메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 22, Issue 2, 2000, Pages 501-547

Cultural relativism

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0345936799     PISSN: 02750392     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1353/hrq.2000.0027     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (77)

References (168)
  • 1
    • 9744262929 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I am grateful to Rhoda Howard, Louis Pojman, Paul Warren and, especially, Michael Burke for helpful comments. I am also grateful to my students in P326, Ethical Theory, for useful questions and discussions.
  • 2
    • 9744239240 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The terminology in this essay is not out of the ordinary, but nor is it universal. For instance, some authors use "ethical relativism" for what this article calls "cultural relativism," reserving the latter term for the view that different cultures accept different moral principles. Also, the terms "agent relativism," "transcendentalism," "moral liberalism," and "Victorian morality," all of which appear in this article, have more than one use in moral philosophy.
  • 3
    • 84928224417 scopus 로고
    • The Unanswered Challenge of Relativism and the Consequences for Human Rights
    • Especially those disciplines concerned with international human rights. See, e.g., Alison Dundes Renteln, The Unanswered Challenge of Relativism and the Consequences for Human Rights, 7 HUM. RTS. Q. 514 (1985); Alison Dundes Renteln, Relativism and the Search for Human Rights, 90 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 56 (1988); ALISON DUNDES RENTELN, INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS: UNIVERSALISM VERSUS RELATIVISM (1990); Terry Nardin, The Problem of Relativism in International Ethics, 18 MILLENNIUM 149 (1989); Martha C. Nussbaum, Human Functioning and Social Justice: In Defense of Aristotelian Essentialism, 20 POL. THEORY 203, 203-04 (1992) (recounting conversations that reveal the prevalence of cultural relativism among academics); Sam Garkawe, The Impact of the Doctrine of Cultural Relativism on the Australian Legal System, 2 E LAW-MURDOCH UNIV. ELEC. J.L., Apr. 1995, available in 〈http://www.murdoch.edu.au/elaw/issues/v2n1/ garkawe.txt〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000); Donald J. Puchala, The Ethics of Globalism, 5 REP. & PAPERS 2 (1995), available in 〈http://www.yale.edu/acuns/NEW_publications/ 95_Holmes_Lecture.html〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000) (recounting conference events that reveal the prevalence and influence of cultural relativism); Elvin Hatch, The Good Side of Relativism, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 371 (1997). Some valuable correctives to this trend are Nussbaum, supra, at 205-46; Puchala, supra, at 3-17; Rhoda E. Howard, Cultural Absolutism and the Nostalgia for Community, 15 HUM. RTS. Q. 315 (1993); Ray Kiely, Third Worldist Relativism: A New Form of Imperialism, 25 J. CONTEMP. ASIA 159 (1995); Anne F. Bayefsky, Cultural Sovereignty, Relativism, and International Human Rights: New Excuses for Old Strategies, 9 RATIO JURIS 42 (1996).
    • (1985) Hum. Rts. Q. , vol.7 , pp. 514
    • Renteln, A.D.1
  • 4
    • 84982060375 scopus 로고
    • Relativism and the Search for Human Rights
    • Especially those disciplines concerned with international human rights. See, e.g., Alison Dundes Renteln, The Unanswered Challenge of Relativism and the Consequences for Human Rights, 7 HUM. RTS. Q. 514 (1985); Alison Dundes Renteln, Relativism and the Search for Human Rights, 90 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 56 (1988); ALISON DUNDES RENTELN, INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS: UNIVERSALISM VERSUS RELATIVISM (1990); Terry Nardin, The Problem of Relativism in International Ethics, 18 MILLENNIUM 149 (1989); Martha C. Nussbaum, Human Functioning and Social Justice: In Defense of Aristotelian Essentialism, 20 POL. THEORY 203, 203-04 (1992) (recounting conversations that reveal the prevalence of cultural relativism among academics); Sam Garkawe, The Impact of the Doctrine of Cultural Relativism on the Australian Legal System, 2 E LAW-MURDOCH UNIV. ELEC. J.L., Apr. 1995, available in 〈http://www.murdoch.edu.au/elaw/issues/v2n1/ garkawe.txt〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000); Donald J. Puchala, The Ethics of Globalism, 5 REP. & PAPERS 2 (1995), available in 〈http://www.yale.edu/acuns/NEW_publications/ 95_Holmes_Lecture.html〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000) (recounting conference events that reveal the prevalence and influence of cultural relativism); Elvin Hatch, The Good Side of Relativism, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 371 (1997). Some valuable correctives to this trend are Nussbaum, supra, at 205-46; Puchala, supra, at 3-17; Rhoda E. Howard, Cultural Absolutism and the Nostalgia for Community, 15 HUM. RTS. Q. 315 (1993); Ray Kiely, Third Worldist Relativism: A New Form of Imperialism, 25 J. CONTEMP. ASIA 159 (1995); Anne F. Bayefsky, Cultural Sovereignty, Relativism, and International Human Rights: New Excuses for Old Strategies, 9 RATIO JURIS 42 (1996).
    • (1988) Am. Anthropologist , vol.90 , pp. 56
    • Renteln, A.D.1
  • 5
    • 0003496095 scopus 로고
    • Especially those disciplines concerned with international human rights. See, e.g., Alison Dundes Renteln, The Unanswered Challenge of Relativism and the Consequences for Human Rights, 7 HUM. RTS. Q. 514 (1985); Alison Dundes Renteln, Relativism and the Search for Human Rights, 90 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 56 (1988); ALISON DUNDES RENTELN, INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS: UNIVERSALISM VERSUS RELATIVISM (1990); Terry Nardin, The Problem of Relativism in International Ethics, 18 MILLENNIUM 149 (1989); Martha C. Nussbaum, Human Functioning and Social Justice: In Defense of Aristotelian Essentialism, 20 POL. THEORY 203, 203-04 (1992) (recounting conversations that reveal the prevalence of cultural relativism among academics); Sam Garkawe, The Impact of the Doctrine of Cultural Relativism on the Australian Legal System, 2 E LAW-MURDOCH UNIV. ELEC. J.L., Apr. 1995, available in 〈http://www.murdoch.edu.au/elaw/issues/v2n1/ garkawe.txt〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000); Donald J. Puchala, The Ethics of Globalism, 5 REP. & PAPERS 2 (1995), available in 〈http://www.yale.edu/acuns/NEW_publications/ 95_Holmes_Lecture.html〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000) (recounting conference events that reveal the prevalence and influence of cultural relativism); Elvin Hatch, The Good Side of Relativism, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 371 (1997). Some valuable correctives to this trend are Nussbaum, supra, at 205-46; Puchala, supra, at 3-17; Rhoda E. Howard, Cultural Absolutism and the Nostalgia for Community, 15 HUM. RTS. Q. 315 (1993); Ray Kiely, Third Worldist Relativism: A New Form of Imperialism, 25 J. CONTEMP. ASIA 159 (1995); Anne F. Bayefsky, Cultural Sovereignty, Relativism, and International Human Rights: New Excuses for Old Strategies, 9 RATIO JURIS 42 (1996).
    • (1990) International Human Rights: Universalism Versus Relativism
    • Renteln, A.D.1
  • 6
    • 34447140448 scopus 로고
    • The Problem of Relativism in International Ethics
    • Especially those disciplines concerned with international human rights. See, e.g., Alison Dundes Renteln, The Unanswered Challenge of Relativism and the Consequences for Human Rights, 7 HUM. RTS. Q. 514 (1985); Alison Dundes Renteln, Relativism and the Search for Human Rights, 90 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 56 (1988); ALISON DUNDES RENTELN, INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS: UNIVERSALISM VERSUS RELATIVISM (1990); Terry Nardin, The Problem of Relativism in International Ethics, 18 MILLENNIUM 149 (1989); Martha C. Nussbaum, Human Functioning and Social Justice: In Defense of Aristotelian Essentialism, 20 POL. THEORY 203, 203-04 (1992) (recounting conversations that reveal the prevalence of cultural relativism among academics); Sam Garkawe, The Impact of the Doctrine of Cultural Relativism on the Australian Legal System, 2 E LAW-MURDOCH UNIV. ELEC. J.L., Apr. 1995, available in 〈http://www.murdoch.edu.au/elaw/issues/v2n1/ garkawe.txt〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000); Donald J. Puchala, The Ethics of Globalism, 5 REP. & PAPERS 2 (1995), available in 〈http://www.yale.edu/acuns/NEW_publications/ 95_Holmes_Lecture.html〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000) (recounting conference events that reveal the prevalence and influence of cultural relativism); Elvin Hatch, The Good Side of Relativism, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 371 (1997). Some valuable correctives to this trend are Nussbaum, supra, at 205-46; Puchala, supra, at 3-17; Rhoda E. Howard, Cultural Absolutism and the Nostalgia for Community, 15 HUM. RTS. Q. 315 (1993); Ray Kiely, Third Worldist Relativism: A New Form of Imperialism, 25 J. CONTEMP. ASIA 159 (1995); Anne F. Bayefsky, Cultural Sovereignty, Relativism, and International Human Rights: New Excuses for Old Strategies, 9 RATIO JURIS 42 (1996).
    • (1989) Millennium , vol.18 , pp. 149
    • Nardin, T.1
  • 7
    • 84970641107 scopus 로고
    • Human Functioning and Social Justice: In Defense of Aristotelian Essentialism
    • Especially those disciplines concerned with international human rights. See, e.g., Alison Dundes Renteln, The Unanswered Challenge of Relativism and the Consequences for Human Rights, 7 HUM. RTS. Q. 514 (1985); Alison Dundes Renteln, Relativism and the Search for Human Rights, 90 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 56 (1988); ALISON DUNDES RENTELN, INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS: UNIVERSALISM VERSUS RELATIVISM (1990); Terry Nardin, The Problem of Relativism in International Ethics, 18 MILLENNIUM 149 (1989); Martha C. Nussbaum, Human Functioning and Social Justice: In Defense of Aristotelian Essentialism, 20 POL. THEORY 203, 203-04 (1992) (recounting conversations that reveal the prevalence of cultural relativism among academics); Sam Garkawe, The Impact of the Doctrine of Cultural Relativism on the Australian Legal System, 2 E LAW-MURDOCH UNIV. ELEC. J.L., Apr. 1995, available in 〈http://www.murdoch.edu.au/elaw/issues/v2n1/ garkawe.txt〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000); Donald J. Puchala, The Ethics of Globalism, 5 REP. & PAPERS 2 (1995), available in 〈http://www.yale.edu/acuns/NEW_publications/ 95_Holmes_Lecture.html〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000) (recounting conference events that reveal the prevalence and influence of cultural relativism); Elvin Hatch, The Good Side of Relativism, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 371 (1997). Some valuable correctives to this trend are Nussbaum, supra, at 205-46; Puchala, supra, at 3-17; Rhoda E. Howard, Cultural Absolutism and the Nostalgia for Community, 15 HUM. RTS. Q. 315 (1993); Ray Kiely, Third Worldist Relativism: A New Form of Imperialism, 25 J. CONTEMP. ASIA 159 (1995); Anne F. Bayefsky, Cultural Sovereignty, Relativism, and International Human Rights: New Excuses for Old Strategies, 9 RATIO JURIS 42 (1996).
    • (1992) Pol. Theory , vol.20 , pp. 203
    • Nussbaum, M.C.1
  • 8
    • 0345362891 scopus 로고
    • The Impact of the Doctrine of Cultural Relativism on the Australian Legal System
    • Apr. visited 9 Feb.
    • Especially those disciplines concerned with international human rights. See, e.g., Alison Dundes Renteln, The Unanswered Challenge of Relativism and the Consequences for Human Rights, 7 HUM. RTS. Q. 514 (1985); Alison Dundes Renteln, Relativism and the Search for Human Rights, 90 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 56 (1988); ALISON DUNDES RENTELN, INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS: UNIVERSALISM VERSUS RELATIVISM (1990); Terry Nardin, The Problem of Relativism in International Ethics, 18 MILLENNIUM 149 (1989); Martha C. Nussbaum, Human Functioning and Social Justice: In Defense of Aristotelian Essentialism, 20 POL. THEORY 203, 203-04 (1992) (recounting conversations that reveal the prevalence of cultural relativism among academics); Sam Garkawe, The Impact of the Doctrine of Cultural Relativism on the Australian Legal System, 2 E LAW-MURDOCH UNIV. ELEC. J.L., Apr. 1995, available in 〈http://www.murdoch.edu.au/elaw/issues/v2n1/ garkawe.txt〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000); Donald J. Puchala, The Ethics of Globalism, 5 REP. & PAPERS 2 (1995), available in 〈http://www.yale.edu/acuns/NEW_publications/ 95_Holmes_Lecture.html〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000) (recounting conference events that reveal the prevalence and influence of cultural relativism); Elvin Hatch, The Good Side of Relativism, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 371 (1997). Some valuable correctives to this trend are Nussbaum, supra, at 205-46; Puchala, supra, at 3-17; Rhoda E. Howard, Cultural Absolutism and the Nostalgia for Community, 15 HUM. RTS. Q. 315 (1993); Ray Kiely, Third Worldist Relativism: A New Form of Imperialism, 25 J. CONTEMP. ASIA 159 (1995); Anne F. Bayefsky, Cultural Sovereignty, Relativism, and International Human Rights: New Excuses for Old Strategies, 9 RATIO JURIS 42 (1996).
    • (1995) E Law-murdoch Univ. Elec. J.L. , vol.2
    • Garkawe, S.1
  • 9
    • 9744283885 scopus 로고
    • The Ethics of Globalism
    • visited 9 Feb.
    • Especially those disciplines concerned with international human rights. See, e.g., Alison Dundes Renteln, The Unanswered Challenge of Relativism and the Consequences for Human Rights, 7 HUM. RTS. Q. 514 (1985); Alison Dundes Renteln, Relativism and the Search for Human Rights, 90 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 56 (1988); ALISON DUNDES RENTELN, INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS: UNIVERSALISM VERSUS RELATIVISM (1990); Terry Nardin, The Problem of Relativism in International Ethics, 18 MILLENNIUM 149 (1989); Martha C. Nussbaum, Human Functioning and Social Justice: In Defense of Aristotelian Essentialism, 20 POL. THEORY 203, 203-04 (1992) (recounting conversations that reveal the prevalence of cultural relativism among academics); Sam Garkawe, The Impact of the Doctrine of Cultural Relativism on the Australian Legal System, 2 E LAW-MURDOCH UNIV. ELEC. J.L., Apr. 1995, available in 〈http://www.murdoch.edu.au/elaw/issues/v2n1/ garkawe.txt〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000); Donald J. Puchala, The Ethics of Globalism, 5 REP. & PAPERS 2 (1995), available in 〈http://www.yale.edu/acuns/NEW_publications/ 95_Holmes_Lecture.html〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000) (recounting conference events that reveal the prevalence and influence of cultural relativism); Elvin Hatch, The Good Side of Relativism, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 371 (1997). Some valuable correctives to this trend are Nussbaum, supra, at 205-46; Puchala, supra, at 3-17; Rhoda E. Howard, Cultural Absolutism and the Nostalgia for Community, 15 HUM. RTS. Q. 315 (1993); Ray Kiely, Third Worldist Relativism: A New Form of Imperialism, 25 J. CONTEMP. ASIA 159 (1995); Anne F. Bayefsky, Cultural Sovereignty, Relativism, and International Human Rights: New Excuses for Old Strategies, 9 RATIO JURIS 42 (1996).
    • (1995) Rep. & Papers , vol.5 , pp. 2
    • Puchala, D.J.1
  • 10
    • 0003926612 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Good Side of Relativism
    • Especially those disciplines concerned with international human rights. See, e.g., Alison Dundes Renteln, The Unanswered Challenge of Relativism and the Consequences for Human Rights, 7 HUM. RTS. Q. 514 (1985); Alison Dundes Renteln, Relativism and the Search for Human Rights, 90 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 56 (1988); ALISON DUNDES RENTELN, INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS: UNIVERSALISM VERSUS RELATIVISM (1990); Terry Nardin, The Problem of Relativism in International Ethics, 18 MILLENNIUM 149 (1989); Martha C. Nussbaum, Human Functioning and Social Justice: In Defense of Aristotelian Essentialism, 20 POL. THEORY 203, 203-04 (1992) (recounting conversations that reveal the prevalence of cultural relativism among academics); Sam Garkawe, The Impact of the Doctrine of Cultural Relativism on the Australian Legal System, 2 E LAW-MURDOCH UNIV. ELEC. J.L., Apr. 1995, available in 〈http://www.murdoch.edu.au/elaw/issues/v2n1/ garkawe.txt〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000); Donald J. Puchala, The Ethics of Globalism, 5 REP. & PAPERS 2 (1995), available in 〈http://www.yale.edu/acuns/NEW_publications/ 95_Holmes_Lecture.html〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000) (recounting conference events that reveal the prevalence and influence of cultural relativism); Elvin Hatch, The Good Side of Relativism, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 371 (1997). Some valuable correctives to this trend are Nussbaum, supra, at 205-46; Puchala, supra, at 3-17; Rhoda E. Howard, Cultural Absolutism and the Nostalgia for Community, 15 HUM. RTS. Q. 315 (1993); Ray Kiely, Third Worldist Relativism: A New Form of Imperialism, 25 J. CONTEMP. ASIA 159 (1995); Anne F. Bayefsky, Cultural Sovereignty, Relativism, and International Human Rights: New Excuses for Old Strategies, 9 RATIO JURIS 42 (1996).
    • (1997) J. Anthropological Res. , vol.53 , pp. 371
    • Hatch, E.1
  • 11
    • 84924124087 scopus 로고
    • Cultural Absolutism and the Nostalgia for Community
    • Especially those disciplines concerned with international human rights. See, e.g., Alison Dundes Renteln, The Unanswered Challenge of Relativism and the Consequences for Human Rights, 7 HUM. RTS. Q. 514 (1985); Alison Dundes Renteln, Relativism and the Search for Human Rights, 90 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 56 (1988); ALISON DUNDES RENTELN, INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS: UNIVERSALISM VERSUS RELATIVISM (1990); Terry Nardin, The Problem of Relativism in International Ethics, 18 MILLENNIUM 149 (1989); Martha C. Nussbaum, Human Functioning and Social Justice: In Defense of Aristotelian Essentialism, 20 POL. THEORY 203, 203-04 (1992) (recounting conversations that reveal the prevalence of cultural relativism among academics); Sam Garkawe, The Impact of the Doctrine of Cultural Relativism on the Australian Legal System, 2 E LAW-MURDOCH UNIV. ELEC. J.L., Apr. 1995, available in 〈http://www.murdoch.edu.au/elaw/issues/v2n1/ garkawe.txt〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000); Donald J. Puchala, The Ethics of Globalism, 5 REP. & PAPERS 2 (1995), available in 〈http://www.yale.edu/acuns/NEW_publications/ 95_Holmes_Lecture.html〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000) (recounting conference events that reveal the prevalence and influence of cultural relativism); Elvin Hatch, The Good Side of Relativism, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 371 (1997). Some valuable correctives to this trend are Nussbaum, supra, at 205-46; Puchala, supra, at 3-17; Rhoda E. Howard, Cultural Absolutism and the Nostalgia for Community, 15 HUM. RTS. Q. 315 (1993); Ray Kiely, Third Worldist Relativism: A New Form of Imperialism, 25 J. CONTEMP. ASIA 159 (1995); Anne F. Bayefsky, Cultural Sovereignty, Relativism, and International Human Rights: New Excuses for Old Strategies, 9 RATIO JURIS 42 (1996).
    • (1993) Hum. Rts. Q. , vol.15 , pp. 315
    • Howard, R.E.1
  • 12
    • 84937291764 scopus 로고
    • Third Worldist Relativism: A New Form of Imperialism
    • Especially those disciplines concerned with international human rights. See, e.g., Alison Dundes Renteln, The Unanswered Challenge of Relativism and the Consequences for Human Rights, 7 HUM. RTS. Q. 514 (1985); Alison Dundes Renteln, Relativism and the Search for Human Rights, 90 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 56 (1988); ALISON DUNDES RENTELN, INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS: UNIVERSALISM VERSUS RELATIVISM (1990); Terry Nardin, The Problem of Relativism in International Ethics, 18 MILLENNIUM 149 (1989); Martha C. Nussbaum, Human Functioning and Social Justice: In Defense of Aristotelian Essentialism, 20 POL. THEORY 203, 203-04 (1992) (recounting conversations that reveal the prevalence of cultural relativism among academics); Sam Garkawe, The Impact of the Doctrine of Cultural Relativism on the Australian Legal System, 2 E LAW-MURDOCH UNIV. ELEC. J.L., Apr. 1995, available in 〈http://www.murdoch.edu.au/elaw/issues/v2n1/ garkawe.txt〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000); Donald J. Puchala, The Ethics of Globalism, 5 REP. & PAPERS 2 (1995), available in 〈http://www.yale.edu/acuns/NEW_publications/ 95_Holmes_Lecture.html〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000) (recounting conference events that reveal the prevalence and influence of cultural relativism); Elvin Hatch, The Good Side of Relativism, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 371 (1997). Some valuable correctives to this trend are Nussbaum, supra, at 205-46; Puchala, supra, at 3-17; Rhoda E. Howard, Cultural Absolutism and the Nostalgia for Community, 15 HUM. RTS. Q. 315 (1993); Ray Kiely, Third Worldist Relativism: A New Form of Imperialism, 25 J. CONTEMP. ASIA 159 (1995); Anne F. Bayefsky, Cultural Sovereignty, Relativism, and International Human Rights: New Excuses for Old Strategies, 9 RATIO JURIS 42 (1996).
    • (1995) J. Contemp. Asia , vol.25 , pp. 159
    • Kiely, R.1
  • 13
    • 9644278987 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cultural Sovereignty, Relativism, and International Human Rights: New Excuses for Old Strategies
    • Especially those disciplines concerned with international human rights. See, e.g., Alison Dundes Renteln, The Unanswered Challenge of Relativism and the Consequences for Human Rights, 7 HUM. RTS. Q. 514 (1985); Alison Dundes Renteln, Relativism and the Search for Human Rights, 90 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 56 (1988); ALISON DUNDES RENTELN, INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS: UNIVERSALISM VERSUS RELATIVISM (1990); Terry Nardin, The Problem of Relativism in International Ethics, 18 MILLENNIUM 149 (1989); Martha C. Nussbaum, Human Functioning and Social Justice: In Defense of Aristotelian Essentialism, 20 POL. THEORY 203, 203-04 (1992) (recounting conversations that reveal the prevalence of cultural relativism among academics); Sam Garkawe, The Impact of the Doctrine of Cultural Relativism on the Australian Legal System, 2 E LAW-MURDOCH UNIV. ELEC. J.L., Apr. 1995, available in 〈http://www.murdoch.edu.au/elaw/issues/v2n1/ garkawe.txt〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000); Donald J. Puchala, The Ethics of Globalism, 5 REP. & PAPERS 2 (1995), available in 〈http://www.yale.edu/acuns/NEW_publications/ 95_Holmes_Lecture.html〉 (visited 9 Feb. 2000) (recounting conference events that reveal the prevalence and influence of cultural relativism); Elvin Hatch, The Good Side of Relativism, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 371 (1997). Some valuable correctives to this trend are Nussbaum, supra, at 205-46; Puchala, supra, at 3-17; Rhoda E. Howard, Cultural Absolutism and the Nostalgia for Community, 15 HUM. RTS. Q. 315 (1993); Ray Kiely, Third Worldist Relativism: A New Form of Imperialism, 25 J. CONTEMP. ASIA 159 (1995); Anne F. Bayefsky, Cultural Sovereignty, Relativism, and International Human Rights: New Excuses for Old Strategies, 9 RATIO JURIS 42 (1996).
    • (1996) Ratio Juris , vol.9 , pp. 42
    • Bayefsky, A.F.1
  • 14
    • 9744221573 scopus 로고
    • chs. 1-2
    • Critical studies of cultural relativism are numerous. Useful ones include the "correctives" in note 3. See also W.T. STACE, THE CONCEPT OF MORALS chs. 1-2, 10 (1937); Elgin Williams, Anthropology for the Common Man, 49 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 84 (1947); Frank E. Hartung, Cultural Relativity and Moral Judgments, 21 PHIL. SCI. 118 (1954); Paul F. Schmidt, Some Criticisms of Cultural Relativism, 52 J. PHIL. 780 (1955); David Bidney, The Philosophical Presuppositions of Cultural Relativism and Cultural Absolutism, in ETHICS AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES 51 (Leo Ward ed., 1959); RICHARD B. BRANDT, ETHICAL THEORY ch. 11 (1959); T. L. McClintock, The Argument for Ethical Relativism from the Diversity of Morals, 47 MONIST 528 (1963); PAUL W. TAYLOR, PRINCIPLES OF ETHICS ch. 2 (1975); William H. Shaw, Relativism and Objectivity in Ethics, in MORALITY AND MORAL CONTROVERSIES 31 (John Arthur ed., 1981); F. C. WHITE, KNOWLEDGE AND RELATIVISM chs. 4-5 (1983); JEFFREY STOUT, ETHICS AFTER BABEL pt. 1 (1988); LOUIS P. POJMAN, ETHICS: DISCOVERING RIGHT AND WRONG chs. 2-3 (2d ed. 1995). My discussion has benefitted from these authors at many points. A related note: this article was finished in all essentials in mid-1997; hence, it makes little use of items that have appeared since then. Among those items are the following, which I recommend highly: Elizabeth M. Zechenter, In the Name of Culture: Cultural Relativism and the Abuse of the Individual, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 319 (1997); Michael J. Perry, Are Human Rights Universal?: The Relativist Challenge and Related Matters, 19 HUM. RTS. Q. 461 (1997); MICHELE M. MOODY-ADAMS, FIELDVVORK IN FAMILIAR PLACES: MORALITY, CULTURE, AND PHILOSOPHY (1997); William Max Knorpp Jr., What Relativism Isn't, 73 PHILOSOPHY 277 (1998); JOHN W. COOK, MORALITY AND CULTURAL DIFFERENCES (1999).
