메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 2, Issue 3, 2003, Pages 281-305

The weaknesses of strong intersubjectivism: Habermas's conception of justice

Author keywords

Argumentation; Constructivism; Democratic legitimacy; Habermas; Intersubjectivism; Justice; Truth

Indexed keywords


EID: 17044433403     PISSN: 14748851     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1177/1474885103002003003     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (10)

References (90)
  • 1
    • 33947254903 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 11 October
    • Die Zeit (11 October 2001). Habermas was awarded the prize on 15 Oct.
    • (2001) Die Zeit
  • 5
    • 85033646636 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Habermas uses the terms 'moral validity' and 'justice' synonymously
    • Habermas uses the terms 'moral validity' and 'justice' synonymously.
  • 7
    • 0011569109 scopus 로고
    • Frankfurt am Main: Fischer
    • (1st published as (1944) Dialektik der Aufklärung. Frankfurt am Main: Fischer.)
    • (1944) Dialektik der Aufklärung
  • 8
    • 0004272799 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • tr. R. Hullot-Kentor. London: Athlone Press
    • T.W. Adorno (1997) Aesthetic Theory, tr. R. Hullot-Kentor. London: Athlone Press,
    • (1997) Aesthetic Theory
    • Adorno, T.W.1
  • 9
    • 0007424840 scopus 로고
    • Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp
    • (1st published as (1970) Ästhetische Theorie. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.)
    • (1970) Ästhetische Theorie
  • 15
    • 84972640503 scopus 로고
    • Habermas, Autonomy and the Identity of the Self
    • Whereas his position with regard to moral autonomy seems clear-cut, Habermas's view of self-realization is harder to ascertain. He seems to shift between two positions, a stronger one that ties self-realization to an intersubjectively construed conception of ethical validity, and a weaker one that sees ethical validity as a purely subjective affair. For a critical discussion of the questions of autonomy and self-realization in Habermas's work, see M. Cooke (1992) 'Habermas, Autonomy and the Identity of the Self, Philosophy and Social Criticism 18(1/2): 270-91,
    • (1992) Philosophy and Social Criticism , vol.18 , Issue.1-2 , pp. 270-291
    • Cooke, M.1
  • 16
    • 84972777917 scopus 로고
    • Realizing the Post-Conventional Self
    • and (1994) 'Realizing the Post-Conventional Self, Philosophy and Social Criticism 20(3/4): 87-101.
    • (1994) Philosophy and Social Criticism , vol.20 , Issue.3-4 , pp. 87-101
  • 17
    • 0009866707 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Questioning Autonomy: The Feminist Challenge and the Challenge for Feminism
    • R. Kearney and M. Dooley (eds) London and New York: Routledge
    • See M. Cooke (1998) 'Questioning Autonomy: The Feminist Challenge and the Challenge for Feminism', in R. Kearney and M. Dooley (eds) Questioning Ethics, pp. 258-82. London and New York: Routledge.
    • (1998) Questioning Ethics , pp. 258-282
    • Cooke, M.1
  • 18
    • 0038224086 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Habermas, Feminism and the Question of Autonomy
    • P. Dews (ed.) Oxford: Blackwell
    • (1999) 'Habermas, Feminism and the Question of Autonomy', in P. Dews (ed.) Habermas: A Critical Reader, pp. 178-210. Oxford: Blackwell.
    • (1999) Habermas: A Critical Reader , pp. 178-210
  • 20
    • 84866574674 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Naturalismus und Anti-Naturalismus bei Habermas
    • See also P. Dews (2001) 'Naturalismus und Anti-Naturalismus bei Habermas', Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 49(6): 861-71.
    • (2001) Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie , vol.49 , Issue.6 , pp. 861-871
    • Dews, P.1
  • 21
    • 0002304082 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Space of One's Own: Autonomy, Privacy, Liberty
    • See Cooke (1998 and 1999, in n. 10); also
    • See Cooke (1998 and 1999, in n. 10); also M. Cooke (1999) 'A Space of One's Own: Autonomy, Privacy, Liberty', Philosophy and Social Criticism 25(1): 23-53.
    • (1999) Philosophy and Social Criticism , vol.25 , Issue.1 , pp. 23-53
    • Cooke, M.1
  • 23
    • 84866583726 scopus 로고
    • Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp
    • (ist published as (1992) Eaktizität und Geltung. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.)
