메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 58, Issue 2, 2004, Pages 333-365

Aquinas on the nature of human beings

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 12144253748     PISSN: 00346632     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: None     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (40)

References (177)
  • 1
    • 12144249431 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I do not accomplish such a comparison in this paper but plan to do so in future projects.
  • 2
    • 12144269439 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The terms "rational soul" and "human soul" will be used interchangeably throughout this paper.
  • 3
    • 0345356118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 3
    • See Boethius, Contra Eutychen et Nestorium, chap. 3; Aquinas, Summa Theologiae (hereafter, "ST") I, q. 29, a. 1. All translations are my own and, unless otherwise specified, are taken from the Leonine edition of Aquinas's works: S. Thomae Aquinatis Doctoris Angelici Opera Omnia (Rome: Commissio Leonina, 1882-).
    • Contra Eutychen et Nestorium
    • Boethius1
  • 4
    • 84860081916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aquinas
    • I, q. 29, a. 1. All translations are my own and, unless otherwise specified, are taken from the Leonine edition of Aquinas's works: S. Thomae Aquinatis Doctoris Angelici Opera Omnia (Rome: Commissio Leonina, 1882-)
    • See Boethius, Contra Eutychen et Nestorium, chap. 3; Aquinas, Summa Theologiae (hereafter, "ST") I, q. 29, a. 1. All translations are my own and, unless otherwise specified, are taken from the Leonine edition of Aquinas's works: S. Thomae Aquinatis Doctoris Angelici Opera Omnia (Rome: Commissio Leonina, 1882-).
    • Summa Theologiae (Hereafter, "ST")
  • 5
    • 84860081915 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aquinas
    • bk. 4, chap. 38
    • By this term, Aquinas intends the Greek term hypostasis (Latin: suppositum). The terms hypostasis and suppositum are logically distinct in Aquinas's mind, but they refer to the same thing in reality; hence, I make no distinction between the terms here. See Aquinas, Summa contra Gentiles (hereafter, "SCG"), bk. 4, chap. 38.
    • Summa Contra Gentiles (Hereafter, "SCG")
  • 6
    • 84860084161 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aquinas
    • q. un., a. 3
    • Aquinas, Quaestio disputata de anima (hereafter, "QDA"), q. un., a. 3. Compare QDA, q. un., a. 1, sed contra; SCG, bk. 2, chap. 60; Aquinas, In decem libros ethicorum Aristotelis ad Nicomachum expositio (hereafter, "In NE"), bk. 1, lect. 10; In NE, bk. 10, lect. 10.
    • Quaestio Disputata de Anima (Hereafter, "QDA")
  • 7
    • 12144256214 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. un., a. 1, sed contra
    • Aquinas, Quaestio disputata de anima (hereafter, "QDA"), q. un., a. 3. Compare QDA, q. un., a. 1, sed contra; SCG, bk. 2, chap. 60; Aquinas, In decem libros ethicorum Aristotelis ad Nicomachum expositio (hereafter, "In NE"), bk. 1, lect. 10; In NE, bk. 10, lect. 10.
    • QDA
  • 8
    • 12144249430 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 2, chap. 60
    • Aquinas, Quaestio disputata de anima (hereafter, "QDA"), q. un., a. 3. Compare QDA, q. un., a. 1, sed contra; SCG, bk. 2, chap. 60; Aquinas, In decem libros ethicorum Aristotelis ad Nicomachum expositio (hereafter, "In NE"), bk. 1, lect. 10; In NE, bk. 10, lect. 10.
    • SCG
  • 10
    • 12144263086 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 10, lect. 10
    • Aquinas, Quaestio disputata de anima (hereafter, "QDA"), q. un., a. 3. Compare QDA, q. un., a. 1, sed contra; SCG, bk. 2, chap. 60; Aquinas, In decem libros ethicorum Aristotelis ad Nicomachum expositio (hereafter, "In NE"), bk. 1, lect. 10; In NE, bk. 10, lect. 10.
    • NE
  • 11
    • 12144277295 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Aquinas recognizes different types of beings as persons. In addition to human beings, Aquinas claims that angels are persons and that God exists as three distinct persons. Since my interest in this paper is solely with human persons, I will not entertain any further discussion of such other types of persons.
  • 14
    • 12144270657 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 2, chap. 68
    • See SCG, bk. 2, chap. 68; Aquinas, In Aristotelis librum De anima commentarium (hereafter, "In DA"), bk. 2, lect. 2.
    • SCG
  • 16
    • 12144252376 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 2, chap. 69
    • SCG, bk. 2, chap. 69.
    • SCG
  • 18
    • 12144281984 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 76, a. 1
    • See ST I, q. 76, a. 1.
    • ST , vol.1
  • 19
    • 12144264664 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. un., a. 10; SCG, bk. 2, chap. 57
    • See QDA, q. un., a. 10; SCG, bk. 2, chap. 57.
    • QDA
  • 20
    • 12144261054 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • See Robert Pasnau, Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 88.
    • (2002) Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature , pp. 88
    • Pasnau, R.1
  • 21
    • 12144261488 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 2, chap. 56
    • Aquinas states that two things that are joined by a contact of power (contactus virtutis), that is, one thing is the efficient cause of change in the other, do not result in an unqualified unity. See SCG, bk. 2, chap. 56; Norman Kretzmann, The Metaphysics of Creation: Aquinas's Natural Theology in Summa Contra Gentiles II (New York: Oxford University Press, 1999), 278-90.
    • SCG
  • 22
    • 12144251611 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Aquinas states that two things that are joined by a contact of power (contactus virtutis), that is, one thing is the efficient cause of change in the other, do not result in an unqualified unity. See SCG, bk. 2, chap. 56; Norman Kretzmann, The Metaphysics of Creation: Aquinas's Natural Theology in Summa Contra Gentiles II (New York: Oxford University Press, 1999), 278-90.
    • (1999) The Metaphysics of Creation: Aquinas's Natural Theology in Summa Contra Gentiles II , pp. 278-290
    • Kretzmann, N.1
  • 23
    • 84860084158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aquinas
    • chap. 211
    • This qualifier is utilized here due to Aquinas's understanding of the Incarnation of Christ, in which the unified substantial existence of both human and divine natures precludes a new ontological entity having come into existence when Christ's soul assumed a human body. See Aquinas, Compendium theologiae (hereafter, "CT"), chap. 211.
    • Compendium Theologiae (Hereafter, "CT")
  • 24
    • 12144273871 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aquinas
    • For his account of how elements combine to form a new substance, see Aquinas, De mixtione elementorum; SCG, bk. 4, chap. 35; In M, bk. 7, lect. 17, 1680; ST I, q. 47, a. 2; ST I, q. 76, a. 4, ad 4; QDA, q. un., a. 9, ad 10.
    • De Mixtione Elementorum
  • 25
    • 12144252377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 4, chap. 35
    • For his account of how elements combine to form a new substance, see Aquinas, De mixtione elementorum; SCG, bk. 4, chap. 35; In M, bk. 7, lect. 17, 1680; ST I, q. 47, a. 2; ST I, q. 76, a. 4, ad 4; QDA, q. un., a. 9, ad 10.
    • SCG
  • 26
    • 12144257068 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 7, lect. 17
    • For his account of how elements combine to form a new substance, see Aquinas, De mixtione elementorum; SCG, bk. 4, chap. 35; In M, bk. 7, lect. 17, 1680; ST I, q. 47, a. 2; ST I, q. 76, a. 4, ad 4; QDA, q. un., a. 9, ad 10.
    • M , pp. 1680
  • 27
    • 12144251989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 47, a. 2
    • For his account of how elements combine to form a new substance, see Aquinas, De mixtione elementorum; SCG, bk. 4, chap. 35; In M, bk. 7, lect. 17, 1680; ST I, q. 47, a. 2; ST I, q. 76, a. 4, ad 4; QDA, q. un., a. 9, ad 10.
    • ST I
  • 28
    • 12144276900 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 76, a. 4, ad 4
    • For his account of how elements combine to form a new substance, see Aquinas, De mixtione elementorum; SCG, bk. 4, chap. 35; In M, bk. 7, lect. 17, 1680; ST I, q. 47, a. 2; ST I, q. 76, a. 4, ad 4; QDA, q. un., a. 9, ad 10.