    • (1937) The Concept of Morals , pp. 10
    • Stace, W.T.1
  • 15
    • 0347367919 scopus 로고
    • Anthropology for the Common Man
    • Critical studies of cultural relativism are numerous. Useful ones include the "correctives" in note 3. See also W.T. STACE, THE CONCEPT OF MORALS chs. 1-2, 10 (1937); Elgin Williams, Anthropology for the Common Man, 49 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 84 (1947); Frank E. Hartung, Cultural Relativity and Moral Judgments, 21 PHIL. SCI. 118 (1954); Paul F. Schmidt, Some Criticisms of Cultural Relativism, 52 J. PHIL. 780 (1955); David Bidney, The Philosophical Presuppositions of Cultural Relativism and Cultural Absolutism, in ETHICS AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES 51 (Leo Ward ed., 1959); RICHARD B. BRANDT, ETHICAL THEORY ch. 11 (1959); T. L. McClintock, The Argument for Ethical Relativism from the Diversity of Morals, 47 MONIST 528 (1963); PAUL W. TAYLOR, PRINCIPLES OF ETHICS ch. 2 (1975); William H. Shaw, Relativism and Objectivity in Ethics, in MORALITY AND MORAL CONTROVERSIES 31 (John Arthur ed., 1981); F. C. WHITE, KNOWLEDGE AND RELATIVISM chs. 4-5 (1983); JEFFREY STOUT, ETHICS AFTER BABEL pt. 1 (1988); LOUIS P. POJMAN, ETHICS: DISCOVERING RIGHT AND WRONG chs. 2-3 (2d ed. 1995). My discussion has benefitted from these authors at many points. A related note: this article was finished in all essentials in mid-1997; hence, it makes little use of items that have appeared since then. Among those items are the following, which I recommend highly: Elizabeth M. Zechenter, In the Name of Culture: Cultural Relativism and the Abuse of the Individual, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 319 (1997); Michael J. Perry, Are Human Rights Universal?: The Relativist Challenge and Related Matters, 19 HUM. RTS. Q. 461 (1997); MICHELE M. MOODY-ADAMS, FIELDVVORK IN FAMILIAR PLACES: MORALITY, CULTURE, AND PHILOSOPHY (1997); William Max Knorpp Jr., What Relativism Isn't, 73 PHILOSOPHY 277 (1998); JOHN W. COOK, MORALITY AND CULTURAL DIFFERENCES (1999).
    • (1947) Am. Anthropologist , vol.49 , pp. 84
    • Williams, E.1
  • 16
    • 85056007140 scopus 로고
    • Cultural Relativity and Moral Judgments
    • Critical studies of cultural relativism are numerous. Useful ones include the "correctives" in note 3. See also W.T. STACE, THE CONCEPT OF MORALS chs. 1-2, 10 (1937); Elgin Williams, Anthropology for the Common Man, 49 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 84 (1947); Frank E. Hartung, Cultural Relativity and Moral Judgments, 21 PHIL. SCI. 118 (1954); Paul F. Schmidt, Some Criticisms of Cultural Relativism, 52 J. PHIL. 780 (1955); David Bidney, The Philosophical Presuppositions of Cultural Relativism and Cultural Absolutism, in ETHICS AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES 51 (Leo Ward ed., 1959); RICHARD B. BRANDT, ETHICAL THEORY ch. 11 (1959); T. L. McClintock, The Argument for Ethical Relativism from the Diversity of Morals, 47 MONIST 528 (1963); PAUL W. TAYLOR, PRINCIPLES OF ETHICS ch. 2 (1975); William H. Shaw, Relativism and Objectivity in Ethics, in MORALITY AND MORAL CONTROVERSIES 31 (John Arthur ed., 1981); F. C. WHITE, KNOWLEDGE AND RELATIVISM chs. 4-5 (1983); JEFFREY STOUT, ETHICS AFTER BABEL pt. 1 (1988); LOUIS P. POJMAN, ETHICS: DISCOVERING RIGHT AND WRONG chs. 2-3 (2d ed. 1995). My discussion has benefitted from these authors at many points. A related note: this article was finished in all essentials in mid-1997; hence, it makes little use of items that have appeared since then. Among those items are the following, which I recommend highly: Elizabeth M. Zechenter, In the Name of Culture: Cultural Relativism and the Abuse of the Individual, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 319 (1997); Michael J. Perry, Are Human Rights Universal?: The Relativist Challenge and Related Matters, 19 HUM. RTS. Q. 461 (1997); MICHELE M. MOODY-ADAMS, FIELDVVORK IN FAMILIAR PLACES: MORALITY, CULTURE, AND PHILOSOPHY (1997); William Max Knorpp Jr., What Relativism Isn't, 73 PHILOSOPHY 277 (1998); JOHN W. COOK, MORALITY AND CULTURAL DIFFERENCES (1999).
    • (1954) Phil. Sci. , vol.21 , pp. 118
    • Hartung, F.E.1
  • 17
    • 0345117457 scopus 로고
    • Some Criticisms of Cultural Relativism
    • Critical studies of cultural relativism are numerous. Useful ones include the "correctives" in note 3. See also W.T. STACE, THE CONCEPT OF MORALS chs. 1-2, 10 (1937); Elgin Williams, Anthropology for the Common Man, 49 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 84 (1947); Frank E. Hartung, Cultural Relativity and Moral Judgments, 21 PHIL. SCI. 118 (1954); Paul F. Schmidt, Some Criticisms of Cultural Relativism, 52 J. PHIL. 780 (1955); David Bidney, The Philosophical Presuppositions of Cultural Relativism and Cultural Absolutism, in ETHICS AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES 51 (Leo Ward ed., 1959); RICHARD B. BRANDT, ETHICAL THEORY ch. 11 (1959); T. L. McClintock, The Argument for Ethical Relativism from the Diversity of Morals, 47 MONIST 528 (1963); PAUL W. TAYLOR, PRINCIPLES OF ETHICS ch. 2 (1975); William H. Shaw, Relativism and Objectivity in Ethics, in MORALITY AND MORAL CONTROVERSIES 31 (John Arthur ed., 1981); F. C. WHITE, KNOWLEDGE AND RELATIVISM chs. 4-5 (1983); JEFFREY STOUT, ETHICS AFTER BABEL pt. 1 (1988); LOUIS P. POJMAN, ETHICS: DISCOVERING RIGHT AND WRONG chs. 2-3 (2d ed. 1995). My discussion has benefitted from these authors at many points. A related note: this article was finished in all essentials in mid-1997; hence, it makes little use of items that have appeared since then. Among those items are the following, which I recommend highly: Elizabeth M. Zechenter, In the Name of Culture: Cultural Relativism and the Abuse of the Individual, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 319 (1997); Michael J. Perry, Are Human Rights Universal?: The Relativist Challenge and Related Matters, 19 HUM. RTS. Q. 461 (1997); MICHELE M. MOODY-ADAMS, FIELDVVORK IN FAMILIAR PLACES: MORALITY, CULTURE, AND PHILOSOPHY (1997); William Max Knorpp Jr., What Relativism Isn't, 73 PHILOSOPHY 277 (1998); JOHN W. COOK, MORALITY AND CULTURAL DIFFERENCES (1999).
    • (1955) J. Phil. , vol.52 , pp. 780
    • Schmidt, P.F.1
  • 18
    • 9744260717 scopus 로고
    • The Philosophical Presuppositions of Cultural Relativism and Cultural Absolutism
    • Leo Ward ed.
    • Critical studies of cultural relativism are numerous. Useful ones include the "correctives" in note 3. See also W.T. STACE, THE CONCEPT OF MORALS chs. 1-2, 10 (1937); Elgin Williams, Anthropology for the Common Man, 49 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 84 (1947); Frank E. Hartung, Cultural Relativity and Moral Judgments, 21 PHIL. SCI. 118 (1954); Paul F. Schmidt, Some Criticisms of Cultural Relativism, 52 J. PHIL. 780 (1955); David Bidney, The Philosophical Presuppositions of Cultural Relativism and Cultural Absolutism, in ETHICS AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES 51 (Leo Ward ed., 1959); RICHARD B. BRANDT, ETHICAL THEORY ch. 11 (1959); T. L. McClintock, The Argument for Ethical Relativism from the Diversity of Morals, 47 MONIST 528 (1963); PAUL W. TAYLOR, PRINCIPLES OF ETHICS ch. 2 (1975); William H. Shaw, Relativism and Objectivity in Ethics, in MORALITY AND MORAL CONTROVERSIES 31 (John Arthur ed., 1981); F. C. WHITE, KNOWLEDGE AND RELATIVISM chs. 4-5 (1983); JEFFREY STOUT, ETHICS AFTER BABEL pt. 1 (1988); LOUIS P. POJMAN, ETHICS: DISCOVERING RIGHT AND WRONG chs. 2-3 (2d ed. 1995). My discussion has benefitted from these authors at many points. A related note: this article was finished in all essentials in mid-1997; hence, it makes little use of items that have appeared since then. Among those items are the following, which I recommend highly: Elizabeth M. Zechenter, In the Name of Culture: Cultural Relativism and the Abuse of the Individual, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 319 (1997); Michael J. Perry, Are Human Rights Universal?: The Relativist Challenge and Related Matters, 19 HUM. RTS. Q. 461 (1997); MICHELE M. MOODY-ADAMS, FIELDVVORK IN FAMILIAR PLACES: MORALITY, CULTURE, AND PHILOSOPHY (1997); William Max Knorpp Jr., What Relativism Isn't, 73 PHILOSOPHY 277 (1998); JOHN W. COOK, MORALITY AND CULTURAL DIFFERENCES (1999).
    • (1959) Ethics and the Social Sciences , pp. 51
    • Bidney, D.1
  • 19
    • 0004171296 scopus 로고
    • ch. 11
    • Critical studies of cultural relativism are numerous. Useful ones include the "correctives" in note 3. See also W.T. STACE, THE CONCEPT OF MORALS chs. 1-2, 10 (1937); Elgin Williams, Anthropology for the Common Man, 49 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 84 (1947); Frank E. Hartung, Cultural Relativity and Moral Judgments, 21 PHIL. SCI. 118 (1954); Paul F. Schmidt, Some Criticisms of Cultural Relativism, 52 J. PHIL. 780 (1955); David Bidney, The Philosophical Presuppositions of Cultural Relativism and Cultural Absolutism, in ETHICS AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES 51 (Leo Ward ed., 1959); RICHARD B. BRANDT, ETHICAL THEORY ch. 11 (1959); T. L. McClintock, The Argument for Ethical Relativism from the Diversity of Morals, 47 MONIST 528 (1963); PAUL W. TAYLOR, PRINCIPLES OF ETHICS ch. 2 (1975); William H. Shaw, Relativism and Objectivity in Ethics, in MORALITY AND MORAL CONTROVERSIES 31 (John Arthur ed., 1981); F. C. WHITE, KNOWLEDGE AND RELATIVISM chs. 4-5 (1983); JEFFREY STOUT, ETHICS AFTER BABEL pt. 1 (1988); LOUIS P. POJMAN, ETHICS: DISCOVERING RIGHT AND WRONG chs. 2-3 (2d ed. 1995). My discussion has benefitted from these authors at many points. A related note: this article was finished in all essentials in mid-1997; hence, it makes little use of items that have appeared since then. Among those items are the following, which I recommend highly: Elizabeth M. Zechenter, In the Name of Culture: Cultural Relativism and the Abuse of the Individual, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 319 (1997); Michael J. Perry, Are Human Rights Universal?: The Relativist Challenge and Related Matters, 19 HUM. RTS. Q. 461 (1997); MICHELE M. MOODY-ADAMS, FIELDVVORK IN FAMILIAR PLACES: MORALITY, CULTURE, AND PHILOSOPHY (1997); William Max Knorpp Jr., What Relativism Isn't, 73 PHILOSOPHY 277 (1998); JOHN W. COOK, MORALITY AND CULTURAL DIFFERENCES (1999).
    • (1959) Ethical Theory
    • Brandt, R.B.1
  • 20
    • 9744271127 scopus 로고
    • The Argument for Ethical Relativism from the Diversity of Morals
    • Critical studies of cultural relativism are numerous. Useful ones include the "correctives" in note 3. See also W.T. STACE, THE CONCEPT OF MORALS chs. 1-2, 10 (1937); Elgin Williams, Anthropology for the Common Man, 49 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 84 (1947); Frank E. Hartung, Cultural Relativity and Moral Judgments, 21 PHIL. SCI. 118 (1954); Paul F. Schmidt, Some Criticisms of Cultural Relativism, 52 J. PHIL. 780 (1955); David Bidney, The Philosophical Presuppositions of Cultural Relativism and Cultural Absolutism, in ETHICS AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES 51 (Leo Ward ed., 1959); RICHARD B. BRANDT, ETHICAL THEORY ch. 11 (1959); T. L. McClintock, The Argument for Ethical Relativism from the Diversity of Morals, 47 MONIST 528 (1963); PAUL W. TAYLOR, PRINCIPLES OF ETHICS ch. 2 (1975); William H. Shaw, Relativism and Objectivity in Ethics, in MORALITY AND MORAL CONTROVERSIES 31 (John Arthur ed., 1981); F. C. WHITE, KNOWLEDGE AND RELATIVISM chs. 4-5 (1983); JEFFREY STOUT, ETHICS AFTER BABEL pt. 1 (1988); LOUIS P. POJMAN, ETHICS: DISCOVERING RIGHT AND WRONG chs. 2-3 (2d ed. 1995). My discussion has benefitted from these authors at many points. A related note: this article was finished in all essentials in mid-1997; hence, it makes little use of items that have appeared since then. Among those items are the following, which I recommend highly: Elizabeth M. Zechenter, In the Name of Culture: Cultural Relativism and the Abuse of the Individual, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 319 (1997); Michael J. Perry, Are Human Rights Universal?: The Relativist Challenge and Related Matters, 19 HUM. RTS. Q. 461 (1997); MICHELE M. MOODY-ADAMS, FIELDVVORK IN FAMILIAR PLACES: MORALITY, CULTURE, AND PHILOSOPHY (1997); William Max Knorpp Jr., What Relativism Isn't, 73 PHILOSOPHY 277 (1998); JOHN W. COOK, MORALITY AND CULTURAL DIFFERENCES (1999).
    • (1963) Monist , vol.47 , pp. 528
    • McClintock, T.L.1
  • 21
    • 9744267898 scopus 로고
    • ch. 2
    • Critical studies of cultural relativism are numerous. Useful ones include the "correctives" in note 3. See also W.T. STACE, THE CONCEPT OF MORALS chs. 1-2, 10 (1937); Elgin Williams, Anthropology for the Common Man, 49 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 84 (1947); Frank E. Hartung, Cultural Relativity and Moral Judgments, 21 PHIL. SCI. 118 (1954); Paul F. Schmidt, Some Criticisms of Cultural Relativism, 52 J. PHIL. 780 (1955); David Bidney, The Philosophical Presuppositions of Cultural Relativism and Cultural Absolutism, in ETHICS AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES 51 (Leo Ward ed., 1959); RICHARD B. BRANDT, ETHICAL THEORY ch. 11 (1959); T. L. McClintock, The Argument for Ethical Relativism from the Diversity of Morals, 47 MONIST 528 (1963); PAUL W. TAYLOR, PRINCIPLES OF ETHICS ch. 2 (1975); William H. Shaw, Relativism and Objectivity in Ethics, in MORALITY AND MORAL CONTROVERSIES 31 (John Arthur ed., 1981); F. C. WHITE, KNOWLEDGE AND RELATIVISM chs. 4-5 (1983); JEFFREY STOUT, ETHICS AFTER BABEL pt. 1 (1988); LOUIS P. POJMAN, ETHICS: DISCOVERING RIGHT AND WRONG chs. 2-3 (2d ed. 1995). My discussion has benefitted from these authors at many points. A related note: this article was finished in all essentials in mid-1997; hence, it makes little use of items that have appeared since then. Among those items are the following, which I recommend highly: Elizabeth M. Zechenter, In the Name of Culture: Cultural Relativism and the Abuse of the Individual, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 319 (1997); Michael J. Perry, Are Human Rights Universal?: The Relativist Challenge and Related Matters, 19 HUM. RTS. Q. 461 (1997); MICHELE M. MOODY-ADAMS, FIELDVVORK IN FAMILIAR PLACES: MORALITY, CULTURE, AND PHILOSOPHY (1997); William Max Knorpp Jr., What Relativism Isn't, 73 PHILOSOPHY 277 (1998); JOHN W. COOK, MORALITY AND CULTURAL DIFFERENCES (1999).
    • (1975) Principles of Ethics
    • Taylor, P.W.1
  • 22
    • 9744253463 scopus 로고
    • Relativism and Objectivity in Ethics
    • John Arthur ed.
    • Critical studies of cultural relativism are numerous. Useful ones include the "correctives" in note 3. See also W.T. STACE, THE CONCEPT OF MORALS chs. 1-2, 10 (1937); Elgin Williams, Anthropology for the Common Man, 49 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 84 (1947); Frank E. Hartung, Cultural Relativity and Moral Judgments, 21 PHIL. SCI. 118 (1954); Paul F. Schmidt, Some Criticisms of Cultural Relativism, 52 J. PHIL. 780 (1955); David Bidney, The Philosophical Presuppositions of Cultural Relativism and Cultural Absolutism, in ETHICS AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES 51 (Leo Ward ed., 1959); RICHARD B. BRANDT, ETHICAL THEORY ch. 11 (1959); T. L. McClintock, The Argument for Ethical Relativism from the Diversity of Morals, 47 MONIST 528 (1963); PAUL W. TAYLOR, PRINCIPLES OF ETHICS ch. 2 (1975); William H. Shaw, Relativism and Objectivity in Ethics, in MORALITY AND MORAL CONTROVERSIES 31 (John Arthur ed., 1981); F. C. WHITE, KNOWLEDGE AND RELATIVISM chs. 4-5 (1983); JEFFREY STOUT, ETHICS AFTER BABEL pt. 1 (1988); LOUIS P. POJMAN, ETHICS: DISCOVERING RIGHT AND WRONG chs. 2-3 (2d ed. 1995). My discussion has benefitted from these authors at many points. A related note: this article was finished in all essentials in mid-1997; hence, it makes little use of items that have appeared since then. Among those items are the following, which I recommend highly: Elizabeth M. Zechenter, In the Name of Culture: Cultural Relativism and the Abuse of the Individual, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 319 (1997); Michael J. Perry, Are Human Rights Universal?: The Relativist Challenge and Related Matters, 19 HUM. RTS. Q. 461 (1997); MICHELE M. MOODY-ADAMS, FIELDVVORK IN FAMILIAR PLACES: MORALITY, CULTURE, AND PHILOSOPHY (1997); William Max Knorpp Jr., What Relativism Isn't, 73 PHILOSOPHY 277 (1998); JOHN W. COOK, MORALITY AND CULTURAL DIFFERENCES (1999).
    • (1981) Morality and Moral COntroversies , pp. 31
    • Shaw, W.H.1
  • 23
    • 5544312550 scopus 로고
    • chs. 4-5
    • Critical studies of cultural relativism are numerous. Useful ones include the "correctives" in note 3. See also W.T. STACE, THE CONCEPT OF MORALS chs. 1-2, 10 (1937); Elgin Williams, Anthropology for the Common Man, 49 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 84 (1947); Frank E. Hartung, Cultural Relativity and Moral Judgments, 21 PHIL. SCI. 118 (1954); Paul F. Schmidt, Some Criticisms of Cultural Relativism, 52 J. PHIL. 780 (1955); David Bidney, The Philosophical Presuppositions of Cultural Relativism and Cultural Absolutism, in ETHICS AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES 51 (Leo Ward ed., 1959); RICHARD B. BRANDT, ETHICAL THEORY ch. 11 (1959); T. L. McClintock, The Argument for Ethical Relativism from the Diversity of Morals, 47 MONIST 528 (1963); PAUL W. TAYLOR, PRINCIPLES OF ETHICS ch. 2 (1975); William H. Shaw, Relativism and Objectivity in Ethics, in MORALITY AND MORAL CONTROVERSIES 31 (John Arthur ed., 1981); F. C. WHITE, KNOWLEDGE AND RELATIVISM chs. 4-5 (1983); JEFFREY STOUT, ETHICS AFTER BABEL pt. 1 (1988); LOUIS P. POJMAN, ETHICS: DISCOVERING RIGHT AND WRONG chs. 2-3 (2d ed. 1995). My discussion has benefitted from these authors at many points. A related note: this article was finished in all essentials in mid-1997; hence, it makes little use of items that have appeared since then. Among those items are the following, which I recommend highly: Elizabeth M. Zechenter, In the Name of Culture: Cultural Relativism and the Abuse of the Individual, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 319 (1997); Michael J. Perry, Are Human Rights Universal?: The Relativist Challenge and Related Matters, 19 HUM. RTS. Q. 461 (1997); MICHELE M. MOODY-ADAMS, FIELDVVORK IN FAMILIAR PLACES: MORALITY, CULTURE, AND PHILOSOPHY (1997); William Max Knorpp Jr., What Relativism Isn't, 73 PHILOSOPHY 277 (1998); JOHN W. COOK, MORALITY AND CULTURAL DIFFERENCES (1999).
    • (1983) Knowledge and Relativism
    • White, F.C.1
  • 24
    • 9744242464 scopus 로고
    • Critical studies of cultural relativism are numerous. Useful ones include the "correctives" in note 3. See also W.T. STACE, THE CONCEPT OF MORALS chs. 1-2, 10 (1937); Elgin Williams, Anthropology for the Common Man, 49 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 84 (1947); Frank E. Hartung, Cultural Relativity and Moral Judgments, 21 PHIL. SCI. 118 (1954); Paul F. Schmidt, Some Criticisms of Cultural Relativism, 52 J. PHIL. 780 (1955); David Bidney, The Philosophical Presuppositions of Cultural Relativism and Cultural Absolutism, in ETHICS AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES 51 (Leo Ward ed., 1959); RICHARD B. BRANDT, ETHICAL THEORY ch. 11 (1959); T. L. McClintock, The Argument for Ethical Relativism from the Diversity of Morals, 47 MONIST 528 (1963); PAUL W. TAYLOR, PRINCIPLES OF ETHICS ch. 2 (1975); William H. Shaw, Relativism and Objectivity in Ethics, in MORALITY AND MORAL CONTROVERSIES 31 (John Arthur ed., 1981); F. C. WHITE, KNOWLEDGE AND RELATIVISM chs. 4-5 (1983); JEFFREY STOUT, ETHICS AFTER BABEL pt. 1 (1988); LOUIS P. POJMAN, ETHICS: DISCOVERING RIGHT AND WRONG chs. 2-3 (2d ed. 1995). My discussion has benefitted from these authors at many points. A related note: this article was finished in all essentials in mid-1997; hence, it makes little use of items that have appeared since then. Among those items are the following, which I recommend highly: Elizabeth M. Zechenter, In the Name of Culture: Cultural Relativism and the Abuse of the Individual, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 319 (1997); Michael J. Perry, Are Human Rights Universal?: The Relativist Challenge and Related Matters, 19 HUM. RTS. Q. 461 (1997); MICHELE M. MOODY-ADAMS, FIELDVVORK IN FAMILIAR PLACES: MORALITY, CULTURE, AND PHILOSOPHY (1997); William Max Knorpp Jr., What Relativism Isn't, 73 PHILOSOPHY 277 (1998); JOHN W. COOK, MORALITY AND CULTURAL DIFFERENCES (1999).
    • (1988) Ethics After Babel , Issue.1 PART
    • Stout, J.1
  • 25
    • 0003974219 scopus 로고
    • chs. 2-3 2d ed.
    • Critical studies of cultural relativism are numerous. Useful ones include the "correctives" in note 3. See also W.T. STACE, THE CONCEPT OF MORALS chs. 1-2, 10 (1937); Elgin Williams, Anthropology for the Common Man, 49 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 84 (1947); Frank E. Hartung, Cultural Relativity and Moral Judgments, 21 PHIL. SCI. 118 (1954); Paul F. Schmidt, Some Criticisms of Cultural Relativism, 52 J. PHIL. 780 (1955); David Bidney, The Philosophical Presuppositions of Cultural Relativism and Cultural Absolutism, in ETHICS AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES 51 (Leo Ward ed., 1959); RICHARD B. BRANDT, ETHICAL THEORY ch. 11 (1959); T. L. McClintock, The Argument for Ethical Relativism from the Diversity of Morals, 47 MONIST 528 (1963); PAUL W. TAYLOR, PRINCIPLES OF ETHICS ch. 2 (1975); William H. Shaw, Relativism and Objectivity in Ethics, in MORALITY AND MORAL CONTROVERSIES 31 (John Arthur ed., 1981); F. C. WHITE, KNOWLEDGE AND RELATIVISM chs. 4-5 (1983); JEFFREY STOUT, ETHICS AFTER BABEL pt. 1 (1988); LOUIS P. POJMAN, ETHICS: DISCOVERING RIGHT AND WRONG chs. 2-3 (2d ed. 1995). My discussion has benefitted from these authors at many points. A related note: this article was finished in all essentials in mid-1997; hence, it makes little use of items that have appeared since then. Among those items are the following, which I recommend highly: Elizabeth M. Zechenter, In the Name of Culture: Cultural Relativism and the Abuse of the Individual, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 319 (1997); Michael J. Perry, Are Human Rights Universal?: The Relativist Challenge and Related Matters, 19 HUM. RTS. Q. 461 (1997); MICHELE M. MOODY-ADAMS, FIELDVVORK IN FAMILIAR PLACES: MORALITY, CULTURE, AND PHILOSOPHY (1997); William Max Knorpp Jr., What Relativism Isn't, 73 PHILOSOPHY 277 (1998); JOHN W. COOK, MORALITY AND CULTURAL DIFFERENCES (1999).