    • (1992) Eaktizität und Geltung
  • 24
    • 85033660182 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Habermas sometimes characterizes moral autonomy as a purely cognitive concept, lacking any volitional dimension (see e.g. Habermas (n. 13), p. 155, where he refers to the 'purely cognitive validity claim' of moral norms). To deny a volitional moment to moral autonomy would be absurd, however, given that autonomy has always been understood to involve the exercise of human free will.
  • 26
    • 0004130431 scopus 로고
    • tr. W. M. Hohengarten. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • See J. Habermas (1992) Postmetaphysical Thinking, tr. W. M. Hohengarten. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,
    • (1992) Postmetaphysical Thinking
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 27
    • 0004317555 scopus 로고
    • Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp
    • (ist published as (1988) Postmetaphysisches Denken, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.)
    • (1988) Postmetaphysisches Denken
  • 28
    • 0039885410 scopus 로고
    • Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp
    • J. Habermas (1991) Texte und Kontexte, p. 127. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
    • (1991) Texte und Kontexte , pp. 127
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 29
    • 0000352104 scopus 로고
    • Reply to Habermas
    • This concern is evident in Rawls's distinction between a 'modus vivendi' and 'stability for the right reasons', J. Rawls (1995) 'Reply to Habermas', Journal of Philosophy 92(3): 132-80, 147.
    • (1995) Journal of Philosophy , vol.92 , Issue.3 , pp. 132-180
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 30
    • 85033650632 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Cooke (1998, in n. 10), esp. pp. 272-82
    • See Cooke (1998, in n. 10), esp. pp. 272-82.
  • 31
    • 84917097412 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Between "Objectivism" and "Contextualism": The Normative Foundations of Social Philosophy
    • Cf.
    • Cf. M. Cooke (2000) 'Between "Objectivism" and "Contextualism": The Normative Foundations of Social Philosophy', Critical Horizons 1(2): 193-227.
    • (2000) Critical Horizons , vol.1 , Issue.2 , pp. 193-227
    • Cooke, M.1
  • 32
    • 85033659943 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Habermas (1984, in n. 7), pp. 40-42. For a critical discussion of this distinction, see Cooke (n. 15), pp. 31-32
    • Habermas (1984, in n. 7), pp. 40-42. For a critical discussion of this distinction, see Cooke (n. 15), pp. 31-32.
  • 33
    • 85033659583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Cooke (1994, in n. 9), pp. 91-97, I argue that Habermas fails to distinguish between two senses in which ethical judgements can be regarded as context-specific; the first addresses the question of who recognizes the validity of the judgement and the second addresses the question of for whom the judgement is recognized to be valid. His failure to make this distinction means that he is forced to deny to ethically valid judgements - or to valid laws - the sense of unconditionality he attaches to moral norms and to true propositions. Arguably, however, valid ethical judgements and valid laws, too, have a connotation of unconditionality, despite their context-specificity in the second of the above senses
    • In Cooke (1994, in n. 9), pp. 91-97, I argue that Habermas fails to distinguish between two senses in which ethical judgements can be regarded as context-specific; the first addresses the question of who recognizes the validity of the judgement and the second addresses the question of for whom the judgement is recognized to be valid. His failure to make this distinction means that he is forced to deny to ethically valid judgements - or to valid laws - the sense of unconditionality he attaches to moral norms and to true propositions. Arguably, however, valid ethical judgements and valid laws, too, have a connotation of unconditionality, despite their context-specificity in the second of the above senses.
  • 34
    • 33846148214 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Critical Theory and Religion
    • D.Z. Phillips and T. Tessin (eds) London: Palgrave
    • For a discussion of religious validity claims see M. Cooke (2001) 'Critical Theory and Religion', in D.Z. Phillips and T. Tessin (eds) Philosophy of Religion in the 21st Century, pp. 211-43. London: Palgrave.
