-
2
-
-
27744558688
-
'Tort Law in the Aristotelian Tradition'
-
D. Owen (ed.), (Oxford: Clarendon Press)
-
'Tort Law in the Aristotelian Tradition' in D. Owen (ed.), Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995) 131-58.
-
(1995)
Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law
, pp. 131-158
-
-
-
4
-
-
0003666422
-
-
(New Haven and London: Yale University Press): the book built on a series of articles published in the 1960s
-
G. Calabresi, The Costs of Accidents (New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1970): The book built on a series of articles published in the 1960s.
-
(1970)
The Costs of Accidents
-
-
Calabresi, G.1
-
5
-
-
0003774434
-
-
See generally (Boston and Toronto: Little Brown and Company) first published in and now in its 5th edition
-
See generally R. A. Posner, Economic Analysis of Law (Boston and Toronto: Little Brown and Company) first published in 1972 and now in its 5th edition.
-
(1972)
Economic Analysis of Law
-
-
Posner, R.A.1
-
6
-
-
27844538267
-
'The Uses of History in Law and Economics'
-
659
-
R. Harris, 'The Uses of History in Law and Economics' (2003) 4 Theoretical Inquiries in Law 659, 660.
-
(2003)
Theoretical Inquiries in Law
, vol.4
, pp. 660
-
-
Harris, R.1
-
7
-
-
27744516597
-
'"Economists' Reasons" for Common Law Decisions - A Preliminary Inquiry'
-
Economic analysis of aspects of private law attracted attention in no less than six contributions to the first two issues of this Journal:
-
Economic analysis of aspects of private law attracted attention in no less than six contributions to the first two issues of this Journal: R. S. Summers and L. B. Kelley, '"Economists' Reasons" for Common Law Decisions - A Preliminary Inquiry' (1981) 1 OJLS 213
-
(1981)
OJLS
, vol.1
, pp. 213
-
-
Summers, R.S.1
Kelley, L.B.2
-
8
-
-
17444422593
-
'Social Sciences and Law - The Relevance of Economic Theories'
-
C. K. Rowley, 'Social Sciences and Law - The Relevance of Economic Theories' (1981) 1 OJLS 391
-
(1981)
OJLS
, vol.1
, pp. 391
-
-
Rowley, C.K.1
-
9
-
-
0001828988
-
'Economic Loss in Tort'
-
W. Bishop, 'Economic Loss in Tort' (1982) 2 OJLS 1
-
(1982)
OJLS
, vol.2
, pp. 1
-
-
Bishop, W.1
-
10
-
-
27744472027
-
'Justice and Justifications for Tort Liability'
-
P. Cane, 'Justice and Justifications for Tort Liability' (1982) 2 OJLS 30
-
(1982)
OJLS
, vol.2
, pp. 30
-
-
Cane, P.1
-
11
-
-
0010960512
-
'The Economic Loss Problem: A Comment on Bishop'
-
M. J. Rizzo, 'The Economic Loss Problem: A Comment on Bishop' (1982) 2 OJLS 207
-
(1982)
OJLS
, vol.2
, pp. 207
-
-
Rizzo, M.J.1
-
12
-
-
27744512259
-
'Economic Loss: A Reply to Rizzo'
-
W. Bishop, 'Economic Loss: A Reply to Rizzo' (1982) 2 OJLS 207.
-
(1982)
OJLS
, vol.2
, pp. 207
-
-
Bishop, W.1
-
13
-
-
0041931911
-
'Corrective Justice in Recent Theories of Tort Law'
-
R. A. Posner, 'Corrective Justice in Recent Theories of Tort Law' (1981) 10 JLS 187.
-
(1981)
JLS
, vol.10
, pp. 187
-
-
Posner, R.A.1
-
14
-
-
27744467245
-
'Can Strict Liability be Generalized?
-
See also (reviewing R. A. Epstein, A Theory of Strict Liability (San Francisco: Cato Institute, 1980))
-
See also I. Englard, 'Can Strict Liability be Generalized? (1982) 2 OJLS 245 (reviewing R. A. Epstein, A Theory of Strict Liability (San Francisco: Cato Institute, 1980)).
-
(1982)
OJLS
, vol.2
, pp. 245
-
-
Englard, I.1
-
15
-
-
3042635832
-
'Rawls in Tort Theory: Themes and Counter-Themes'
-
Benjamin Zipursky thinks that John Rawls', first published in 1971, was instrumental in the development of justice-based accounts of tort law: 1923. But Rawls said almost nothing about private law, and the first major contribution to private law theory inspired by Rawls' path-breaking work - Arthur Ripstein's, Equality, Responsibility and the Law - was not published until 1999
-
Benjamin Zipursky thinks that John Rawls', A Theory of Justice, first published in 1971, was instrumental in the development of justice-based accounts of tort law: B. Zipursky, 'Rawls in Tort Theory: Themes and Counter-Themes' (2004) 72 Fordham LR 1923, 1930-1. But Rawls said almost nothing about private law, and the first major contribution to private law theory inspired by Rawls' path-breaking work - Arthur Ripstein's, Equality, Responsibility and the Law - was not published until 1999.