    • (1995) Ethics: Discovering Right and Wrong
    • Pojman, L.P.1
  • 26
    • 0009248133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the Name of Culture: Cultural Relativism and the Abuse of the Individual
    • Critical studies of cultural relativism are numerous. Useful ones include the "correctives" in note 3. See also W.T. STACE, THE CONCEPT OF MORALS chs. 1-2, 10 (1937); Elgin Williams, Anthropology for the Common Man, 49 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 84 (1947); Frank E. Hartung, Cultural Relativity and Moral Judgments, 21 PHIL. SCI. 118 (1954); Paul F. Schmidt, Some Criticisms of Cultural Relativism, 52 J. PHIL. 780 (1955); David Bidney, The Philosophical Presuppositions of Cultural Relativism and Cultural Absolutism, in ETHICS AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES 51 (Leo Ward ed., 1959); RICHARD B. BRANDT, ETHICAL THEORY ch. 11 (1959); T. L. McClintock, The Argument for Ethical Relativism from the Diversity of Morals, 47 MONIST 528 (1963); PAUL W. TAYLOR, PRINCIPLES OF ETHICS ch. 2 (1975); William H. Shaw, Relativism and Objectivity in Ethics, in MORALITY AND MORAL CONTROVERSIES 31 (John Arthur ed., 1981); F. C. WHITE, KNOWLEDGE AND RELATIVISM chs. 4-5 (1983); JEFFREY STOUT, ETHICS AFTER BABEL pt. 1 (1988); LOUIS P. POJMAN, ETHICS: DISCOVERING RIGHT AND WRONG chs. 2-3 (2d ed. 1995). My discussion has benefitted from these authors at many points. A related note: this article was finished in all essentials in mid-1997; hence, it makes little use of items that have appeared since then. Among those items are the following, which I recommend highly: Elizabeth M. Zechenter, In the Name of Culture: Cultural Relativism and the Abuse of the Individual, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 319 (1997); Michael J. Perry, Are Human Rights Universal?: The Relativist Challenge and Related Matters, 19 HUM. RTS. Q. 461 (1997); MICHELE M. MOODY-ADAMS, FIELDVVORK IN FAMILIAR PLACES: MORALITY, CULTURE, AND PHILOSOPHY (1997); William Max Knorpp Jr., What Relativism Isn't, 73 PHILOSOPHY 277 (1998); JOHN W. COOK, MORALITY AND CULTURAL DIFFERENCES (1999).
    • (1997) J. Anthropological Res. , vol.53 , pp. 319
    • Zechenter, E.M.1
  • 27
    • 0001136329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Are Human Rights Universal?: The Relativist Challenge and Related Matters
    • Critical studies of cultural relativism are numerous. Useful ones include the "correctives" in note 3. See also W.T. STACE, THE CONCEPT OF MORALS chs. 1-2, 10 (1937); Elgin Williams, Anthropology for the Common Man, 49 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 84 (1947); Frank E. Hartung, Cultural Relativity and Moral Judgments, 21 PHIL. SCI. 118 (1954); Paul F. Schmidt, Some Criticisms of Cultural Relativism, 52 J. PHIL. 780 (1955); David Bidney, The Philosophical Presuppositions of Cultural Relativism and Cultural Absolutism, in ETHICS AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES 51 (Leo Ward ed., 1959); RICHARD B. BRANDT, ETHICAL THEORY ch. 11 (1959); T. L. McClintock, The Argument for Ethical Relativism from the Diversity of Morals, 47 MONIST 528 (1963); PAUL W. TAYLOR, PRINCIPLES OF ETHICS ch. 2 (1975); William H. Shaw, Relativism and Objectivity in Ethics, in MORALITY AND MORAL CONTROVERSIES 31 (John Arthur ed., 1981); F. C. WHITE, KNOWLEDGE AND RELATIVISM chs. 4-5 (1983); JEFFREY STOUT, ETHICS AFTER BABEL pt. 1 (1988); LOUIS P. POJMAN, ETHICS: DISCOVERING RIGHT AND WRONG chs. 2-3 (2d ed. 1995). My discussion has benefitted from these authors at many points. A related note: this article was finished in all essentials in mid-1997; hence, it makes little use of items that have appeared since then. Among those items are the following, which I recommend highly: Elizabeth M. Zechenter, In the Name of Culture: Cultural Relativism and the Abuse of the Individual, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 319 (1997); Michael J. Perry, Are Human Rights Universal?: The Relativist Challenge and Related Matters, 19 HUM. RTS. Q. 461 (1997); MICHELE M. MOODY-ADAMS, FIELDVVORK IN FAMILIAR PLACES: MORALITY, CULTURE, AND PHILOSOPHY (1997); William Max Knorpp Jr., What Relativism Isn't, 73 PHILOSOPHY 277 (1998); JOHN W. COOK, MORALITY AND CULTURAL DIFFERENCES (1999).
    • (1997) Hum. Rts. Q. , vol.19 , pp. 461
    • Perry, M.J.1
  • 28
    • 1642531766 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Critical studies of cultural relativism are numerous. Useful ones include the "correctives" in note 3. See also W.T. STACE, THE CONCEPT OF MORALS chs. 1-2, 10 (1937); Elgin Williams, Anthropology for the Common Man, 49 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 84 (1947); Frank E. Hartung, Cultural Relativity and Moral Judgments, 21 PHIL. SCI. 118 (1954); Paul F. Schmidt, Some Criticisms of Cultural Relativism, 52 J. PHIL. 780 (1955); David Bidney, The Philosophical Presuppositions of Cultural Relativism and Cultural Absolutism, in ETHICS AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES 51 (Leo Ward ed., 1959); RICHARD B. BRANDT, ETHICAL THEORY ch. 11 (1959); T. L. McClintock, The Argument for Ethical Relativism from the Diversity of Morals, 47 MONIST 528 (1963); PAUL W. TAYLOR, PRINCIPLES OF ETHICS ch. 2 (1975); William H. Shaw, Relativism and Objectivity in Ethics, in MORALITY AND MORAL CONTROVERSIES 31 (John Arthur ed., 1981); F. C. WHITE, KNOWLEDGE AND RELATIVISM chs. 4-5 (1983); JEFFREY STOUT, ETHICS AFTER BABEL pt. 1 (1988); LOUIS P. POJMAN, ETHICS: DISCOVERING RIGHT AND WRONG chs. 2-3 (2d ed. 1995). My discussion has benefitted from these authors at many points. A related note: this article was finished in all essentials in mid-1997; hence, it makes little use of items that have appeared since then. Among those items are the following, which I recommend highly: Elizabeth M. Zechenter, In the Name of Culture: Cultural Relativism and the Abuse of the Individual, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 319 (1997); Michael J. Perry, Are Human Rights Universal?: The Relativist Challenge and Related Matters, 19 HUM. RTS. Q. 461 (1997); MICHELE M. MOODY-ADAMS, FIELDWORK IN FAMILIAR PLACES: MORALITY, CULTURE, AND PHILOSOPHY (1997); William Max Knorpp Jr., What Relativism Isn't, 73 PHILOSOPHY 277 (1998); JOHN W. COOK, MORALITY AND CULTURAL DIFFERENCES (1999).
    • (1997) Fieldwork in Familiar Places: Morality, Culture, and Philosophy
    • Moody-Adams, M.M.1
  • 29
    • 9744257415 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What Relativism Isn't
    • Critical studies of cultural relativism are numerous. Useful ones include the "correctives" in note 3. See also W.T. STACE, THE CONCEPT OF MORALS chs. 1-2, 10 (1937); Elgin Williams, Anthropology for the Common Man, 49 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 84 (1947); Frank E. Hartung, Cultural Relativity and Moral Judgments, 21 PHIL. SCI. 118 (1954); Paul F. Schmidt, Some Criticisms of Cultural Relativism, 52 J. PHIL. 780 (1955); David Bidney, The Philosophical Presuppositions of Cultural Relativism and Cultural Absolutism, in ETHICS AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES 51 (Leo Ward ed., 1959); RICHARD B. BRANDT, ETHICAL THEORY ch. 11 (1959); T. L. McClintock, The Argument for Ethical Relativism from the Diversity of Morals, 47 MONIST 528 (1963); PAUL W. TAYLOR, PRINCIPLES OF ETHICS ch. 2 (1975); William H. Shaw, Relativism and Objectivity in Ethics, in MORALITY AND MORAL CONTROVERSIES 31 (John Arthur ed., 1981); F. C. WHITE, KNOWLEDGE AND RELATIVISM chs. 4-5 (1983); JEFFREY STOUT, ETHICS AFTER BABEL pt. 1 (1988); LOUIS P. POJMAN, ETHICS: DISCOVERING RIGHT AND WRONG chs. 2-3 (2d ed. 1995). My discussion has benefitted from these authors at many points. A related note: this article was finished in all essentials in mid-1997; hence, it makes little use of items that have appeared since then. Among those items are the following, which I recommend highly: Elizabeth M. Zechenter, In the Name of Culture: Cultural Relativism and the Abuse of the Individual, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 319 (1997); Michael J. Perry, Are Human Rights Universal?: The Relativist Challenge and Related Matters, 19 HUM. RTS. Q. 461 (1997); MICHELE M. MOODY-ADAMS, FIELDVVORK IN FAMILIAR PLACES: MORALITY, CULTURE, AND PHILOSOPHY (1997); William Max Knorpp Jr., What Relativism Isn't, 73 PHILOSOPHY 277 (1998); JOHN W. COOK, MORALITY AND CULTURAL DIFFERENCES (1999).
    • (1998) Philosophy , vol.73 , pp. 277
    • Knorpp Jr., W.M.1
  • 30
    • 0003462141 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Critical studies of cultural relativism are numerous. Useful ones include the "correctives" in note 3. See also W.T. STACE, THE CONCEPT OF MORALS chs. 1-2, 10 (1937); Elgin Williams, Anthropology for the Common Man, 49 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 84 (1947); Frank E. Hartung, Cultural Relativity and Moral Judgments, 21 PHIL. SCI. 118 (1954); Paul F. Schmidt, Some Criticisms of Cultural Relativism, 52 J. PHIL. 780 (1955); David Bidney, The Philosophical Presuppositions of Cultural Relativism and Cultural Absolutism, in ETHICS AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES 51 (Leo Ward ed., 1959); RICHARD B. BRANDT, ETHICAL THEORY ch. 11 (1959); T. L. McClintock, The Argument for Ethical Relativism from the Diversity of Morals, 47 MONIST 528 (1963); PAUL W. TAYLOR, PRINCIPLES OF ETHICS ch. 2 (1975); William H. Shaw, Relativism and Objectivity in Ethics, in MORALITY AND MORAL CONTROVERSIES 31 (John Arthur ed., 1981); F. C. WHITE, KNOWLEDGE AND RELATIVISM chs. 4-5 (1983); JEFFREY STOUT, ETHICS AFTER BABEL pt. 1 (1988); LOUIS P. POJMAN, ETHICS: DISCOVERING RIGHT AND WRONG chs. 2-3 (2d ed. 1995). My discussion has benefitted from these authors at many points. A related note: this article was finished in all essentials in mid-1997; hence, it makes little use of items that have appeared since then. Among those items are the following, which I recommend highly: Elizabeth M. Zechenter, In the Name of Culture: Cultural Relativism and the Abuse of the Individual, 53 J. ANTHROPOLOGICAL RES. 319 (1997); Michael J. Perry, Are Human Rights Universal?: The Relativist Challenge and Related Matters, 19 HUM. RTS. Q. 461 (1997); MICHELE M. MOODY-ADAMS, FIELDVVORK IN FAMILIAR PLACES: MORALITY, CULTURE, AND PHILOSOPHY (1997); William Max Knorpp Jr., What Relativism Isn't, 73 PHILOSOPHY 277 (1998); JOHN W. COOK, MORALITY AND CULTURAL DIFFERENCES (1999).
    • (1999) Morality and Cultural Differences
    • Cook, J.W.1
  • 31
    • 9744280887 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One of my aims is to avoid the errors listed in the Appendix
    • One of my aims is to avoid the errors listed in the Appendix.
  • 32
    • 9744284683 scopus 로고
    • ch. 2 2d ed.
    • For a prime example, see JAMES F. DOWNS, CULTURES IN CRISIS ch. 2 (2d ed. 1975). Downs not only fails to pin down the moral theory he intends, but allows it to change from page to page and to remain entangled with nonmoral ones. For other examples, see RUTH BENEDICT, PATTERNS OF CULTURE 278 (1934); Ruth Benedict, Ideologies in the Light of Comparative Data, in AN ANTHROPOLOGIST AT WORK 383-84 (Margaret Mead ed., 1959); MELVILLE J. HERSKOVITS, CULTURAL RELATIVISM: PERSPECTIVES IN CULTURAL PLURALISM 14, 15, 32-33, 93, 101 (Frances Herskovits ed., 1973).
    • (1975) Cultures in Crisis
    • Downs, J.F.1
  • 33
    • 0004110550 scopus 로고
    • For a prime example, see JAMES F. DOWNS, CULTURES IN CRISIS ch. 2 (2d ed. 1975). Downs not only fails to pin down the moral theory he intends, but allows it to change from page to page and to remain entangled with nonmoral ones. For other examples, see RUTH BENEDICT, PATTERNS OF CULTURE 278 (1934); Ruth Benedict, Ideologies in the Light of Comparative Data, in AN ANTHROPOLOGIST AT WORK 383-84 (Margaret Mead ed., 1959); MELVILLE J. HERSKOVITS, CULTURAL RELATIVISM: PERSPECTIVES IN CULTURAL PLURALISM 14, 15, 32-33, 93, 101 (Frances Herskovits ed., 1973).
    • (1934) Patterns of Culture , pp. 278
    • Benedict, R.1
  • 34
    • 84925151553 scopus 로고
    • Ideologies in the Light of Comparative Data
    • Margaret Mead ed.
    • For a prime example, see JAMES F. DOWNS, CULTURES IN CRISIS ch. 2 (2d ed. 1975). Downs not only fails to pin down the moral theory he intends, but allows it to change from page to page and to remain entangled with nonmoral ones. For other examples, see RUTH BENEDICT, PATTERNS OF CULTURE 278 (1934); Ruth Benedict, Ideologies in the Light of Comparative Data, in AN ANTHROPOLOGIST AT WORK 383-84 (Margaret Mead ed., 1959); MELVILLE J. HERSKOVITS, CULTURAL RELATIVISM: PERSPECTIVES IN CULTURAL PLURALISM 14, 15, 32-33, 93, 101 (Frances Herskovits ed., 1973).
    • (1959) An Anthropologist at Work , pp. 383-384
    • Benedict, R.1
  • 35
    • 0004183178 scopus 로고
    • Frances Herskovits ed.
    • For a prime example, see JAMES F. DOWNS, CULTURES IN CRISIS ch. 2 (2d ed. 1975). Downs not only fails to pin down the moral theory he intends, but allows it to change from page to page and to remain entangled with nonmoral ones. For other examples, see RUTH BENEDICT, PATTERNS OF CULTURE 278 (1934); Ruth Benedict, Ideologies in the Light of Comparative Data, in AN ANTHROPOLOGIST AT WORK 383-84 (Margaret Mead ed., 1959); MELVILLE J. HERSKOVITS, CULTURAL RELATIVISM: PERSPECTIVES IN CULTURAL PLURALISM 14, 15, 32-33, 93, 101 (Frances Herskovits ed., 1973).
    • (1973) Cultural Relativism: Perspectives in Cultural Pluralism , pp. 14
    • Herskovits, M.J.1
  • 36
    • 84933101908 scopus 로고
    • Anthropology and the Abnormal
    • I have in mind BENEDICT, supra note 6; Ruth Benedict, Anthropology and the Abnormal, 10 J. GEN. PSYCHOL. 59 (1934); HERSKOVITS, supra note 6; MELVILLE J. HERSKOVITS, MAN AND HIS WORKS (1948); and WILLIAM GRAHAM SUMNER, FOLKWAYS (1906). (Some would add Edward Westermarck to this list, but he is properly classified as a moral subjectivist, not as a cultural relativist.) Benedict's work reflects the influence of Oswald Spengler, who defends cultural relativism in 1 OSWALD SPENGLER, THE DECLINE OF THE WEST 345-46 (Charles F. Atkinson trans., 1932) (rev. ed. 1922). A lesser known relativist, well worth consulting, is CLARENCE E. AYRES, HOLIER THAN THOU: THE WAY OF THE RIGHTEOUS (1929). Additional endorsements of cultural relativism are easy to find. See, e.g., ALLEN WHEELIS, THE QUEST FOR IDENTITY 94-96 (1958); EDMUND R. LEACH, A RUNAWAY WORLD? 48 (1968); Paul Piccone, Introduction, 106 TELOS 8 (1996). For recent defenses (as opposed to mere endorsements) of relativism, see RENTELN, supra note 3, ch. 3; Clifford Geertz, Anti Anti-Relativism, 86 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 263 (1984). Actually, "defenses" is not quite accurate. Geertz's aim is not to support relativism, but to point out faults and excesses of anti-relativists. Renteln's chief aim is to "correct the caricatured picture of relativism" and to uncover the implications of relativism for human rights issues. RENTELN, supra note 3, ch. 3. So it is not surprising that neither author adds to the stock of arguments used by Sumner, Benedict, and Herskovits. A valuable history of cultural relativism is ELVIN HATCH, CULTURE AND MORALITY: THE RELATIVITY OF VALUES IN ANTHROPOLOGY (1983).
    • (1934) J. Gen. Psychol. , vol.10 , pp. 59
    • Benedict, R.1
  • 37
    • 0003979835 scopus 로고
    • I have in mind BENEDICT, supra note 6; Ruth Benedict, Anthropology and the Abnormal, 10 J. GEN. PSYCHOL. 59 (1934); HERSKOVITS, supra note 6; MELVILLE J. HERSKOVITS, MAN AND HIS WORKS (1948); and WILLIAM GRAHAM SUMNER, FOLKWAYS (1906). (Some would add Edward Westermarck to this list, but he is properly classified as a moral subjectivist, not as a cultural relativist.) Benedict's work reflects the influence of Oswald Spengler, who defends cultural relativism in 1 OSWALD SPENGLER, THE DECLINE OF THE WEST 345-46 (Charles F. Atkinson trans., 1932) (rev. ed. 1922). A lesser known relativist, well worth consulting, is CLARENCE E. AYRES, HOLIER THAN THOU: THE WAY OF THE RIGHTEOUS (1929). Additional endorsements of cultural relativism are easy to find. See, e.g., ALLEN WHEELIS, THE QUEST FOR IDENTITY 94-96 (1958); EDMUND R. LEACH, A RUNAWAY WORLD? 48 (1968); Paul Piccone, Introduction, 106 TELOS 8 (1996). For recent defenses (as opposed to mere endorsements) of relativism, see RENTELN, supra note 3, ch. 3; Clifford Geertz, Anti Anti-Relativism, 86 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 263 (1984). Actually, "defenses" is not quite accurate. Geertz's aim is not to support relativism, but to point out faults and excesses of anti-relativists. Renteln's chief aim is to "correct the caricatured picture of relativism" and to uncover the implications of relativism for human rights issues. RENTELN, supra note 3, ch. 3. So it is not surprising that neither author adds to the stock of arguments used by Sumner, Benedict, and Herskovits. A valuable history of cultural relativism is ELVIN HATCH, CULTURE AND MORALITY: THE RELATIVITY OF VALUES IN ANTHROPOLOGY (1983).
    • (1948) Man and His Works
    • Herskovits, M.J.1
  • 38
    • 0004205157 scopus 로고
    • I have in mind BENEDICT, supra note 6; Ruth Benedict, Anthropology and the Abnormal, 10 J. GEN. PSYCHOL. 59 (1934); HERSKOVITS, supra note 6; MELVILLE J. HERSKOVITS, MAN AND HIS WORKS (1948); and WILLIAM GRAHAM SUMNER, FOLKWAYS (1906). (Some would add Edward Westermarck to this list, but he is properly classified as a moral subjectivist, not as a cultural relativist.) Benedict's work reflects the influence of Oswald Spengler, who defends cultural relativism in 1 OSWALD SPENGLER, THE DECLINE OF THE WEST 345-46 (Charles F. Atkinson trans., 1932) (rev. ed. 1922). A lesser known relativist, well worth consulting, is CLARENCE E. AYRES, HOLIER THAN THOU: THE WAY OF THE RIGHTEOUS (1929). Additional endorsements of cultural relativism are easy to find. See, e.g., ALLEN WHEELIS, THE QUEST FOR IDENTITY 94-96 (1958); EDMUND R. LEACH, A RUNAWAY WORLD? 48 (1968); Paul Piccone, Introduction, 106 TELOS 8 (1996). For recent defenses (as opposed to mere endorsements) of relativism, see RENTELN, supra note 3, ch. 3; Clifford Geertz, Anti Anti-Relativism, 86 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 263 (1984). Actually, "defenses" is not quite accurate. Geertz's aim is not to support relativism, but to point out faults and excesses of anti-relativists. Renteln's chief aim is to "correct the caricatured picture of relativism" and to uncover the implications of relativism for human rights issues. RENTELN, supra note 3, ch. 3. So it is not surprising that neither author adds to the stock of arguments used by Sumner, Benedict, and Herskovits. A valuable history of cultural relativism is ELVIN HATCH, CULTURE AND MORALITY: THE RELATIVITY OF VALUES IN ANTHROPOLOGY (1983).
    • (1906) Folkways
    • Sumner, W.G.1
  • 39
    • 9744246486 scopus 로고
    • Charles F. Atkinson trans., (rev. ed. 1922)
    • I have in mind BENEDICT, supra note 6; Ruth Benedict, Anthropology and the Abnormal, 10 J. GEN. PSYCHOL. 59 (1934); HERSKOVITS, supra note 6; MELVILLE J. HERSKOVITS, MAN AND HIS WORKS (1948); and WILLIAM GRAHAM SUMNER, FOLKWAYS (1906). (Some would add Edward Westermarck to this list, but he is properly classified as a moral subjectivist, not as a cultural relativist.) Benedict's work reflects the influence of Oswald Spengler, who defends cultural relativism in 1 OSWALD SPENGLER, THE DECLINE OF THE WEST 345-46 (Charles F. Atkinson trans., 1932) (rev. ed. 1922). A lesser known relativist, well worth consulting, is CLARENCE E. AYRES, HOLIER THAN THOU: THE WAY OF THE RIGHTEOUS (1929). Additional endorsements of cultural relativism are easy to find. See, e.g., ALLEN WHEELIS, THE QUEST FOR IDENTITY 94-96 (1958); EDMUND R. LEACH, A RUNAWAY WORLD? 48 (1968); Paul Piccone, Introduction, 106 TELOS 8 (1996). For recent defenses (as opposed to mere endorsements) of relativism, see RENTELN, supra note 3, ch. 3; Clifford Geertz, Anti Anti-Relativism, 86 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 263 (1984). Actually, "defenses" is not quite accurate. Geertz's aim is not to support relativism, but to point out faults and excesses of anti-relativists. Renteln's chief aim is to "correct the caricatured picture of relativism" and to uncover the implications of relativism for human rights issues. RENTELN, supra note 3, ch. 3. So it is not surprising that neither author adds to the stock of arguments used by Sumner, Benedict, and Herskovits. A valuable history of cultural relativism is ELVIN HATCH, CULTURE AND MORALITY: THE RELATIVITY OF VALUES IN ANTHROPOLOGY (1983).
    • (1932) The Decline of the West , pp. 345-346
    • Spengler, O.1
  • 40
    • 0038982812 scopus 로고
    • I have in mind BENEDICT, supra note 6; Ruth Benedict, Anthropology and the Abnormal, 10 J. GEN. PSYCHOL. 59 (1934); HERSKOVITS, supra note 6; MELVILLE J. HERSKOVITS, MAN AND HIS WORKS (1948); and WILLIAM GRAHAM SUMNER, FOLKWAYS (1906). (Some would add Edward Westermarck to this list, but he is properly classified as a moral subjectivist, not as a cultural relativist.) Benedict's work reflects the influence of Oswald Spengler, who defends cultural relativism in 1 OSWALD SPENGLER, THE DECLINE OF THE WEST 345-46 (Charles F. Atkinson trans., 1932) (rev. ed. 1922). A lesser known relativist, well worth consulting, is CLARENCE E. AYRES, HOLIER THAN THOU: THE WAY OF THE RIGHTEOUS (1929). Additional endorsements of cultural relativism are easy to find. See, e.g., ALLEN WHEELIS, THE QUEST FOR IDENTITY 94-96 (1958); EDMUND R. LEACH, A RUNAWAY WORLD? 48 (1968); Paul Piccone, Introduction, 106 TELOS 8 (1996). For recent defenses (as opposed to mere endorsements) of relativism, see RENTELN, supra note 3, ch. 3; Clifford Geertz, Anti Anti-Relativism, 86 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 263 (1984). Actually, "defenses" is not quite accurate. Geertz's aim is not to support relativism, but to point out faults and excesses of anti-relativists. Renteln's chief aim is to "correct the caricatured picture of relativism" and to uncover the implications of relativism for human rights issues. RENTELN, supra note 3, ch. 3. So it is not surprising that neither author adds to the stock of arguments used by Sumner, Benedict, and Herskovits. A valuable history of cultural relativism is ELVIN HATCH, CULTURE AND MORALITY: THE RELATIVITY OF VALUES IN ANTHROPOLOGY (1983).