    • (2001) Philosophy of Religion in the 21st Century , pp. 211-243
    • Cooke, M.1
  • 35
    • 42649122071 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Die Stellung der Religion bei Jürgen Habermas
    • K. Dethloff, L. Nagl and F. Wolfram (eds) Düsseldorf: Parerga
    • M. Cooke (2002) 'Die Stellung der Religion bei Jürgen Habermas', in K. Dethloff, L. Nagl and F. Wolfram (eds) Religion, Moderne, Postmoderne: Philosophisch-theologische Erkundungen, pp. 99-119. Düsseldorf: Parerga.
    • (2002) Religion, Moderne, Postmoderne: Philosophisch-theologische Erkundungen , pp. 99-119
    • Cooke, M.1
  • 36
    • 0004292881 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp
    • See my critical discussion of Habermas on this point in Cooke (n. 15), pp. 29-35. However, in recent years, Habermas has begun to acknowledge that the normative suppositions guiding argumentation vary from context to context (see e.g. his 'Richtigkeit versus Wahrheit: zum Sinn der Sollgeltung moralischer Urteile und Normen', in Habermas (1999) Wahrheit und Rechtfertigung, pp. 271-318, 302. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp).
    • (1999) Wahrheit und Rechtfertigung , pp. 271-318
    • Habermas1
  • 37
    • 0001969316 scopus 로고
    • Wahrheitstheorien
    • H. Fahrenbach (ed.) Pfüllingen: Neske
    • J. Habermas (1973) 'Wahrheitstheorien', in H. Fahrenbach (ed.) Wirklichkeit und Reflexion. Pfüllingen: Neske.
    • (1973) Wirklichkeit und Reflexion
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 38
    • 85033642224 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Habermas compares his approach to moral validity with Rawls's constructivist one. See Habermas (n. 24), p. 301 and (n. 13), p. 156. In the latter text, there are two significant differences between the German original and the English translation. Whereas the German version reads: 'moral norms . . . are surely not just "discovered" but constructed at the same time' (my translation), the English reads: 'moral norms . . . are surely not just "discovered" but partly "constructed" at the same time'.
  • 39
    • 0003624191 scopus 로고
    • New York: Columbia University Press, esp. lecture III
    • J. Rawls (1993) Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press, esp. lecture III.
    • (1993) Political Liberalism
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 40
    • 0001501318 scopus 로고
    • Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory
    • Cf.
    • Cf. J. Rawls (1980) 'Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory', Journal of Philosophy 77: 517-72.
    • (1980) Journal of Philosophy , vol.77 , pp. 517-572
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 41
    • 0034358444 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Five Arguments for Deliberative Democracy
    • M. Cooke (2000) 'Five Arguments for Deliberative Democracy', Political Studies 48(5): 947-69, 958.
    • (2000) Political Studies , vol.48 , Issue.5 , pp. 947-969
    • Cooke, M.1
  • 42
    • 0002247751 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy
    • Cf. S. Benhabib (ed.) Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press
    • Cf. S. Benhabib (1996) 'Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy', in S. Benhabib (ed.) Democracy and Difference, p. 76. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
    • (1996) Democracy and Difference , pp. 76
    • Benhabib, S.1
  • 43
    • 85033659544 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In Habermas (n. 24), p. 297, he writes that a rational consensus (achieved under ideal conditions) guarantees the rightness of moral judgements
    • In Habermas (n. 24), p. 297, he writes that a rational consensus (achieved under ideal conditions) guarantees the rightness of moral judgements.
  • 44
    • 38949146191 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Realismus und Konstruktivismus in der kantianischen Moralphilosophie - Das Beispiel der Diskursethik
    • C. Lafont (2002) 'Realismus und Konstruktivismus in der kantianischen Moralphilosophie - das Beispiel der Diskursethik', Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie, 50(1): 39-52.
    • (2002) Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie , vol.50 , Issue.1 , pp. 39-52
    • Lafont, C.1
  • 45
    • 0002253097 scopus 로고
    • tr. D. Midgley, esp. pp. 160-68. Cambridge: Polity Press
    • Wellmer makes a similar point in 'Ethics and Dialogue', in A. Wellmer (1991) The Persistence of Modernity, tr. D. Midgley, pp. 113-231, esp. pp. 160-68. Cambridge: Polity Press,
    • (1991) The Persistence of Modernity , pp. 113-231
    • Wellmer, A.1
  • 46
    • 0346925969 scopus 로고
    • Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp
    • (1st published as (1986) Ethik und Dialog. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.)