-
(2004)
Fordham LR
, vol.72
, pp. 1930-1931
-
-
Zipursky, B.1
-
16
-
-
3042541248
-
'The Division of Responsibility and the Law of Tort'
-
See also
-
See also A. Ripstein, 'The Division of Responsibility and the Law of Tort' (2004) 72 Fordham LR 1811
-
(2004)
Fordham LR
, vol.72
, pp. 1811
-
-
Ripstein, A.1
-
17
-
-
3042545284
-
'Ripstein, Rawls and Responsibility'
-
S. Perry, 'Ripstein, Rawls and Responsibility' (2004) 72 Fordham LR 1845.
-
(2004)
Fordham LR
, vol.72
, pp. 1845
-
-
Perry, S.R.1
-
18
-
-
27744546939
-
'The Distributive Turn: Mischief, Misfortune and Tort Law'
-
Anyway, some justice theorists expressly reject Rawlsian 'political' understandings of tort law in favour of some 'pre-political' account: B. Bix (ed.), (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
-
Anyway, some justice theorists expressly reject Rawlsian 'political' understandings of tort law in favour of some 'pre-political' account: S. R. Perry, 'The Distributive Turn: Mischief, Misfortune and Tort Law' in B. Bix (ed.), Analyzing Law: New Essays in Legal Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998).
-
(1998)
Analyzing Law: New Essays in Legal Theory
-
-
Perry, S.R.1
-
19
-
-
0001609162
-
'Property Rules, Liability Rules and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral
-
e.g
-
e.g. G. Calabresi and A. D. Melamed, 'Property Rules, Liability Rules and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral (1972) 85 Harvard LR 1089
-
(1972)
Harvard LR
, vol.85
, pp. 1089
-
-
Calabresi, G.1
Melamed, A.D.2
-
20
-
-
84935412452
-
'The Pointlessness of Pareto: Carrying Coase Further'
-
G. Calabresi, 'The Pointlessness of Pareto: Carrying Coase Further' (1991) 100 Yale LJ 1211.
-
(1991)
Yale LJ
, vol.100
, pp. 1211
-
-
Calabresi, G.1
-
23
-
-
0003793797
-
-
Calabresi has also been identified as founder of the 'New Haven school' of law and economics, whereas Posner is associated with the 'Chicago (or 'neo-classical') school': (Princeton: Princeton University Press) ch 2
-
Calabresi has also been identified as founder of the 'New Haven school' of law and economics, whereas Posner is associated with the 'Chicago (or 'neo-classical') school': N. Mercuro and S. G. Medema, Economics and the Law: From Posner to Postmodernism (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1997), ch 2.
-
(1997)
Economics and the Law: From Posner to Postmodernism
-
-
Mercuro, N.1
Medema, S.G.2
-
25
-
-
27744544034
-
-
(ed.), (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press)
-
C. A. Sunstein (ed.), Behavioural Law and Economics (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000);
-
(2000)
Behavioural Law and Economics
-
-
Sunstein, C.A.1
-
26
-
-
27744490012
-
'Cognitive Science'
-
J. G. Backhaus (ed.), (Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar) ch 21
-
J. N. Drobak, 'Cognitive Science' in J. G. Backhaus (ed.), The Elgar Companion to Law and Economics (Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar, 1999), ch 21.
-
(1999)
The Elgar Companion to Law and Economics
-
-
Drobak, J.N.1
-
27
-
-
78149446644
-
-
e.g. (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press)
-
e.g. E. A. Posner, Law and Social Norms (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 2000);
-
(2000)
Law and Social Norms
-
-
Posner, E.A.1
-
28
-
-
27744440203
-
'Law Versus Morality as Regulators of Conduct'
-
S. Shavell, 'Law Versus Morality as Regulators of Conduct' (2002) 4 American L and Econ R 227.
-
(2002)
American L and Econ R
, vol.4
, pp. 227
-
-
Shavell, S.1
-
30
-
-
84919618795
-
-
See, e.g. (eds), (Oxford, Oxford University Press)
-
See, e.g. C. Parker, C. Scott, N. Lacey and J. Braithwaite (eds), Regulating Law (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2004).
-
(2004)
Regulating Law
-
-
Parker, C.1
Scott, C.2
Lacey, N.3
Braithwaite, J.4
-
31
-
-
27744607282
-
'Contract as a Mechanism of Distributive Justice'
-
It has attracted much attention in the pages of this Journal in recent years: notably
-
It has attracted much attention in the pages of this Journal in recent years: Notably W. N. R. Lucy, 'Contract as a Mechanism of Distributive Justice' (1989) 9 OJLS 132
-
(1989)
OJLS
, vol.9
, pp. 132
-
-
Lucy, W.N.R.1
-
32
-
-
27744491926
-
'Rethinking the Common Law'
-
(reviewing J. Coleman, Risks and Wrongs (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992))
-
W. N. R. Lucy, 'Rethinking the Common Law' (1994) 14 OJLS 539 (reviewing J. Coleman, Risks and Wrongs (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992));
-
(1994)
OJLS
, vol.14
, pp. 539
-
-
Lucy, W.N.R.1
-
33
-
-
0346788352
-
'Corrective Justice and Correlativity in Private Law'
-
(reviewing E. J. Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law (Cambridge, Mass and London: Harvard University Press, 1995))
-
P. Cane, 'Corrective Justice and Correlativity in Private Law' (1996) 16 OJLS 471 (reviewing E. J. Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law (Cambridge, Mass and London: Harvard University Press, 1995));
-
(1996)
OJLS
, vol.16
, pp. 471
-
-
