메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 23, Issue 1, 1999, Pages 144-165

Unity without identity: A new look at material constitution

(1)  Baker, Lynne Rudder a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 12144282642     PISSN: 03636550     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1111/1475-4975.00008     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (54)

References (31)
  • 1
    • 0004279749 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Basil Blackwell
    • For recent debate, see, for example, David Wiggins in Sameness and Substance (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1980).
    • (1980) Sameness and Substance
    • Wiggins, D.1
  • 2
    • 12144265038 scopus 로고
    • Constitution Is Not Identity
    • Also
    • Also, see Mark Johnston, "Constitution Is Not Identity," Mind 101 (1992): 89-105.
    • (1992) Mind , vol.101 , pp. 89-105
    • Johnston, M.1
  • 3
    • 0007704274 scopus 로고
    • Counterparts and Their Bodies
    • Johnston was responding to the recent work on "contingent identity" by, e.g., David Lewis, "Counterparts and Their Bodies," Journal of Philosophy 68 (1971): 203-11;
    • (1971) Journal of Philosophy , vol.68 , pp. 203-211
    • Lewis, D.1
  • 6
    • 17444365567 scopus 로고
    • Re-Identifying Matter
    • and Denis Robinson, "Re-Identifying Matter," Philosophical Review 81 (1982): 317-42.
    • (1982) Philosophical Review , vol.81 , pp. 317-342
    • Robinson, D.1
  • 7
    • 33644923678 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield
    • For an excellent collection of articles espousing different answers to the question, see Material Constitution: A Reader, Michael Rea, ed. (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1997).
    • (1997) Material Constitution: A Reader
    • Rea, M.1
  • 8
    • 79953961189 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • and Sydney Shoemaker in Identity, Cause and Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986) - have proposed that persons and bodies are related in a way similar to what I am calling "constitution." I see as kindred spirits all who construe the relation as a kind of composition without identity.
    • (1986) Sydney Shoemaker in Identity, Cause and Mind
  • 9
    • 84922067391 scopus 로고
    • Copper Statues and Pieces of Copper: A Challenge to the Standard Account
    • Michael B. Burke, "Copper Statues and Pieces of Copper: A Challenge to the Standard Account," Analysis 52 (1992): 12-17.
    • (1992) Analysis , vol.52 , pp. 12-17
    • Burke, M.B.1
  • 10
    • 53249092571 scopus 로고
    • Essence, and Indiscernibility
    • See his "Identity, Essence, and Indiscernibility," Journal of Philosophy 84 (1987): 293-314. Many who use the term "contingent identity" do distinguish that relation from genuine identity, which is construed (rightly, I think) as a necessary relation. I think that it is misleading to insist that "contingent identity" names a relation that is not identity.
    • (1987) Journal of Philosophy , vol.84 , pp. 293-314
  • 11
    • 77951034188 scopus 로고
    • Postscripts to 'Survival and Identity
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Denial of the identity of the statue and the piece of marble does not by itself commit one to constitution. An alternative to constitution is to construe objects as four-dimensional space-time worms that have temporal parts; then, although the statue and the piece of marble are not identical, they have current temporal "stages" that are identical. I cannot discuss this alternative here. See David Lewis, "Postscripts to 'Survival and Identity,'" in Philosophical Papers, Vol. I (New York: Oxford University Press, 1983): 76-77.
    • (1983) Philosophical Papers , pp. 76-77
    • Lewis, D.1
  • 12
    • 0009330626 scopus 로고
    • Parthood and Identity across Time
    • For a critique of the temporal-parts view, see Judith Jarvis Thomson, "Parthood and Identity across Time," Journal of Philosophy 80 (1983): 201-20.
    • (1983) Journal of Philosophy , vol.80 , pp. 201-220
    • Jarvis Thomson, J.1
  • 13
    • 12144255400 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Why Constitution Is Not Identity
    • I am assuming that the piece of marble that now constitutes David is the same piece of marble as one of a different shape that was once in a quarry. If you think that shape is essential to pieces of marble, then change the example to the one I used in "Why Constitution Is Not Identity," in which the statue Discobolus comes into existence at the same time as the piece of bronze that constitutes it. See my "Why Constitution Is Not Identity," Journal of Philosophy 94 (1997): 599-621.
    • (1997) Journal of Philosophy , vol.94 , pp. 599-621
  • 14
    • 1142272761 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Blackwell
    • According to Robert C. Sleigh, Jr., Leibniz meant his "law" to be understood like this: "if individual x is distinct from individual y then there is some intrinsic, non-relational property F that x has and y lacks, or vice versa" ("Identity of Indiscernibles," in A Companion to Metaphysics, Jaegwon Kim and Ernest Sosa, eds. [Oxford: Blackwell, 1995]: 234).
    • (1995) A Companion to Metaphysics , pp. 234
    • Kim, J.1    Sosa, E.2
  • 15
    • 34250171320 scopus 로고
    • Harold Noonan aims to rebut Johnston in Constitution Is Identity
    • This consideration leads straight to a counterexample to the conviction that "if y is a paradigm F and x is intrinsically exactly like y, then x is an F." Using sophisticated metaphysical arguments, Mark Johnston aims to undermine this principle in "Constitution Is Not Identity"; Harold Noonan aims to rebut Johnston in "Constitution Is Identity," Mind 102 (1993): 133-46.
    • (1993) Mind , vol.102 , pp. 133-146
  • 16
    • 79952057191 scopus 로고
    • Modalities and Intensional Languages
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Cf. Ruth Barcan Marcus, "Modalities and Intensional Languages," in Modalities: Philosophical Essays (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993): 3-23, first published in Synthese 13 (1961): 303-22. So I don't take what is called "contingent identity" to be identity; and I'm unsure whether what is called "relative identity" is coherent. In any case, I am not committed to relative identity.
