메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 12, Issue 1, 2004, Pages 65-78

A Kantian Defense of Self-Ownership

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 1342327352     PISSN: 09638016     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9760.2004.00191.x     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (22)

References (49)
  • 2
    • 0004128375 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, also see pp. 211-13
    • G. A. Cohen, Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Equality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), pp. 238-42; also see pp. 211-13.
    • (1997) Self-ownership, Freedom, and Equality , pp. 238-242
    • Cohen, G.A.1
  • 3
    • 84937323134 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Freedom and self-ownership
    • 1-23
    • Daniel Attas, "Freedom and self-ownership," Social Theory and Practice, 26 (2000), 1-23 at pp. 11-15; George Brenkert, "Self-ownership, freedom, and autonomy," Journal of Ethics, 2 (1998), 27-55 at pp. 50-2.
    • (2000) Social Theory and Practice , vol.26 , pp. 11-15
    • Attas, D.1
  • 4
    • 1342298685 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Self-ownership, freedom, and autonomy
    • 27-55
    • Daniel Attas, "Freedom and self-ownership," Social Theory and Practice, 26 (2000), 1-23 at pp. 11-15; George Brenkert, "Self-ownership, freedom, and autonomy," Journal of Ethics, 2 (1998), 27-55 at pp. 50-2.
    • (1998) Journal of Ethics , vol.2 , pp. 50-52
    • Brenkert, G.1
  • 5
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • The contrast with John Rawls, whose Kantianism is spelled out in exquisite detail in 40 of A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), is instructive.
    • (1999) A Theory of Justice
  • 6
    • 0004305896 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, [1785])
    • Hereafter GMM and MM, respectively. Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, [1785] 1997); Immanuel Kant, Metaphysics of Morals, trans. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, [1797] 1996).
    • (1997) Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals
    • Kant, I.1
  • 7
    • 0004291536 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • trans. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, [1797])
    • Hereafter GMM and MM, respectively. Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, [1785] 1997); Immanuel Kant, Metaphysics of Morals, trans. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, [1797] 1996).
    • (1996) Metaphysics of Morals
    • Kant, I.1
  • 8
    • 1342298688 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MM, p. 56
    • MM, p. 56.
  • 9
    • 1342319870 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GMM, p. 38; emphasis added
    • GMM, p. 38; emphasis added.
  • 10
    • 1342298677 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Suicide: ibid.; voluntary servitude: MM, pp. 66, 104
    • Suicide: ibid.; voluntary servitude: MM, pp. 66, 104; organ sales and self-mutilation: MM, p. 177; prostitution: MM, p. 63; premarital sex: MM, p. 127; failure to develop one's talents: GMM, pp. 38-9.
  • 11
    • 1342319871 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MM, p. 177; prostitution: MM, p. 63; premarital sex: MM, p. 127; failure to develop one's talents: GMM, pp. 38-9.
    • Suicide: ibid.; voluntary servitude: MM, pp. 66, 104; organ sales and self-mutilation: MM, p. 177; prostitution: MM, p. 63; premarital sex: MM, p. 127; failure to develop one's talents: GMM, pp. 38-9.
  • 12
    • 1342298680 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 38; MM, p. 30
    • Ibid., p. 38; MM, p. 30.
  • 13
    • 1342298676 scopus 로고
    • A right to do wrong
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • For an extended defense of this proposition, see Jeremy Waldron, "A right to do wrong," Liberal Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), pp. 63-87.
    • (1993) Liberal Rights , pp. 63-87
    • Waldron, J.1
  • 14
    • 1342341132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am not claiming that Kant himself held this view. He states in MM that "killing oneself is a crime (murder)" (p. 176). Thus, he would have been as unlikely to endorse a duty of noninterference in suicide as a duty of noninterference in homicide.
  • 16
    • 1342298679 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GMM, p. 31
    • GMM, p. 31.