    • ST I
  • 29
    • 12144261489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. un., a. 9, ad 10
    • For his account of how elements combine to form a new substance, see Aquinas, De mixtione elementorum; SCG, bk. 4, chap. 35; In M, bk. 7, lect. 17, 1680; ST I, q. 47, a. 2; ST I, q. 76, a. 4, ad 4; QDA, q. un., a. 9, ad 10.
    • QDA
  • 31
    • 12144267475 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 75, a. 4
    • Aquinas, De ente et essentia (hereafter, "DEE"), chap. 2. Compare ST I, q. 75, a. 4.
    • ST , vol.1
  • 32
    • 12144255400 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why constitution is not identity
    • Aquinas's notion of composition without identity is similar to the contemporary notion of constitution without identity. For elucidation and defense of the latter notion, see Lynne Rudder Baker, "Why Constitution Is Not Identity," Journal of Philosophy 94 (1997): 599-621; Baker, "Unity Without Identity: A New Look at Material Constitution," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23, ed. Howard Wettstein (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 144-65; Frederick Doepke, "Spatially Coinciding Objects," Ratio 24 (1982): 45-60; Mark Johnston, "Constitution Is Not Identity," Mind 101 (1992): 89-105; E. J. Lowe, "Instantiation, Identity and Constitution," Philosophical Studies 44 (1983): 45-59; J. M. Shorter, "On Coinciding in Space and Time," Philosophy 52 (1977): 399-408; Judith Jarvis Thomson, "Parthood and Identity Across Time," Journal of Philosophy 80 (1983): 201-20; Thomson, "The Statue and the Clay," Nous 32 (1998): 149-73; David Wiggins, "On Being in the Same Place at the Same Time," The Philosophical Review 77 (1968): 90-5. For application of this notion to the issue of human nature, see Lynne Rudder Baker, Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000); Kevin Corcoran, "Persons, Bodies, and the Constitution Relation," Southern Journal of Philosophy 37 (1999): 1-20.
    • (1997) Journal of Philosophy , vol.94 , pp. 599-621
    • Baker, L.R.1
  • 33
    • 12144282642 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unity without identity: A new look at material constitution
    • ed. Howard Wettstein (Oxford: Blackwell)
    • Aquinas's notion of composition without identity is similar to the contemporary notion of constitution without identity. For elucidation and defense of the latter notion, see Lynne Rudder Baker, "Why Constitution Is Not Identity," Journal of Philosophy 94 (1997): 599-621; Baker, "Unity Without Identity: A New Look at Material Constitution," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23, ed. Howard Wettstein (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 144-65; Frederick Doepke, "Spatially Coinciding Objects," Ratio 24 (1982): 45-60; Mark Johnston, "Constitution Is Not Identity," Mind 101 (1992): 89-105; E. J. Lowe, "Instantiation, Identity and Constitution," Philosophical Studies 44 (1983): 45-59; J. M. Shorter, "On Coinciding in Space and Time," Philosophy 52 (1977): 399-408; Judith Jarvis Thomson, "Parthood and Identity Across Time," Journal of Philosophy 80 (1983): 201-20; Thomson, "The Statue and the Clay," Nous 32 (1998): 149-73; David Wiggins, "On Being in the Same Place at the Same Time," The Philosophical Review 77 (1968): 90-5. For application of this notion to the issue of human nature, see Lynne Rudder Baker, Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000); Kevin Corcoran, "Persons, Bodies, and the Constitution Relation," Southern Journal of Philosophy 37 (1999): 1-20.
    • (1999) Midwest Studies in Philosophy , vol.23 , pp. 144-165
    • Baker1
  • 34
    • 84925978911 scopus 로고
    • Spatially coinciding objects
    • Aquinas's notion of composition without identity is similar to the contemporary notion of constitution without identity. For elucidation and defense of the latter notion, see Lynne Rudder Baker, "Why Constitution Is Not Identity," Journal of Philosophy 94 (1997): 599-621; Baker, "Unity Without Identity: A New Look at Material Constitution," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23, ed. Howard Wettstein (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 144-65; Frederick Doepke, "Spatially Coinciding Objects," Ratio 24 (1982): 45-60; Mark Johnston, "Constitution Is Not Identity," Mind 101 (1992): 89-105; E. J. Lowe, "Instantiation, Identity and Constitution," Philosophical Studies 44 (1983): 45-59; J. M. Shorter, "On Coinciding in Space and Time," Philosophy 52 (1977): 399-408; Judith Jarvis Thomson, "Parthood and Identity Across Time," Journal of Philosophy 80 (1983): 201-20; Thomson, "The Statue and the Clay," Nous 32 (1998): 149-73; David Wiggins, "On Being in the Same Place at the Same Time," The Philosophical Review 77 (1968): 90-5. For application of this notion to the issue of human nature, see Lynne Rudder Baker, Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000); Kevin Corcoran, "Persons, Bodies, and the Constitution Relation," Southern Journal of Philosophy 37 (1999): 1-20.
    • (1982) Ratio , vol.24 , pp. 45-60
    • Doepke, F.1
  • 35
    • 12144265038 scopus 로고
    • Constitution is not identity
    • Aquinas's notion of composition without identity is similar to the contemporary notion of constitution without identity. For elucidation and defense of the latter notion, see Lynne Rudder Baker, "Why Constitution Is Not Identity," Journal of Philosophy 94 (1997): 599-621; Baker, "Unity Without Identity: A New Look at Material Constitution," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23, ed. Howard Wettstein (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 144-65; Frederick Doepke, "Spatially Coinciding Objects," Ratio 24 (1982): 45-60; Mark Johnston, "Constitution Is Not Identity," Mind 101 (1992): 89-105; E. J. Lowe, "Instantiation, Identity and Constitution," Philosophical Studies 44 (1983): 45-59; J. M. Shorter, "On Coinciding in Space and Time," Philosophy 52 (1977): 399-408; Judith Jarvis Thomson, "Parthood and Identity Across Time," Journal of Philosophy 80 (1983): 201-20; Thomson, "The Statue and the Clay," Nous 32 (1998): 149-73; David Wiggins, "On Being in the Same Place at the Same Time," The Philosophical Review 77 (1968): 90-5. For application of this notion to the issue of human nature, see Lynne Rudder Baker, Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000); Kevin Corcoran, "Persons, Bodies, and the Constitution Relation," Southern Journal of Philosophy 37 (1999): 1-20.
    • (1992) Mind , vol.101 , pp. 89-105
    • Johnston, M.1
  • 36
    • 12144272039 scopus 로고
    • Instantiation, identity and constitution
    • Aquinas's notion of composition without identity is similar to the contemporary notion of constitution without identity. For elucidation and defense of the latter notion, see Lynne Rudder Baker, "Why Constitution Is Not Identity," Journal of Philosophy 94 (1997): 599-621; Baker, "Unity Without Identity: A New Look at Material Constitution," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23, ed. Howard Wettstein (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 144-65; Frederick Doepke, "Spatially Coinciding Objects," Ratio 24 (1982): 45-60; Mark Johnston, "Constitution Is Not Identity," Mind 101 (1992): 89-105; E. J. Lowe, "Instantiation, Identity and Constitution," Philosophical Studies 44 (1983): 45-59; J. M. Shorter, "On Coinciding in Space and Time," Philosophy 52 (1977): 399-408; Judith Jarvis Thomson, "Parthood and Identity Across Time," Journal of Philosophy 80 (1983): 201-20; Thomson, "The Statue and the Clay," Nous 32 (1998): 149-73; David Wiggins, "On Being in the Same Place at the Same Time," The Philosophical Review 77 (1968): 90-5. For application of this notion to the issue of human nature, see Lynne Rudder Baker, Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000); Kevin Corcoran, "Persons, Bodies, and the Constitution Relation," Southern Journal of Philosophy 37 (1999): 1-20.