Cane, P.1
-
34
-
-
27744510487
-
'The Common Law According to Hegel'
-
(reviewing A. Brudner, The Unity of the Common Law (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995))
-
W. N. R. Lucy, 'The Common Law According to Hegel' (1997) 17 OJLS 685 (reviewing A. Brudner, The Unity of the Common Law (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995));
-
(1997)
OJLS
, vol.17
, pp. 685
-
-
Lucy, W.N.R.1
-
35
-
-
27744515202
-
'Instituting Property'
-
(reviewing J. W. Harris, Property and Justice (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1996))
-
A. Pottage, 'Instituting Property' (1998) 9 OJLS 331 (reviewing J. W. Harris, Property and Justice (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1996));
-
(1998)
OJLS
, vol.9
, pp. 331
-
-
Pottage, A.1
-
36
-
-
27744543212
-
'Convention and Justification: Professor Harris on Property and Justice'
-
A. Reeve, 'Convention and Justification: Professor Harris on Property and Justice' (1999) 19 OJLS 324
-
(1999)
OJLS
, vol.19
, pp. 324
-
-
Reeve, A.1
-
37
-
-
27744608292
-
'The Evolution of Tort'
-
(reviewing P. S. Atiyah, The Damages Lottery (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 1997)
-
S. Deakin, 'The Evolution of Tort' (1999) 19 OJLS 537 (reviewing P. S. Atiyah, The Damages Lottery (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 1997),
-
(1999)
OJLS
, vol.19
, pp. 537
-
-
Deakin, S.1
-
40
-
-
0345582473
-
'Mens Rea in Tort Law'
-
P. Cane, 'Mens Rea in Tort Law' (2000) 20 OJLS 533
-
(2000)
OJLS
, vol.20
, pp. 533
-
-
Cane, P.1
-
41
-
-
27744581621
-
'Ripstein on Equality, Responsibility and the Law'
-
(reviewing A. Ripstein, Equality, Responsibility and the Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999))
-
J. Perkins, 'Ripstein on Equality, Responsibility and the Law' (2000) 20 OJLS 673 (reviewing A. Ripstein, Equality, Responsibility and the Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999));
-
(2000)
OJLS
, vol.20
, pp. 673
-
-
Perkins, J.1
-
42
-
-
27744529894
-
'Private Law and Private Narratives'
-
(reviewing T. Honoré, Responsibility and Fault (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 1999))
-
A. Ripstein, 'Private Law and Private Narratives' (2000) 20 OJLS 683 (reviewing T. Honoré, Responsibility and Fault (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 1999));
-
(2000)
OJLS
, vol.20
, pp. 683
-
-
Ripstein, A.1
-
43
-
-
27744600673
-
'On the Autonomy of Corrective Justice'
-
D. Klimchuk, 'On the Autonomy of Corrective Justice' (2003) 23 OJLS 49.
-
(2003)
OJLS
, vol.23
, pp. 49
-
-
Klimchuk, D.1
-
44
-
-
0004106103
-
-
It is important in this context to distinguish between 'instrumental' and 'functional' approaches to law. Some - but certainly not all - justice theorists reject not only the idea that law is best understood as an instrument of 'social policy' but also the idea that it has any 'function' other than - in Weinrib's famous phrase - 'to be private law': (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press)
-
It is important in this context to distinguish between 'instrumental' and 'functional' approaches to law. Some - but certainly not all - justice theorists reject not only the idea that law is best understood as an instrument of 'social policy' but also the idea that it has any 'function' other than - in Weinrib's famous phrase - 'to be private law': The Idea of Private Law (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1995), 5.
-
(1995)
The Idea of Private Law
, pp. 5
-
-
-
45
-
-
0038751705
-
-
For Weinrib, law is best understood 'formalistically'. Jules Coleman, by contrast, calls himself a pragmatist, and distinguishes between 'social' and 'constitutive' functions of law: (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
-
For Weinrib, law is best understood 'formalistically'. Jules Coleman, by contrast, calls himself a pragmatist, and distinguishes between 'social' and 'constitutive' functions of law: The Practice of Principle (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), 14.
-
(2001)
The Practice of Principle
, pp. 14
-
-
-
46
-
-
0042744330
-
-
See also ch 7. Weinrib rejects attempts by Coleman (e.g. Markets, Morals and the Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998)) and Stephen Perry (e.g. S. R. Perry, 'The Moral Foundations of Tort Law' 77 Iowa LR 449) to explain tort law in 'moral' terms
-
See also Cane, The Anatomy of Tort Law, ch 7. Weinrib rejects attempts by Coleman (e.g. Markets, Morals and the Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998)) and Stephen Perry (e.g. S. R. Perry, 'The Moral Foundations of Tort Law' (1992) 77 Iowa LR 449) to explain tort law in 'moral' terms.
-
(1992)
The Anatomy of Tort Law
-
-
Cane, P.1
-
47
-
-
27744482395
-
'Mixed Theories of Tort Law'
-
1801
-
G. T. Schwartz, 'Mixed Theories of Tort Law' (1997) 75 Texas LR 1801, 1810.
-
(1997)
Texas LR
, vol.75
, pp. 1810
-
-
Schwartz, G.T.1
-
48
-
-
84936159761
-
'Jurisprudence and Gender'
-
See, e.g
-
See, e.g. R. West, 'Jurisprudence and Gender' (1988) 55 U of Chicago LR 1.