    • (1929) Holier Than Thou: The Way of the Righteous
    • Ayres, C.E.1
  • 41
    • 0004241444 scopus 로고
    • I have in mind BENEDICT, supra note 6; Ruth Benedict, Anthropology and the Abnormal, 10 J. GEN. PSYCHOL. 59 (1934); HERSKOVITS, supra note 6; MELVILLE J. HERSKOVITS, MAN AND HIS WORKS (1948); and WILLIAM GRAHAM SUMNER, FOLKWAYS (1906). (Some would add Edward Westermarck to this list, but he is properly classified as a moral subjectivist, not as a cultural relativist.) Benedict's work reflects the influence of Oswald Spengler, who defends cultural relativism in 1 OSWALD SPENGLER, THE DECLINE OF THE WEST 345-46 (Charles F. Atkinson trans., 1932) (rev. ed. 1922). A lesser known relativist, well worth consulting, is CLARENCE E. AYRES, HOLIER THAN THOU: THE WAY OF THE RIGHTEOUS (1929). Additional endorsements of cultural relativism are easy to find. See, e.g., ALLEN WHEELIS, THE QUEST FOR IDENTITY 94-96 (1958); EDMUND R. LEACH, A RUNAWAY WORLD? 48 (1968); Paul Piccone, Introduction, 106 TELOS 8 (1996). For recent defenses (as opposed to mere endorsements) of relativism, see RENTELN, supra note 3, ch. 3; Clifford Geertz, Anti Anti-Relativism, 86 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 263 (1984). Actually, "defenses" is not quite accurate. Geertz's aim is not to support relativism, but to point out faults and excesses of anti-relativists. Renteln's chief aim is to "correct the caricatured picture of relativism" and to uncover the implications of relativism for human rights issues. RENTELN, supra note 3, ch. 3. So it is not surprising that neither author adds to the stock of arguments used by Sumner, Benedict, and Herskovits. A valuable history of cultural relativism is ELVIN HATCH, CULTURE AND MORALITY: THE RELATIVITY OF VALUES IN ANTHROPOLOGY (1983).
    • (1958) The Quest for Identity , pp. 94-96
    • Wheelis, A.1
  • 42
    • 0010182120 scopus 로고
    • I have in mind BENEDICT, supra note 6; Ruth Benedict, Anthropology and the Abnormal, 10 J. GEN. PSYCHOL. 59 (1934); HERSKOVITS, supra note 6; MELVILLE J. HERSKOVITS, MAN AND HIS WORKS (1948); and WILLIAM GRAHAM SUMNER, FOLKWAYS (1906). (Some would add Edward Westermarck to this list, but he is properly classified as a moral subjectivist, not as a cultural relativist.) Benedict's work reflects the influence of Oswald Spengler, who defends cultural relativism in 1 OSWALD SPENGLER, THE DECLINE OF THE WEST 345-46 (Charles F. Atkinson trans., 1932) (rev. ed. 1922). A lesser known relativist, well worth consulting, is CLARENCE E. AYRES, HOLIER THAN THOU: THE WAY OF THE RIGHTEOUS (1929). Additional endorsements of cultural relativism are easy to find. See, e.g., ALLEN WHEELIS, THE QUEST FOR IDENTITY 94-96 (1958); EDMUND R. LEACH, A RUNAWAY WORLD? 48 (1968); Paul Piccone, Introduction, 106 TELOS 8 (1996). For recent defenses (as opposed to mere endorsements) of relativism, see RENTELN, supra note 3, ch. 3; Clifford Geertz, Anti Anti-Relativism, 86 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 263 (1984). Actually, "defenses" is not quite accurate. Geertz's aim is not to support relativism, but to point out faults and excesses of anti-relativists. Renteln's chief aim is to "correct the caricatured picture of relativism" and to uncover the implications of relativism for human rights issues. RENTELN, supra note 3, ch. 3. So it is not surprising that neither author adds to the stock of arguments used by Sumner, Benedict, and Herskovits. A valuable history of cultural relativism is ELVIN HATCH, CULTURE AND MORALITY: THE RELATIVITY OF VALUES IN ANTHROPOLOGY (1983).
    • (1968) A Runaway World? , pp. 48
    • Leach, E.R.1
  • 43
    • 84937281090 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Introduction
    • I have in mind BENEDICT, supra note 6; Ruth Benedict, Anthropology and the Abnormal, 10 J. GEN. PSYCHOL. 59 (1934); HERSKOVITS, supra note 6; MELVILLE J. HERSKOVITS, MAN AND HIS WORKS (1948); and WILLIAM GRAHAM SUMNER, FOLKWAYS (1906). (Some would add Edward Westermarck to this list, but he is properly classified as a moral subjectivist, not as a cultural relativist.) Benedict's work reflects the influence of Oswald Spengler, who defends cultural relativism in 1 OSWALD SPENGLER, THE DECLINE OF THE WEST 345-46 (Charles F. Atkinson trans., 1932) (rev. ed. 1922). A lesser known relativist, well worth consulting, is CLARENCE E. AYRES, HOLIER THAN THOU: THE WAY OF THE RIGHTEOUS (1929). Additional endorsements of cultural relativism are easy to find. See, e.g., ALLEN WHEELIS, THE QUEST FOR IDENTITY 94-96 (1958); EDMUND R. LEACH, A RUNAWAY WORLD? 48 (1968); Paul Piccone, Introduction, 106 TELOS 8 (1996). For recent defenses (as opposed to mere endorsements) of relativism, see RENTELN, supra note 3, ch. 3; Clifford Geertz, Anti Anti-Relativism, 86 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 263 (1984). Actually, "defenses" is not quite accurate. Geertz's aim is not to support relativism, but to point out faults and excesses of anti-relativists. Renteln's chief aim is to "correct the caricatured picture of relativism" and to uncover the implications of relativism for human rights issues. RENTELN, supra note 3, ch. 3. So it is not surprising that neither author adds to the stock of arguments used by Sumner, Benedict, and Herskovits. A valuable history of cultural relativism is ELVIN HATCH, CULTURE AND MORALITY: THE RELATIVITY OF VALUES IN ANTHROPOLOGY (1983).
    • (1996) Telos , vol.106 , pp. 8
    • Piccone, P.1
  • 44
    • 84982344105 scopus 로고
    • Anti Anti-Relativism
    • I have in mind BENEDICT, supra note 6; Ruth Benedict, Anthropology and the Abnormal, 10 J. GEN. PSYCHOL. 59 (1934); HERSKOVITS, supra note 6; MELVILLE J. HERSKOVITS, MAN AND HIS WORKS (1948); and WILLIAM GRAHAM SUMNER, FOLKWAYS (1906). (Some would add Edward Westermarck to this list, but he is properly classified as a moral subjectivist, not as a cultural relativist.) Benedict's work reflects the influence of Oswald Spengler, who defends cultural relativism in 1 OSWALD SPENGLER, THE DECLINE OF THE WEST 345-46 (Charles F. Atkinson trans., 1932) (rev. ed. 1922). A lesser known relativist, well worth consulting, is CLARENCE E. AYRES, HOLIER THAN THOU: THE WAY OF THE RIGHTEOUS (1929). Additional endorsements of cultural relativism are easy to find. See, e.g., ALLEN WHEELIS, THE QUEST FOR IDENTITY 94-96 (1958); EDMUND R. LEACH, A RUNAWAY WORLD? 48 (1968); Paul Piccone, Introduction, 106 TELOS 8 (1996). For recent defenses (as opposed to mere endorsements) of relativism, see RENTELN, supra note 3, ch. 3; Clifford Geertz, Anti Anti-Relativism, 86 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 263 (1984). Actually, "defenses" is not quite accurate. Geertz's aim is not to support relativism, but to point out faults and excesses of anti-relativists. Renteln's chief aim is to "correct the caricatured picture of relativism" and to uncover the implications of relativism for human rights issues. RENTELN, supra note 3, ch. 3. So it is not surprising that neither author adds to the stock of arguments used by Sumner, Benedict, and Herskovits. A valuable history of cultural relativism is ELVIN HATCH, CULTURE AND MORALITY: THE RELATIVITY OF VALUES IN ANTHROPOLOGY (1983).
    • (1984) Am. Anthropologist , vol.86 , pp. 263
    • Geertz, C.1
  • 45
    • 0009251424 scopus 로고
    • I have in mind BENEDICT, supra note 6; Ruth Benedict, Anthropology and the Abnormal, 10 J. GEN. PSYCHOL. 59 (1934); HERSKOVITS, supra note 6; MELVILLE J. HERSKOVITS, MAN AND HIS WORKS (1948); and WILLIAM GRAHAM SUMNER, FOLKWAYS (1906). (Some would add Edward Westermarck to this list, but he is properly classified as a moral subjectivist, not as a cultural relativist.) Benedict's work reflects the influence of Oswald Spengler, who defends cultural relativism in 1 OSWALD SPENGLER, THE DECLINE OF THE WEST 345-46 (Charles F. Atkinson trans., 1932) (rev. ed. 1922). A lesser known relativist, well worth consulting, is CLARENCE E. AYRES, HOLIER THAN THOU: THE WAY OF THE RIGHTEOUS (1929). Additional endorsements of cultural relativism are easy to find. See, e.g., ALLEN WHEELIS, THE QUEST FOR IDENTITY 94-96 (1958); EDMUND R. LEACH, A RUNAWAY WORLD? 48 (1968); Paul Piccone, Introduction, 106 TELOS 8 (1996). For recent defenses (as opposed to mere endorsements) of relativism, see RENTELN, supra note 3, ch. 3; Clifford Geertz, Anti Anti-Relativism, 86 AM. ANTHROPOLOGIST 263 (1984). Actually, "defenses" is not quite accurate. Geertz's aim is not to support relativism, but to point out faults and excesses of anti-relativists. Renteln's chief aim is to "correct the caricatured picture of relativism" and to uncover the implications of relativism for human rights issues. RENTELN, supra note 3, ch. 3. So it is not surprising that neither author adds to the stock of arguments used by Sumner, Benedict, and Herskovits. A valuable history of cultural relativism is ELVIN HATCH, CULTURE AND MORALITY: THE RELATIVITY OF VALUES IN ANTHROPOLOGY (1983).
    • (1983) Culture and Morality: The Relativity of Values in Anthropology
    • Hatch, E.1
  • 46
    • 9744224026 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The point that they are human beings is not superfluous. Some philosophers use "people" interchangeably with "rational agents," implying that nonhuman rational agents would count as people. This article does not use "people" this broadly.
  • 47
    • 9744285440 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The concept of a nonexistent yet realistically imaginable culture (or person), although fuzzy, is not too fuzzy to be useful. History provides many (though not the only) examples of such cultures, just as science fiction provides many examples of "cultures" that fail to qualify. One reason for extending "cultures" to realistically imaginable cultures, not just to actual ones, is that it enables us to avoid Error 6 in the Appendix. Anyone out to detail some of the central features of realistically imaginable cultures or persons would profit from Nussbaum, supra note 3, at 214-23.
  • 48
    • 9744255912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Three comments: First, in this article "right," "wrong," etc., mean "morally right," "morally wrong," etc. Second, some remarks pertinent to statements i and j are in the Appendix, and much is said about k in Section IV. Third, "X is prima facie wrong" means the same as "other things being equal, X is wrong."
  • 49
    • 9744236975 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is not the only way for "stealing is wrong" to make a covert reference (as I use that term) to C. It would do so if "wrong" were a relational term (like "tall") and C were the relevant reference class.
  • 50
    • 9744283148 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Two remarks: first, I am assuming that a moral judgment is valid for group X only if it is valid for each member of X. Second, as my wording indicates, I am deliberately ignoring the possibility that some moral judgments are relative to group X, but not to group Y, in their truth, and to Y, but not to X, in their content. This view lacks proponents, not to mention plausibility.
  • 51
    • 84976013323 scopus 로고
    • Given the meaning of "culturally relative," some brands of relativism face a curious problem. They assert that some moral judgments are valid for no one. But if "X is wrong" is valid for no one, it seems to follow that "X is not wrong" is valid for everyone, in which case cultural relativism is false. Having mentioned this problem, I will put it aside, except to say that the relativists who face it are not alone. A variation of it plagues error theories of moral judgment. (For such a theory, see J.L. MACKIE, ETHICS: INVENTING RIGHT AND WRONG (1977).) If we agree with error theorists that all moral judgments, including "stealing is wrong," are false, we seem to imply that "stealing is not wrong" is true, in which case not all moral judgments are false. For more on this problem and the prospects for overcoming it, see Jonathan Harrison, Mackie's Moral Scepticism, 57 PHIL. 173 (1982).
    • (1977) Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong
    • Mackie, J.L.1
  • 52
    • 84976013323 scopus 로고
    • Mackie's Moral Scepticism
    • Given the meaning of "culturally relative," some brands of relativism face a curious problem. They assert that some moral judgments are valid for no one. But if "X is wrong" is valid for no one, it seems to follow that "X is not wrong" is valid for everyone, in which case cultural relativism is false. Having mentioned this problem, I will put it aside, except to say that the relativists who face it are not alone. A variation of it plagues error theories of moral judgment. (For such a theory, see J.L. MACKIE, ETHICS: INVENTING RIGHT AND WRONG (1977).) If we agree with error theorists that all moral judgments, including "stealing is wrong," are false, we seem to imply that "stealing is not wrong" is true, in which case not all moral judgments are false. For more on this problem and the prospects for overcoming it, see Jonathan Harrison, Mackie's Moral Scepticism, 57 PHIL. 173 (1982).
    • (1982) Phil. , vol.57 , pp. 173
    • Harrison, J.1
  • 53
    • 84925899438 scopus 로고
    • Ethical Relativism and the Problem of Incoherence
    • SUMNER, supra note 7, §§ 31, 65, 439; HERSKOVITS, supra note 6, at 101; Benedict, supra note 7, at 73. The terms "agent relativism" and "appraiser relativism," by the way, are borrowed from David Lyons, Ethical Relativism and the Problem of Incoherence, 86 ETHICS 107 (1976). (Lyons uses the terms "agent's-group relativism" and "appraiser's-group relativism.")
    • (1976) Ethics , vol.86 , pp. 107
    • Lyons, D.1
  • 54
    • 0003631346 scopus 로고
    • ch. 6 2d ed.
    • A pristine example of moral nihilism is the emotive theory defended by A.J. AYER, LANGUAGE, TRUTH AND LOGIC ch. 6 (2d ed. 1946).
    • (1946) Language, Truth and Logic
    • Ayer, A.J.1
  • 55
    • 9744231087 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is not only the standard way of interpreting cultural relativism, but the only charitable way. It also is borne out by the unqualified way in which cultural relativists state their thesis. See, e.g., SUMNER, supra note 7, §§ 31, 42, 65, 439, 572; HERSKOVITS, supra note 6, at 101; Benedict, supra note 7, at 73. Also relevant are RENTEIN, supra note 3, at 68-69; Schmidt, supra note 4, at 781-82.
  • 56
    • 9744272895 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For example, Sumner, Benedict, and Herskovits seem to do this at times. (I say "seem" because they are not entirely clear about the thesis they intend.) See SUMNER, supra note 7, § 232; BENEDICT, supra note 6, at 2; HERSKOVITS, supra note 6, at 15.
  • 57
    • 0003886748 scopus 로고
    • And when they do have such a view in mind, we usually find them rejecting it. See, e.g., HATCH, supra note 7, chs. 5, 7; H. RUSSELL BERNARD, RESEARCH METHODS IN CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 117 (1988); Henry H. Bagish, Confessions of a Former Cultural Relativist, in ANTHROPOLOGY 90/91, at 30 (Elvio Angeloni ed., 1990); STANLEY JEYARAJA TAMBIAH, MAGIC, SCIENCE, RELIGION, AND THE SCOPE OF RATIONALITY 128-29 (1990); Janine Hitchens, Critical Implications of Franz Boas' Theory and Methodology, 19 DIALECTICAL ANTHROPOLOGY 237, 248-49 (1994); CONRAD PHILLIP KOTTAK, ANTHROPOLOGY: THE EXPLORATION OF HUMAN DIVERSITY 45-46 (6th ed. 1994); James P. Spradley & David W. McCurdy, Culture and the Contemporary World, in CONFORMITY AND CONFLICT 8 (James P. Spradley & David W. McCurdy eds., 9th ed. 1997). A second point: when contemporary anthropologists write about "cultural relativism," they sometimes choose words that suggest one of the theories in Section II. But when their words are read in context, the view in question almost always turns out to be one of those below. This point may pertain to a few of the authors in note 19.
    • (1988) Research Methods in Cultural Anthropology , pp. 117
    • Russell Bernard, H.1
  • 58
    • 84982356126 scopus 로고
    • Confessions of a Former Cultural Relativist
    • Elvio Angeloni ed.
    • And when they do have such a view in mind, we usually find them rejecting it. See, e.g., HATCH, supra note 7, chs. 5, 7; H. RUSSELL BERNARD, RESEARCH METHODS IN CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 117 (1988); Henry H. Bagish, Confessions of a Former Cultural Relativist, in ANTHROPOLOGY 90/91, at 30 (Elvio Angeloni ed., 1990); STANLEY JEYARAJA TAMBIAH, MAGIC, SCIENCE, RELIGION, AND THE SCOPE OF RATIONALITY 128-29 (1990); Janine Hitchens, Critical Implications of Franz Boas' Theory and Methodology, 19 DIALECTICAL ANTHROPOLOGY 237, 248-49 (1994); CONRAD PHILLIP KOTTAK, ANTHROPOLOGY: THE EXPLORATION OF HUMAN DIVERSITY 45-46 (6th ed. 1994); James P. Spradley & David W. McCurdy, Culture and the Contemporary World, in CONFORMITY AND CONFLICT 8 (James P. Spradley & David W. McCurdy eds., 9th ed. 1997). A second point: when contemporary anthropologists write about "cultural relativism," they sometimes choose words that suggest one of the theories in Section II. But when their words are read in context, the view in question almost always turns out to be one of those below. This point may pertain to a few of the authors in note 19.
    • (1990) Anthropology , vol.90-91 , pp. 30
    • Bagish, H.H.1
  • 59
    • 0003765893 scopus 로고
    • And when they do have such a view in mind, we usually find them rejecting it. See, e.g., HATCH, supra note 7, chs. 5, 7; H. RUSSELL BERNARD, RESEARCH METHODS IN CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 117 (1988); Henry H. Bagish, Confessions of a Former Cultural Relativist, in ANTHROPOLOGY 90/91, at 30 (Elvio Angeloni ed., 1990); STANLEY JEYARAJA TAMBIAH, MAGIC, SCIENCE, RELIGION, AND THE SCOPE OF RATIONALITY 128-29 (1990); Janine Hitchens, Critical Implications of Franz Boas' Theory and Methodology, 19 DIALECTICAL ANTHROPOLOGY 237, 248-49 (1994); CONRAD PHILLIP KOTTAK, ANTHROPOLOGY: THE EXPLORATION OF HUMAN DIVERSITY 45-46 (6th ed. 1994); James P. Spradley & David W. McCurdy, Culture and the Contemporary World, in CONFORMITY AND CONFLICT 8 (James P. Spradley & David W. McCurdy eds., 9th ed. 1997). A second point: when contemporary anthropologists write about "cultural relativism," they sometimes choose words that suggest one of the theories in Section II. But when their words are read in context, the view in question almost always turns out to be one of those below. This point may pertain to a few of the authors in note 19.
    • (1990) Magic, Science, Religion, and the Scope of Rationality , pp. 128-129
    • Tambiah, S.J.1
  • 60
    • 9744269346 scopus 로고
    • Critical Implications of Franz Boas' Theory and Methodology
    • And when they do have such a view in mind, we usually find them rejecting it. See, e.g., HATCH, supra note 7, chs. 5, 7; H. RUSSELL BERNARD, RESEARCH METHODS IN CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 117 (1988); Henry H. Bagish, Confessions of a Former Cultural Relativist, in ANTHROPOLOGY 90/91, at 30 (Elvio Angeloni ed., 1990); STANLEY JEYARAJA TAMBIAH, MAGIC, SCIENCE, RELIGION, AND THE SCOPE OF RATIONALITY 128-29 (1990); Janine Hitchens, Critical Implications of Franz Boas' Theory and Methodology, 19 DIALECTICAL ANTHROPOLOGY 237, 248-49 (1994); CONRAD PHILLIP KOTTAK, ANTHROPOLOGY: THE EXPLORATION OF HUMAN DIVERSITY 45-46 (6th ed. 1994); James P. Spradley & David W. McCurdy, Culture and the Contemporary World, in CONFORMITY AND CONFLICT 8 (James P. Spradley & David W. McCurdy eds., 9th ed. 1997). A second point: when contemporary anthropologists write about "cultural relativism," they sometimes choose words that suggest one of the theories in Section II. But when their words are read in context, the view in question almost always turns out to be one of those below. This point may pertain to a few of the authors in note 19.
    • (1994) Dialectical Anthropology , vol.19 , pp. 237
    • Hitchens, J.1
  • 61
    • 0004314538 scopus 로고
    • 6th ed.
    • And when they do have such a view in mind, we usually find them rejecting it. See, e.g., HATCH, supra note 7, chs. 5, 7; H. RUSSELL BERNARD, RESEARCH METHODS IN CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 117 (1988); Henry H. Bagish, Confessions of a Former Cultural Relativist, in ANTHROPOLOGY 90/91, at 30 (Elvio Angeloni ed., 1990); STANLEY JEYARAJA TAMBIAH, MAGIC, SCIENCE, RELIGION, AND THE SCOPE OF RATIONALITY 128-29 (1990); Janine Hitchens, Critical Implications of Franz Boas' Theory and Methodology, 19 DIALECTICAL ANTHROPOLOGY 237, 248-49 (1994); CONRAD PHILLIP KOTTAK, ANTHROPOLOGY: THE EXPLORATION OF HUMAN DIVERSITY 45-46 (6th ed. 1994); James P. Spradley & David W. McCurdy, Culture and the Contemporary World, in CONFORMITY AND CONFLICT 8 (James P. Spradley & David W. McCurdy eds., 9th ed. 1997). A second point: when contemporary anthropologists write about "cultural relativism," they sometimes choose words that suggest one of the theories in Section II. But when their words are read in context, the view in question almost always turns out to be one of those below. This point may pertain to a few of the authors in note 19.
    • (1994) Anthropology: The Exploration of Human Diversity , pp. 45-46
    • Kottak, C.P.1
  • 62
    • 9744274940 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Culture and the Contemporary World
    • James P. Spradley & David W. McCurdy eds., 9th ed.
    • And when they do have such a view in mind, we usually find them rejecting it. See, e.g., HATCH, supra note 7, chs. 5, 7; H. RUSSELL BERNARD, RESEARCH METHODS IN CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 117 (1988); Henry H. Bagish, Confessions of a Former Cultural Relativist, in ANTHROPOLOGY 90/91, at 30 (Elvio Angeloni ed., 1990); STANLEY JEYARAJA TAMBIAH, MAGIC, SCIENCE, RELIGION, AND THE SCOPE OF RATIONALITY 128-29 (1990); Janine Hitchens, Critical Implications of Franz Boas' Theory and Methodology, 19 DIALECTICAL ANTHROPOLOGY 237, 248-49 (1994); CONRAD PHILLIP KOTTAK, ANTHROPOLOGY: THE EXPLORATION OF HUMAN DIVERSITY 45-46 (6th ed. 1994); James P. Spradley & David W. McCurdy, Culture and the Contemporary World, in CONFORMITY AND CONFLICT 8 (James P. Spradley & David W. McCurdy eds., 9th ed. 1997). A second point: when contemporary anthropologists write about "cultural relativism," they sometimes choose words that suggest one of the theories in Section II. But when their words are read in context, the view in question almost always turns out to be one of those below. This point may pertain to a few of the authors in note 19.
    • (1997) Conformity and Conflict , pp. 8
    • Spradley, J.P.1    McCurdy, D.W.2
  • 63
    • 9744251988 scopus 로고
    • 3d ed.
    • These posilions are not new in anthropology (Benedict and Herskovits held both), nor is the habit of calling them "cultural relativism." What is new - i.e., different from the first half of the century - is the habit of restricting that term to these positions, thereby excluding the moral theories in Section II. For the first of the two positions, see RICHLEY H. CRAPO, CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 17, 38-39 (3d ed. 1993); MICHAEL C. HOWARD, CONTEMPORARY CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 5-6, 14 (4th ed. 1993); SERENA NANDA, CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 17, 19 (5th ed. 1994); F. Allan Hanson, Racism and Relativism, 10 TIKKUN 63, 66 (1995). For the second position, see HATCH, supra note 7, at 11; Bagish, supra note 18, at 33-34; MARVIN HARRIS, CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 10-11 (3d ed. 1991); David H.P. Maybury-Lewis, A Special Sort of Pleading: Anthropology at the Service of Ethnic Groups, in TALKING ABOUT PEOPLE: READINGS IN CONTEMPORARY CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 16, 17 (William A. Haviland & Robert J. Gordon eds., 2d ed. 1996).
    • (1993) Cultural Anthropology , vol.17 , pp. 38-39
    • Crapo, R.H.1
  • 64
    • 9744255160 scopus 로고
    • 4th ed.