    • (1983) Philosophical Studies , vol.44 , pp. 45-59
    • Lowe, E.J.1
  • 37
    • 84971120666 scopus 로고
    • On coinciding in space and time
    • Aquinas's notion of composition without identity is similar to the contemporary notion of constitution without identity. For elucidation and defense of the latter notion, see Lynne Rudder Baker, "Why Constitution Is Not Identity," Journal of Philosophy 94 (1997): 599-621; Baker, "Unity Without Identity: A New Look at Material Constitution," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23, ed. Howard Wettstein (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 144-65; Frederick Doepke, "Spatially Coinciding Objects," Ratio 24 (1982): 45-60; Mark Johnston, "Constitution Is Not Identity," Mind 101 (1992): 89-105; E. J. Lowe, "Instantiation, Identity and Constitution," Philosophical Studies 44 (1983): 45-59; J. M. Shorter, "On Coinciding in Space and Time," Philosophy 52 (1977): 399-408; Judith Jarvis Thomson, "Parthood and Identity Across Time," Journal of Philosophy 80 (1983): 201-20; Thomson, "The Statue and the Clay," Nous 32 (1998): 149-73; David Wiggins, "On Being in the Same Place at the Same Time," The Philosophical Review 77 (1968): 90-5. For application of this notion to the issue of human nature, see Lynne Rudder Baker, Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000); Kevin Corcoran, "Persons, Bodies, and the Constitution Relation," Southern Journal of Philosophy 37 (1999): 1-20.
    • (1977) Philosophy , vol.52 , pp. 399-408
    • Shorter, J.M.1
  • 38
    • 0009330626 scopus 로고
    • Parthood and identity across time
    • Aquinas's notion of composition without identity is similar to the contemporary notion of constitution without identity. For elucidation and defense of the latter notion, see Lynne Rudder Baker, "Why Constitution Is Not Identity," Journal of Philosophy 94 (1997): 599-621; Baker, "Unity Without Identity: A New Look at Material Constitution," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23, ed. Howard Wettstein (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 144-65; Frederick Doepke, "Spatially Coinciding Objects," Ratio 24 (1982): 45-60; Mark Johnston, "Constitution Is Not Identity," Mind 101 (1992): 89-105; E. J. Lowe, "Instantiation, Identity and Constitution," Philosophical Studies 44 (1983): 45-59; J. M. Shorter, "On Coinciding in Space and Time," Philosophy 52 (1977): 399-408; Judith Jarvis Thomson, "Parthood and Identity Across Time," Journal of Philosophy 80 (1983): 201-20; Thomson, "The Statue and the Clay," Nous 32 (1998): 149-73; David Wiggins, "On Being in the Same Place at the Same Time," The Philosophical Review 77 (1968): 90-5. For application of this notion to the issue of human nature, see Lynne Rudder Baker, Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000); Kevin Corcoran, "Persons, Bodies, and the Constitution Relation," Southern Journal of Philosophy 37 (1999): 1-20.
    • (1983) Journal of Philosophy , vol.80 , pp. 201-220
    • Thomson, J.J.1
  • 39
    • 12144279862 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The statue and the clay
    • Aquinas's notion of composition without identity is similar to the contemporary notion of constitution without identity. For elucidation and defense of the latter notion, see Lynne Rudder Baker, "Why Constitution Is Not Identity," Journal of Philosophy 94 (1997): 599-621; Baker, "Unity Without Identity: A New Look at Material Constitution," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23, ed. Howard Wettstein (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 144-65; Frederick Doepke, "Spatially Coinciding Objects," Ratio 24 (1982): 45-60; Mark Johnston, "Constitution Is Not Identity," Mind 101 (1992): 89-105; E. J. Lowe, "Instantiation, Identity and Constitution," Philosophical Studies 44 (1983): 45-59; J. M. Shorter, "On Coinciding in Space and Time," Philosophy 52 (1977): 399-408; Judith Jarvis Thomson, "Parthood and Identity Across Time," Journal of Philosophy 80 (1983): 201-20; Thomson, "The Statue and the Clay," Nous 32 (1998): 149-73; David Wiggins, "On Being in the Same Place at the Same Time," The Philosophical Review 77 (1968): 90-5. For application of this notion to the issue of human nature, see Lynne Rudder Baker, Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000); Kevin Corcoran, "Persons, Bodies, and the Constitution Relation," Southern Journal of Philosophy 37 (1999): 1-20.
    • (1998) Nous , vol.32 , pp. 149-173
    • Thomson1
  • 40
    • 12144275658 scopus 로고
    • On being in the same place at the same time
    • Aquinas's notion of composition without identity is similar to the contemporary notion of constitution without identity. For elucidation and defense of the latter notion, see Lynne Rudder Baker, "Why Constitution Is Not Identity," Journal of Philosophy 94 (1997): 599-621; Baker, "Unity Without Identity: A New Look at Material Constitution," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23, ed. Howard Wettstein (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 144-65; Frederick Doepke, "Spatially Coinciding Objects," Ratio 24 (1982): 45-60; Mark Johnston, "Constitution Is Not Identity," Mind 101 (1992): 89-105; E. J. Lowe, "Instantiation, Identity and Constitution," Philosophical Studies 44 (1983): 45-59; J. M. Shorter, "On Coinciding in Space and Time," Philosophy 52 (1977): 399-408; Judith Jarvis Thomson, "Parthood and Identity Across Time," Journal of Philosophy 80 (1983): 201-20; Thomson, "The Statue and the Clay," Nous 32 (1998): 149-73; David Wiggins, "On Being in the Same Place at the Same Time," The Philosophical Review 77 (1968): 90-5. For application of this notion to the issue of human nature, see Lynne Rudder Baker, Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000); Kevin Corcoran, "Persons, Bodies, and the Constitution Relation," Southern Journal of Philosophy 37 (1999): 1-20.
    • (1968) The Philosophical Review , vol.77 , pp. 90-95
    • Wiggins, D.1
  • 41
    • 0003751914 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Aquinas's notion of composition without identity is similar to the contemporary notion of constitution without identity. For elucidation and defense of the latter notion, see Lynne Rudder Baker, "Why Constitution Is Not Identity," Journal of Philosophy 94 (1997): 599-621; Baker, "Unity Without Identity: A New Look at Material Constitution," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23, ed. Howard Wettstein (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 144-65; Frederick Doepke, "Spatially Coinciding Objects," Ratio 24 (1982): 45-60; Mark Johnston, "Constitution Is Not Identity," Mind 101 (1992): 89-105; E. J. Lowe, "Instantiation, Identity and Constitution," Philosophical Studies 44 (1983): 45-59; J. M. Shorter, "On Coinciding in Space and Time," Philosophy 52 (1977): 399-408; Judith Jarvis Thomson, "Parthood and Identity Across Time," Journal of Philosophy 80 (1983): 201-20; Thomson, "The Statue and the Clay," Nous 32 (1998): 149-73; David Wiggins, "On Being in the Same Place at the Same Time," The Philosophical Review 77 (1968): 90-5. For application of this notion to the issue of human nature, see Lynne Rudder Baker, Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000); Kevin Corcoran, "Persons, Bodies, and the Constitution Relation," Southern Journal of Philosophy 37 (1999): 1-20.
    • (2000) Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View
    • Baker, L.R.1
  • 42
    • 12144267276 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Persons, bodies, and the constitution relation
    • Aquinas's notion of composition without identity is similar to the contemporary notion of constitution without identity. For elucidation and defense of the latter notion, see Lynne Rudder Baker, "Why Constitution Is Not Identity," Journal of Philosophy 94 (1997): 599-621; Baker, "Unity Without Identity: A New Look at Material Constitution," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23, ed. Howard Wettstein (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 144-65; Frederick Doepke, "Spatially Coinciding Objects," Ratio 24 (1982): 45-60; Mark Johnston, "Constitution Is Not Identity," Mind 101 (1992): 89-105; E. J. Lowe, "Instantiation, Identity and Constitution," Philosophical Studies 44 (1983): 45-59; J. M. Shorter, "On Coinciding in Space and Time," Philosophy 52 (1977): 399-408; Judith Jarvis Thomson, "Parthood and Identity Across Time," Journal of Philosophy 80 (1983): 201-20; Thomson, "The Statue and the Clay," Nous 32 (1998): 149-73; David Wiggins, "On Being in the Same Place at the Same Time," The Philosophical Review 77 (1968): 90-5. For application of this notion to the issue of human nature, see Lynne Rudder Baker, Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000); Kevin Corcoran, "Persons, Bodies, and the Constitution Relation," Southern Journal of Philosophy 37 (1999): 1-20.
    • (1999) Southern Journal of Philosophy , vol.37 , pp. 1-20
    • Corcoran, K.1
  • 43
    • 12144250189 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 7, lect. 17
    • In M, bk. 7, lect. 17, 1674.
