virtues
-
R. Crisp, ed, Oxford: Clarendon
-
I take Kant's ethics to be practical and built into a first-person conception of oneself, and thus my strategy is to emphasize that the retrospective perspective of the evaluator is beside the point; on the merits of this strategy, see O. O'Neill, 'Kant's Virtues,' in How Should One Live? R. Crisp, ed. (Oxford: Clarendon 1996);
-
(1996)
How Should One Live
-
-
O'Neill, O.1
-
41
-
-
34250231350
-
Why Moral Agents Became Ghosts
-
Doubts about Kant's conception of character have been fostered also by the metaphysical interpretation of the distinction between intelligible and phenomenal character; see A. McIntyre, 'Why Moral Agents Became Ghosts,' Synthese (1982) 295-312, and Williams. I put aside discussion of this issue, and endorse Allison's replies based on the practical interpretation of the distinction, see Allison.
-
(1982)
Synthese
, pp. 295-312
-
-
McIntyre, A.1
-
43
-
-
0003965241
-
Eichmann in Jerusalem
-
London: Penguin
-
I leave aside the objection that reverence for the law describes or encourages the despicable attitude of following a rule. On this issue, see H. Arendt, Eichmann in Jerusalem: Report on the Banality of Evil (London: Penguin 1963), 134-8;
-
(1963)
Report on the Banality of Evil
, pp. 134-138
-
-
Arendt, H.1
-
44
-
-
0001798458
-
Love as a Moral Emotion
-
at 346
-
As Velleman explains in commenting this passage, the object of respect is the capacity for legislation (Geseztgebung) not a given law (Gesezt); see D. Velleman, 'Love as a Moral Emotion,' Ethics 109 (1999) 338-74, at 346. But this objection also mistakes the object and the nature of the attitude that reverence for the law expresses. That is, reverence for the law must also be distinguished from the ground that motivates the agent to act according to a duty. Reverence for the law is the attitude that is distinctive and peculiar to the agent that performs his duty for its own sake, that is, the agents that understands and values autonomy and acts autonomously. Since in this sense autonomy is a qualification of the will, one cannot act out of reverence for the law when she merely follows a given rule.
-
(1999)
Ethics
, vol.109
, pp. 338-374
-
-
Velleman, D.1
-
45
-
-
0040816098
-
Iris Murdoch and the Domain of the Moral
-
In fact, Murdoch is more aware of this similarity than contemporary readers are; compare L. Blum, 'Iris Murdoch and the Domain of the Moral,' Philosophical Studies 50 (1986) 343-67
-
(1986)
Philosophical Studies
, vol.50
, pp. 343-367
-
-
Blum, L.1
-
47
-
-
84971127799
-
Kant's Virtue Ethics
-
See R. Louden, 'Kant's Virtue Ethics,' Philosophy 61 (1986) 473-89;
-
(1986)
Philosophy
, vol.61
, pp. 473-489
-
-
Louden, R.1
-
48
-
-
84948044987
-
Kant After Virtue
-
O. O'Neill, 'Kant After Virtue,' Inquiry 26 (1983) 387-405;
-
(1983)
Inquiry
, vol.26
, pp. 387-405
-
-
O'Neill, O.1
-
50
-
-
84964932929
-
Final Form of Kant's Practical Philosophy
-
A. Wood, 'Final Form of Kant's Practical Philosophy,' Southern Journal of Philosophy 36 (1997) 1-21.
-
(1997)
Southern Journal of Philosophy
, vol.36
, pp. 1-21
-
-
Wood, A.1
-
51
-
-
0004113926
-
-
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
-
For example, Anderson writes: 'We can see that Kantian ethics is hampered by the fact that it recognizes only two ways of valuing things, use and respect. These two modes of evaluations are not enough to account for the richness of our experience of value and our practices' (Elizabeth Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics [Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press 1993], 9).
-
(1993)
Value in Ethics and Economics
, vol.9
-
-
Anderson, E.1
-
52
-
-
83455240567
-
Two Kinds of Respect
-
S. Darwall, 'Two Kinds of Respect,' Ethics 88 (1977) 36-49. I am solely interested in the standard sense, according to which respect is based on the dignity of the persons, and therefore everybody deserves it (independently of personal merit, role or office).
-
(1977)
Ethics
, vol.88
, pp. 36-49
-
-
Darwall, S.1
-
54
-
-
0006288137
-
Losing Your Concepts
-
On the implications of Murdoch's diagnosis of this loss of moral concepts, see C. Diamond, 'Losing Your Concepts,' Ethics 98 (1988) 255-77.
-
(1988)
Ethics
, vol.98
, pp. 255-277
-
-
Diamond, C.1
|