    • These posilions are not new in anthropology (Benedict and Herskovits held both), nor is the habit of calling them "cultural relativism." What is new - i.e., different from the first half of the century - is the habit of restricting that term to these positions, thereby excluding the moral theories in Section II. For the first of the two positions, see RICHLEY H. CRAPO, CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 17, 38-39 (3d ed. 1993); MICHAEL C. HOWARD, CONTEMPORARY CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 5-6, 14 (4th ed. 1993); SERENA NANDA, CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 17, 19 (5th ed. 1994); F. Allan Hanson, Racism and Relativism, 10 TIKKUN 63, 66 (1995). For the second position, see HATCH, supra note 7, at 11; Bagish, supra note 18, at 33-34; MARVIN HARRIS, CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 10-11 (3d ed. 1991); David H.P. Maybury-Lewis, A Special Sort of Pleading: Anthropology at the Service of Ethnic Groups, in TALKING ABOUT PEOPLE: READINGS IN CONTEMPORARY CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 16, 17 (William A. Haviland & Robert J. Gordon eds., 2d ed. 1996).
    • (1993) Contemporary Cultural Anthropology , vol.5-6 , pp. 14
    • Howard, M.C.1
  • 65
    • 9744269675 scopus 로고
    • 5th ed.
    • These posilions are not new in anthropology (Benedict and Herskovits held both), nor is the habit of calling them "cultural relativism." What is new - i.e., different from the first half of the century - is the habit of restricting that term to these positions, thereby excluding the moral theories in Section II. For the first of the two positions, see RICHLEY H. CRAPO, CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 17, 38-39 (3d ed. 1993); MICHAEL C. HOWARD, CONTEMPORARY CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 5-6, 14 (4th ed. 1993); SERENA NANDA, CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 17, 19 (5th ed. 1994); F. Allan Hanson, Racism and Relativism, 10 TIKKUN 63, 66 (1995). For the second position, see HATCH, supra note 7, at 11; Bagish, supra note 18, at 33-34; MARVIN HARRIS, CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 10-11 (3d ed. 1991); David H.P. Maybury-Lewis, A Special Sort of Pleading: Anthropology at the Service of Ethnic Groups, in TALKING ABOUT PEOPLE: READINGS IN CONTEMPORARY CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 16, 17 (William A. Haviland & Robert J. Gordon eds., 2d ed. 1996).
    • (1994) Cultural Anthropology , vol.17 , pp. 19
    • Nanda, S.1
  • 66
    • 84937282603 scopus 로고
    • Racism and Relativism
    • These posilions are not new in anthropology (Benedict and Herskovits held both), nor is the habit of calling them "cultural relativism." What is new - i.e., different from the first half of the century - is the habit of restricting that term to these positions, thereby excluding the moral theories in Section II. For the first of the two positions, see RICHLEY H. CRAPO, CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 17, 38-39 (3d ed. 1993); MICHAEL C. HOWARD, CONTEMPORARY CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 5-6, 14 (4th ed. 1993); SERENA NANDA, CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 17, 19 (5th ed. 1994); F. Allan Hanson, Racism and Relativism, 10 TIKKUN 63, 66 (1995). For the second position, see HATCH, supra note 7, at 11; Bagish, supra note 18, at 33-34; MARVIN HARRIS, CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 10-11 (3d ed. 1991); David H.P. Maybury-Lewis, A Special Sort of Pleading: Anthropology at the Service of Ethnic Groups, in TALKING ABOUT PEOPLE: READINGS IN CONTEMPORARY CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 16, 17 (William A. Haviland & Robert J. Gordon eds., 2d ed. 1996).
    • (1995) Tikkun , vol.10 , pp. 63
    • Hanson, F.A.1
  • 67
    • 0004040789 scopus 로고
    • 3d ed.
    • These posilions are not new in anthropology (Benedict and Herskovits held both), nor is the habit of calling them "cultural relativism." What is new - i.e., different from the first half of the century - is the habit of restricting that term to these positions, thereby excluding the moral theories in Section II. For the first of the two positions, see RICHLEY H. CRAPO, CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 17, 38-39 (3d ed. 1993); MICHAEL C. HOWARD, CONTEMPORARY CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 5-6, 14 (4th ed. 1993); SERENA NANDA, CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 17, 19 (5th ed. 1994); F. Allan Hanson, Racism and Relativism, 10 TIKKUN 63, 66 (1995). For the second position, see HATCH, supra note 7, at 11; Bagish, supra note 18, at 33-34; MARVIN HARRIS, CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 10-11 (3d ed. 1991); David H.P. Maybury-Lewis, A Special Sort of Pleading: Anthropology at the Service of Ethnic Groups, in TALKING ABOUT PEOPLE: READINGS IN CONTEMPORARY CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 16, 17 (William A. Haviland & Robert J. Gordon eds., 2d ed. 1996).
    • (1991) Cultural Anthropology , pp. 10-11
    • Harris, M.1
  • 68
    • 84886605486 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Special Sort of Pleading: Anthropology at the Service of Ethnic Groups
    • William A. Haviland & Robert J. Gordon eds., 2d ed.
    • These posilions are not new in anthropology (Benedict and Herskovits held both), nor is the habit of calling them "cultural relativism." What is new - i.e., different from the first half of the century - is the habit of restricting that term to these positions, thereby excluding the moral theories in Section II. For the first of the two positions, see RICHLEY H. CRAPO, CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 17, 38-39 (3d ed. 1993); MICHAEL C. HOWARD, CONTEMPORARY CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 5-6, 14 (4th ed. 1993); SERENA NANDA, CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 17, 19 (5th ed. 1994); F. Allan Hanson, Racism and Relativism, 10 TIKKUN 63, 66 (1995). For the second position, see HATCH, supra note 7, at 11; Bagish, supra note 18, at 33-34; MARVIN HARRIS, CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 10-11 (3d ed. 1991); David H.P. Maybury-Lewis, A Special Sort of Pleading: Anthropology at the Service of Ethnic Groups, in TALKING ABOUT PEOPLE: READINGS IN CONTEMPORARY CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY 16, 17 (William A. Haviland & Robert J. Gordon eds., 2d ed. 1996).
    • (1996) Talking About People: Readings in Contemporary Cultural Anthropology , vol.16 , pp. 17
    • Maybury-Lewis, D.H.P.1
  • 69
    • 9744244632 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is emphasized by some of the social scientists who accept these views. Examples are HATCH, supra note 7, at 11; Hanson, supra note 19; HOWARD, supra note 19; Maybury-Lewis, supra note 19.
  • 70
    • 0343272562 scopus 로고
    • The Concept of Value in Modern Anthropology
    • A. L. Kroeber ed.
    • This dated view is common among philosophers; unfortunately, it often blinds them to some worthwhile literature. I have in mind the many useful criticisms of cultural relativism that have been written by anthropologists. Three examples: HATCH, supra note 7, chs. 4-5; Bidney, supra note 4; David Bidney, The Concept of Value in Modern Anthropology, in ANTHROPOLOGY TODAY 682 (A. L. Kroeber ed., 1953).
    • (1953) Anthropology Today , pp. 682
    • Bidney, D.1
  • 71
    • 9744225556 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., Ayres, supra note 7; WHEELIS, supra note 7
    • See, e.g., Ayres, supra note 7; WHEELIS, supra note 7.
  • 72
    • 9744226128 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • A metaethical theory aims to illuminate one or more features of moral language or thought, perhaps even to provide a comprehensive account of such language and thought. A normative ethical theory furnishes moral guidance by, say, providing a method for identifying valid moral judgments. In saying that cultural relativism is strictly metaethical, I am deviating from the views of Sumner, Benedict, and Herskovits, who intend their theory to be normative as well as metaethical. But I am doing so in a charitable way, a way that cuts down on the number of objections to which they are open. Insofar as Sumner, Benedict, and Herskovits defend a normative theory, that theory is a brand of agent relativism or appraiser relativism, and hence open to the objections in Section IV. See generally the passages cited in notes 14 and 27.
  • 73
    • 9744258492 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Not everything I call a "version of universalism" counts as a full-blown normative theory, though many such theories are indeed versions of universalism.
  • 74
    • 9744234110 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cultural Relativism, Universalism, and the Burden of Proof
    • Much of the material in this section is taken, with slight modifications, from two of my previous papers: John J. Tilley, Cultural Relativism, Universalism, and the Burden of Proof, 27 MILLENNIUM 275 (1998); John J. Tilley, The Problem for Normative Cultural Relativism, 11 RATIO JURIS 272 (1998) [hereinafter Tilley, The Problem]. The same goes for some other portions of this essay. For instance, much of Section VII, part F, appears in Tilley, The Problem, supra, at 281-82.
    • (1998) Millennium , vol.27 , pp. 275
    • Tilley, J.J.1
  • 75
    • 9744247279 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Problem for Normative Cultural Relativism
    • hereinafter Tilley, The Problem
    • Much of the material in this section is taken, with slight modifications, from two of my previous papers: John J. Tilley, Cultural Relativism, Universalism, and the Burden of Proof, 27 MILLENNIUM 275 (1998); John J. Tilley, The Problem for Normative Cultural Relativism, 11 RATIO JURIS 272 (1998) [hereinafter Tilley, The Problem]. The same goes for some other portions of this essay. For instance, much of Section VII, part F, appears in Tilley, The Problem, supra, at 281-82.
    • (1998) Ratio Juris , vol.11 , pp. 272
    • Tilley, J.J.1
  • 76
    • 9744266440 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra
    • Much of the material in this section is taken, with slight modifications, from two of my previous papers: John J. Tilley, Cultural Relativism, Universalism, and the Burden of Proof, 27 MILLENNIUM 275 (1998); John J. Tilley, The Problem for Normative Cultural Relativism, 11 RATIO JURIS 272 (1998) [hereinafter Tilley, The Problem]. The same goes for some other portions of this essay. For instance, much of Section VII, part F, appears in Tilley, The Problem, supra, at 281-82.
    • The Problem , pp. 281-282
    • Tilley1
  • 78
    • 9744230365 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For variants of this view, see SUMNER, supra note 7, § 439; Benedict, supra note 7, at 73.
  • 79
    • 9744275646 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For a hint as to how they might proceed, see the second sentence in note 11. Frankly, I believe that a close scrutiny of cultural relativism would uncover problems of the kind discussed in Section IV. I will not pursue this because I want to focus on the arguments for cultural relativism.
  • 80
    • 9744220827 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Most of these arguments fall into three categories. Those in the first category aim to show that relativism is confirmed by the study of diverse cultures. Those in the second aim to reveal desirable aspects of relativism or undesirable aspects of universalism. Those in the third aim to illustrate by example that what is wrong in one culture is not wrong in the next, or that widely different customs can be equally right. Presumably, we are to infer from the examples that relativism is true, no doubt because it so easily explains the illustrated point. Arguments of all three types appear in the classic texts of relativism, though often in only embryonic form. For example, what I later dub the "nomad argument" and the "ethnocentrism argument" are suggested, respectively, by SUMNER, supra note 7, § 333; and HERSKOVITS, supra note 6, at 50. The "tolerance argument" is suggested in BENEDICT, supra note 6, at 37, 278; and in HERSKOVITS, supra note 7, at 76, 78. For the "research argument," see HERSKOVITS, supra note 6, at 14-15, 39, 51, 101; HERSKOVITS, supra note 7, at 78.
  • 82
    • 9744243951 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Other customs could have been chosen here, for example, the Dinka's ritual burial of spear-masters or the Inuit's custom of female infanticide.
  • 83
    • 9744279465 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The term "our culture" (and any term akin to it), both here and elsewhere in this article, need not refer to the author's culture. It can be interpreted to refer to most any culture the reader chooses, though in a few cases this may require minor adjustments in the relevant passage or argument.
  • 84
    • 65849253541 scopus 로고
    • There's No Such Thing as Free Speech and It's a Good Thing, Too
    • Francis J. Beckwith & Michael E. Bauman eds.
    • Stanley Fish, There's No Such Thing as Free Speech and It's a Good Thing, Too, in ARE YOU POLITICALLY CORRECT?: DEBATING AMERICA'S CULTURAL STANDARDS 43, 51 (Francis J. Beckwith & Michael E. Bauman eds., 1993).
    • (1993) Are You Politically Correct?: Debating America's Cultural Standards , vol.43 , pp. 51
    • Fish, S.1
  • 85
    • 9744262160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Even when this requirement exists, it seldom creates great difficulties. But I will let this pass.
  • 86
    • 9744285439 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • "But who's to say what 'morality' means! Maybe for me it means nothing more than Victorian morality!" Whatever the attractions of this response, relativists would be wise to avoid it. If relativism says nothing about the morality of rape, torture, and racism, if it implies nothing about whether "slavery is wrong" and "genocide is evil" are universally valid, it contributes nothing to moral theory.
  • 87
    • 9744251354 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Notes 2, 24, and 51 are relevant here. For examples of moral liberalism, see STACE, supra note 4, chs. 3, 7-8; HATCH, supra note 7, ch. 7. Neither author makes the mistake mentioned later in this paragraph.
  • 88
    • 9744233373 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, e.g., BENEDICT, supra note 6, at 37, 278; HERSKOVITS, supra note 6, at 33, 93-94; HERSKOVITS, supra note 7, at 76. For a pertinent and helpful discussion of Benedict's work, see Williams, supra note 4.
  • 89
    • 9744276432 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • STOUT, supra note 4, at 86-87
    • STOUT, supra note 4, at 86-87.
  • 90
    • 0004651070 scopus 로고
    • Moral Relativism Defended
    • Likewise, whether "genocide is not good" is universally valid is not settled by determining whether "you should not commit genocide" is true no matter who "you" designates. For this reason, Gilbert Harman's thesis in Gilbert Harman, Moral Relativism Defended, 84 PHIL. REV. 3 (1975), is irrelevant to the present topic (and not very contentious - see STOUT, supra note 4, at 90). Harman argues that "inner judgments," meaning judgments that evaluate an agent in relation to an action (e.g., "you should not do X"), are relative to reasons with two features: They are endorsed by the person making the judgment; and they are capable of motivating the evaluated agent. Harman's argument does not tie inner judgments specifically to culture, nor does it address moral judgments as they are defined in this paper. In short, it does not support cultural relativism. For criticism of Harman's thesis, see B.C. Postow, Moral Relativism Avoided, 60 PERSONALIST 95 (1979); David Copp, Harman on Internalism, Relativism, and Logical Form, 92 ETHICS 227 (1982); John Tilley, Inner Judgments and Moral Relativism, 18 PHILOSOPHIA 171 (1988); ROBERT L. ARRINGTON, RATIONALISM, REALISM, AND RELATIVISM 202 (1989).
    • (1975) Phil. Rev. , vol.84 , pp. 3
    • Harman, G.1
  • 91
    • 9744220826 scopus 로고
    • Moral Relativism Avoided
    • Likewise, whether "genocide is not good" is universally valid is not settled by determining whether "you should not commit genocide" is true no matter who "you" designates. For this reason, Gilbert Harman's thesis in Gilbert Harman, Moral Relativism Defended, 84 PHIL. REV. 3 (1975), is irrelevant to the present topic (and not very contentious - see STOUT, supra note 4, at 90). Harman argues that "inner judgments," meaning judgments that evaluate an agent in relation to an action (e.g., "you should not do X"), are relative to reasons with two features: They are endorsed by the person making the judgment; and they are capable of motivating the evaluated agent. Harman's argument does not tie inner judgments specifically to culture, nor does it address moral judgments as they are defined in this paper. In short, it does not support cultural relativism. For criticism of Harman's thesis, see B.C. Postow, Moral Relativism Avoided, 60 PERSONALIST 95 (1979); David Copp, Harman on Internalism, Relativism, and Logical Form, 92 ETHICS 227 (1982); John Tilley, Inner Judgments and Moral Relativism, 18 PHILOSOPHIA 171 (1988); ROBERT L. ARRINGTON, RATIONALISM, REALISM, AND RELATIVISM 202 (1989).
    • (1979) Personalist , vol.60 , pp. 95
    • Postow, B.C.1
  • 92
    • 84925978393 scopus 로고
    • Harman on Internalism, Relativism, and Logical Form
    • Likewise, whether "genocide is not good" is universally valid is not settled by determining whether "you should not commit genocide" is true no matter who "you" designates. For this reason, Gilbert Harman's thesis in Gilbert Harman, Moral Relativism Defended, 84 PHIL. REV. 3 (1975), is irrelevant to the present topic (and not very contentious - see STOUT, supra note 4, at 90). Harman argues that "inner judgments," meaning judgments that evaluate an agent in relation to an action (e.g., "you should not do X"), are relative to reasons with two features: They are endorsed by the person making the judgment; and they are capable of motivating the evaluated agent. Harman's argument does not tie inner judgments specifically to culture, nor does it address moral judgments as they are defined in this paper. In short, it does not support cultural relativism. For criticism of Harman's thesis, see B.C. Postow, Moral Relativism Avoided, 60 PERSONALIST 95 (1979); David Copp, Harman on Internalism, Relativism, and Logical Form, 92 ETHICS 227 (1982); John Tilley, Inner Judgments and Moral Relativism, 18 PHILOSOPHIA 171 (1988); ROBERT L. ARRINGTON, RATIONALISM, REALISM, AND RELATIVISM 202 (1989).
    • (1982) Ethics , vol.92 , pp. 227
    • Copp, D.1
  • 93
    • 9744261423 scopus 로고
    • Inner Judgments and Moral Relativism
    • Likewise, whether "genocide is not good" is universally valid is not settled by determining whether "you should not commit genocide" is true no matter who "you" designates. For this reason, Gilbert Harman's thesis in Gilbert Harman, Moral Relativism Defended, 84 PHIL. REV. 3 (1975), is irrelevant to the present topic (and not very contentious - see STOUT, supra note 4, at 90). Harman argues that "inner judgments," meaning judgments that evaluate an agent in relation to an action (e.g., "you should not do X"), are relative to reasons with two features: They are endorsed by the person making the judgment; and they are capable of motivating the evaluated agent. Harman's argument does not tie inner judgments specifically to culture, nor does it address moral judgments as they are defined in this paper. In short, it does not support cultural relativism. For criticism of Harman's thesis, see B.C. Postow, Moral Relativism Avoided, 60 PERSONALIST 95 (1979); David Copp, Harman on Internalism, Relativism, and Logical Form, 92 ETHICS 227 (1982); John Tilley, Inner Judgments and Moral Relativism, 18 PHILOSOPHIA 171 (1988); ROBERT L. ARRINGTON, RATIONALISM, REALISM, AND RELATIVISM 202 (1989).
    • (1988) Philosophia , vol.18 , pp. 171
    • Tilley, J.1
  • 94
    • 0346588223 scopus 로고
    • Likewise, whether "genocide is not good" is universally valid is not settled by determining whether "you should not commit genocide" is true no matter who "you" designates. For this reason, Gilbert Harman's thesis in Gilbert Harman, Moral Relativism Defended, 84 PHIL. REV. 3 (1975), is irrelevant to the present topic (and not very contentious - see STOUT, supra note 4, at 90). Harman argues that "inner judgments," meaning judgments that evaluate an agent in relation to an action (e.g., "you should not do X"), are relative to reasons with two features: They are endorsed by the person making the judgment; and they are capable of motivating the evaluated agent. Harman's argument does not tie inner judgments specifically to culture, nor does it address moral judgments as they are defined in this paper. In short, it does not support cultural relativism. For criticism of Harman's thesis, see B.C. Postow, Moral Relativism Avoided, 60 PERSONALIST 95 (1979); David Copp, Harman on Internalism, Relativism, and Logical Form, 92 ETHICS 227 (1982); John Tilley, Inner Judgments and Moral Relativism, 18 PHILOSOPHIA 171 (1988); ROBERT L. ARRINGTON, RATIONALISM, REALISM, AND RELATIVISM 202 (1989).
    • (1989) Rationalism, Realism, and Relativism , pp. 202
    • Arrington, R.L.1
  • 95
    • 9744234826 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It goes without saying that what we are dubbing "circumstances" are sometimes tied to culture. For instance, what counts as a joke in one society might count as an insult in another, owing to cultural differences between the societies. Clearly, this truism about circumstances lends no support to relativism. It is light-years apart from the view that no moral judgment is universally valid.
  • 96
    • 9744260716 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The usual term is "situational relativism." "Situationism" is useful because "relativism" does not appear in it; so we risk no confusion with cultural relativism.
  • 97
    • 0345879487 scopus 로고
    • Republic
    • bk. 1, 331c, Edith Hamilton & Huntington Cairns eds.
    • Many people find this surprising. They have the vague idea that situationism is a discovery of the last hundred years or so. Some of them even believe that relativists deserve credit for the discovery. Lest these errors gain any more currency, the case against them will be documented with especial thoroughness. See PLATO, Republic, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO bk. 1, 331c, at 580 (Edith Hamilton & Huntington Cairns eds., 1963); ARISTOTLE, Ethica Nicomachea, in THE BASIC WORKS OF ARISTOTLE bk. 2, 1104a1-9, 1109b14-27, at 953, 964 (Richard McKeon ed., 1941); CICERO, The Offices, in CICERO'S OFFICES 14-15 ,27, 120, 124-25 (Thomas Cockman trans., J.M. Dent & Sons 1949); 1 ST. THOMAS AQUINAS, SUMMA THEOLOGICA I, q.19, a.6, ad.1 (Fathers of the English Dominican Province trans., Benziger Bros. 1947-48); id. at I-II, q.7, aa.2-3; id. at I-II, q.18, aa.3-4 & 10-11; id. at I-II, q.73, a.7; id. at I-II, q.94, a.4; JOHN LOCKE, Essays on the Law of Nature, in LOCKE: POLITICAL ESSAYS essay 7, at 120 (Mark Goldie ed., 1997); William Wollaston, The Religion of Nature Delineated, in 1 BRITISH MORALISTS §§ 287-88, at 248-49 (D. D. Raphael ed., 1969) (1724); EDWARD BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO MORAL PHILOSOPHY 27-28 (Thoemmes Press 1994) (1745); DAVID FORDYCE, THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 47-48, 107 (Thoemmes Press 1990) (1754); ADAM FERGUSON, INSTITUTES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 163-64 (Garland 1978) (1773); RICHARD PRICE, A REVIEW OF THE PRINCIPAL QUESTIONS IN MORALS 164-65 175-76 (D. Daiches Raphael ed., 1948) (1787); ADAM SMITH, THE THEORY OF MORAL SENTIMENTS 174, 331-32, 339-40 (D.D. Raphael & A.L. Macfie eds., 1976) (1759); JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION ch. 7, § 21, at 194-95 (Wilfrid Harrison ed., 1948) (1823); 2 DUGALD STEWART, THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE ACTIVE AND MORAL POWERS OF MAN 326 (1828); GEORGE ELIOT, THE MILL ON THE FLOSS bk. 7, ch. 2, at 628 (A.S. Byatt ed., 1979) (1860); 2 ADOLF WUTTKE, CHRISTIAN ETHICS 133-39 (John P. Lacroix trans., 1873); PAUL JANET, THE THEORY OF MORALS 163-64 (Mary Chapman trans., 1883); WALTER H. HILL, ETHICS 62-64 (2d ed. 1878); J.H. MUIRHEAD, THE ELEMENTS OF ETHICS 197, 213 (1892).
    • (1963) The Collected Dialogues of Plato , pp. 580
    • Plato1
  • 98
    • 0003356034 scopus 로고
    • Ethica Nicomachea
    • bk. 2, 1104a1-9, 1109b14-27, Richard McKeon ed.
    • Many people find this surprising. They have the vague idea that situationism is a discovery of the last hundred years or so. Some of them even believe that relativists deserve credit for the discovery. Lest these errors gain any more currency, the case against them will be documented with especial thoroughness. See PLATO, Republic, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO bk. 1, 331c, at 580 (Edith Hamilton & Huntington Cairns eds., 1963); ARISTOTLE, Ethica Nicomachea, in THE BASIC WORKS OF ARISTOTLE bk. 2, 1104a1-9, 1109b14-27, at 953, 964 (Richard McKeon ed., 1941); CICERO, The Offices, in CICERO'S OFFICES 14-15 ,27, 120, 124-25 (Thomas Cockman trans., J.M. Dent & Sons 1949); 1 ST. THOMAS AQUINAS, SUMMA THEOLOGICA I, q.19, a.6, ad.1 (Fathers of the English Dominican Province trans., Benziger Bros. 1947-48); id. at I-II, q.7, aa.2-3; id. at I-II, q.18, aa.3-4 & 10-11; id. at I-II, q.73, a.7; id. at I-II, q.94, a.4; JOHN LOCKE, Essays on the Law of Nature, in LOCKE: POLITICAL ESSAYS essay 7, at 120 (Mark Goldie ed., 1997); William Wollaston, The Religion of Nature Delineated, in 1 BRITISH MORALISTS §§ 287-88, at 248-49 (D. D. Raphael ed., 1969) (1724); EDWARD BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO MORAL PHILOSOPHY 27-28 (Thoemmes Press 1994) (1745); DAVID FORDYCE, THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 47-48, 107 (Thoemmes Press 1990) (1754); ADAM FERGUSON, INSTITUTES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 163-64 (Garland 1978) (1773); RICHARD PRICE, A REVIEW OF THE PRINCIPAL QUESTIONS IN MORALS 164-65 175-76 (D. Daiches Raphael ed., 1948) (1787); ADAM SMITH, THE THEORY OF MORAL SENTIMENTS 174, 331-32, 339-40 (D.D. Raphael & A.L. Macfie eds., 1976) (1759); JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION ch. 7, § 21, at 194-95 (Wilfrid Harrison ed., 1948) (1823); 2 DUGALD STEWART, THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE ACTIVE AND MORAL POWERS OF MAN 326 (1828); GEORGE ELIOT, THE MILL ON THE FLOSS bk. 7, ch. 2, at 628 (A.S. Byatt ed., 1979) (1860); 2 ADOLF WUTTKE, CHRISTIAN ETHICS 133-39 (John P. Lacroix trans., 1873); PAUL JANET, THE THEORY OF MORALS 163-64 (Mary Chapman trans., 1883); WALTER H. HILL, ETHICS 62-64 (2d ed. 1878); J.H. MUIRHEAD, THE ELEMENTS OF ETHICS 197, 213 (1892).