    • M , pp. 1674
  • 44
    • 9744284451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aquinas
    • q. un., a. 11, ad 20
    • See Aquinas, Quaestio disputata de spiritualibus creaturis (hereafter, "QDSC"), q. un., a. 11, ad 20. Referring to a human being's soul and body as parts requires a more extended notion of "part" than the standard conception of parts as integral to a substance, in the way a roof, walls, and floor are parts of a house. Such parts are composites of matter and form that exist even when they do not compose something else. Soul and body, on the other hand, can be understood as metaphysical parts that do not exist without composing a human being. For more on this distinction, see Eleonore Stump, Aquinas (New York: Routledge, 2003), 42, 209-10; Aquinas, Scriptum super sententiis magistri Petri Lombardi (hereafter, "In Sent"), bk. 2, dist. 3, q. 1, a. 4.
    • Quaestio Disputata de Spiritualibus Creaturis (Hereafter, "QDSC")
  • 45
    • 9744284451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Routledge
    • See Aquinas, Quaestio disputata de spiritualibus creaturis (hereafter, "QDSC"), q. un., a. 11, ad 20. Referring to a human being's soul and body as parts requires a more extended notion of "part" than the standard conception of parts as integral to a substance, in the way a roof, walls, and floor are parts of a house. Such parts are composites of matter and form that exist even when they do not compose something else. Soul and body, on the other hand, can be understood as metaphysical parts that do not exist without composing a human being. For more on this distinction, see Eleonore Stump, Aquinas (New York: Routledge, 2003), 42, 209-10; Aquinas, Scriptum super sententiis magistri Petri Lombardi (hereafter, "In Sent"), bk. 2, dist. 3, q. 1, a. 4.
    • (2003) Aquinas , vol.42 , pp. 209-210
    • Stump, E.1
  • 46
    • 9744284451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aquinas
    • bk. 2, dist. 3, q. 1, a. 4
    • See Aquinas, Quaestio disputata de spiritualibus creaturis (hereafter, "QDSC"), q. un., a. 11, ad 20. Referring to a human being's soul and body as parts requires a more extended notion of "part" than the standard conception of parts as integral to a substance, in the way a roof, walls, and floor are parts of a house. Such parts are composites of matter and form that exist even when they do not compose something else. Soul and body, on the other hand, can be understood as metaphysical parts that do not exist without composing a human being. For more on this distinction, see Eleonore Stump, Aquinas (New York: Routledge, 2003), 42, 209-10; Aquinas, Scriptum super sententiis magistri Petri Lombardi (hereafter, "In Sent"), bk. 2, dist. 3, q. 1, a. 4.
    • Scriptum Super Sententiis Magistri Petri Lombardi (Hereafter, "in Sent")
  • 47
    • 12144278650 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 2, chap. 50
    • SCG, bk. 2, chap. 50. Compare QDA, q. un., a. 6, ad 14.
    • SCG
  • 48
    • 12144251216 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. un., a. 6, ad 14
    • SCG, bk. 2, chap. 50. Compare QDA, q. un., a. 6, ad 14.
    • QDA
  • 49
    • 12144251610 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 77, aa. 5-8
    • See ST I, q. 77, aa. 5-8; QDA, q. un., a. 12, ad 16.
    • ST I
  • 50
    • 12144267278 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. un., a. 12, ad 16
    • See ST I, q. 77, aa. 5-8; QDA, q. un., a. 12, ad 16.
    • QDA
  • 51
    • 0009198524 scopus 로고
    • Non-cartesian substance dualism and materialism without reductionism
    • Eleonore Stump, "Non-Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism Without Reductionism," Faith and Philosophy 12 (1995): 512. See ST I, q. 75, a. 2, ad 2; ST I, q. 77, a. 5; DUI, chap. 4; In NE, bk. 10, lect. 6; QDSC, q. un., a. 2, ad 2; CT, chap. 85.
    • (1995) Faith and Philosophy , vol.12 , pp. 512
    • Stump, E.1
  • 52
    • 12144253173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 75, a. 2, ad 2
    • Eleonore Stump, "Non-Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism Without Reductionism," Faith and Philosophy 12 (1995): 512. See ST I, q. 75, a. 2, ad 2; ST I, q. 77, a. 5; DUI, chap. 4; In NE, bk. 10, lect. 6; QDSC, q. un., a. 2, ad 2; CT, chap. 85.
    • ST I
  • 53
    • 12144249818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 77, a. 5
    • Eleonore Stump, "Non-Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism Without Reductionism," Faith and Philosophy 12 (1995): 512. See ST I, q. 75, a. 2, ad 2; ST I, q. 77, a. 5; DUI, chap. 4; In NE, bk. 10, lect. 6; QDSC, q. un., a. 2, ad 2; CT, chap. 85.
    • ST I
  • 54
    • 12144269437 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 4; In NE, bk. 10, lect. 6
    • Eleonore Stump, "Non-Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism Without Reductionism," Faith and Philosophy 12 (1995): 512. See ST I, q. 75, a. 2, ad 2; ST I, q. 77, a. 5; DUI, chap. 4; In NE, bk. 10, lect. 6; QDSC, q. un., a. 2, ad 2; CT, chap. 85.
    • DUI
  • 55
    • 12144268228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. un., a. 2, ad 2
    • Eleonore Stump, "Non-Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism Without Reductionism," Faith and Philosophy 12 (1995): 512. See ST I, q. 75, a. 2, ad 2; ST I, q. 77, a. 5; DUI, chap. 4; In NE, bk. 10, lect. 6; QDSC, q. un., a. 2, ad 2; CT, chap. 85.
    • QDSC
  • 56
    • 12144266844 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 85
    • Eleonore Stump, "Non-Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism Without Reductionism," Faith and Philosophy 12 (1995): 512. See ST I, q. 75, a. 2, ad 2; ST I, q. 77, a. 5; DUI, chap. 4; In NE, bk. 10, lect. 6; QDSC, q. un., a. 2, ad 2; CT, chap. 85.
    • CT
  • 57
    • 12144273117 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 3
    • See DUI, chap. 3.
    • DUI
  • 58
    • 12144259257 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pasnau, Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature, 389. See ST II-II, q. 83, a. 11, ad 5; Aquinas, In Aristotelis libros de caelo et mundo, bk. 1, lect. 24.
    • Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature , vol.389
  • 59
    • 12144252792 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 83, a. 11, ad 5
    • Pasnau, Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature, 389. See ST II-II, q. 83, a. 11, ad 5; Aquinas, In Aristotelis libros de caelo et mundo, bk. 1, lect. 24.
    • ST , vol.2 , Issue.2
  • 60
    • 12144262651 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aquinas
    • bk. 1, lect. 24
    • Pasnau, Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature, 389. See ST II-II, q. 83, a. 11, ad 5; Aquinas, In Aristotelis libros de caelo et mundo, bk. 1, lect. 24.
    • Aristotelis Libros de Caelo et Mundo
  • 61
    • 84875355788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stump, Aquinas, 52-3. See ST, supp., q. 69, aa. 2-5; q. 70, aa. 2-3 ; q. 72, a. 2.
    • Aquinas , pp. 52-53
    • Stump1
  • 62
    • 12144259708 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 69, aa. 2-5
    • Stump, Aquinas, 52-3. See ST, supp., q. 69, aa. 2-5; q. 70, aa. 2-3 ; q. 72, a. 2.
    • ST , Issue.SUPPL.
  • 63
    • 12144284247 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 70, aa. 2-3
    • Stump, Aquinas, 52-3. See ST, supp., q. 69, aa. 2-5; q. 70, aa. 2-3 ; q. 72, a. 2.
  • 64
    • 12144260825 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 72, a. 2
    • Stump, Aquinas, 52-3. See ST, supp., q. 69, aa. 2-5; q. 70, aa. 2-3 ; q. 72, a. 2.
  • 66
  • 67
    • 12144280837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 77, a. 8
    • See ST I, q. 77, a. 8.
    • ST , vol.1
  • 68
    • 12144263667 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 1, dist. 8, q. 5, a. 2, ad 1
    • See In Sent, bk. 1, dist. 8, q. 5, a. 2, ad 1.
    • Sent
  • 69
    • 84860089637 scopus 로고
    • Aquinas
    • (Turin: Marietti), prop. 5
    • Aquinas, In librum de causis expositio (hereafter, "In LDC"), ed. Ceslao Pera (Turin: Marietti, 1955), prop. 5. Compare ST I, q. 90, a. 2; q. 118, a. 2; SCG, bk. 2, chaps. 87-8.