-
(1988)
U of Chicago LR
, vol.55
, pp. 1
-
-
West, R.1
-
50
-
-
0001201964
-
'A Critique of Torts'
-
R. Abel, 'A Critique of Torts' (1990) 37 UCLALR 785
-
(1990)
UCLALR
, vol.37
, pp. 785
-
-
Abel, R.1
-
52
-
-
84948675880
-
'Critical Legal Theory'
-
For an accessible brief account of critical legal theory more generally see M. V. Tushnet, M. P. Golding and W. A. Edmundson (eds), (Malden, MA: Blackwell)
-
For an accessible brief account of critical legal theory more generally see M. V. Tushnet, 'Critical Legal Theory' in M. P. Golding and W. A. Edmundson (eds), The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2005).
-
(2005)
The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory
-
-
-
53
-
-
1142297078
-
'Tort Law and the Feminist Critique of Reason'
-
e.g. A. Bottomley (ed.), (London: Cavendish Publishing)
-
e.g. J. Conaghan, 'Tort Law and the Feminist Critique of Reason' in A. Bottomley (ed.), Feminist Perspectives on the Foundational Subjects of Law (London: Cavendish Publishing, 1996) 47-85
-
(1996)
Feminist Perspectives on the Foundational Subjects of Law
, pp. 47-85
-
-
Conaghan, J.1
-
54
-
-
0345982280
-
'The Architecture of Bias: Deep Structures in Tort Law'
-
M. Chamallas, 'The Architecture of Bias: Deep Structures in Tort Law' (1998) 146 U Pa LR 463
-
(1998)
U Pa LR
, vol.146
, pp. 463
-
-
Chamallas, M.1
-
56
-
-
27744524278
-
'Feminist Approaches to Tort Law Revisited - A Reply to Professor Schwartz
-
(Online Edition), Article 7
-
A. Jacob, 'Feminist Approaches to Tort Law Revisited - A Reply to Professor Schwartz (2001) 2 Theoretical Inquiries in Law (Online Edition), No 1, Article 7
-
(2001)
Theoretical Inquiries in Law
, vol.2
, Issue.1
-
-
Jacob, A.1
-
57
-
-
0347080098
-
'Restatement (Third) of Torts: General Principles and the Prescription of Masculine Order'
-
A. Bernstein, 'Restatement (Third) of Torts: General Principles and the Prescription of Masculine Order' (2001) 54 Vanderbilt LR 1367
-
(2001)
Vanderbilt LR
, vol.54
, pp. 1367
-
-
Bernstein, A.1
-
58
-
-
22644446359
-
'Tort Law and Feminist Critique'
-
It is striking that all of the most prominent economic and justice theorists of private law writing in English are male
-
J. Conaghan, 'Tort Law and Feminist Critique' (2003) 56 Current Legal Problems 175. It is striking that all of the most prominent economic and justice theorists of private law writing in English are male.
-
(2003)
Current Legal Problems
, vol.56
, pp. 175
-
-
Conaghan, J.1
-
59
-
-
84873555054
-
'Corrective and Distributive Justice'
-
See below
-
See 'Corrective and Distributive Justice', below.
-
-
-
-
60
-
-
27744541788
-
-
For an attempt to develop what might be called a 'critical' approach to law and economics see (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
-
For an attempt to develop what might be called a 'critical' approach to law and economics see R. P. Malloy, Law and Market Economy: Reinterpreting the Values of Law and Economics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000);
-
(2000)
Law and Market Economy: Reinterpreting the Values of Law and Economics
-
-
Malloy, R.P.1
-
63
-
-
27744461390
-
'Criticizing and Constructing Accounts of Legal Reasoning'
-
On the difference between theory in this sense and 'scientific' theories see 303
-
On the difference between theory in this sense and 'scientific' theories see W. N. R. Lucy, 'Criticizing and Constructing Accounts of Legal Reasoning' (1994) 14 OJLS 303, 310-11.
-
(1994)
OJLS
, vol.14
, pp. 310-311
-
-
Lucy, W.N.R.1
-
64
-
-
4143106582
-
'Correlativity, Personality, and the Emerging Consensus on Corrective Justice'
-
(Online Edition), Article 4
-
E. J. Weinrib, 'Correlativity, Personality, and the Emerging Consensus on Corrective Justice' (2001) 2 Theoretical Inquiries in Law (Online Edition), No 1, Article 4.
-
(2001)
Theoretical Inquiries in Law
, vol.2
, Issue.1
-
-
Weinrib, E.J.1
-
65
-
-
0040974650
-
'The Aims and Authority of Moral Theory'
-
For a suggestive discussion of similar issues in moral theory see
-
see T. M. Scanlon, 'The Aims and Authority of Moral Theory' (1992) 12 OJLS 1
-
(1992)
OJLS
, vol.12
, pp. 1
-
-
Scanlon, T.M.1
-
66
-
-
4143106582
-
'Correlativity, Personality, and the Emerging Consensus on Corrective Justice'
-
This is surely true of the thin concept of 'personality' that Ernest Weinrib offers as an explanation of the 'content' of private law: see (Online Edition), Article 4
-
This is surely true of the thin concept of 'personality' that Ernest Weinrib offers as an explanation of the 'content' of private law: See above, n 24.
-
(1992)
Theoretical Inquiries in Law
, vol.2
, pp. 1
-
-
Weinrib, E.J.1
-
67
-
-
27744587597
-
'Critical Notice: Too Much Invested to Quit'
-
Although Ripstein detects a trend in law-and-economics away from descriptive analysis and towards prescription: 1
-
Although Ripstein detects a trend in law-and-economics away from descriptive analysis and towards prescription: A. Ripstein, 'Critical Notice: Too Much Invested to Quit' (2004) 20 Economics and Philosophy 1, 3.