    • (1941) The Basic Works of Aristotle , pp. 953
    • Aristotle1
  • 99
    • 9744267899 scopus 로고
    • The Offices
    • Thomas Cockman trans.,J.M. Dent & Sons
    • Many people find this surprising. They have the vague idea that situationism is a discovery of the last hundred years or so. Some of them even believe that relativists deserve credit for the discovery. Lest these errors gain any more currency, the case against them will be documented with especial thoroughness. See PLATO, Republic, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO bk. 1, 331c, at 580 (Edith Hamilton & Huntington Cairns eds., 1963); ARISTOTLE, Ethica Nicomachea, in THE BASIC WORKS OF ARISTOTLE bk. 2, 1104a1-9, 1109b14-27, at 953, 964 (Richard McKeon ed., 1941); CICERO, The Offices, in CICERO'S OFFICES 14-15 ,27, 120, 124-25 (Thomas Cockman trans., J.M. Dent & Sons 1949); 1 ST. THOMAS AQUINAS, SUMMA THEOLOGICA I, q.19, a.6, ad.1 (Fathers of the English Dominican Province trans., Benziger Bros. 1947-48); id. at I-II, q.7, aa.2-3; id. at I-II, q.18, aa.3-4 & 10-11; id. at I-II, q.73, a.7; id. at I-II, q.94, a.4; JOHN LOCKE, Essays on the Law of Nature, in LOCKE: POLITICAL ESSAYS essay 7, at 120 (Mark Goldie ed., 1997); William Wollaston, The Religion of Nature Delineated, in 1 BRITISH MORALISTS §§ 287-88, at 248-49 (D. D. Raphael ed., 1969) (1724); EDWARD BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO MORAL PHILOSOPHY 27-28 (Thoemmes Press 1994) (1745); DAVID FORDYCE, THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 47-48, 107 (Thoemmes Press 1990) (1754); ADAM FERGUSON, INSTITUTES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 163-64 (Garland 1978) (1773); RICHARD PRICE, A REVIEW OF THE PRINCIPAL QUESTIONS IN MORALS 164-65 175-76 (D. Daiches Raphael ed., 1948) (1787); ADAM SMITH, THE THEORY OF MORAL SENTIMENTS 174, 331-32, 339-40 (D.D. Raphael & A.L. Macfie eds., 1976) (1759); JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION ch. 7, § 21, at 194-95 (Wilfrid Harrison ed., 1948) (1823); 2 DUGALD STEWART, THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE ACTIVE AND MORAL POWERS OF MAN 326 (1828); GEORGE ELIOT, THE MILL ON THE FLOSS bk. 7, ch. 2, at 628 (A.S. Byatt ed., 1979) (1860); 2 ADOLF WUTTKE, CHRISTIAN ETHICS 133-39 (John P. Lacroix trans., 1873); PAUL JANET, THE THEORY OF MORALS 163-64 (Mary Chapman trans., 1883); WALTER H. HILL, ETHICS 62-64 (2d ed. 1878); J.H. MUIRHEAD, THE ELEMENTS OF ETHICS 197, 213 (1892).
    • (1949) Cicero's Offices , pp. 14-15
    • Cicero1
  • 100
    • 0004296635 scopus 로고
    • q.19, a.6, ad.1 Fathers of the English Dominican Province trans., Benziger Bros.
    • Many people find this surprising. They have the vague idea that situationism is a discovery of the last hundred years or so. Some of them even believe that relativists deserve credit for the discovery. Lest these errors gain any more currency, the case against them will be documented with especial thoroughness. See PLATO, Republic, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO bk. 1, 331c, at 580 (Edith Hamilton & Huntington Cairns eds., 1963); ARISTOTLE, Ethica Nicomachea, in THE BASIC WORKS OF ARISTOTLE bk. 2, 1104a1-9, 1109b14-27, at 953, 964 (Richard McKeon ed., 1941); CICERO, The Offices, in CICERO'S OFFICES 14-15 ,27, 120, 124-25 (Thomas Cockman trans., J.M. Dent & Sons 1949); 1 ST. THOMAS AQUINAS, SUMMA THEOLOGICA I, q.19, a.6, ad.1 (Fathers of the English Dominican Province trans., Benziger Bros. 1947-48); id. at I-II, q.7, aa.2-3; id. at I-II, q.18, aa.3-4 & 10-11; id. at I-II, q.73, a.7; id. at I-II, q.94, a.4; JOHN LOCKE, Essays on the Law of Nature, in LOCKE: POLITICAL ESSAYS essay 7, at 120 (Mark Goldie ed., 1997); William Wollaston, The Religion of Nature Delineated, in 1 BRITISH MORALISTS §§ 287-88, at 248-49 (D. D. Raphael ed., 1969) (1724); EDWARD BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO MORAL PHILOSOPHY 27-28 (Thoemmes Press 1994) (1745); DAVID FORDYCE, THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 47-48, 107 (Thoemmes Press 1990) (1754); ADAM FERGUSON, INSTITUTES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 163-64 (Garland 1978) (1773); RICHARD PRICE, A REVIEW OF THE PRINCIPAL QUESTIONS IN MORALS 164-65 175-76 (D. Daiches Raphael ed., 1948) (1787); ADAM SMITH, THE THEORY OF MORAL SENTIMENTS 174, 331-32, 339-40 (D.D. Raphael & A.L. Macfie eds., 1976) (1759); JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION ch. 7, § 21, at 194-95 (Wilfrid Harrison ed., 1948) (1823); 2 DUGALD STEWART, THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE ACTIVE AND MORAL POWERS OF MAN 326 (1828); GEORGE ELIOT, THE MILL ON THE FLOSS bk. 7, ch. 2, at 628 (A.S. Byatt ed., 1979) (1860); 2 ADOLF WUTTKE, CHRISTIAN ETHICS 133-39 (John P. Lacroix trans., 1873); PAUL JANET, THE THEORY OF MORALS 163-64 (Mary Chapman trans., 1883); WALTER H. HILL, ETHICS 62-64 (2d ed. 1878); J.H. MUIRHEAD, THE ELEMENTS OF ETHICS 197, 213 (1892).
    • (1947) Summa Theologica I
    • Aquinas, St.T.1
  • 101
    • 9744265372 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Essays on the Law of Nature
    • essay 7, Mark Goldie ed.
    • Many people find this surprising. They have the vague idea that situationism is a discovery of the last hundred years or so. Some of them even believe that relativists deserve credit for the discovery. Lest these errors gain any more currency, the case against them will be documented with especial thoroughness. See PLATO, Republic, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO bk. 1, 331c, at 580 (Edith Hamilton & Huntington Cairns eds., 1963); ARISTOTLE, Ethica Nicomachea, in THE BASIC WORKS OF ARISTOTLE bk. 2, 1104a1-9, 1109b14-27, at 953, 964 (Richard McKeon ed., 1941); CICERO, The Offices, in CICERO'S OFFICES 14-15 ,27, 120, 124-25 (Thomas Cockman trans., J.M. Dent & Sons 1949); 1 ST. THOMAS AQUINAS, SUMMA THEOLOGICA I, q.19, a.6, ad.1 (Fathers of the English Dominican Province trans., Benziger Bros. 1947-48); id. at I-II, q.7, aa.2-3; id. at I-II, q.18, aa.3-4 & 10-11; id. at I-II, q.73, a.7; id. at I-II, q.94, a.4; JOHN LOCKE, Essays on the Law of Nature, in LOCKE: POLITICAL ESSAYS essay 7, at 120 (Mark Goldie ed., 1997); William Wollaston, The Religion of Nature Delineated, in 1 BRITISH MORALISTS §§ 287-88, at 248-49 (D. D. Raphael ed., 1969) (1724); EDWARD BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO MORAL PHILOSOPHY 27-28 (Thoemmes Press 1994) (1745); DAVID FORDYCE, THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 47-48, 107 (Thoemmes Press 1990) (1754); ADAM FERGUSON, INSTITUTES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 163-64 (Garland 1978) (1773); RICHARD PRICE, A REVIEW OF THE PRINCIPAL QUESTIONS IN MORALS 164-65 175-76 (D. Daiches Raphael ed., 1948) (1787); ADAM SMITH, THE THEORY OF MORAL SENTIMENTS 174, 331-32, 339-40 (D.D. Raphael & A.L. Macfie eds., 1976) (1759); JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION ch. 7, § 21, at 194-95 (Wilfrid Harrison ed., 1948) (1823); 2 DUGALD STEWART, THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE ACTIVE AND MORAL POWERS OF MAN 326 (1828); GEORGE ELIOT, THE MILL ON THE FLOSS bk. 7, ch. 2, at 628 (A.S. Byatt ed., 1979) (1860); 2 ADOLF WUTTKE, CHRISTIAN ETHICS 133-39 (John P. Lacroix trans., 1873); PAUL JANET, THE THEORY OF MORALS 163-64 (Mary Chapman trans., 1883); WALTER H. HILL, ETHICS 62-64 (2d ed. 1878); J.H. MUIRHEAD, THE ELEMENTS OF ETHICS 197, 213 (1892).
    • (1997) Locke: Political Essays , pp. 120
    • Locke, J.1
  • 102
    • 80054473040 scopus 로고
    • The Religion of Nature Delineated
    • §§ 287-88, D. D. Raphael ed., (1724);
    • Many people find this surprising. They have the vague idea that situationism is a discovery of the last hundred years or so. Some of them even believe that relativists deserve credit for the discovery. Lest these errors gain any more currency, the case against them will be documented with especial thoroughness. See PLATO, Republic, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO bk. 1, 331c, at 580 (Edith Hamilton & Huntington Cairns eds., 1963); ARISTOTLE, Ethica Nicomachea, in THE BASIC WORKS OF ARISTOTLE bk. 2, 1104a1-9, 1109b14-27, at 953, 964 (Richard McKeon ed., 1941); CICERO, The Offices, in CICERO'S OFFICES 14-15 ,27, 120, 124-25 (Thomas Cockman trans., J.M. Dent & Sons 1949); 1 ST. THOMAS AQUINAS, SUMMA THEOLOGICA I, q.19, a.6, ad.1 (Fathers of the English Dominican Province trans., Benziger Bros. 1947-48); id. at I-II, q.7, aa.2-3; id. at I-II, q.18, aa.3-4 & 10-11; id. at I-II, q.73, a.7; id. at I-II, q.94, a.4; JOHN LOCKE, Essays on the Law of Nature, in LOCKE: POLITICAL ESSAYS essay 7, at 120 (Mark Goldie ed., 1997); William Wollaston, The Religion of Nature Delineated, in 1 BRITISH MORALISTS §§ 287-88, at 248-49 (D. D. Raphael ed., 1969) (1724); EDWARD BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO MORAL PHILOSOPHY 27-28 (Thoemmes Press 1994) (1745); DAVID FORDYCE, THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 47-48, 107 (Thoemmes Press 1990) (1754); ADAM FERGUSON, INSTITUTES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 163-64 (Garland 1978) (1773); RICHARD PRICE, A REVIEW OF THE PRINCIPAL QUESTIONS IN MORALS 164-65 175-76 (D. Daiches Raphael ed., 1948) (1787); ADAM SMITH, THE THEORY OF MORAL SENTIMENTS 174, 331-32, 339-40 (D.D. Raphael & A.L. Macfie eds., 1976) (1759); JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION ch. 7, § 21, at 194-95 (Wilfrid Harrison ed., 1948) (1823); 2 DUGALD STEWART, THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE ACTIVE AND MORAL POWERS OF MAN 326 (1828); GEORGE ELIOT, THE MILL ON THE FLOSS bk. 7, ch. 2, at 628 (A.S. Byatt ed., 1979) (1860); 2 ADOLF WUTTKE, CHRISTIAN ETHICS 133-39 (John P. Lacroix trans., 1873); PAUL JANET, THE THEORY OF MORALS 163-64 (Mary Chapman trans., 1883); WALTER H. HILL, ETHICS 62-64 (2d ed. 1878); J.H. MUIRHEAD, THE ELEMENTS OF ETHICS 197, 213 (1892).
    • (1969) British Moralists , vol.1 , pp. 248-249
    • Wollaston, W.1
  • 103
    • 9744246485 scopus 로고
    • Thoemmes Press (1745)
    • Many people find this surprising. They have the vague idea that situationism is a discovery of the last hundred years or so. Some of them even believe that relativists deserve credit for the discovery. Lest these errors gain any more currency, the case against them will be documented with especial thoroughness. See PLATO, Republic, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO bk. 1, 331c, at 580 (Edith Hamilton & Huntington Cairns eds., 1963); ARISTOTLE, Ethica Nicomachea, in THE BASIC WORKS OF ARISTOTLE bk. 2, 1104a1-9, 1109b14-27, at 953, 964 (Richard McKeon ed., 1941); CICERO, The Offices, in CICERO'S OFFICES 14-15 ,27, 120, 124-25 (Thomas Cockman trans., J.M. Dent & Sons 1949); 1 ST. THOMAS AQUINAS, SUMMA THEOLOGICA I, q.19, a.6, ad.1 (Fathers of the English Dominican Province trans., Benziger Bros. 1947-48); id. at I-II, q.7, aa.2-3; id. at I-II, q.18, aa.3-4 & 10-11; id. at I-II, q.73, a.7; id. at I-II, q.94, a.4; JOHN LOCKE, Essays on the Law of Nature, in LOCKE: POLITICAL ESSAYS essay 7, at 120 (Mark Goldie ed., 1997); William Wollaston, The Religion of Nature Delineated, in 1 BRITISH MORALISTS §§ 287-88, at 248-49 (D. D. Raphael ed., 1969) (1724); EDWARD BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO MORAL PHILOSOPHY 27-28 (Thoemmes Press 1994) (1745); DAVID FORDYCE, THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 47-48, 107 (Thoemmes Press 1990) (1754); ADAM FERGUSON, INSTITUTES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 163-64 (Garland 1978) (1773); RICHARD PRICE, A REVIEW OF THE PRINCIPAL QUESTIONS IN MORALS 164-65 175-76 (D. Daiches Raphael ed., 1948) (1787); ADAM SMITH, THE THEORY OF MORAL SENTIMENTS 174, 331-32, 339-40 (D.D. Raphael & A.L. Macfie eds., 1976) (1759); JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION ch. 7, § 21, at 194-95 (Wilfrid Harrison ed., 1948) (1823); 2 DUGALD STEWART, THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE ACTIVE AND MORAL POWERS OF MAN 326 (1828); GEORGE ELIOT, THE MILL ON THE FLOSS bk. 7, ch. 2, at 628 (A.S. Byatt ed., 1979) (1860); 2 ADOLF WUTTKE, CHRISTIAN ETHICS 133-39 (John P. Lacroix trans., 1873); PAUL JANET, THE THEORY OF MORALS 163-64 (Mary Chapman trans., 1883); WALTER H. HILL, ETHICS 62-64 (2d ed. 1878); J.H. MUIRHEAD, THE ELEMENTS OF ETHICS 197, 213 (1892).
    • (1994) An Introduction To Moral Philosophy , pp. 27-28
    • Bentham, E.1
  • 104
    • 9744220081 scopus 로고
    • Thoemmes Press (1754)
    • Many people find this surprising. They have the vague idea that situationism is a discovery of the last hundred years or so. Some of them even believe that relativists deserve credit for the discovery. Lest these errors gain any more currency, the case against them will be documented with especial thoroughness. See PLATO, Republic, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO bk. 1, 331c, at 580 (Edith Hamilton & Huntington Cairns eds., 1963); ARISTOTLE, Ethica Nicomachea, in THE BASIC WORKS OF ARISTOTLE bk. 2, 1104a1-9, 1109b14-27, at 953, 964 (Richard McKeon ed., 1941); CICERO, The Offices, in CICERO'S OFFICES 14-15 ,27, 120, 124-25 (Thomas Cockman trans., J.M. Dent & Sons 1949); 1 ST. THOMAS AQUINAS, SUMMA THEOLOGICA I, q.19, a.6, ad.1 (Fathers of the English Dominican Province trans., Benziger Bros. 1947-48); id. at I-II, q.7, aa.2-3; id. at I-II, q.18, aa.3-4 & 10-11; id. at I-II, q.73, a.7; id. at I-II, q.94, a.4; JOHN LOCKE, Essays on the Law of Nature, in LOCKE: POLITICAL ESSAYS essay 7, at 120 (Mark Goldie ed., 1997); William Wollaston, The Religion of Nature Delineated, in 1 BRITISH MORALISTS §§ 287-88, at 248-49 (D. D. Raphael ed., 1969) (1724); EDWARD BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO MORAL PHILOSOPHY 27-28 (Thoemmes Press 1994) (1745); DAVID FORDYCE, THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 47-48, 107 (Thoemmes Press 1990) (1754); ADAM FERGUSON, INSTITUTES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 163-64 (Garland 1978) (1773); RICHARD PRICE, A REVIEW OF THE PRINCIPAL QUESTIONS IN MORALS 164-65 175-76 (D. Daiches Raphael ed., 1948) (1787); ADAM SMITH, THE THEORY OF MORAL SENTIMENTS 174, 331-32, 339-40 (D.D. Raphael & A.L. Macfie eds., 1976) (1759); JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION ch. 7, § 21, at 194-95 (Wilfrid Harrison ed., 1948) (1823); 2 DUGALD STEWART, THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE ACTIVE AND MORAL POWERS OF MAN 326 (1828); GEORGE ELIOT, THE MILL ON THE FLOSS bk. 7, ch. 2, at 628 (A.S. Byatt ed., 1979) (1860); 2 ADOLF WUTTKE, CHRISTIAN ETHICS 133-39 (John P. Lacroix trans., 1873); PAUL JANET, THE THEORY OF MORALS 163-64 (Mary Chapman trans., 1883); WALTER H. HILL, ETHICS 62-64 (2d ed. 1878); J.H. MUIRHEAD, THE ELEMENTS OF ETHICS 197, 213 (1892).
    • (1990) The Elements of Moral Philosophy , vol.47-48 , pp. 107
    • Fordyce, D.1
  • 105
    • 0346134185 scopus 로고
    • Garland (1773)
    • Many people find this surprising. They have the vague idea that situationism is a discovery of the last hundred years or so. Some of them even believe that relativists deserve credit for the discovery. Lest these errors gain any more currency, the case against them will be documented with especial thoroughness. See PLATO, Republic, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO bk. 1, 331c, at 580 (Edith Hamilton & Huntington Cairns eds., 1963); ARISTOTLE, Ethica Nicomachea, in THE BASIC WORKS OF ARISTOTLE bk. 2, 1104a1-9, 1109b14-27, at 953, 964 (Richard McKeon ed., 1941); CICERO, The Offices, in CICERO'S OFFICES 14-15 ,27, 120, 124-25 (Thomas Cockman trans., J.M. Dent & Sons 1949); 1 ST. THOMAS AQUINAS, SUMMA THEOLOGICA I, q.19, a.6, ad.1 (Fathers of the English Dominican Province trans., Benziger Bros. 1947-48); id. at I-II, q.7, aa.2-3; id. at I-II, q.18, aa.3-4 & 10-11; id. at I-II, q.73, a.7; id. at I-II, q.94, a.4; JOHN LOCKE, Essays on the Law of Nature, in LOCKE: POLITICAL ESSAYS essay 7, at 120 (Mark Goldie ed., 1997); William Wollaston, The Religion of Nature Delineated, in 1 BRITISH MORALISTS §§ 287-88, at 248-49 (D. D. Raphael ed., 1969) (1724); EDWARD BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO MORAL PHILOSOPHY 27-28 (Thoemmes Press 1994) (1745); DAVID FORDYCE, THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 47-48, 107 (Thoemmes Press 1990) (1754); ADAM FERGUSON, INSTITUTES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 163-64 (Garland 1978) (1773); RICHARD PRICE, A REVIEW OF THE PRINCIPAL QUESTIONS IN MORALS 164-65 175-76 (D. Daiches Raphael ed., 1948) (1787); ADAM SMITH, THE THEORY OF MORAL SENTIMENTS 174, 331-32, 339-40 (D.D. Raphael & A.L. Macfie eds., 1976) (1759); JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION ch. 7, § 21, at 194-95 (Wilfrid Harrison ed., 1948) (1823); 2 DUGALD STEWART, THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE ACTIVE AND MORAL POWERS OF MAN 326 (1828); GEORGE ELIOT, THE MILL ON THE FLOSS bk. 7, ch. 2, at 628 (A.S. Byatt ed., 1979) (1860); 2 ADOLF WUTTKE, CHRISTIAN ETHICS 133-39 (John P. Lacroix trans., 1873); PAUL JANET, THE THEORY OF MORALS 163-64 (Mary Chapman trans., 1883); WALTER H. HILL, ETHICS 62-64 (2d ed. 1878); J.H. MUIRHEAD, THE ELEMENTS OF ETHICS 197, 213 (1892).
    • (1978) Institutes of Moral Philosophy , pp. 163-164
    • Ferguson, A.1
  • 106
    • 9744226878 scopus 로고
    • D. Daiches Raphael ed., (1787)
    • Many people find this surprising. They have the vague idea that situationism is a discovery of the last hundred years or so. Some of them even believe that relativists deserve credit for the discovery. Lest these errors gain any more currency, the case against them will be documented with especial thoroughness. See PLATO, Republic, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO bk. 1, 331c, at 580 (Edith Hamilton & Huntington Cairns eds., 1963); ARISTOTLE, Ethica Nicomachea, in THE BASIC WORKS OF ARISTOTLE bk. 2, 1104a1-9, 1109b14-27, at 953, 964 (Richard McKeon ed., 1941); CICERO, The Offices, in CICERO'S OFFICES 14-15 ,27, 120, 124-25 (Thomas Cockman trans., J.M. Dent & Sons 1949); 1 ST. THOMAS AQUINAS, SUMMA THEOLOGICA I, q.19, a.6, ad.1 (Fathers of the English Dominican Province trans., Benziger Bros. 1947-48); id. at I-II, q.7, aa.2-3; id. at I-II, q.18, aa.3-4 & 10-11; id. at I-II, q.73, a.7; id. at I-II, q.94, a.4; JOHN LOCKE, Essays on the Law of Nature, in LOCKE: POLITICAL ESSAYS essay 7, at 120 (Mark Goldie ed., 1997); William Wollaston, The Religion of Nature Delineated, in 1 BRITISH MORALISTS §§ 287-88, at 248-49 (D. D. Raphael ed., 1969) (1724); EDWARD BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO MORAL PHILOSOPHY 27-28 (Thoemmes Press 1994) (1745); DAVID FORDYCE, THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 47-48, 107 (Thoemmes Press 1990) (1754); ADAM FERGUSON, INSTITUTES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 163-64 (Garland 1978) (1773); RICHARD PRICE, A REVIEW OF THE PRINCIPAL QUESTIONS IN MORALS 164-65 175-76 (D. Daiches Raphael ed., 1948) (1787); ADAM SMITH, THE THEORY OF MORAL SENTIMENTS 174, 331-32, 339-40 (D.D. Raphael & A.L. Macfie eds., 1976) (1759); JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION ch. 7, § 21, at 194-95 (Wilfrid Harrison ed., 1948) (1823); 2 DUGALD STEWART, THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE ACTIVE AND MORAL POWERS OF MAN 326 (1828); GEORGE ELIOT, THE MILL ON THE FLOSS bk. 7, ch. 2, at 628 (A.S. Byatt ed., 1979) (1860); 2 ADOLF WUTTKE, CHRISTIAN ETHICS 133-39
    • (1948) A Review of the Principal Questions in Morals , pp. 164-165
    • Price, R.1
  • 107
    • 9744224793 scopus 로고
    • D.D. Raphael & A.L. Macfie eds., (1759)
    • Many people find this surprising. They have the vague idea that situationism is a discovery of the last hundred years or so. Some of them even believe that relativists deserve credit for the discovery. Lest these errors gain any more currency, the case against them will be documented with especial thoroughness. See PLATO, Republic, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO bk. 1, 331c, at 580 (Edith Hamilton & Huntington Cairns eds., 1963); ARISTOTLE, Ethica Nicomachea, in THE BASIC WORKS OF ARISTOTLE bk. 2, 1104a1-9, 1109b14-27, at 953, 964 (Richard McKeon ed., 1941); CICERO, The Offices, in CICERO'S OFFICES 14-15 ,27, 120, 124-25 (Thomas Cockman trans., J.M. Dent & Sons 1949); 1 ST. THOMAS AQUINAS, SUMMA THEOLOGICA I, q.19, a.6, ad.1 (Fathers of the English Dominican Province trans., Benziger Bros. 1947-48); id. at I-II, q.7, aa.2-3; id. at I-II, q.18, aa.3-4 & 10-11; id. at I-II, q.73, a.7; id. at I-II, q.94, a.4; JOHN LOCKE, Essays on the Law of Nature, in LOCKE: POLITICAL ESSAYS essay 7, at 120 (Mark Goldie ed., 1997); William Wollaston, The Religion of Nature Delineated, in 1 BRITISH MORALISTS §§ 287-88, at 248-49 (D. D. Raphael ed., 1969) (1724); EDWARD BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO MORAL PHILOSOPHY 27-28 (Thoemmes Press 1994) (1745); DAVID FORDYCE, THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 47-48, 107 (Thoemmes Press 1990) (1754); ADAM FERGUSON, INSTITUTES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 163-64 (Garland 1978) (1773); RICHARD PRICE, A REVIEW OF THE PRINCIPAL QUESTIONS IN MORALS 164-65 175-76 (D. Daiches Raphael ed., 1948) (1787); ADAM SMITH, THE THEORY OF MORAL SENTIMENTS 174, 331-32, 339-40 (D.D. Raphael & A.L. Macfie eds., 1976) (1759); JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION ch. 7, § 21, at 194-95 (Wilfrid Harrison ed., 1948) (1823); 2 DUGALD STEWART, THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE ACTIVE AND MORAL POWERS OF MAN 326 (1828); GEORGE ELIOT, THE MILL ON THE FLOSS bk. 7, ch. 2, at 628 (A.S. Byatt ed., 1979) (1860); 2 ADOLF WUTTKE, CHRISTIAN ETHICS 133-39 (John P. Lacroix trans., 1873); PAUL JANET, THE THEORY OF MORALS 163-64 (Mary Chapman trans., 1883); WALTER H. HILL, ETHICS 62-64 (2d ed. 1878); J.H. MUIRHEAD, THE ELEMENTS OF ETHICS 197, 213 (1892).