    • (1955) Librum de Causis Expositio (Hereafter, "in LDC")
    • Pera, C.1
  • 70
    • 12144273870 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 90, a. 2; q. 118, a. 2
    • Aquinas, In librum de causis expositio (hereafter, "In LDC"), ed. Ceslao Pera (Turin: Marietti, 1955), prop. 5. Compare ST I, q. 90, a. 2; q. 118, a. 2; SCG, bk. 2, chaps. 87-8.
    • ST I
  • 71
    • 12144262273 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 2, chaps. 87-8
    • Aquinas, In librum de causis expositio (hereafter, "In LDC"), ed. Ceslao Pera (Turin: Marietti, 1955), prop. 5. Compare ST I, q. 90, a. 2; q. 118, a. 2; SCG, bk. 2, chaps. 87-8.
    • SCG
  • 72
    • 12144265426 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 75, a. 6
    • See ST I, q. 75, a. 6; SCG, bk. 2, chaps. 79-81; Joseph Bobik, Aquinas on Being and Essence (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1965), 151-2.
    • ST I
  • 73
    • 12144285259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 2, chaps. 79-81
    • See ST I, q. 75, a. 6; SCG, bk. 2, chaps. 79-81; Joseph Bobik, Aquinas on Being and Essence (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1965), 151-2.
    • SCG
  • 74
    • 0041149286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press
    • See ST I, q. 75, a. 6; SCG, bk. 2, chaps. 79-81; Joseph Bobik, Aquinas on Being and Essence (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1965), 151-2.
    • (1965) Aquinas on Being and Essence , pp. 151-152
    • Bobik, J.1
  • 75
    • 84860081918 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Aquinas
    • q. 13, a. 4
    • Aquinas, Quaestiones disputatae de veritate (hereafter, "QDV"), q. 13, a. 4. Compare CT, chap. 84; ST I, q. 75, a. 6. In In LDC, prop. 15, Aquinas argues that a human soul's ability to know itself reflexively also requires that it be separable from its body.
    • Quaestiones Disputatae de Veritate (Hereafter, "QDV")
  • 76
    • 12144258852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 84
    • Aquinas, Quaestiones disputatae de veritate (hereafter, "QDV"), q. 13, a. 4. Compare CT, chap. 84; ST I, q. 75, a. 6. In In LDC, prop. 15, Aquinas argues that a human soul's ability to know itself reflexively also requires that it be separable from its body.
    • CT
  • 77
    • 12144276101 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 75, a. 6
    • Aquinas, Quaestiones disputatae de veritate (hereafter, "QDV"), q. 13, a. 4. Compare CT, chap. 84; ST I, q. 75, a. 6. In In LDC, prop. 15, Aquinas argues that a human soul's ability to know itself reflexively also requires that it be separable from its body.
    • ST , vol.1
  • 78
    • 12144274288 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • prop. 15, Aquinas argues that a human soul's ability to know itself reflexively also requires that it be separable from its body
    • Aquinas, Quaestiones disputatae de veritate (hereafter, "QDV"), q. 13, a. 4. Compare CT, chap. 84; ST I, q. 75, a. 6. In In LDC, prop. 15, Aquinas argues that a human soul's ability to know itself reflexively also requires that it be separable from its body.
    • LDC
  • 79
    • 12144259704 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. un., a. 1, ad 1
    • See QDA, q. un., a. 1, ad 1; Kevin White, "Aquinas on the Immediacy of the Union of Soul and Body," in Studies in Thomistic Theology, ed. Paul Lockey (Houston: Center for Thomistic Studies, 1995), 209-80.
    • QDA
  • 80
    • 12144250969 scopus 로고
    • Aquinas on the immediacy of the union of soul and body
    • ed. Paul Lockey (Houston: Center for Thomistic Studies)
    • See QDA, q. un., a. 1, ad 1; Kevin White, "Aquinas on the Immediacy of the Union of Soul and Body," in Studies in Thomistic Theology, ed. Paul Lockey (Houston: Center for Thomistic Studies, 1995), 209-80.
    • (1995) Studies in Thomistic Theology , pp. 209-280
    • White, K.1
  • 81
    • 12144266436 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Phantasms are not simply our ordinary sensory images. Rather, phantasms are the leftover impressions from those sensory images
    • The term phantasmata, transliterated as phantasms, is sometimes translated as sense impressions or sensory images. Such translations, however, are problematic. As Pasnau describes it, "phantasms are not simply our ordinary sensory images. Rather, phantasms are the leftover impressions from those sensory images" (Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature, 279; see 278-95). Norman Kretzmann describes them as "cognitive likenesses of particular external things reinstated in physical configurations of the organ of phantasia [that is, the brain]" (The Metaphysics of Creation, 355; see 350-64). The purpose of phantasms is to be available for the intellect to use in abstracting the intelligible form of perceived things. Hence, phantasms are between the immediate mental impression of an object perceived by sensation and the intellectual understanding of that object's nature as abstracted from any individuating characteristics.
    • Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature , vol.279 , pp. 278-295
  • 82
    • 12144260823 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cognitive likenesses of particular external things reinstated in physical configurations of the organ of phantasia [that is, the brain]
    • The term phantasmata, transliterated as phantasms, is sometimes translated as sense impressions or sensory images. Such translations, however, are problematic. As Pasnau describes it, "phantasms are not simply our ordinary sensory images. Rather, phantasms are the leftover impressions from those sensory images" (Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature, 279; see 278-95). Norman Kretzmann describes them as "cognitive likenesses of particular external things reinstated in physical configurations of the organ of phantasia [that is, the brain]" (The Metaphysics of Creation, 355; see 350-64). The purpose of phantasms is to be available for the intellect to use in abstracting the intelligible form of perceived things. Hence, phantasms are between the immediate mental impression of an object perceived by sensation and the intellectual understanding of that object's nature as abstracted from any individuating characteristics.
    • The Metaphysics of Creation , vol.355 , pp. 350-364
  • 83
    • 12144274287 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. un., a. 2; ST I, q. 101, a. 2
    • See QDA, q. un., a. 2; ST I, q. 101, a. 2.
    • QDA
  • 84
    • 12144264241 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. un., a. 3, ad 16
    • See QDA, q. un., a. 3, ad 16.
    • QDA
  • 85
    • 12144258443 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 2, chap. 76; In DA, bk. 3, lect. 7
    • See SCG, bk. 2, chap. 76; In DA, bk. 3, lect. 7; QDA, q. un., a. 4, ad 8; DUI, chaps. 2, 4.
    • SCG
  • 86
    • 12144264662 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. un., a. 4, ad 8
    • See SCG, bk. 2, chap. 76; In DA, bk. 3, lect. 7; QDA, q. un., a. 4, ad 8; DUI, chaps. 2, 4.
    • QDA
  • 87
    • 12144281582 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chaps. 2, 4
    • See SCG, bk. 2, chap. 76; In DA, bk. 3, lect. 7; QDA, q. un., a. 4, ad 8; DUI, chaps. 2, 4.
    • DUI
  • 88
    • 12144267275 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. un., a. 11, ad 14
    • See QDSC, q. un., a. 11, ad 14; In DA, bk. 2, lect. 2; SCG, bk. 2, chap. 68; ST I, q. 76, a. 1. Note that to speak of a human soul as having capacities means only that it is the foundation, that is, the actualizing principle, for such capacities; as discussed above, the human being composed of a human soul is the proper subject of ascription for the vegetative, sensitive, and intellective capacities proper to human nature.
    • QDSC
  • 89
    • 12144264052 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 2, lect. 2
    • See QDSC, q. un., a. 11, ad 14; In DA, bk. 2, lect. 2; SCG, bk. 2, chap. 68; ST I, q. 76, a. 1. Note that to speak of a human soul as having capacities means only that it is the foundation, that is, the actualizing principle, for such capacities; as discussed above, the human being composed of a human soul is the proper subject of ascription for the vegetative, sensitive, and intellective capacities proper to human nature.
    • DA
  • 90
    • 12144277925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 2, chap. 68
    • See QDSC, q. un., a. 11, ad 14; In DA, bk. 2, lect. 2; SCG, bk. 2, chap. 68; ST I, q. 76, a. 1. Note that to speak of a human soul as having capacities means only that it is the foundation, that is, the actualizing principle, for such capacities; as discussed above, the human being composed of a human soul is the proper subject of ascription for the vegetative, sensitive, and intellective capacities proper to human nature.