-
(2004)
Economics and Philosophy
, vol.20
, pp. 3
-
-
Ripstein, A.1
-
68
-
-
0346788352
-
Corrective Justice and Correlativity in Private Law'
-
471
-
P. Cane, Corrective Justice and Correlativity in Private Law' (1996) 16 OJLS 471, 485-87.
-
(1996)
OJLS
, vol.16
, pp. 485-487
-
-
Cane, P.1
-
69
-
-
27744475422
-
'Markets and Morals in Contract and Tort'
-
396, Coleman defines the core of tort law in terms of a 'pretheoretic conception of [its] central elements' (The Practice of Principle, 15 n 2, 38). It is not clear how this procedure relates to his pragmatic methodology of focusing on tort law as a set of practices. Why start with a 'conception' of tort law rather than a description?
-
P. Cane, 'Markets and Morals in Contract and Tort' (1993) 13 LS 396, 406. Coleman defines the core of tort law in terms of a 'pretheoretic conception of [its] central elements' (The Practice of Principle, 15 n 2, 38). It is not clear how this procedure relates to his pragmatic methodology of focusing on tort law as a set of practices. Why start with a 'conception' of tort law rather than a description?
-
(1993)
LS
, vol.13
, pp. 406
-
-
Cane, P.1
-
71
-
-
85055307747
-
'Interpretive Legal Theory and the Academic Lawyer'
-
For a different approach see esp 330-31
-
For a different approach see A. Beever and C. Rickert, 'Interpretive Legal Theory and the Academic Lawyer' (2005) 68 MLR 320, esp 330-31.
-
(2005)
MLR
, vol.68
, pp. 320
-
-
Beever, A.1
Rickert, C.2
-
74
-
-
31144458448
-
-
This distinction is perhaps captured in the contrast between 'philosophy of law' and 'legal theory'. Coleman also speaks of 'ground-level practices', and 'lower mid-level', 'higher mid-level' and 'upper level' principles and concepts
-
This distinction is perhaps captured in the contrast between 'philosophy of law' and 'legal theory'. Coleman also speaks of 'ground-level practices', and 'lower mid-level', 'higher mid-level' and 'upper level' principles and concepts: The Practice of Principle, 54-56.
-
The Practice of Principle
, pp. 54-56
-
-
-
76
-
-
27744461390
-
'Criticizing and Constructing Accounts of Legal Reasoning'
-
But critical theorists are not the only ones to do so: On the difference between theory in this sense and 'scientific' theories see 303
-
But critical theorists are not the only ones to do so: Lucy, above n 23.
-
(1994)
OJLS
, vol.14
, pp. 310-311
-
-
Lucy, W.N.R.1
-
77
-
-
27744495559
-
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press
-
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1968.
-
(1968)
-
-
-
78
-
-
27744600674
-
-
Oxford, Clarendon Press
-
Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1961.
-
(1961)
-
-
-
79
-
-
27744529895
-
-
note
-
But why, for instance, do they show no interest in finding out how actual participants in legal practices understand them?
-
-
-
-
80
-
-
0004229596
-
-
As noted earlier, regulation scholars also view (private) law instrumentally. A major attempt to understand contract law as regulation in the light of empirical research is (Oxford: Oxford University Press) reviewed by Campbell D. 'Reflexivity and Welfarism in the Modern Law of Contract' (2000) 20 OJLS 477
-
As noted earlier, regulation scholars also view (private) law instrumentally. A major attempt to understand contract law as regulation in the light of empirical research is H. Collins, Regulating Contracts (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), reviewed by D. Campbell, 'Reflexivity and Welfarism in the Modern Law of Contract' (2000) 20 OJLS 477.
-
(1999)
Regulating Contracts
-
-
Collins, H.1
-
81
-
-
27744604528
-
'The Unexpected Guest: Law and Economics, Law and Other Cognate Disciplines and the Future of Legal Scholarship'
-
argues that scientific method is the legacy of economic analysis to the legal academy. It is true that economic analysts lay great emphasis on the construction of testable hypotheses; but actual testing is relatively rare
-
T. S. Ulen, 'The Unexpected Guest: Law and Economics, Law and Other Cognate Disciplines and the Future of Legal Scholarship' (2004) 79 Chicago-Kent LR 403 argues that scientific method is the legacy of economic analysis to the legal academy. It is true that economic analysts lay great emphasis on the construction of testable hypotheses; but actual testing is relatively rare.
-
(2004)
Chicago-Kent LR
, vol.79
, pp. 403
-
-
Ulen, T.S.1
-
82
-
-
77956742725
-
'A Social Contract Conception of the Tort Law of Accidents'
-
Jules Coleman's discussion of settlements (Markets, Morals and the Law, ch 9) is exceptional, as is Gregory Keating's insurance-oriented analysis of tort law as concerned with harm-infliction, not risk-creation: G. J. Postema (ed.), (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
-
Jules Coleman's discussion of settlements (Markets, Morals and the Law, ch 9) is exceptional, as is Gregory Keating's insurance-oriented analysis of tort law as concerned with harm-infliction, not risk-creation: 'A Social Contract Conception of the Tort Law of Accidents' in G. J. Postema (ed.), Philosophy and the Law of Torts (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001). Weinrib's view appears to be that liability insurance is merely a mode of implementing corrective justice (Cane, Responsibility in Law and Morality, 243-45); but others (such as Keating) suggest that it also renders tort law's corrective aim and effects distributionally tolerable.