    • (1976) The Theory of Moral Sentiments , vol.174 , pp. 331-332
    • Smith, A.1
  • 108
    • 84866836363 scopus 로고
    • ch. 7, § 21, Wilfrid Harrison ed., (1823)
    • Many people find this surprising. They have the vague idea that situationism is a discovery of the last hundred years or so. Some of them even believe that relativists deserve credit for the discovery. Lest these errors gain any more currency, the case against them will be documented with especial thoroughness. See PLATO, Republic, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO bk. 1, 331c, at 580 (Edith Hamilton & Huntington Cairns eds., 1963); ARISTOTLE, Ethica Nicomachea, in THE BASIC WORKS OF ARISTOTLE bk. 2, 1104a1-9, 1109b14-27, at 953, 964 (Richard McKeon ed., 1941); CICERO, The Offices, in CICERO'S OFFICES 14-15 ,27, 120, 124-25 (Thomas Cockman trans., J.M. Dent & Sons 1949); 1 ST. THOMAS AQUINAS, SUMMA THEOLOGICA I, q.19, a.6, ad.1 (Fathers of the English Dominican Province trans., Benziger Bros. 1947-48); id. at I-II, q.7, aa.2-3; id. at I-II, q.18, aa.3-4 & 10-11; id. at I-II, q.73, a.7; id. at I-II, q.94, a.4; JOHN LOCKE, Essays on the Law of Nature, in LOCKE: POLITICAL ESSAYS essay 7, at 120 (Mark Goldie ed., 1997); William Wollaston, The Religion of Nature Delineated, in 1 BRITISH MORALISTS §§ 287-88, at 248-49 (D. D. Raphael ed., 1969) (1724); EDWARD BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO MORAL PHILOSOPHY 27-28 (Thoemmes Press 1994) (1745); DAVID FORDYCE, THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 47-48, 107 (Thoemmes Press 1990) (1754); ADAM FERGUSON, INSTITUTES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 163-64 (Garland 1978) (1773); RICHARD PRICE, A REVIEW OF THE PRINCIPAL QUESTIONS IN MORALS 164-65 175-76 (D. Daiches Raphael ed., 1948) (1787); ADAM SMITH, THE THEORY OF MORAL SENTIMENTS 174, 331-32, 339-40 (D.D. Raphael & A.L. Macfie eds., 1976) (1759); JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION ch. 7, § 21, at 194-95 (Wilfrid Harrison ed., 1948) (1823); 2 DUGALD STEWART, THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE ACTIVE AND MORAL POWERS OF MAN 326 (1828); GEORGE ELIOT, THE MILL ON THE FLOSS bk. 7, ch. 2, at 628 (A.S. Byatt ed., 1979) (1860); 2 ADOLF WUTTKE, CHRISTIAN ETHICS 133-39 (John P. Lacroix trans., 1873); PAUL JANET, THE THEORY OF MORALS 163-64 (Mary Chapman trans., 1883); WALTER H. HILL, ETHICS 62-64 (2d ed. 1878); J.H. MUIRHEAD, THE ELEMENTS OF ETHICS 197, 213 (1892).
    • (1948) An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation , pp. 194-195
    • Bentham, J.1
  • 109
    • 77952277058 scopus 로고
    • Many people find this surprising. They have the vague idea that situationism is a discovery of the last hundred years or so. Some of them even believe that relativists deserve credit for the discovery. Lest these errors gain any more currency, the case against them will be documented with especial thoroughness. See PLATO, Republic, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO bk. 1, 331c, at 580 (Edith Hamilton & Huntington Cairns eds., 1963); ARISTOTLE, Ethica Nicomachea, in THE BASIC WORKS OF ARISTOTLE bk. 2, 1104a1-9, 1109b14-27, at 953, 964 (Richard McKeon ed., 1941); CICERO, The Offices, in CICERO'S OFFICES 14-15 ,27, 120, 124-25 (Thomas Cockman trans., J.M. Dent & Sons 1949); 1 ST. THOMAS AQUINAS, SUMMA THEOLOGICA I, q.19, a.6, ad.1 (Fathers of the English Dominican Province trans., Benziger Bros. 1947-48); id. at I-II, q.7, aa.2-3; id. at I-II, q.18, aa.3-4 & 10-11; id. at I-II, q.73, a.7; id. at I-II, q.94, a.4; JOHN LOCKE, Essays on the Law of Nature, in LOCKE: POLITICAL ESSAYS essay 7, at 120 (Mark Goldie ed., 1997); William Wollaston, The Religion of Nature Delineated, in 1 BRITISH MORALISTS §§ 287-88, at 248-49 (D. D. Raphael ed., 1969) (1724); EDWARD BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO MORAL PHILOSOPHY 27-28 (Thoemmes Press 1994) (1745); DAVID FORDYCE, THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 47-48, 107 (Thoemmes Press 1990) (1754); ADAM FERGUSON, INSTITUTES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 163-64 (Garland 1978) (1773); RICHARD PRICE, A REVIEW OF THE PRINCIPAL QUESTIONS IN MORALS 164-65 175-76 (D. Daiches Raphael ed., 1948) (1787); ADAM SMITH, THE THEORY OF MORAL SENTIMENTS 174, 331-32, 339-40 (D.D. Raphael & A.L. Macfie eds., 1976) (1759); JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION ch. 7, § 21, at 194-95 (Wilfrid Harrison ed., 1948) (1823); 2 DUGALD STEWART, THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE ACTIVE AND MORAL POWERS OF MAN 326 (1828); GEORGE ELIOT, THE MILL ON THE FLOSS bk. 7, ch. 2, at 628 (A.S. Byatt ed., 1979) (1860); 2 ADOLF WUTTKE, CHRISTIAN ETHICS 133-39 (John P. Lacroix trans., 1873); PAUL JANET, THE THEORY OF MORALS 163-64 (Mary Chapman trans., 1883); WALTER H. HILL, ETHICS 62-64 (2d ed. 1878); J.H. MUIRHEAD, THE ELEMENTS OF ETHICS 197, 213 (1892).
    • (1828) The Philosophy of the Active and Moral Powers of Man , pp. 326
    • Stewart, D.1
  • 110
    • 0004154221 scopus 로고
    • bk. 7, ch. 2, A.S. Byatt ed., (1860)
    • Many people find this surprising. They have the vague idea that situationism is a discovery of the last hundred years or so. Some of them even believe that relativists deserve credit for the discovery. Lest these errors gain any more currency, the case against them will be documented with especial thoroughness. See PLATO, Republic, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO bk. 1, 331c, at 580 (Edith Hamilton & Huntington Cairns eds., 1963); ARISTOTLE, Ethica Nicomachea, in THE BASIC WORKS OF ARISTOTLE bk. 2, 1104a1-9, 1109b14-27, at 953, 964 (Richard McKeon ed., 1941); CICERO, The Offices, in CICERO'S OFFICES 14-15 ,27, 120, 124-25 (Thomas Cockman trans., J.M. Dent & Sons 1949); 1 ST. THOMAS AQUINAS, SUMMA THEOLOGICA I, q.19, a.6, ad.1 (Fathers of the English Dominican Province trans., Benziger Bros. 1947-48); id. at I-II, q.7, aa.2-3; id. at I-II, q.18, aa.3-4 & 10-11; id. at I-II, q.73, a.7; id. at I-II, q.94, a.4; JOHN LOCKE, Essays on the Law of Nature, in LOCKE: POLITICAL ESSAYS essay 7, at 120 (Mark Goldie ed., 1997); William Wollaston, The Religion of Nature Delineated, in 1 BRITISH MORALISTS §§ 287-88, at 248-49 (D. D. Raphael ed., 1969) (1724); EDWARD BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO MORAL PHILOSOPHY 27-28 (Thoemmes Press 1994) (1745); DAVID FORDYCE, THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 47-48, 107 (Thoemmes Press 1990) (1754); ADAM FERGUSON, INSTITUTES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 163-64 (Garland 1978) (1773); RICHARD PRICE, A REVIEW OF THE PRINCIPAL QUESTIONS IN MORALS 164-65 175-76 (D. Daiches Raphael ed., 1948) (1787); ADAM SMITH, THE THEORY OF MORAL SENTIMENTS 174, 331-32, 339-40 (D.D. Raphael & A.L. Macfie eds., 1976) (1759); JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION ch. 7, § 21, at 194-95 (Wilfrid Harrison ed., 1948) (1823); 2 DUGALD STEWART, THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE ACTIVE AND MORAL POWERS OF MAN 326 (1828); GEORGE ELIOT, THE MILL ON THE FLOSS bk. 7, ch. 2, at 628 (A.S. Byatt ed., 1979) (1860); 2 ADOLF WUTTKE, CHRISTIAN ETHICS 133-39 (John P. Lacroix trans., 1873); PAUL JANET, THE THEORY OF MORALS 163-64 (Mary Chapman trans., 1883); WALTER H. HILL, ETHICS 62-64 (2d ed. 1878); J.H. MUIRHEAD, THE ELEMENTS OF ETHICS 197, 213 (1892).
    • (1979) The Mill on the Floss , pp. 628
    • Eliot, G.1
  • 111
    • 9744236268 scopus 로고
    • John P. Lacroix trans.
    • Many people find this surprising. They have the vague idea that situationism is a discovery of the last hundred years or so. Some of them even believe that relativists deserve credit for the discovery. Lest these errors gain any more currency, the case against them will be documented with especial thoroughness. See PLATO, Republic, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO bk. 1, 331c, at 580 (Edith Hamilton & Huntington Cairns eds., 1963); ARISTOTLE, Ethica Nicomachea, in THE BASIC WORKS OF ARISTOTLE bk. 2, 1104a1-9, 1109b14-27, at 953, 964 (Richard McKeon ed., 1941); CICERO, The Offices, in CICERO'S OFFICES 14-15 ,27, 120, 124-25 (Thomas Cockman trans., J.M. Dent & Sons 1949); 1 ST. THOMAS AQUINAS, SUMMA THEOLOGICA I, q.19, a.6, ad.1 (Fathers of the English Dominican Province trans., Benziger Bros. 1947-48); id. at I-II, q.7, aa.2-3; id. at I-II, q.18, aa.3-4 & 10-11; id. at I-II, q.73, a.7; id. at I-II, q.94, a.4; JOHN LOCKE, Essays on the Law of Nature, in LOCKE: POLITICAL ESSAYS essay 7, at 120 (Mark Goldie ed., 1997); William Wollaston, The Religion of Nature Delineated, in 1 BRITISH MORALISTS §§ 287-88, at 248-49 (D. D. Raphael ed., 1969) (1724); EDWARD BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO MORAL PHILOSOPHY 27-28 (Thoemmes Press 1994) (1745); DAVID FORDYCE, THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 47-48, 107 (Thoemmes Press 1990) (1754); ADAM FERGUSON, INSTITUTES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 163-64 (Garland 1978) (1773); RICHARD PRICE, A REVIEW OF THE PRINCIPAL QUESTIONS IN MORALS 164-65 175-76 (D. Daiches Raphael ed., 1948) (1787); ADAM SMITH, THE THEORY OF MORAL SENTIMENTS 174, 331-32, 339-40 (D.D. Raphael & A.L. Macfie eds., 1976) (1759); JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION ch. 7, § 21, at 194-95 (Wilfrid Harrison ed., 1948) (1823); 2 DUGALD STEWART, THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE ACTIVE AND MORAL POWERS OF MAN 326 (1828); GEORGE ELIOT, THE MILL ON THE FLOSS bk. 7, ch. 2, at 628 (A.S. Byatt ed., 1979) (1860); 2 ADOLF WUTTKE, CHRISTIAN ETHICS 133-39 (John P. Lacroix trans., 1873); PAUL JANET, THE THEORY OF MORALS 163-64 (Mary Chapman trans., 1883); WALTER H. HILL, ETHICS 62-64 (2d ed. 1878); J.H. MUIRHEAD, THE ELEMENTS OF ETHICS 197, 213 (1892).
    • (1873) Christian Ethics , pp. 133-139
    • Wuttke, A.1
  • 112
    • 9744222324 scopus 로고
    • Mary Chapman trans.
    • Many people find this surprising. They have the vague idea that situationism is a discovery of the last hundred years or so. Some of them even believe that relativists deserve credit for the discovery. Lest these errors gain any more currency, the case against them will be documented with especial thoroughness. See PLATO, Republic, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO bk. 1, 331c, at 580 (Edith Hamilton & Huntington Cairns eds., 1963); ARISTOTLE, Ethica Nicomachea, in THE BASIC WORKS OF ARISTOTLE bk. 2, 1104a1-9, 1109b14-27, at 953, 964 (Richard McKeon ed., 1941); CICERO, The Offices, in CICERO'S OFFICES 14-15 ,27, 120, 124-25 (Thomas Cockman trans., J.M. Dent & Sons 1949); 1 ST. THOMAS AQUINAS, SUMMA THEOLOGICA I, q.19, a.6, ad.1 (Fathers of the English Dominican Province trans., Benziger Bros. 1947-48); id. at I-II, q.7, aa.2-3; id. at I-II, q.18, aa.3-4 & 10-11; id. at I-II, q.73, a.7; id. at I-II, q.94, a.4; JOHN LOCKE, Essays on the Law of Nature, in LOCKE: POLITICAL ESSAYS essay 7, at 120 (Mark Goldie ed., 1997); William Wollaston, The Religion of Nature Delineated, in 1 BRITISH MORALISTS §§ 287-88, at 248-49 (D. D. Raphael ed., 1969) (1724); EDWARD BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO MORAL PHILOSOPHY 27-28 (Thoemmes Press 1994) (1745); DAVID FORDYCE, THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 47-48, 107 (Thoemmes Press 1990) (1754); ADAM FERGUSON, INSTITUTES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 163-64 (Garland 1978) (1773); RICHARD PRICE, A REVIEW OF THE PRINCIPAL QUESTIONS IN MORALS 164-65 175-76 (D. Daiches Raphael ed., 1948) (1787); ADAM SMITH, THE THEORY OF MORAL SENTIMENTS 174, 331-32, 339-40 (D.D. Raphael & A.L. Macfie eds., 1976) (1759); JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION ch. 7, § 21, at 194-95 (Wilfrid Harrison ed., 1948) (1823); 2 DUGALD STEWART, THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE ACTIVE AND MORAL POWERS OF MAN 326 (1828); GEORGE ELIOT, THE MILL ON THE FLOSS bk. 7, ch. 2, at 628 (A.S. Byatt ed., 1979) (1860); 2 ADOLF WUTTKE, CHRISTIAN ETHICS 133-39 (John P. Lacroix trans., 1873); PAUL JANET, THE THEORY OF MORALS 163-64 (Mary Chapman trans., 1883); WALTER H. HILL, ETHICS 62-64 (2d ed. 1878); J.H. MUIRHEAD, THE ELEMENTS OF ETHICS 197, 213 (1892).
    • (1883) The Theory of Morals , pp. 163-164
    • Janet, P.1
  • 113
    • 9744262927 scopus 로고
    • 2d ed.
    • Many people find this surprising. They have the vague idea that situationism is a discovery of the last hundred years or so. Some of them even believe that relativists deserve credit for the discovery. Lest these errors gain any more currency, the case against them will be documented with especial thoroughness. See PLATO, Republic, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO bk. 1, 331c, at 580 (Edith Hamilton & Huntington Cairns eds., 1963); ARISTOTLE, Ethica Nicomachea, in THE BASIC WORKS OF ARISTOTLE bk. 2, 1104a1-9, 1109b14-27, at 953, 964 (Richard McKeon ed., 1941); CICERO, The Offices, in CICERO'S OFFICES 14-15 ,27, 120, 124-25 (Thomas Cockman trans., J.M. Dent & Sons 1949); 1 ST. THOMAS AQUINAS, SUMMA THEOLOGICA I, q.19, a.6, ad.1 (Fathers of the English Dominican Province trans., Benziger Bros. 1947-48); id. at I-II, q.7, aa.2-3; id. at I-II, q.18, aa.3-4 & 10-11; id. at I-II, q.73, a.7; id. at I-II, q.94, a.4; JOHN LOCKE, Essays on the Law of Nature, in LOCKE: POLITICAL ESSAYS essay 7, at 120 (Mark Goldie ed., 1997); William Wollaston, The Religion of Nature Delineated, in 1 BRITISH MORALISTS §§ 287-88, at 248-49 (D. D. Raphael ed., 1969) (1724); EDWARD BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO MORAL PHILOSOPHY 27-28 (Thoemmes Press 1994) (1745); DAVID FORDYCE, THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 47-48, 107 (Thoemmes Press 1990) (1754); ADAM FERGUSON, INSTITUTES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 163-64 (Garland 1978) (1773); RICHARD PRICE, A REVIEW OF THE PRINCIPAL QUESTIONS IN MORALS 164-65 175-76 (D. Daiches Raphael ed., 1948) (1787); ADAM SMITH, THE THEORY OF MORAL SENTIMENTS 174, 331-32, 339-40 (D.D. Raphael & A.L. Macfie eds., 1976) (1759); JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION ch. 7, § 21, at 194-95 (Wilfrid Harrison ed., 1948) (1823); 2 DUGALD STEWART, THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE ACTIVE AND MORAL POWERS OF MAN 326 (1828); GEORGE ELIOT, THE MILL ON THE FLOSS bk. 7, ch. 2, at 628 (A.S. Byatt ed., 1979) (1860); 2 ADOLF WUTTKE, CHRISTIAN ETHICS 133-39 (John P. Lacroix trans., 1873); PAUL JANET, THE THEORY OF MORALS 163-64 (Mary Chapman trans., 1883); WALTER H. HILL, ETHICS 62-64 (2d ed. 1878); J.H. MUIRHEAD, THE ELEMENTS OF ETHICS 197, 213 (1892).
    • (1878) Ethics , pp. 62-64
    • Hill, W.H.1
  • 114
    • 9744256658 scopus 로고
    • Many people find this surprising. They have the vague idea that situationism is a discovery of the last hundred years or so. Some of them even believe that relativists deserve credit for the discovery. Lest these errors gain any more currency, the case against them will be documented with especial thoroughness. See PLATO, Republic, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO bk. 1, 331c, at 580 (Edith Hamilton & Huntington Cairns eds., 1963); ARISTOTLE, Ethica Nicomachea, in THE BASIC WORKS OF ARISTOTLE bk. 2, 1104a1-9, 1109b14-27, at 953, 964 (Richard McKeon ed., 1941); CICERO, The Offices, in CICERO'S OFFICES 14-15 ,27, 120, 124-25 (Thomas Cockman trans., J.M. Dent & Sons 1949); 1 ST. THOMAS AQUINAS, SUMMA THEOLOGICA I, q.19, a.6, ad.1 (Fathers of the English Dominican Province trans., Benziger Bros. 1947-48); id. at I-II, q.7, aa.2-3; id. at I-II, q.18, aa.3-4 & 10-11; id. at I-II, q.73, a.7; id. at I-II, q.94, a.4; JOHN LOCKE, Essays on the Law of Nature, in LOCKE: POLITICAL ESSAYS essay 7, at 120 (Mark Goldie ed., 1997); William Wollaston, The Religion of Nature Delineated, in 1 BRITISH MORALISTS §§ 287-88, at 248-49 (D. D. Raphael ed., 1969) (1724); EDWARD BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO MORAL PHILOSOPHY 27-28 (Thoemmes Press 1994) (1745); DAVID FORDYCE, THE ELEMENTS OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 47-48, 107 (Thoemmes Press 1990) (1754); ADAM FERGUSON, INSTITUTES OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY 163-64 (Garland 1978) (1773); RICHARD PRICE, A REVIEW OF THE PRINCIPAL QUESTIONS IN MORALS 164-65 175-76 (D. Daiches Raphael ed., 1948) (1787); ADAM SMITH, THE THEORY OF MORAL SENTIMENTS 174, 331-32, 339-40 (D.D. Raphael & A.L. Macfie eds., 1976) (1759); JEREMY BENTHAM, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE PRINCIPLES OF MORALS AND LEGISLATION ch. 7, § 21, at 194-95 (Wilfrid Harrison ed., 1948) (1823); 2 DUGALD STEWART, THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE ACTIVE AND MORAL POWERS OF MAN 326 (1828); GEORGE ELIOT, THE MILL ON THE FLOSS bk. 7, ch. 2, at 628 (A.S. Byatt ed., 1979) (1860); 2 ADOLF WUTTKE, CHRISTIAN ETHICS 133-39 (John P. Lacroix trans., 1873); PAUL JANET, THE THEORY OF MORALS 163-64 (Mary Chapman trans., 1883); WALTER H. HILL, ETHICS 62-64 (2d ed. 1878); J.H. MUIRHEAD, THE ELEMENTS OF ETHICS 197, 213 (1892).
    • (1892) The Elements of Ethics , pp. 197
    • Muirhead, J.H.1
  • 115
    • 0040894321 scopus 로고
    • Some Truths about Truth
    • For useful discussions, see STOUT, supra note 4, pt. 1; Max Hocutt, Some Truths about Truth, 22 BEHAV. & PHIL. 1-5 (1994).
    • (1994) Behav. & Phil. , vol.22 , pp. 1-5
    • Hocutt, M.1
  • 116
    • 0004289648 scopus 로고
    • ch. 9
    • An accessible defense of the correspondence theory - or a correspondence theory-is in JOHN R. SEARLE, THE CONSTRUCTION OF SOCIAL REALITY ch. 9 (1995). Also helpful is Hocutt, supra note 43.
    • (1995) The Construction of Social Reality
    • Searle, J.R.1
  • 117
    • 9744286663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I might have overlooked the fourth one had I not heard Dennis Stampe mention it. The example - about the chili - is his.
  • 118
    • 0003687747 scopus 로고
    • Indeed, fallibilists who reject relativism are numerous. Two examples are STOUT, supra note 4, pt. 1; and DAVID O. BRINK, MORAL REALISM AND THE FOUNDATIONS OF ETHICS (1989). A second point: The footnoted sentence suggests that just as fallibilists can be universalists, nonfallibilists can be cultural relativists. This is indeed the case. Nonfallibilism, in its classic form (known as foundationalism), asserts that some beliefs are incorrigible and that others are justified insofar as they are, or can be, reliably derived from the incorrigible ones. This thesis comports with the view that every moral truth tacitly refers to, and in that sense is "relative to," a specific culture. In short, a moral belief can be founded on incorrigible truths and at the same time be indexed to, or tacitly about, a particular culture. (Sumner and Herskovits can be interpreted along these lines, though it would take some work to show this.) Thus, the debate over fallibilism cannot settle the debate over relativism, and vice versa. We must keep these issues distinct.
    • (1989) Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics
    • Brink, D.O.1
  • 119
    • 0004137475 scopus 로고
    • Foundationalism is defined in note 46. Alternatives to it include coherentism and minimal (or fallibilist) foundationalism. Each of these views incorporates fallibilism; neither entails cultural relativism or anything close to it. Both views are discussed in ROBERT AUDI, THE STRUCTURE OF JUSTIFICATION (1993). Coherentism is also discussed in BRINK, supra note 46, ch. 5.
    • (1993) The Structure of Justification
    • Audi, R.1
  • 120
    • 0039487748 scopus 로고
    • ch. 5
    • For a more detailed discussion, see MARCUS GEORGE SINGER, GENERALIZATION IN ETHICS ch. 5 (1971). Also relevant are STACE, supra note 4, ch. 4 ; NICHOLAS RESCHER, OBJECTIVITY: THE OBLIGATIONS OF IMPERSONAL REASON 136-44 (1997). My treatment of rules, principles, and particular moral judgments is fairly traditional and perhaps oversimplified. For a more complicated picture, see ARRINGTON, supra note 39, ch. 1. The complications undermine none of the main results of this section.
    • (1971) Generalization in Ethics
    • Singer, M.G.1
  • 121
    • 0009337835 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For a more detailed discussion, see MARCUS GEORGE SINGER, GENERALIZATION IN ETHICS ch. 5 (1971). Also relevant are STACE, supra note 4, ch. 4 ; NICHOLAS RESCHER, OBJECTIVITY: THE OBLIGATIONS OF IMPERSONAL REASON 136-44 (1997). My treatment of rules, principles, and particular moral judgments is fairly traditional and perhaps oversimplified. For a more complicated picture, see ARRINGTON, supra note 39, ch. 1. The complications undermine none of the main results of this section.
    • (1997) Objectivity: The Obligations of Impersonal Reason , pp. 136-144
    • Rescher, N.1
  • 122
    • 9744274412 scopus 로고
    • The Ideal of a Rational Morality
    • My definition of absolutism, specifically my insertion of "ordinary" in front of "moral rules," reflects the influence of Marcus George Singer, The Ideal of a Rational Morality, 60 PROC. & ADDRESSES AM. PHIL. ASSN. 15, 28 (1986).