    • SCG
  • 91
    • 12144250188 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 76, a. 1. Note that to speak of a human soul as having capacities means only that it is the foundation, that is, the actualizing principle, for such capacities; as discussed above, the human being composed of a human soul is the proper subject of ascription for the vegetative, sensitive, and intellective capacities proper to human nature.
    • See QDSC, q. un., a. 11, ad 14; In DA, bk. 2, lect. 2; SCG, bk. 2, chap. 68; ST I, q. 76, a. 1. Note that to speak of a human soul as having capacities means only that it is the foundation, that is, the actualizing principle, for such capacities; as discussed above, the human being composed of a human soul is the proper subject of ascription for the vegetative, sensitive, and intellective capacities proper to human nature.
    • ST I
  • 92
    • 12144284847 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. un., a. 8, ad 15
    • QDA, q. un., a. 8, ad 15. Compare QDA, q. un., a. 10, ad 1-2; In DA, bk. 2, lects. 1, 19; ST I, q. 76, a. 5, ad 3; q. 91, a. 3.
    • QDA
  • 93
    • 12144281583 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. un., a. 10, ad 1-2
    • QDA, q. un., a. 8, ad 15. Compare QDA, q. un., a. 10, ad 1-2; In DA, bk. 2, lects. 1, 19; ST I, q. 76, a. 5, ad 3; q. 91, a. 3.
    • QDA
  • 94
    • 12144249423 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 2, lects. 1, 19
    • QDA, q. un., a. 8, ad 15. Compare QDA, q. un., a. 10, ad 1-2; In DA, bk. 2, lects. 1, 19; ST I, q. 76, a. 5, ad 3; q. 91, a. 3.
    • DA
  • 95
    • 12144281211 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 76, a. 5, ad 3
    • QDA, q. un., a. 8, ad 15. Compare QDA, q. un., a. 10, ad 1-2; In DA, bk. 2, lects. 1, 19; ST I, q. 76, a. 5, ad 3; q. 91, a. 3.
    • ST I
  • 96
    • 12144281985 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 91, a. 3
    • QDA, q. un., a. 8, ad 15. Compare QDA, q. un., a. 10, ad 1-2; In DA, bk. 2, lects. 1, 19; ST I, q. 76, a. 5, ad 3; q. 91, a. 3.
  • 98
    • 12144276899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • By these examples, I am not asserting that a human soul has these qualities in itself; rather, a human soul has these qualities by its capacity to actualize a material body to have them.
  • 99
    • 12144276514 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 90, a. 4, ad 1
    • ST I, q. 90, a. 4, ad 1. Compare SCG, bk. 2, chap. 83.
    • ST I
  • 100
    • 12144257434 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 2, chap. 83
    • ST I, q. 90, a. 4, ad 1. Compare SCG, bk. 2, chap. 83.
    • SCG
  • 101
    • 84860077030 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 76, a. l, ad 6. I specifically use the definite article - "the" body - in my translation, because it is not to any body with which a separated soul has a natural inclination to be united, but to that particular body of which it is the substantial form
    • ST I, q. 76, a. l, ad 6. I specifically use the definite article - "the" body - in my translation, because it is not to any body with which a separated soul has a natural inclination to be united, but to that particular body of which it is the substantial form. See my "The Metaphysics of Resurrection: Issues of Identity in Thomas Aquinas," American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 74, supp. (2000): 215-30.
    • ST I
  • 102
    • 12144265035 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The metaphysics of resurrection: Issues of identity in thomas aquinas
    • ST I, q. 76, a. l, ad 6. I specifically use the definite article - "the" body - in my translation, because it is not to any body with which a separated soul has a natural inclination to be united, but to that particular body of which it is the substantial form. See my "The Metaphysics of Resurrection: Issues of Identity in Thomas Aquinas," American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 74, supp. (2000): 215-30.
    • (2000) American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly , vol.74 , Issue.SUPPL. , pp. 215-230
  • 103
    • 12144258850 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. un., a. 2, ad 5
    • QDSC, q. un., a. 2, ad 5. Compare Aquinas, Quaestiones disputatae de potentia dei (hereafter, "QDP") q. 5, a. 10; ST supp., q. 93, a. 1.
    • QDSC
  • 105
    • 12144272037 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 75, a. 4, ad 2
    • ST I, q. 75, a. 4, ad 2. Compare ST I, q. 29, a. l, ad 5.
    • ST I
  • 106
    • 12144279441 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 29, a. l, ad 5
    • ST I, q. 75, a. 4, ad 2. Compare ST I, q. 29, a. l, ad 5.
    • ST I
  • 107
    • 62449318809 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This is especially true in the early treatise De ente et essentia.
    • De Ente et Essentia
  • 108
    • 12144273485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Subsistent in a rational nature
    • q. 29, a. 3
    • A subsistent being cannot be an accidental quality of a substance. It subsists on its own. Aquinas highlights this quality of persons in an alternative definition he gives: "subsistent in a rational nature" (ST I, q. 29, a. 3).
    • ST I
  • 109
    • 12144250972 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 75, a. 2, ad 1
    • ST I, q. 75, a. 2, ad 1. Compare QDSC, q. un., a. 2, ad 16; QDP, q. 9, a. 1, ad 4; QDA, q. un., a. 1, ad 4; In DA, bk. 2, lect. 1. See Stump, "Non-Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism Without Reductionism," 517.
    • ST , vol.1
  • 110
    • 12144270262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. un., a. 2, ad 16
    • ST I, q. 75, a. 2, ad 1. Compare QDSC, q. un., a. 2, ad 16; QDP, q. 9, a. 1, ad 4; QDA, q. un., a. 1, ad 4; In DA, bk. 2, lect. 1. See Stump, "Non-Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism Without Reductionism," 517.
    • QDSC
  • 111
    • 12144280834 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 9, a. 1, ad 4
    • ST I, q. 75, a. 2, ad 1. Compare QDSC, q. un., a. 2, ad 16; QDP, q. 9, a. 1, ad 4; QDA, q. un., a. 1, ad 4; In DA, bk. 2, lect. 1. See Stump, "Non-Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism Without Reductionism," 517.
    • QDP
  • 112
    • 12144265821 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. un., a. 1, ad 4
    • ST I, q. 75, a. 2, ad 1. Compare QDSC, q. un., a. 2, ad 16; QDP, q. 9, a. 1, ad 4; QDA, q. un., a. 1, ad 4; In DA, bk. 2, lect. 1. See Stump, "Non-Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism Without Reductionism," 517.
    • QDA
  • 113
    • 12144273483 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 2, lect. 1.
    • ST I, q. 75, a. 2, ad 1. Compare QDSC, q. un., a. 2, ad 16; QDP, q. 9, a. 1, ad 4; QDA, q. un., a. 1, ad 4; In DA, bk. 2, lect. 1. See Stump, "Non-Cartesian Substance Dualism and Materialism Without Reductionism," 517.
    • DA
  • 115
    • 12144271252 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 75, a. 2, sed contra
    • See ST I, q. 75, a. 2, sed contra.
    • ST , vol.1
  • 116
    • 12144258445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 5, lect. 10, 905
    • In M, bk. 5, lect. 10, 905.
    • M
  • 117
    • 12144272827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 2
    • DEE, chap. 2. See Bobik, Aquinas on Being and Essence, 75-80.
    • DEE
  • 119
    • 12144270263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 2, a. 6, ad 1; q. 10, a. 5
    • Compare QDV, q. 2, a. 6, ad 1; q. 10, a. 5.
    • QDV
  • 120
    • 85046642871 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press
    • In translating dimensiones interminatis thus, I disagree with John Wippel, who offers the translation "indeterminate dimensions." Wippel's translation creates a tension in Aquinas's thought, if not an outright contradiction, that I contend is not present. See John Wippel, The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas: From Finite Being to Uncreated Being (Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 2000), 358, 362.
    • (2000) The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas: From Finite Being to Uncreated Being , pp. 358
    • Wippel, J.1
  • 121
    • 12144252372 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 4, a. 2 (emphasis added)
    • In BDT, q. 4, a. 2 (emphasis added).
    • BDT
  • 124
    • 12144270655 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 76, a. 6, ad 2. Compare QDP, q. 9, a. 1
    • ST I, q. 76, a. 6, ad 2. Compare QDP, q. 9, a. 1.