  • 17
    • 1342298683 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • p. 191, Also see Chapter 5 of John Stuart Mill's essay Utilitarianism
    • O'Neill, p. 191, Also see Chapter 5 of John Stuart Mill's essay Utilitarianism.
    • O'Neill1
  • 20
    • 1342277578 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GMM, p. 31
    • GMM, p. 31.
  • 21
    • 1342319873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 33
    • Ibid., p. 33.
  • 22
    • 1342277577 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 32
    • Ibid., p. 32.
  • 23
    • 1342341129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Themes in Kant's Moral Philosophy
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, especially pp. 498-506
    • John Rawls identifies a procedure - which he refers to as the Four-Step CI-Procedure - for universalizing a maxim: first, state the maxim; second, generalize the maxim; third, transform the generalized maxim into a law of nature; finally, append this law of nature to existing laws of nature and analyze the resulting "social equilibrium"; "Themes in Kant's Moral Philosophy," Collected Papers, ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), pp. 497-528, especially pp. 498-506.
    • (1999) Collected Papers , pp. 497-528
    • Freeman, S.1
  • 24
    • 1342277580 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GMM, p. 32
    • GMM, p. 32.
  • 25
    • 1342298681 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • "Passivity" is used here in the following very specific sense: "submission ... to external force or another's will" (OED).
  • 26
    • 0004051088 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • GMM, p. 34. Also see Barbara Herman, The Practice of Moral Judgment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), p. 126, and Christine Korsgaard, Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), pp. 133-59.
    • (1993) The Practice of Moral Judgment , pp. 126
    • Herman, B.1
  • 27
    • 0003584929 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • GMM, p. 34. Also see Barbara Herman, The Practice of Moral Judgment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), p. 126, and Christine Korsgaard, Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), pp. 133-59.
    • (1996) Creating the Kingdom of Ends , pp. 133-159
    • Korsgaard, C.1
  • 28
    • 1342341134 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See GMM, p. 46
    • See GMM, p. 46, on the "holy will."
  • 29
    • 26744454855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ed. Allan Wood and George di Giovanni (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, [1793]
    • MM, p. 221; Immanuel Kant, Religion Within the Boundaries of Mere Reason and Other Writings, ed. Allan Wood and George di Giovanni (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, [1793] 1998), p. 180n. Also see Kant's sharp criticisms of paternalism in both MM, p. 94 and "Theory and practice," Political Writings, ed. Hans Reiss (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 74.
    • (1998) Religion Within the Boundaries of Mere Reason and Other Writings
    • Kant, I.1
  • 30
    • 1342341131 scopus 로고
    • Theory and practice
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • MM, p. 221; Immanuel Kant, Religion Within the Boundaries of Mere Reason and Other Writings, ed. Allan Wood and George di Giovanni (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, [1793] 1998), p. 180n. Also see Kant's sharp criticisms of paternalism in both MM, p. 94 and "Theory and practice," Political Writings, ed. Hans Reiss (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 74.
    • (1991) Political Writings , pp. 74
    • Reiss, H.1
  • 31
    • 0041695440 scopus 로고
    • Servility and self-respect
    • Thomas Hill makes a complementary case against submission to exploitation and paternalism in "Servility and self-respect," Monist, 57 (1973), 87-104.
    • (1973) Monist , vol.57 , pp. 87-104
  • 32
    • 1342277581 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GMM, p, 48
    • GMM, p, 48.
  • 33
    • 1342319874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 38
    • Ibid., p. 38.
  • 35
    • 1342298684 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In some cases, children may be as capable as adults of recognizing and obeying the moral law. More than adults, however, their actions, even when consistent with the moral law, are the result of a heteronomous will, i.e., a will guided by "attraction or constraint" (GMM, p. 41). As they mature, they will (hopefully) internalize the moral law and come to see it not as something imposed from without, but rather as a code given to oneself, a product of self-legislation. I will later return to this point.