-
(2001)
Philosophy and the Law of Torts
-
-
-
83
-
-
36849036584
-
-
Alan Brudner accepts that tort practice contains both instrumental and non-instrumental elements, but seeks a monistic Hegelian integration of the two elements in the concept of 'dialogic community': (Berkeley: University of California Press)
-
Alan Brudner accepts that tort practice contains both instrumental and non-instrumental elements, but seeks a monistic Hegelian integration of the two elements in the concept of 'dialogic community': The Unity of the Common Law: Studies in Hegelian Juripsridence (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995).
-
(1995)
The Unity of the Common Law: Studies in Hegelian Juripsridence
-
-
-
84
-
-
0037650378
-
-
Demonstration of conflict, contradiction and consequent indeterminacy in the law was a major part of the critical legal studies project in the 1970s and 1980s. Some critical theorists see law's multi-dimensional schizophrenia not as a problem needing to be solved by a search for some higher-level explanatory or justificatory concept but as an opportunity that can be exploited for strategic purposes: e.g. (London: Pluto Press, 2nd edn)
-
Demonstration of conflict, contradiction and consequent indeterminacy in the law was a major part of the critical legal studies project in the 1970s and 1980s. Some critical theorists see law's multi-dimensional schizophrenia not as a problem needing to be solved by a search for some higher-level explanatory or justificatory concept but as an opportunity that can be exploited for strategic purposes: E.g. Conaghan and Mansell, above n 18, 193.
-
(1999)
The Wrongs of Tort
, pp. 193
-
-
Conaghan, J.1
Mansell, W.2
-
85
-
-
27744543214
-
'Fairness and Welfare from a Comparative Law Perspective'
-
A related issue concerns the 'geographical' reach of theories: e.g
-
A related issue concerns the 'geographical' reach of theories: E.g. H. Spector, 'Fairness and Welfare from a Comparative Law Perspective' (2004) 79 Chicago-Kent LR 521
-
(2004)
Chicago-Kent LR
, vol.79
, pp. 521
-
-
Spector, H.1
-
88
-
-
27744510487
-
'The Common Law According to Hegel'
-
See also (n 14 above)
-
See also Lucy, 'The Common Law According to Hegel' (n 14 above), 692-95.
-
(1989)
OJLS
, vol.9
, pp. 692-695
-
-
Lucy, W.N.R.1
-
89
-
-
0013096712
-
'The Common Law and Legal Theory'
-
See, especially, in A.W.B. Simpson (ed.) (Oxford: Clarendon Press)
-
See, especially, A. W. B. Simpson, 'The Common Law and Legal Theory' in A. W. B. Simpson (ed.), Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence (Second Series) (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1973);
-
(1973)
Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence (Second Series)
-
-
Simpson, A.W.B.1
-
91
-
-
46749102755
-
'The Philosophy of the Common Law'
-
in J. Coleman S. Shapiro (eds), (Oxford: Oxford University Press), It is note-worthy that the chapters on (the common law of) tort, contract and property in the latter volume appear to make no reference to Postema's ground-breaking work
-
'The Philosophy of the Common Law' in J. Coleman and S. Shapiro (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002). It is note-worthy that the chapters on (the common law of) tort, contract and property in the latter volume appear to make no reference to Postema's ground-breaking work.
-
(2002)
The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law
-
-
-
92
-
-
0344288317
-
-
See also (Oxford: Oxford University Press) Posner's quasi-historical thesis, that the common law tends to efficiency over time, was one of his most controversial: Harris, above n 5
-
See also D. Lobban, The Common Law and English Jurisprudence, 1760-1850 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991).
-
(1991)
The Common Law and English Jurisprudence, 1760-1850
-
-
Lobban, D.1
-
93
-
-
27844538267
-
'The Uses of History in Law and Economics'
-
Posner's quasi-historical thesis, that the common law tends to efficiency over time, was one of his most controversial
-
Posner's quasi-historical thesis, that the common law tends to efficiency over time, was one of his most controversial: Harris, above n 5, 669-72
-
(2003)
Theoretical Inquiries in Law
, vol.4
, pp. 669-672
-
-
Harris, R.1
-
95
-
-
0038751705
-
-
Note, for instance, the hermetic separation of the two topics in the two parts of Coleman
-
Note, for instance, the hermetic separation of the two topics in the two parts of Coleman, The Practice of Principle.
-
The Practice of Principle
-
-
-
97
-
-
77956774244
-
'Economics, Moral Philosophy and the Positive Analysis of Law'
-
But see in Postema (ed.)
-
But see M. Geistfeld, 'Economics, Moral Philosophy and the Positive Analysis of Law' in Postema (ed.), Philosophy and the Law of Torts.
-
Philosophy and the Law of Torts
-
-
Geistfeld, M.1
-
98
-
-
0142138821
-
'Civil Recourse, not Corrective Justice'
-
The most extreme version of this approach is Zipursky's argument that private law should be understood not in terms of the correlative rights and obligations of claimant and defendant, but in terms of a right of the claimant, as against the state, to provision of mechanisms and procedures for suing the defendant: 'civil recourse' not 'corrective justice' as he puts it
-
The most extreme version of this approach is Zipursky's argument that private law should be understood not in terms of the correlative rights and obligations of claimant and defendant, but in terms of a right of the claimant, as against the state, to provision of mechanisms and procedures for suing the defendant: 'civil recourse' not 'corrective justice' as he puts it: B. Zipursky, 'Civil Recourse, not Corrective Justice' (2003) 91 Georgetown LJ 695.