    • ST I
  • 125
    • 12144275657 scopus 로고
    • Thomas aquinas: Dimensive quantity as individuating principle
    • Joseph Owens, "Thomas Aquinas: Dimensive Quantity as Individuating Principle," Mediaeval Studies 50 (1988): 289.
    • (1988) Mediaeval Studies , vol.50 , pp. 289
    • Owens, J.1
  • 126
    • 12144261866 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 5, a. 3, ad 3
    • In BDT, q. 5, a. 3, ad 3.
    • BDT
  • 127
    • 12144251605 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 4, a. 2, sed contra
    • Both quotations are from In BDT, q. 4, a. 2, sed contra.
    • BDT
  • 128
    • 84860083593 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 4, a. 3. Compare Aquinas, Quaestiones quodlibetales (hereafter, "QQ") 7, q. 4, a. 3; QQ 9, q. 6, a. 1; ST supp., q. 83, aa. 2-3
    • In BDT, q. 4, a. 3. Compare Aquinas, Quaestiones quodlibetales (hereafter, "QQ") 7, q. 4, a. 3; QQ 9, q. 6, a. 1; ST supp., q. 83, aa. 2-3.
    • BDT
  • 129
    • 12144275656 scopus 로고
    • Individuation in aquinas's super boetium de trinitate, Q. 4
    • See Kevin White, "Individuation in Aquinas's Super Boetium De Trinitate, Q. 4," American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 69 (1995): 553-5. Compare Roderick Chisholm, "Individuation: Some Thomistic Questions and Answers," Grazer Philosophische Studien l (1975): 38; Wippel, The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas, 363.
    • (1995) American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly , vol.69 , pp. 553-555
    • White, K.1
  • 130
    • 12144257065 scopus 로고
    • Individuation: Some thomistic questions and answers
    • Compare Roderick Chisholm
    • See Kevin White, "Individuation in Aquinas's Super Boetium De Trinitate, Q. 4," American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 69 (1995): 553-5. Compare Roderick Chisholm, "Individuation: Some Thomistic Questions and Answers," Grazer Philosophische Studien l (1975): 38; Wippel, The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas, 363.
    • (1975) Grazer Philosophische Studien , vol.50 , pp. 38
  • 131
    • 85046642871 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Kevin White, "Individuation in Aquinas's Super Boetium De Trinitate, Q. 4," American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 69 (1995): 553-5. Compare Roderick Chisholm, "Individuation: Some Thomistic Questions and Answers," Grazer Philosophische Studien l (1975): 38; Wippel, The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas, 363.
    • The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas , pp. 363
    • Wippel1
  • 132
    • 12144273869 scopus 로고
    • Thomas aquinas (B. CA. 1225; D. 1274)
    • ed. Jorge J. E. Gracia (Albany: State University of New York Press)
    • One point of debate concerns the cause of individuation for human beings. Joseph Owens argues that the esse possessed by a human soul that is created individually by God is responsible for the individuated existence of a human being. Lawrence Dewan counters that esse is not a causal factor of individuation, but that the combination of formal, material, and efficient causes brings about both a human being's existence and his existence as an individual substance. See Joseph Owens, "Thomas Aquinas (B. CA. 1225; D. 1274)," in Individuation in Scholasticism: The Latter Middle Ages and the Counter Reformation, 1150-1650, ed. Jorge J. E. Gracia (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1994), 173-94; Lawrence Dewan, "The Individual as a Mode of Being According to Thomas Aquinas," The Thomist 63 (1999): 403-24. Space does not permit me to address this debate here.
    • (1994) Individuation in Scholasticism: The Latter middle Ages and the Counter Reformation, 1150-1650 , pp. 173-194
    • Owens, J.1
  • 133
    • 12144282637 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Individual as a mode of being according to thomas aquinas
    • One point of debate concerns the cause of individuation for human beings. Joseph Owens argues that the esse possessed by a human soul that is created individually by God is responsible for the individuated existence of a human being. Lawrence Dewan counters that esse is not a causal factor of individuation, but that the combination of formal, material, and efficient causes brings about both a human being's existence and his existence as an individual substance. See Joseph Owens, "Thomas Aquinas (B. CA. 1225; D. 1274)," in Individuation in Scholasticism: The Latter Middle Ages and the Counter Reformation, 1150-1650, ed. Jorge J. E. Gracia (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1994), 173-94; Lawrence Dewan, "The Individual as a Mode of Being According to Thomas Aquinas," The Thomist 63 (1999): 403-24. Space does not permit me to address this debate here.
    • (1999) The Thomist , vol.63 , pp. 403-424
    • Dewan, L.1
  • 134
    • 12144255796 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 2, chap.
    • SCG, bk. 2, chap. 80.
    • SCG , pp. 80
  • 135
    • 12144261867 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • ST I, q. 76, a. 2, ad 2. Compare bk. 8, dist. l, q. 5, a. 2, ad 6
    • ST I, q. 76, a. 2, ad 2. Compare In Sent, bk. 8, dist. l, q. 5, a. 2, ad 6; DEE, chap. 5; QDA, q. un., a. l, ad 2; QDSC, q. un., a. 9, ad 3.
    • Sent
  • 136
    • 12144269873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 5
    • ST I, q. 76, a. 2, ad 2. Compare In Sent, bk. 8, dist. l, q. 5, a. 2, ad 6; DEE, chap. 5; QDA, q. un., a. l, ad 2; QDSC, q. un., a. 9, ad 3.
    • DEE
  • 137
    • 12144250576 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. un., a. l, ad 2; QDSC, q. un., a. 9, ad 3
    • ST I, q. 76, a. 2, ad 2. Compare In Sent, bk. 8, dist. l, q. 5, a. 2, ad 6; DEE, chap. 5; QDA, q. un., a. l, ad 2; QDSC, q. un., a. 9, ad 3.
    • QDA
  • 138
    • 12144253619 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. un., a. 9, ad 4. Compare QDSC, q. un., a. 9, ad 15
    • QDSC, q. un., a. 9, ad 4. Compare QDSC, q. un., a. 9, ad 15; QDA, q. un., a. l, ad 10; ST I, q. 76, a. l, ad 6.
    • QDSC
  • 139
    • 12144250577 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. un., a. l, ad 10
    • QDSC, q. un., a. 9, ad 4. Compare QDSC, q. un., a. 9, ad 15; QDA, q. un., a. l, ad 10; ST I, q. 76, a. l, ad 6.
    • QDA
  • 140
    • 12144264057 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 76, a. l, ad 6
    • QDSC, q. un., a. 9, ad 4. Compare QDSC, q. un., a. 9, ad 15; QDA, q. un., a. l, ad 10; ST I, q. 76, a. l, ad 6.
    • ST I
  • 142
    • 12144283016 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • italics Stump's. Compare W. Norris Clarke, The One and the Many: A Contemporary Thomistic Metaphysics (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press)
    • Stump, Aquinas, 54, italics Stump's. Compare W. Norris Clarke, The One and the Many: A Contemporary Thomistic Metaphysics (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 2001), 105; Pasnau, Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature, 182-5.
    • (2001) Aquinas , vol.54 , pp. 105
    • Stump1
  • 143
    • 12144261054 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Stump, Aquinas, 54, italics Stump's. Compare W. Norris Clarke, The One and the Many: A Contemporary Thomistic Metaphysics (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 2001), 105; Pasnau, Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature, 182-5.
    • Thomas Aquinas on Human Nature , pp. 182-185
    • Pasnau1
  • 145
  • 146
    • 12144279440 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 4, chap. 81
    • SCG, bk. 4, chap. 81.
    • SCG
  • 147
    • 12144261485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 119, a. 1, ad 5
    • ST I, q. 119, a. 1, ad 5.
    • ST I
  • 148
    • 0014307594 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 119, a. 1, ad 1; CT, chap. 159
    • See ST I, q. 119, a. 1, ad 1; CT, chap. 159; John Chandlish, "St. Thomas and the Dynamic State of Body Constituents," Journal of the History of Medicine and Applied Sciences 23 (1968): 272-5. Though Aquinas did not have the scientific resources to recognize the existence of cells as constituents of living bodies, he did understand that living bodies decay, that is, lose some material constituents, and are rejuvenated through nutrition, that is, gain new material constituents by digesting food.