    • (1993) Modalities: Philosophical Essays , pp. 3-23
    • Marcus, R.B.1
  • 17
    • 61049498855 scopus 로고
    • Identity
    • For a defense of relative identity, see Peter Geach, "Identity, " in Logic Matters (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1972): 238-49.
    • (1972) Logic Matters , pp. 238-249
    • Geach, P.1
  • 18
    • 0010836407 scopus 로고
    • The Same F
    • For criticisms of relative identity, see John Perry, "The Same F," Philosophical Review 79 (1970): 181-200,
    • (1970) Philosophical Review , vol.79 , pp. 181-200
    • Perry, J.1
  • 19
    • 79954392588 scopus 로고
    • Milton K. Munitz, ed. (New York: New York University
    • Saul A. Kripke, "Identity and Necessity," in Identity and Individuation, Milton K. Munitz, ed. (New York: New York University, 1971): 137. Kripke continues: "And this is so even if the property F is itself of the form of necessarily having some other property G, in particular that of necessarily being identical to a certain object."
    • (1971) Identity and Necessity, in Identity and Individuation , pp. 137
    • Kripke, S.A.1
  • 20
    • 80054562175 scopus 로고
    • Theories of Masses and Problems of Constitution
    • Constitution, as I am construing it, differs in important ways from Dean W. Zimmerman's construal in "Theories of Masses and Problems of Constitution," Philosophical Review 104 (1995): 53-110. Zimmerman takes the relata of constitution to be masses of kinds of stuff. He also permits x and y to constitute one another (74), whereas I require asymmetry. In any case, Zimmerman finds the alleged differences between coincidents ungrounded, and concludes that "coincident physical objects are not to be countenanced" (90). I believe that my account of borrowing, together with my rejection of the thesis that all essential properties are intrinsic, dissolves the difficulties that Zimmerman sees.
    • (1995) Philosophical Review , vol.104 , pp. 53-110
    • Zimmerman, D.W.1
  • 21
    • 0003825113 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Thus, constitution must be sharply distinguished from supervenience. Failure to distinguish between supervenience and constitution has caused a great deal of confusion in the philosophy of mind. See my Explaining Attitudes: A Practical Approach to the Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995): 132.
    • (1995) Explaining Attitudes: A Practical Approach to the Mind , pp. 132
  • 22
    • 0003940388 scopus 로고
    • For detailed discussions of supervenience, see Jaegwon Kim's Supervenience and Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993).
    • (1993) Supervenience and Mind
    • Kim, J.1
  • 23
    • 34548534344 scopus 로고
    • Matter
    • For an interesting discussion of stuff and things, see Vere Chappell, "Matter," Journal of Philosophy 70 (1973): 679-96.
    • (1973) Journal of Philosophy , vol.70 , pp. 679-696
    • Chappell, V.1
  • 24
    • 34250213605 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Essentialists and Essentialism
    • A recent example may be found in Michael Delia Rocca, "Essentialists and Essentialism," Journal of Philosophy 93 (1996): 186-202. In "Why Constitution Is Not Identity," I have a direct argument against Della Rocca.
    • (1996) Journal of Philosophy , vol.93 , pp. 186-202
    • Delia Rocca, M.1
  • 26
    • 0004216686 scopus 로고
    • LaSalle, IL: Open Court Publishing
    • E.g., with respect to nonessential properties that are such that they may not be rooted outside the times at which they are had (as defined by Chisholm), Chisholm thinks that ordinary things (like tables) borrow such properties from what constitutes them, and not vice versa. See Roderick Chisholm, Person and Object: A Study in Metaphysics (LaSalle, IL: Open Court Publishing, 1976): 100-101.
    • (1976) Person and Object: A Study in Metaphysics , pp. 100-101
    • Chisholm, R.1
  • 27
    • 85085589701 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Persons in Metaphysical Perspective
    • LaSalle, IL: Open Court Publishing
    • The counterexamples that I give to the bottom-up-borrowing-only claim in the text all concern nonessential properties, and all conform to Chisholm's definition of properties that are such that they may not be rooted outside the times at which they are had. So, I think that they are counterexamples to Chisholm's view. For a detailed discussion, see my "Persons in Metaphysical Perspective" in The Philosophy of Roderick M. Chisholm (Library of Living Philosophers, Vol. 25) (LaSalle, IL: Open Court Publishing, 1997): 433-53.
    • (1997) The Philosophy of Roderick M. Chisholm Library of Living Philosophers , vol.25 , pp. 433-453
  • 29
    • 79953968955 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Perry, "The Same F." Notice that my construal no more invokes relative identity than does Perry's.
    • The Same F
    • Perry, J.1
  • 30
    • 0002464097 scopus 로고
    • Survival and Identity
    • AmElie Oksenberg Rorty, ed. (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press
    • Harold Noonan comments, "It is a deeply engrained conviction in many philosophical circles that if x is an F and y is an F and x and y are not identical then x and y cannot legitimately be counted as one F." He notes, however, that it "is perfectly possible to count by a relation weaker than, i.e., not entailing, identity." See "Constitution Is Identity," 138. In discussing fission cases of persons, David Lewis justifies counting by a weaker relation than identity in "Survival and Identity," in The Identities of Persons, AmElie Oksenberg Rorty, ed. (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1976): 26-28.
    • (1976) The Identities of Persons , pp. 26-28
    • Lewis, D.1
  • 31
    • 0039484167 scopus 로고
    • There Are No Ordinary Things
    • E.g., see Peter Unger, "There Are No Ordinary Things," Synthese 71 (1979): 117-54;
    • (1979) Synthese , vol.71 , pp. 117-154
    • Unger, P.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.