    • (1986) Proc. & Addresses Am. Phil. Assn. , vol.60 , pp. 15
    • Singer, M.G.1
  • 123
    • 3042923599 scopus 로고
    • Frank Thilly trans.
    • Five examples: POJMAN, supra note 4, at 47; RESCHER, supra note 48, at 164; SINGER, supra note 48, at 123-33; FRIEDRICH PAULSEN, A SYSTEM OF ETHICS 233-35, 360-63 (Frank Thilly trans., 1899); KWASI WIREDU, CULTURAL UNIVERSALS AND PARTICULARS: AN AFRICAN PERSPECTIVE 65-66 (1996). See also STACE, supra note 4, at 193-94; TAYLOR, supra note 4, at 26-29; SMITH, supra note 42, at 174. An objection may come to mind here: namely, that when relativists identify universalism with absolutism, they are not using "absolutism" the way I do. This objection is addressed in Section VII, part H.
    • (1899) A System of Ethics , pp. 233-235
    • Paulsen, F.1
  • 124
    • 0006671007 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Five examples: POJMAN, supra note 4, at 47; RESCHER, supra note 48, at 164; SINGER, supra note 48, at 123-33; FRIEDRICH PAULSEN, A SYSTEM OF ETHICS 233-35, 360-63 (Frank Thilly trans., 1899); KWASI WIREDU, CULTURAL UNIVERSALS AND PARTICULARS: AN AFRICAN PERSPECTIVE 65-66 (1996). See also STACE, supra note 4, at 193-94; TAYLOR, supra note 4, at 26-29; SMITH, supra note 42, at 174. An objection may come to mind here: namely, that when relativists identify universalism with absolutism, they are not using "absolutism" the way I do. This objection is addressed in Section VII, part H.
    • (1996) Cultural Universals and Particulars: An African Perspective , pp. 65-66
    • Wiredu, K.1
  • 125
    • 9744268644 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This article uses utilitarianism (act utilitarianism) and liberalism, both of which are forms of universalism, to illustrate various points. This is because both views are plausible and familiar. Whether they are true is an independent issue, an issue on which the general points of this essay do not hinge. For an illustration of this claim, see infra note 66 and accompanying text.
  • 126
    • 9744239237 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See HERSKOVITS, supra note 6, at 14; BENEDICT, supra note 6, at 278
    • See HERSKOVITS, supra note 6, at 14; BENEDICT, supra note 6, at 278.
  • 127
    • 9744281609 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Some will contend that (1) is not plausible, that mercy killing is always wrong. We need not dispute their point. If it is true, the nomad argument fails owing to a false premise. If it is not true, the nomad argument fails for reasons stated below.
  • 128
    • 9744284679 scopus 로고
    • Cultural Relativity in Ethics
    • For discussions, summaries, and pieces of this evidence, see the following authors and the many others they cite: BRANDT, supra note 4, at 285-88; W.H. Davis, Cultural Relativity in Ethics, 9 S. HUMAN. REV. 51 (1975); Frances V. Harbour, Basic Moral Values: A Shared Core, 9 ETHICS & INT'L AFF. 155 (1995). Also relevant are WIREDU, supra note 50, ch. 6; and 1 WILLIAM EDWARD HARTPOLE LECKY, HISTORY OF EUROPEAN MORALS FROM AUGUSTUS TO CHARLEMAGNE 91-110 (George Braziller 1955) (1869).
    • (1975) S. Human. Rev. , vol.9 , pp. 51
    • Davis, W.H.1
  • 129
    • 84976113377 scopus 로고
    • Basic Moral Values: A Shared Core
    • For discussions, summaries, and pieces of this evidence, see the following authors and the many others they cite: BRANDT, supra note 4, at 285-88; W.H. Davis, Cultural Relativity in Ethics, 9 S. HUMAN. REV. 51 (1975); Frances V. Harbour, Basic Moral Values: A Shared Core, 9 ETHICS & INT'L AFF. 155 (1995). Also relevant are WIREDU, supra note 50, ch. 6; and 1 WILLIAM EDWARD HARTPOLE LECKY, HISTORY OF EUROPEAN MORALS FROM AUGUSTUS TO CHARLEMAGNE 91-110 (George Braziller 1955) (1869).
    • (1995) Ethics & Int'l Aff. , vol.9 , pp. 155
    • Harbour, F.V.1
  • 130
    • 3743143340 scopus 로고
    • George Braziller (1869)
    • For discussions, summaries, and pieces of this evidence, see the following authors and the many others they cite: BRANDT, supra note 4, at 285-88; W.H. Davis, Cultural Relativity in Ethics, 9 S. HUMAN. REV. 51 (1975); Frances V. Harbour, Basic Moral Values: A Shared Core, 9 ETHICS & INT'L AFF. 155 (1995). Also relevant are WIREDU, supra note 50, ch. 6; and 1 WILLIAM EDWARD HARTPOLE LECKY, HISTORY OF EUROPEAN MORALS FROM AUGUSTUS TO CHARLEMAGNE 91-110 (George Braziller 1955) (1869).
    • (1955) History of European Morals from Augustus to Charlemagne , pp. 91-110
    • Lecky, W.E.H.1
  • 131
    • 9744241385 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Also, relativists have no business asking the first question, for their thesis asserts that some moral judgments are valid.
  • 132
    • 0141769667 scopus 로고
    • We should expect this for other reasons as well. For pertinent and useful remarks, see STACE, supra note 4, ch. 10; LECKY, supra note 54; MORRIS GINSBERG, ON THE DIVERSITY OF MORALS 101-10 (1956); Ronald D. Milo, Moral Deadlock, 61 PHIL. 453 (1986); Judith Jarvis Thomson, The No Reason Thesis, in FOUNDATIONS OF MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 1, 15-18 (Ellen Frankel Paul et al. eds., 1990).
    • (1956) On the Diversity of Morals , pp. 101-110
    • Ginsberg, M.1
  • 133
    • 84971160023 scopus 로고
    • Moral Deadlock
    • We should expect this for other reasons as well. For pertinent and useful remarks, see STACE, supra note 4, ch. 10; LECKY, supra note 54; MORRIS GINSBERG, ON THE DIVERSITY OF MORALS 101-10 (1956); Ronald D. Milo, Moral Deadlock, 61 PHIL. 453 (1986); Judith Jarvis Thomson, The No Reason Thesis, in FOUNDATIONS OF MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 1, 15-18 (Ellen Frankel Paul et al. eds., 1990).
    • (1986) Phil. , vol.61 , pp. 453
    • Milo, R.D.1
  • 134
    • 84974069745 scopus 로고
    • The No Reason Thesis
    • Ellen Frankel Paul et al. eds.
    • We should expect this for other reasons as well. For pertinent and useful remarks, see STACE, supra note 4, ch. 10; LECKY, supra note 54; MORRIS GINSBERG, ON THE DIVERSITY OF MORALS 101-10 (1956); Ronald D. Milo, Moral Deadlock, 61 PHIL. 453 (1986); Judith Jarvis Thomson, The No Reason Thesis, in FOUNDATIONS OF MORAL AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY 1, 15-18 (Ellen Frankel Paul et al. eds., 1990).
    • (1990) Foundations of Moral and Political Philosophy , pp. 1
    • Thomson, J.J.1
  • 135
    • 9744268649 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Assuming, that is, that it is possible for different people to accept different ones. See the next paragraph in the text.
  • 136
    • 84866834238 scopus 로고
    • Aren't Moral Judgments "Factual"?
    • § 4
    • For more on this point, which to my knowledge no relativist has adequately addressed, see STOUT, supra note 4, at 19-21; RESCHER, supra note 48, ch. 9; Martin E. Lean, Aren't Moral Judgments "Factual"?, 51 PERSONALIST § 4 (1970); David Cooper, Moral Relativism, 3 MIDWEST STUD. IN PHIL. 97 (1978); J.L.A. Garcia, Relativism and Moral Divergence, 19 METAPHIL. 264, 275-80 (1988).
    • (1970) Personalist , vol.51
    • Lean, M.E.1
  • 137
    • 84985384639 scopus 로고
    • Moral Relativism
    • For more on this point, which to my knowledge no relativist has adequately addressed, see STOUT, supra note 4, at 19-21; RESCHER, supra note 48, ch. 9; Martin E. Lean, Aren't Moral Judgments "Factual"?, 51 PERSONALIST § 4 (1970); David Cooper, Moral Relativism, 3 MIDWEST STUD. IN PHIL. 97 (1978); J.L.A. Garcia, Relativism and Moral Divergence, 19 METAPHIL. 264, 275-80 (1988).
    • (1978) Midwest Stud. in Phil. , vol.3 , pp. 97
    • Cooper, D.1
  • 138
    • 84981406669 scopus 로고
    • Relativism and Moral Divergence
    • For more on this point, which to my knowledge no relativist has adequately addressed, see STOUT, supra note 4, at 19-21; RESCHER, supra note 48, ch. 9; Martin E. Lean, Aren't Moral Judgments "Factual"?, 51 PERSONALIST § 4 (1970); David Cooper, Moral Relativism, 3 MIDWEST STUD. IN PHIL. 97 (1978); J.L.A. Garcia, Relativism and Moral Divergence, 19 METAPHIL. 264, 275-80 (1988).
    • (1988) Metaphil. , vol.19 , pp. 264
    • Garcia, J.L.A.1
  • 139
    • 84933488409 scopus 로고
    • Some people assume that total relativism has been established by the individual or combined work of various "postmodern" thinkers - e.g., Stanley Fish, Jacques Derrida, and Richard Rorty. This assumption is made by JUNG MIN CHOI & JOHN W. MURPHY, THE POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHY OF POLITICAL CORRECTNESS (1992). These authors accept total relativism but never state it clearly. For a brief but sound criticism of their endorsement and use of that thesis, a criticism that applies to many other postmodernists, see Francis J. Beckwith, A Critique of Political Correctness, in PHILOSOPHY: THE QUEST FOR TRUTH 582 (Louis P. Pojman ed., 3d ed. 1996). Three other brief but forceful works on this topic are: Richard D. Mohr, The Perils of Postmodernism, 2 HARV. GAY & LESBIAN REV. 9 (1995); Thomas Nagel, The Sleep of Reason, NEW REPUBLIC, 12 Oct. 1998, at 32; Margarita Rosa Levin, A Defense of Objectivity, in THE THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE: CLASSICAL & CONTEMPORARY READINGS 631 (Louis P. Pojman ed., 2d ed. 1999).
    • (1992) The Politics and Philosophy of Political Correctness
    • Choi, J.M.1    Murphy, J.W.2
  • 140
    • 9744262156 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Critique of Political Correctness
    • Louis P. Pojman ed., 3d ed.
    • Some people assume that total relativism has been established by the individual or combined work of various "postmodern" thinkers - e.g., Stanley Fish, Jacques Derrida, and Richard Rorty. This assumption is made by JUNG MIN CHOI & JOHN W. MURPHY, THE POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHY OF POLITICAL CORRECTNESS (1992). These authors accept total relativism but never state it clearly. For a brief but sound criticism of their endorsement and use of that thesis, a criticism that applies to many other postmodernists, see Francis J. Beckwith, A Critique of Political Correctness, in PHILOSOPHY: THE QUEST FOR TRUTH 582 (Louis P. Pojman ed., 3d ed. 1996). Three other brief but forceful works on this topic are: Richard D. Mohr, The Perils of Postmodernism, 2 HARV. GAY & LESBIAN REV. 9 (1995); Thomas Nagel, The Sleep of Reason, NEW REPUBLIC, 12 Oct. 1998, at 32; Margarita Rosa Levin, A Defense of Objectivity, in THE THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE: CLASSICAL & CONTEMPORARY READINGS 631 (Louis P. Pojman ed., 2d ed. 1999).
    • (1996) Philosophy: The Quest for Truth , pp. 582
    • Beckwith, F.J.1
  • 141
    • 0346773849 scopus 로고
    • The Perils of Postmodernism
    • Some people assume that total relativism has been established by the individual or combined work of various "postmodern" thinkers - e.g., Stanley Fish, Jacques Derrida, and Richard Rorty. This assumption is made by JUNG MIN CHOI & JOHN W. MURPHY, THE POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHY OF POLITICAL CORRECTNESS (1992). These authors accept total relativism but never state it clearly. For a brief but sound criticism of their endorsement and use of that thesis, a criticism that applies to many other postmodernists, see Francis J. Beckwith, A Critique of Political Correctness, in PHILOSOPHY: THE QUEST FOR TRUTH 582 (Louis P. Pojman ed., 3d ed. 1996). Three other brief but forceful works on this topic are: Richard D. Mohr, The Perils of Postmodernism, 2 HARV. GAY & LESBIAN REV. 9 (1995); Thomas Nagel, The Sleep of Reason, NEW REPUBLIC, 12 Oct. 1998, at 32; Margarita Rosa Levin, A Defense of Objectivity, in THE THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE: CLASSICAL & CONTEMPORARY READINGS 631 (Louis P. Pojman ed., 2d ed. 1999).
    • (1995) Harv. Gay & Lesbian Rev. , vol.2 , pp. 9
    • Mohr, R.D.1
  • 142
    • 0040806249 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The Sleep of Reason
    • 12 Oct.
    • Some people assume that total relativism has been established by the individual or combined work of various "postmodern" thinkers - e.g., Stanley Fish, Jacques Derrida, and Richard Rorty. This assumption is made by JUNG MIN CHOI & JOHN W. MURPHY, THE POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHY OF POLITICAL CORRECTNESS (1992). These authors accept total relativism but never state it clearly. For a brief but sound criticism of their endorsement and use of that thesis, a criticism that applies to many other postmodernists, see Francis J. Beckwith, A Critique of Political Correctness, in PHILOSOPHY: THE QUEST FOR TRUTH 582 (Louis P. Pojman ed., 3d ed. 1996). Three other brief but forceful works on this topic are: Richard D. Mohr, The Perils of Postmodernism, 2 HARV. GAY & LESBIAN REV. 9 (1995); Thomas Nagel, The Sleep of Reason, NEW REPUBLIC, 12 Oct. 1998, at 32; Margarita Rosa Levin, A Defense of Objectivity, in THE THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE: CLASSICAL & CONTEMPORARY READINGS 631 (Louis P. Pojman ed., 2d ed. 1999).
    • (1998) New Republic , pp. 32
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 143
    • 0007178964 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A Defense of Objectivity
    • Louis P. Pojman ed., 2d ed.
    • Some people assume that total relativism has been established by the individual or combined work of various "postmodern" thinkers - e.g., Stanley Fish, Jacques Derrida, and Richard Rorty. This assumption is made by JUNG MIN CHOI & JOHN W. MURPHY, THE POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHY OF POLITICAL CORRECTNESS (1992). These authors accept total relativism but never state it clearly. For a brief but sound criticism of their endorsement and use of that thesis, a criticism that applies to many other postmodernists, see Francis J. Beckwith, A Critique of Political Correctness, in PHILOSOPHY: THE QUEST FOR TRUTH 582 (Louis P. Pojman ed., 3d ed. 1996). Three other brief but forceful works on this topic are: Richard D. Mohr, The Perils of Postmodernism, 2 HARV. GAY & LESBIAN REV. 9 (1995); Thomas Nagel, The Sleep of Reason, NEW REPUBLIC, 12 Oct. 1998, at 32; Margarita Rosa Levin, A Defense of Objectivity, in THE THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE: CLASSICAL & CONTEMPORARY READINGS 631 (Louis P. Pojman ed., 2d ed. 1999).
    • (1999) The Theory of Knowledge: Classical & Contemporary Readings , pp. 631
    • Levin, M.R.1
  • 144
    • 0010775848 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Theaetetus
    • supra note 42, 170a-171c
    • See PLATO, Theaetetus, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO, supra note 42, 170a-171c, at 875-77. For recent discussions, see HARVEY SIEGEL, RELATIVISM REFUTED (1987); JAMES F. HARRIS, AGAINST RELATIVISM (1992); John Preston, On Some Objections to Relativism, 5 RATIO JURIS 57 (1992); Harold Zellner, Is Relativism Self-Defeating?, 20 J. PHIL. RES. 287 (1995).
    • The Collected Dialogues of Plato , pp. 875-877
    • Plato1
  • 145
    • 0039981753 scopus 로고
    • See PLATO, Theaetetus, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO, supra note 42, 170a-171c, at 875-77. For recent discussions, see HARVEY SIEGEL, RELATIVISM REFUTED (1987); JAMES F. HARRIS, AGAINST RELATIVISM (1992); John Preston, On Some Objections to Relativism, 5 RATIO JURIS 57 (1992); Harold Zellner, Is Relativism Self-Defeating?, 20 J. PHIL. RES. 287 (1995).
    • (1987) Relativism Refuted
    • Siegel, H.1
  • 146
    • 0007584787 scopus 로고
    • See PLATO, Theaetetus, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO, supra note 42, 170a-171c, at 875-77. For recent discussions, see HARVEY SIEGEL, RELATIVISM REFUTED (1987); JAMES F. HARRIS, AGAINST RELATIVISM (1992); John Preston, On Some Objections to Relativism, 5 RATIO JURIS 57 (1992); Harold Zellner, Is Relativism Self-Defeating?, 20 J. PHIL. RES. 287 (1995).
    • (1992) Against Relativism
    • Harris, J.F.1
  • 147
    • 9744268646 scopus 로고
    • On Some Objections to Relativism
    • See PLATO, Theaetetus, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO, supra note 42, 170a-171c, at 875-77. For recent discussions, see HARVEY SIEGEL, RELATIVISM REFUTED (1987); JAMES F. HARRIS, AGAINST RELATIVISM (1992); John Preston, On Some Objections to Relativism, 5 RATIO JURIS 57 (1992); Harold Zellner, Is Relativism Self-Defeating?, 20 J. PHIL. RES. 287 (1995).
    • (1992) Ratio Juris , vol.5 , pp. 57
    • Preston, J.1
  • 148
    • 9744283143 scopus 로고
    • Is Relativism Self-Defeating?
    • See PLATO, Theaetetus, in THE COLLECTED DIALOGUES OF PLATO, supra note 42, 170a-171c, at 875-77. For recent discussions, see HARVEY SIEGEL, RELATIVISM REFUTED (1987); JAMES F. HARRIS, AGAINST RELATIVISM (1992); John Preston, On Some Objections to Relativism, 5 RATIO JURIS 57 (1992); Harold Zellner, Is Relativism Self-Defeating?, 20 J. PHIL. RES. 287 (1995).
    • (1995) J. Phil. Res. , vol.20 , pp. 287
    • Zellner, H.1
  • 149
    • 9744270395 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Nor will it do to exempt total relativism from what it says about other judgments. If one judgment is exempt from it, perhaps many are, including many moral ones.
  • 150
    • 9744272158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • BENEDICT, supra note 6, at 126. I am not saying (nor denying) that Benedict thinks certainty is attainable. Confidence and certainty are two different things. See infra note 64.
  • 151
    • 9744287398 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Benedict does some confident moralizing in BENEDICT, supra note 6, at 32, 37, 247-50.
  • 152
    • 0003614867 scopus 로고
    • Nathan Houser & Christian Kloesel eds.
    • Two such accounts are mentioned in note 46. The claim that confidence is at home with nonfoundationalism will seem paradoxical if we conflate confidence with philosophical certainly. The greatest confidence we can have in a belief is the confidence produced, or rather constituted by, the absence of sincere doubt. The absence of such doubt requires no certainty of the kind foundationalism deems possible. An excellent source on this subject is 1 CHARLES S. PEIRCE, THE ESSENTIAL PEIRCE: SELECTED PHILOSOPHICAL WRITINGS (Nathan Houser & Christian Kloesel eds., 1992) (see especially essay 7: The Fixation of Belief). Included in this volume is Peirce's 1868 article, Questions Concerning Certain Faculties Claimed for Man. This is a classic critique of foundationalism.
    • (1992) The Essential Peirce: Selected Philosophical Writings
    • Peirce, C.S.1
  • 153
    • 0004347851 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two such accounts are mentioned in note 46. The claim that confidence is at home with nonfoundationalism will seem paradoxical if we conflate confidence with philosophical certainly. The greatest confidence we can have in a belief is the confidence produced, or rather constituted by, the absence of sincere doubt. The absence of such doubt requires no certainty of the kind foundationalism deems possible. An excellent source on this subject is 1 CHARLES S. PEIRCE, THE ESSENTIAL PEIRCE: SELECTED PHILOSOPHICAL WRITINGS (Nathan Houser & Christian Kloesel eds., 1992) (see especially essay 7: The Fixation of Belief). Included in this volume is Peirce's 1868 article, Questions Concerning Certain Faculties Claimed for Man. This is a classic critique of foundationalism.
    • The Fixation of Belief
  • 154
    • 84889409005 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Two such accounts are mentioned in note 46. The claim that confidence is at home with nonfoundationalism will seem paradoxical if we conflate confidence with philosophical certainly. The greatest confidence we can have in a belief is the confidence produced, or rather constituted by, the absence of sincere doubt. The absence of such doubt requires no certainty of the kind foundationalism deems possible. An excellent source on this subject is 1 CHARLES S. PEIRCE, THE ESSENTIAL PEIRCE: SELECTED PHILOSOPHICAL WRITINGS (Nathan Houser & Christian Kloesel eds., 1992) (see especially essay 7: The Fixation of Belief). Included in this volume is Peirce's 1868 article, Questions Concerning Certain Faculties Claimed for Man. This is a classic critique of foundationalism.
    • Questions Concerning Certain Faculties Claimed for Man
  • 155
    • 9744243950 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For the kind of confusion that gives rise to the empirical outlook argument, see CHOI & MURPHY, supra note 59, at 41-42.
  • 156
    • 9744240663 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Nor does it refute most other versions of universalism, e.g., those proposed by Nussbaum, supra note 3, at 212-46; POJMAN, supra note 4, ch. 3; STACE, supra note 4, ch. 7; HATCH, supra note 7, ch. 7; RESCHER, supra note 48, chs. 9-10; SINGER, supra note 48, chs. 1-5.
  • 157
    • 9744287399 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Whether respecting cultural integrity involves condoning all that is customary within a culture is another question. And whether disapproving of a custom requires interfering with it is still another question. Discussion of these issues becomes muddled if they are not distinguished, and even more muddled if we mistakenly think that the injunction to respect cultural integrity requires cultural relativism for its support. Not only does the injunction to respect cultural integrity stand in no need of relativism, it finds relativism a troublesome bedfellow. According to cultural relativism, the judgment "showing respect for cultural integrity is morally right" is not valid for all cultures.
  • 158
    • 9744270396 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For more on how universalism makes room for pluralism, see Nussbaum, supra note 3, at 224-25; Perry, supra note 4, at 471-75; HATCH, supra note 7, ch. 7; WIREDU, supra note 50, chs. 3, 6.
  • 159
    • 9744275642 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • SUMNER, supra note 7, § 232; BENEDICT, supra note 6, at 2-3; HERSKOVITS, supra note 6, at 15-20, 56, 58, 84-85.
  • 160
    • 9744225555 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Suppose, for instance, that a thesis counts as biased if questions, interests, or assumptions shared by only some of the world's cultures contributed to its genesis. Then no doubt is cast on the thesis by showing it to be biased. The Pythagorean theorem is biased in this sense, but it's not implausible on that account.
  • 161
    • 9744255909 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Renteln seems to advocate this strategy. See RENTELN, supra note 3, at 69, 71, 74-76.
  • 162
    • 0003720279 scopus 로고
    • chs. 3
    • On this topic, Elvin Hatch is illuminating. See HATCH, supra note 7, chs. 2-3. See especially id. at 50. See also Bidney, supra note 21, §§ 5-6; CARL N. DEGLER, IN SEARCH OF HUMAN NATURE chs. 3, 8 (1991).
    • (1991) Search of Human Nature , pp. 8
    • Degler, C.N.1
  • 163
    • 9744245709 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • For another angle on the confusion in the naiveté argument, see Beckwith, supra note 59, at 587.
  • 164
    • 9744266158 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral Arguments for Cultural Relativism
    • I discuss this argument more fully, along with some empirical research that may seem, but in fact fails, to buttress it, in John J. Tilley, Moral Arguments for Cultural Relativism, 17 NETH. Q. HUM. RTS. 36 (1999).
    • (1999) Neth. Q. Hum. Rts. , vol.17 , pp. 36
    • Tilley, J.J.1
  • 165
    • 9744268648 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • See, e.g., DOWNS, supra note 6; BENEDICT, supra note 6, at 37, 278; HERSKOVITS, supra note 6, at 15, 33, 93-94, 101; LEACH, supra note 7, ch. 4.
  • 166
    • 0004050201 scopus 로고
    • Nor is this a matter of blind faith. Plausible arguments for universalism are easier to produce than relativists suppose. (What is not so easy to produce are plausible arguments for theories that propose a simple, universal algorithm for moral decisions. Relativists often confuse the arguments for such algorithms with arguments for universalism.) For a brief one, see WIREDU, supra note 50, at 29. For more elaborate ones in the same spirit, see WHITE, supra note 4, chs. 4-5; RESCHER, supra note 48, ch. 9; G.J. WARNOCK, THE OBJECT OF MORALITY (1971).
    • (1971) The Object of Morality
    • Warnock, G.J.1
  • 167
    • 9744259989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Renteln takes care to avoid the mistake discussed here. See RENTELN, supra note 3, ch. 3.
  • 168
    • 9744249136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • This is emphasized in RENTELN, supra note 3, at 73-74.


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.