    • ST I
  • 149
    • 0014307594 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • St. Thomas and the dynamic state of body constituents
    • See ST I, q. 119, a. 1, ad 1; CT, chap. 159; John Chandlish, "St. Thomas and the Dynamic State of Body Constituents," Journal of the History of Medicine and Applied Sciences 23 (1968): 272-5. Though Aquinas did not have the scientific resources to recognize the existence of cells as constituents of living bodies, he did understand that living bodies decay, that is, lose some material constituents, and are rejuvenated through nutrition, that is, gain new material constituents by digesting food.
    • (1968) Journal of the History of Medicine and Applied Sciences , vol.23 , pp. 272-275
    • Chandlish, J.1
  • 153
    • 12144273114 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I will not discuss how significant a material change must be in order for a formal change to occur in an artifact. At one end of the spectrum, a statue of a man may have one of its arms chopped off by vandals and yet remain the same statue. At the other end of the spectrum, a statue may be chopped into a thousand or more pieces by vandals and thereby cease to exist.
  • 154
    • 12144271253 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am utilizing this term to refer to a material substance that occurs in nature, as opposed to an artifact. I am not referring to any created substance, which would include angels who are not material.
  • 155
    • 12144281988 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 79, a. 2, ad 4
    • ST supp., q. 79, a. 2, ad 4.
    • ST Supp.
  • 156
    • 12144261486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See q. 79, a. 2, ad 1
    • See ST supp., q. 79, a. 2, ad 1.
    • ST Supp.
  • 157
    • 12144259707 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 4, chap. 84
    • SCG, bk. 4, chap. 84.
    • SCG
  • 158
    • 12144280836 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 4, chap. 80
    • See SCG, bk. 4, chap. 80
    • SCG
  • 159
    • 12144269036 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • CT, chap. 153
    • CT, chap. 153.
  • 160
    • 12144258447 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 79, a. 2
    • ST supp., q. 79, a. 2.
    • ST Supp.
  • 161
    • 12144272828 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • CT, chap. 154. Compare bk. 4, chap. 81
    • CT, chap. 154. Compare SCG, bk. 4, chap. 81.
    • SCG
  • 162
    • 12144283410 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • bk. 4, chap. 81
    • SCG, bk. 4, chap. 81.
    • SCG
  • 163
    • 12144249426 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In certain passages, such as CT, chap. 154 and ST supp., q. 79, a. 1, ad 3, Aquinas appears to hold the opposite view that the exact same material constituents that composed a human being's body prior to death must compose his resurrected body. However, in CT, chap. 154 and ST supp., q. 80, a. 5, sed contra, Aquinas makes contrary assertions in agreement with the view I outline here. For reasons why I think Aquinas does better to hold the view that any material constituent can compose a human being's resurrected body, see Eberl, "The Metaphysics of Resurrection: Issues of Identity in Thomas Aquinas," 219-22.
    • The Metaphysics of Resurrection: Issues of Identity in Thomas Aquinas , pp. 219-222
    • Eberl1
  • 166
    • 12144271628 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The term "mind" does not precisely correspond to Aquinas's term "intellect." As will be shown, the mind includes certain capacities, such as the estimative capacity, that are distinct from the intellective capacity to understand universal concepts. Thus, the intellect is but one capacity of the mind. Contemporary philosophers, though, often understand the concept of mind in a fashion similar to Aquinas's concept of intellect and thus I propose the above substitution of terms.
  • 167
    • 12144255006 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • There may be many other qualities of a human mind that are also irreducible to the functioning of the brain, but I simply list here two of the most obvious examples that are cited in Aquinas's account as given above.
  • 168
    • 12144281987 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 78, a. 4. That Aquinas recognizes such a cognitive function to be a function of the brain fits with his mechanistic understanding of non-human animals as determined. Animals have the cognitive capacity to recognize goods versus harms, and they must act based upon such recognition. If an animal recognizes something as good, the animal must move toward it. An animal's brain is the origin of motivation for its body. Human beings share the estimative capacity, and it too is localized in the brain. Nevertheless, human beings are not determined by it due to their having higher cognitive capacities that are not defined by what physically occurs in the brain. Human beings are free
    • See ST I, q. 78, a. 4. That Aquinas recognizes such a cognitive function to be a function of the brain fits with his mechanistic understanding of non-human animals as determined. Animals have the cognitive capacity to recognize goods versus harms, and they must act based upon such recognition. If an animal recognizes something as good, the animal must move toward it. An animal's brain is the origin of motivation for its body. Human beings share the estimative capacity, and it too is localized in the brain. Nevertheless, human beings are not determined by it due to their having higher cognitive capacities that are not defined by what physically occurs in the brain. Human beings are free.
    • ST I
  • 169
    • 12144249425 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 84, a. 3. Aquinas recognizes that a human mind may gain knowledge by other means. God may directly infuse knowledge into it, similar to Augustine's account of divine illumination, and it can gain insight and new knowledge by reaching conclusions through discursive reasoning. However, the former is not a natural means of a human mind's acquisition of knowledge, and Aquinas employs it only for the sake of explaining how a separated human soul can gain new knowledge. The latter is part of a human mind's natural intellective processes but is dependent upon sense experience for the formation of the concepts utilized in discursive reasoning
    • See ST I, q. 84, a. 3. Aquinas recognizes that a human mind may gain knowledge by other means. God may directly infuse knowledge into it, similar to Augustine's account of divine illumination, and it can gain insight and new knowledge by reaching conclusions through discursive reasoning. However, the former is not a natural means of a human mind's acquisition of knowledge, and Aquinas employs it only for the sake of explaining how a separated human soul can gain new knowledge. The latter is part of a human mind's natural intellective processes but is dependent upon sense experience for the formation of the concepts utilized in discursive reasoning.
    • ST I
  • 170
    • 12144265036 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 76, a. 5
    • See ST I, q. 76, a. 5; q. 84, a. 7.
    • ST I
  • 171
    • 12144265037 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • q. 84, a. 7
    • See ST I, q. 76, a. 5; q. 84, a. 7.
  • 172
    • 12144277294 scopus 로고
    • On the simplicity of the soul
    • ed. James Tomberlin (Oxford: Blackwell)
    • For a similar assertion, referring to the relationship of a human being and his brain, see Roderick Chisholm, "On the Simplicity of the Soul," in Philosophical Perspectives 5, ed. James Tomberlin (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991), 171.
    • (1991) Philosophical Perspectives , vol.5 , pp. 171
    • Chisholm, R.1
  • 173
    • 0004115597 scopus 로고
    • Ithaca: Cornell University Press
    • As Peter van Inwagen puts it, such things cannot be proper parts of a human body, because they are not "caught up in [its] life." See Peter van Inwagen, Material Beings (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1990), 94.
    • (1990) Material Beings , pp. 94
    • Van Inwagen, P.1
  • 174
    • 12144262648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Things and their parts
    • ed. Howard Wettstein (Oxford: Blackwell)
    • Kit Fine, "Things and Their Parts," in Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23, ed. Howard Wettstein (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999), 65.
    • (1999) Midwest Studies in Philosophy , vol.23 , pp. 65
    • Fine, K.1
  • 176
    • 12144262649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Fing postulates the following identity criterion for rigid embodiments: "The rigid embodiments a, b, c, . . . /R and a,' b,' c,' . . . /R' are the same iff the state of a, b, c, . . . standing in the relation R is the same as that of a,' b,' c,' . . . standing in the relation R'" (ibid., 66).
  • 177
    • 12144250974 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am most indebted to Eleonore Stump, John Kavanaugh, S.J., and Theodore Vitali, C.P. for invaluable comments and helpful discussions throughout the development of this paper, and to Michael Burke for his review of the latest draft. Research for this paper began while I participated in an exchange program between Saint Louis University and the Johann Wolfgang Goethe Universität in Frankfurt am Main, Germany. I am grateful to the Philosophisch-Theologische Hochschule Sankt Georgen for their hospitality, Matthias Lutz-Bachmann for his comments and an invitation to present an early draft of this paper in his graduate colloquium, and to Andreas Niederberger and Stephanie Vesper for helpful discussions. I completed this paper while visiting the Center for Philosophy of Religion at the University of Notre Dame. I wish to thank the members of the Center's weekly reading group, particularly Brian Leftow, Fred Crosson, Michael Rea, Thomas Flint, and Michael Rota for their insightful suggestions. Finally, portions of this paper benefited from being presented at the 2003 Central Division Meeting of the American Philosophical Association and the 38th International Congress on Medieval Studies at Western Michigan University. My gratitude to the audience members at each conference, and in particular to James South for his delivered commentary at the APA.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.