    • (1986) Ethik und Dialog
  • 47
    • 85033657543 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wellmer (n. 30), esp. pp. 168-82
    • Wellmer (n. 30), esp. pp. 168-82.
  • 48
    • 85013787781 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Richard Rorty's Pragmatic Turn
    • M. Cooke (ed.) esp. pp. 365-66. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • J. Habermas (1998) 'Richard Rorty's Pragmatic Turn', in M. Cooke (ed.) Habermas: On the Pragmatics of Communication, pp. 343-82, esp. pp. 365-66. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
    • (1998) Habermas: On the Pragmatics of Communication , pp. 343-382
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 49
    • 34248733482 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Habermas on Meaning and Truth
    • esp. pp. 9-15
    • Ibid. pp. 369-73. Habermas (n. 24), pp. 291-96. See also M. Cooke (2001) 'Habermas on Meaning and Truth', European Journal of Philosophy 9(1): 1-23, esp. pp. 9-15.
    • (2001) European Journal of Philosophy , vol.9 , Issue.1 , pp. 1-23
    • Cooke, M.1
  • 50
    • 85033638049 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Habermas (n. 32), p. 367
    • Habermas (n. 32), p. 367.
  • 52
    • 85033649601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid. pp. 370-72.
  • 53
    • 85033634964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The following reading is an attempt to makes sense of some of the difficulties I elsewhere discerned in Habermas's 'Janus-faced' conception of truth; see Cooke (n. 33), pp. 9-15.
  • 54
    • 85033653392 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Habermas (n. 24), pp. 311-12
    • Cf. Habermas (n. 24), pp. 311-12.
  • 55
    • 85033636008 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid. pp. 293-95
    • Ibid. pp. 293-95.
  • 56
    • 85033638548 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Cooke (n. 15), pp. 29-35
    • See Cooke (n. 15), pp. 29-35.
  • 57
    • 85033656492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Cooke (n. 33), pp. 12-13
    • See Cooke (n. 33), pp. 12-13.
  • 58
    • 85033637610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. M. Cooke (n. 28), esp. pp. 954-56
    • Cf. M. Cooke (n. 28), esp. pp. 954-56.
  • 59
    • 34248735041 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Argumentation and Transformation
    • Cf. esp. pp. 96-97
    • Cf. M. Cooke (2002) 'Argumentation and Transformation', Argumentation 16(1): 79-108, esp. pp. 96-97.
    • (2002) Argumentation , vol.16 , Issue.1 , pp. 79-108
    • Cooke, M.1
  • 60
    • 85033648936 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Cooke (2002, in n. 23), esp. pp. 114-19. Cf. also Cooke (n. 43)
    • See Cooke (2002, in n. 23), esp. pp. 114-19. Cf. also Cooke (n. 43).
  • 61
    • 85033644838 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Habermas consistently refuses to give up his constructivist account of moral validity. See Habermas (n. 32), p. 381, n. 55, and Habermas (n. 24), pp. 271-318.
  • 62
    • 85033659613 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Habermas (n. 24), pp. 307-10
    • Habermas (n. 24), pp. 307-10.
  • 63
    • 85033634685 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lafont (n. 30), esp. pp. 44-45
    • Lafont (n. 30), esp. pp. 44-45.
  • 64
    • 85033649526 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Habermas (n. 24), p. 300 (my emphasis, my translation)
    • Habermas (n. 24), p. 300 (my emphasis, my translation).
  • 65
    • 0003266374 scopus 로고
    • Notes on a Program of Philosophical Justification
    • tr. C. Lenhardt and S. Shierry Weber, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • Habermas sets out the basic elements of his theory of moral validity in J. Habermas (1990) 'Notes on a Program of Philosophical Justification', in his Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, tr. C. Lenhardt and S. Shierry Weber, pp. 43-115. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,
    • (1990) Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action , pp. 43-115
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 67
    • 0002868513 scopus 로고
    • Remarks on Discourse Ethics
    • tr. C. Cronin, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
    • See also J. Habermas (1993) 'Remarks on Discourse Ethics', in Justification and Application, tr. C. Cronin, pp. 19-112. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press,
    • (1993) Justification and Application , pp. 19-112
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 68
    • 0009396776 scopus 로고
    • Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp
    • (ist published as (1991) Erläuterungen zur Diskursethik. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.)