-
(2003)
Georgetown LJ
, vol.91
, pp. 695
-
-
Zipursky, B.1
-
99
-
-
27744588502
-
'Philosophy of Contract Law'
-
J. Coleman and S. Shapiro (eds) (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
-
J.S. Kraus, 'Philosophy of Contract Law' in J. Coleman and S. Shapiro (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002).
-
(2002)
The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law
-
-
Kraus, J.S.1
-
103
-
-
85009446942
-
'Pragmatic Conceptualism'
-
B. Zipursky, 'Pragmatic Conceptualism' (2000) 6 Legal Theory 457.
-
(2000)
Legal Theory
, vol.6
, pp. 457
-
-
Zipursky, B.1
-
104
-
-
27744490012
-
'Cognitive Science'
-
Hayek (associated with the 'Austrian school' of law and economics) developed a widely-noticed evolutionary, institutional theory of the common law and its relationship to statute (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1973), but it has had no discernible influence on economic analysts of private law. On Hayek see in Buckhaus (ed.) ch. 30 (Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar)
-
Hayek (associated with the 'Austrian school' of law and economics) developed a widely-noticed evolutionary, institutional theory of the common law and its relationship to statute (F. A. Hayek, Law, Legislation and Liberty, Vol 1: Rules and Order (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1973); but it has had no discernible influence on economic analysts of private law. On Hayek see L. Van den Hauwe, 'Frederich August von Hayek (1899-1992)' in Backhaus (ed.), above n 10, ch 30.
-
(1999)
Elgar Companion to Law and Economics
-
-
Van den Hauwe, L.1
-
105
-
-
0041878195
-
'Courts, Legislatures and the General Theory of the Second Best in Law and Economics'
-
For an unusual discussion in the Chicago tradition see 189
-
For an unusual discussion in the Chicago tradition see T. S. Ulen, 'Courts, Legislatures and the General Theory of the Second Best in Law and Economics' (1998) 73 Chicago-Kent LR 189, 216-19.
-
(1998)
Chicago-Kent LR
, vol.73
, pp. 216-219
-
-
Ulen, T.S.1
-
106
-
-
27744503678
-
-
note
-
For many justice theorists, tort law is the quintessence of private law because, it is said, it does not create rights but only recognizes and protects rights created by other departments of the law. The same might be said of the law of restitution. The lack of interest in this latter subject in the US explains why it has been more-or-less ignored (until very recently) by most justice theorists.
-
-
-
-
108
-
-
27744448713
-
'Discrimination as Injustice'
-
The points made in this paragraph and the last are brought together nicely by considering legislation that creates statutory tort liability for sex and race discrimination (P. Cane, Tort Law and Economic Interests, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2nd edn, 1996) 157-60) Such legislation, designed partly to achieve what courts could not, is redistributive in intent but operates in private law mode. For a useful discussion see
-
The points made in this paragraph and the last are brought together nicely by considering legislation that creates statutory tort liability for sex and race discrimination (P. Cane, Tort Law and Economic Interests, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2nd edn, 1996), 157-60). Such legislation, designed partly to achieve what courts could not, is redistributive in intent but operates in private law mode. For a useful discussion see J. Gardner, 'Discrimation as Injustice' (1996) 16 OJLS 353
-
(1996)
OJLS
, vol.16
, pp. 353
-
-
Gardner, J.1
-
110
-
-
0037223239
-
'Tort Law and Corrective Justice'
-
See also
-
See also H. Sheinman, 'Tort Law and Corrective Justice' (2003) 22 Law and Philosophy 21.
-
(2003)
Law and Philosophy
, vol.22
, pp. 21
-
-
Sheinman, H.1
-
113
-
-
0004257004
-
-
Posner also argues that while the common law is efficiency-promoting, statute law is not: (Oxford: Clarendon Press) Of course, not all private law is common law and not all public law is statute law. Failure to take account of this basic fact mars much private-law theory
-
Posner also argues that while the common law is efficiency-promoting, statute law is not: Duxbury, above n 12, 409-10. Of course, not all private law is common law and not all public law is statute law. Failure to take account of this basic fact mars much private-law theory.
-
(1995)
Patterns of American Jurisprudence
, pp. 409-410
-
-
Duxbury, N.1
-
114
-
-
27744545978
-
-
note
-
Many private law theorists confine their analyses to one or other of the traditional categories of private law - contract, tort, and so on - and make no claims about private law as such.
-
-
-
-
116
-
-
85138979125
-
'Unjust Enrichment and Corrective Justice'
-
'Corrective' needs to be understood structurally in terms of correlativity. Understood narrowly in terms, for instance, of compensation for wrongs, it cannot even explain all of the law of obligations: see e.g. J. W. Neyers, M. McInnes and S. G. A. Pitel, (Oxford: Hart Publishing)
-
'Corrective' needs to be understood structurally in terms of correlativity. Understood narrowly in terms, for instance, of compensation for wrongs, it cannot even explain all of the law of obligations: See e.g. D. Klimchuk, 'Unjust Enrichment and Corrective Justice' in J. W. Neyers, M. McInnes and S. G. A. Pitel, 'Understanding Unjust Enrichment (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2004);
-
(2004)
'Understanding Unjust Enrichment
-
-
Klimchuk, D.1
-
117
-
-
0345857912
-
'Restitution: The Heart of Corrective Justice'
-
L. Smith, 'Restitution: The Heart of Corrective Justice' (2001) 79 Texas LR 2115.
-
(2001)
Texas LR
, vol.79
, pp. 2115
-
-
Smith, L.1
-
118
-
-
27744456614
-
-
note
-
Crimes are typically prosecuted by state officials representing the public. But in some systems, victims of crime may bring 'private' prosecutions; and the paradigm criminal offence protects interests of individual victims.