  • 36
    • 0004184007 scopus 로고
    • New York: Basic
    • This categorization of nonrational agents is not intended to be exhaustive. For example, mentally incompetent adults constitute a separate category of nonrational agents. They cannot be categorized as children because they are permanently nonrational. Could they be categorized as animals? They are, after all, animate, sensitive, and permanently nonrational. The human conscience revolts against such a possibility, but it seems difficult to argue against, at least on Kantian grounds. Such difficulties provide one motivation for feminist criticisms of Kantian moral and political theories, e.g., Susan Okin, Justice, Gender, and the Family (New York: Basic, 1989).
    • (1989) Justice, Gender, and the Family
    • Okin, S.1
  • 37
    • 84937288609 scopus 로고
    • Personal rights and public space
    • 83-107 (my emphasis)
    • Thomas Nagel, "Personal rights and public space," Philosophy & Public Affairs, 24 (1995), 83-107 at pp. 89-90 (my emphasis). Also see Frances Kamm, "Nonconsequentialism, the person as an end-in-itself and the significance of status," Philosophy & Public Affairs, 21 (1992), 354-89.
    • (1995) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.24 , pp. 89-90
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 38
    • 0026922829 scopus 로고
    • Nonconsequentialism, the person as an end-in-itself and the significance of status
    • Thomas Nagel, "Personal rights and public space," Philosophy & Public Affairs, 24 (1995), 83-107 at pp. 89-90 (my emphasis). Also see Frances Kamm, "Nonconsequentialism, the person as an end-in-itself and the significance of status," Philosophy & Public Affairs, 21 (1992), 354-89.
    • (1992) Philosophy & Public Affairs , vol.21 , pp. 354-389
    • Kamm, F.1
  • 39
    • 0033160143 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What is a Child?
    • For a discussion of children's moral status that is informed by Kant's practical philosophy, see Tamar Schapiro, "What is a Child?" Ethics, 109 (1999), 715-38.
    • (1999) Ethics , vol.109 , pp. 715-738
    • Schapiro, T.1
  • 41
    • 1342277584 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GMM, p. 39
    • GMM, p. 39.
  • 42
    • 1342298682 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ibid., p. 42
    • "The will of a rational being must always be regarded as at the same time lawgiving, since otherwise it could not be thought as an end in itself" (ibid., p. 42).
  • 43
    • 26444470506 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Rawls, "Themes in Kant's Moral Philosophy," pp. 504-6, for an alternative explanation, in which the different formulations represent varied points of view, or perspectives, on the same underlying principle.
    • Themes in Kant's Moral Philosophy , pp. 504-506
    • Rawls1
  • 44
    • 1342319875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GMM, p. 56
    • GMM, p. 56.
  • 45
    • 1342341137 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ibid., p. 58
    • "For we now see that when we think of ourselves as free we transfer ourselves into the world of understanding as members of it and cognize autonomy of the will along with its consequence, morality ..." (ibid., p. 58).
  • 46
    • 1342277583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • MM, p. 91
    • MM, p. 91.
  • 47
    • 1342341136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., p. 123
    • Ibid., p. 123.
  • 48
    • 0003275369 scopus 로고
    • The liberty of the ancients compared with that of the moderns
    • Ibid., p. 121. trans. Biancamaria Fontana (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
    • Ibid., p. 121. Cf. Benjamin Constant, "The liberty of the ancients compared with that of the moderns," The Political Writings of Benjamin Constant, trans. Biancamaria Fontana (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), pp. 307-28.
    • (1988) The Political Writings of Benjamin Constant , pp. 307-328
    • Constant, B.1
  • 49
    • 0004215391 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The preliminary Fifth Article of Kant's "perpetual peace" between states ("No state shall forcibly interfere in the constitution and government of another state") suggests that Kant himself was engaged in such analogizing (Kant, Political Writings, p. 96). He appears to regard such interference as a form of paternalism exactly like that exercised by sovereigns over their own citizens when they interfere with their freedom in order to promote their happiness.
    • Political Writings , pp. 96
    • Kant1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.