    • (1991) Erläuterungen zur Diskursethik
  • 69
    • 85033656688 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Habermas (n. 24), p. 300
    • Habermas (n. 24), p. 300.
  • 70
    • 85033641850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid. p. 301
    • Ibid. p. 301.
  • 71
    • 85033639212 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Wellmer (n. 30), pp. 197-98, makes a similar point in connection with moral validity
    • Wellmer (n. 30), pp. 197-98, makes a similar point in connection with moral validity.
  • 72
    • 85033651746 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Habermas himself uses the word 'assumption' (Unterstellung), though he gives a somewhat different account of its necessity: 'This supposition of an objective world that is independent of our descriptions fulfills a functional requirement of our processes of cooperation and communication. Without this supposition, everyday practices . . . would come apart at the seams'. Habermas (n. 32), p. 359.
  • 73
    • 85033653712 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Habermas (n. 32), p. 360
    • Cf. Habermas (n. 32), p. 360.
  • 74
    • 85033649454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See n. 13 above
    • See n. 13 above.
  • 75
    • 85033646222 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Habermas (n. 13), pp. 151-62. Habermas offers a summary of the differences between morality and law, pp. 451-52 and pp. 459-60
    • Habermas (n. 13), pp. 151-62. Habermas offers a summary of the differences between morality and law, pp. 451-52 and pp. 459-60.
  • 76
    • 85033652648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Habermas (n. 13), pp. 106-11. Cf. also pp. 457-61
    • Habermas (n. 13), pp. 106-11. Cf. also pp. 457-61.
  • 77
    • 85033659999 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • '[The discourse] principle has, to begin with, the cognitive sense of filtering reasons and information, topics and contributions in such a way that the outcome of a discourse enjoys a presumption of rational acceptability; democratic procedure should ground the legitimacy of law': Habermas (n. 13), p. 151
    • '[The discourse] principle has, to begin with, the cognitive sense of filtering reasons and information, topics and contributions in such a way that the outcome of a discourse enjoys a presumption of rational acceptability; democratic procedure should ground the legitimacy of law': Habermas (n. 13), p. 151.
  • 78
    • 85033653136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid. pp. 164-67
    • Ibid. pp. 164-67.
  • 79
    • 85033642546 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid. p. 179
    • Ibid. p. 179.
  • 80
    • 85033641782 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In Habermas (n. 13), he consistently refers to the process of democratic deliberation as a process of both will-formation and opinion-formation. His point is particularly clear on p. 460.
  • 81
    • 85033655408 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For example, ibid. pp. 156 and 458-59
    • For example, ibid. pp. 156 and 458-59.
  • 82
    • 85033635104 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For our present purposes we can leave aside the objection raised by Lafont and others that this conception is inherently unstable.
  • 83
    • 85033647193 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid. pp. 151-62; cf. also pp. 451-52 and 459-60
    • Ibid. pp. 151-62; cf. also pp. 451-52 and 459-60.
  • 84
    • 85033651352 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid
    • Ibid.
  • 85
    • 85033644834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Cooke (n. 28), pp. 952-54
    • See Cooke (n. 28), pp. 952-54.
  • 86
    • 85033636652 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Instead, it takes on the function of an imaginative projection of a condition in which perfect knowledge would be available and perfect mutual understanding, perfect transparency and so on would have been achieved.
  • 87
    • 85033648686 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As a result of his failure to distinguish between two senses in which ethical judgements and laws can be context-specific (see n. 22), Habermas is unable to attach any sense of unconditionality to the validity of laws.
  • 88
    • 85033640966 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • As in the case of truth and justice, the relation between the normative component of democratic legitimacy and argumentation moves in two directions. Thus, not only is the idea of genuinely generally acceptable laws and policies a guiding assumption of democratic argumentation; there is a (historically contingent) conceptual connection between democratic legitimacy and argumentation.
  • 89
    • 85033659281 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Cooke (n. 28), p. 967
    • Cf. Cooke (n. 28), p. 967.
  • 90
    • 85033638976 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • However, as in the case of moral norms and moral autonomy, it is counter-intuitive to make participation in argumentation a prerequisite for cognitive transformation.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.