-
-
-
-
119
-
-
27744563206
-
-
See the next section
-
See the next section.
-
-
-
-
120
-
-
0003626071
-
-
e.g. (Princeton: Princeton University Press)
-
e.g. R. C. Cooter, The Strategic Constitution (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2000);
-
(2000)
The Strategic Constitution
-
-
Cooter, R.C.1
-
121
-
-
0006089934
-
'A Theory of Administrative Law'
-
W. Bishop, 'A Theory of Administrative Law' (1990) 19 J of Legal Stud 489.
-
(1990)
J. of Legal Stud.
, vol.19
, pp. 489
-
-
Bishop, W.1
-
125
-
-
0003529325
-
-
(Oxford: Clarendon Press), (original emphasis)
-
J. Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980), 166 (original emphasis).
-
(1980)
Natural Law and Natural Rights
, pp. 166
-
-
Finnis, J.1
-
126
-
-
84922978193
-
-
It will be noted that in the preceding paragraphs I have assigned various different meanings to 'categorical'. This reflects (unexplained) diversity of usage in the literature
-
Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law, 210-12. It will be noted that in the preceding paragraphs I have assigned various different meanings to 'categorical'. This reflects (unexplained) diversity of usage in the literature.
-
The Idea of Private Law
, pp. 210-212
-
-
Weinrib, E.J.1
-
129
-
-
31144458448
-
-
(at 34 he omits 'appropriately'). Coleman does not say why assault and battery are paradigmatically tortious. He may consider them (wrongly in my opinion) to be 'intentional' torts. Such emphasis on the agent's mental state would put his account in the mainstream of philosophical accounts of responsibility
-
The Practice of Principle, 32 (at 34 he omits 'appropriately'). Coleman does not say why assault and battery are paradigmatically tortious. He may consider them (wrongly in my opinion) to be 'intentional' torts. Such emphasis on the agent's mental state would put his account in the mainstream of philosophical accounts of responsibility.
-
The Practice of Principle
, pp. 32
-
-
-
130
-
-
27744471108
-
-
note
-
Coleman plausibly thinks that developing a 'general theory' of the 'special part' of tort law is unlikely to be possible. It does not follow, of course, that we do not need some theoretical account of what 'tortious' means. The substantive aspect of tort law on which corrective justice theorists concentrate is the account that it(s general part) provides of what it means to be responsible, as opposed to what our responsibilities are (according to tort law).
-
-
-
-
131
-
-
27744436444
-
-
note
-
Klimchuk says that 'rights and duties in distributive justice are agent-general, in corrective justice...agent-specific (n 14 above, 50). On this basis, we might think that whereas the application of legal norms to individual transactions is corrective, making general rules governing classes of transactions is distributive.
-
-
-
-
132
-
-
27744439619
-
-
note
-
For Weinrib, the distinction between corrective and distributive justice marks the boundary between the legal and the political.
-
-
-
-
133
-
-
27744607282
-
'Contracts as a Mechanism of Distributive Justice'
-
Stephen Perry once took a similar view of tort law as a 'localised system of distributive justice: It has attracted much attention in the pages of this Journal in recent years: notably
-
Stephen Perry once took a similar view of tort law as a 'localised system of distributive justice': N 14 above.
-
(1989)
OJLS
, vol.9
, pp. 132
-
-
Lucy, W.N.R.1
-
136
-
-
27744576233
-
'Tort Law and Distributive Justice'
-
P. Cane, 'Tort Law and Distributive Justice' [2001] New Zealand LR 401, 415-9.
-
(2001)
New Zealand LR
, vol.401
, pp. 415-419
-
-
Cane, P.1
-
137
-
-
27744513078
-
-
There is, of course, a further question about whether or not the best way to deal with such unfairness is to change private law: see e.g. (Oxford: Oxford University Press)
-
There is, of course, a further question about whether or not the best way to deal with such unfairness is to change private law: See e.g. S. Smith, Contract Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004), 128-29.
-
(2004)
Contract Theory
, pp. 128-129
-
-
Smith, S.1
-
138
-
-
81055129922
-
'Retributive and Corrective Justice, Criminal and Private Law'
-
For an argument that tort law ought to be abolished because the corrective justice principle on which it rests is retributively and distributively unfair see P. Wahlgren (ed.) Perspectives on Jurisprudence: Essays in Honor of Jes Bjarup
-
For an argument that tort law ought to be abolished because the corrective justice principle on which it rests is retributively and distributively unfair see D. Wood, 'Retributive and Corrective Justice, Criminal and Private Law' in P. Wahlgren (ed.) Perspectives on Jurisprudence: Essays in Honor of Jes Bjarup (2004) 48 Scandinavian Studies in Law 541.
-
(2004)
Scandinavian Studies in Law
, vol.48
, pp. 541
-
-
Wood, D.1
-
141
-
-
27744578329
-
'On the Division of Law-Making Labour
-
211
-
'On the Division of Law-Making Labour (2005) 7 The Judicial Review 211, 228.
-
(2005)
The Judicial Review
, vol.7
, pp. 228
-
-
|