메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 16, Issue 1, 1998, Pages 163-171

“Law and Neoclassical Economics”: A Response to Commentaries

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0041906986     PISSN: 07382480     EISSN: 19399022     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/744326     Document Type: Letter
Times cited : (1)

References (26)
  • 1
    • 84974070921 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • see Ronald Coase's critique of A. W. B. Simpson's historical work
    • For an example of this, see Ronald Coase's critique of A. W. B. Simpson's historical work
    • For an example of this
  • 2
    • 0042129584 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • “Law and Economics and A. W. Brian Simpson,” Journal of Legal Studies 25 : 105. (“He [Simpson] writes about economics and economists from the point
    • on the Coase theorem, “Law and Economics and A. W. Brian Simpson,” Journal of Legal Studies 25 (1996): 105. (“He [Simpson] writes about economics and economists from the point
    • (1996) on the Coase theorem
  • 3
    • 85022770426 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is not surprising to find that his article contains so many misunderstandings of my position and misstatements about me and my work.”)
    • of view of an historian and a lawyer. It is not surprising to find that his article contains so many misunderstandings of my position and misstatements about me and my work.”)
    • of view of an historian and a lawyer
  • 7
    • 0026956612 scopus 로고
    • Gary Salon, “Intergenerational Income Mobility in the United States,” American Economic Review 82 (1992) (Papers and Proceedings of the 104th Annual Meeting of the American Economic Association): 393-108; David Cutter and Lawrence Katz, “Rising Inequality? Changes in the Distribution of Income and Consumption in the 1980's,” American Economic Review 82
    • Economic studies have documented the fact that there is very little intergenerational income mobility in the United States. Gary Salon, “Intergenerational Income Mobility in the United States,” American Economic Review 82 (1992) (Papers and Proceedings of the 104th Annual Meeting of the American Economic Association): 393-108; David Cutter and Lawrence Katz, “Rising Inequality? Changes in the Distribution of Income and Consumption in the 1980's,” American Economic Review 82 (1992): 546-51.
    • (1992) Economic studies have documented the fact that there is very little intergenerational income mobility in the United States , pp. 546-551
  • 10
    • 85022834703 scopus 로고
    • see Steven Croley and Jon Hanson, “Rescuing the Revolution: The Revised Case for Enterprise Liability,” Michigan Law Review 91
    • For a comprehensive discussion of recent debates along these lines, see Steven Croley and Jon Hanson, “Rescuing the Revolution: The Revised Case for Enterprise Liability,” Michigan Law Review 91 (1993): 683-797.
    • (1993) For a comprehensive discussion of recent debates along these lines , pp. 683-797
  • 13
    • 85022807009 scopus 로고
    • For an extended discussion of the role of paternalism and distribution in tort and contract law doctrine, see Duncan Kennedy, “Distributive and Paternalist Motives in Contract and Tort Law, with Special Reference to Compulsory Terms and Unequal Bargaining Power,” Maryland Law Review 41 : 563-658.1 am in agreement with Duxbury that more recent writings by Calabresi may clarify the nature and full implications of these and other distinctions (“Law and Economics, Science and Politics,” 326, n.22).
    • I must admit to not fully exploring one aspect of distinction: Calabresi's paternalist beliefs about the ability of individuals to act in their own self-interest. For an extended discussion of the role of paternalism and distribution in tort and contract law doctrine, see Duncan Kennedy, “Distributive and Paternalist Motives in Contract and Tort Law, with Special Reference to Compulsory Terms and Unequal Bargaining Power,” Maryland Law Review 41 (1982): 563-658.1 am in agreement with Duxbury that more recent writings by Calabresi may clarify the nature and full implications of these and other distinctions (“Law and Economics, Science and Politics,” 326, n.22).
    • (1982) I must admit to not fully exploring one aspect of distinction: Calabresi's paternalist beliefs about the ability of individuals to act in their own self-interest
  • 14
    • 85022874335 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 330-31. Heckman's framing of Coase as a libertarian is somewhat in error. Coase may be more properly labeled as antistatist. See “Looking for Results,” an interview with Coase by Thomas Hozlett, Reason (January), 42: “I've never started off-this is perhaps why I'm not a libertarian-with the idea that a human being has certain rights.”
    • Heckman, “Intellectual Roots,” 330-31. Heckman's framing of Coase as a libertarian is somewhat in error. Coase may be more properly labeled as antistatist. See “Looking for Results,” an interview with Coase by Thomas Hozlett, Reason (January 1997), 42: “I've never started off-this is perhaps why I'm not a libertarian-with the idea that a human being has certain rights.”
    • (1997) “Intellectual Roots,”
    • Heckman1
  • 15
    • 85022747236 scopus 로고
    • American Economic Review 61 (1951): 15. (“[D]on't expect too much of ‘the state,’ be very critical in appraising the prospects for good and for harm to result before calling on ‘Leviathan’ and giving him power.”) For a discussion of Knight's libertarian views, see John McKinney, “Frank Knight and Chicago Libertarianism,” in The Chicago School of Political Economy, ed. Warren J. Samuels (New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers, 1976), 191. For an analysis of Knight's uneasiness with the laissez-faire position, see Sheryl Davis Kasper, “Frank Knight's Case for Laissez-Faire: The Patrimony of the Social Philosophy of the Chicago School,” History of Political Economy 25
    • See Frank Knight, “The Role of Principles in Economics and Politics,” American Economic Review 61 (1951): 15. (“[D]on't expect too much of ‘the state,’ be very critical in appraising the prospects for good and for harm to result before calling on ‘Leviathan’ and giving him power.”) For a discussion of Knight's libertarian views, see John McKinney, “Frank Knight and Chicago Libertarianism,” in The Chicago School of Political Economy, ed. Warren J. Samuels (New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers, 1976), 191. For an analysis of Knight's uneasiness with the laissez-faire position, see Sheryl Davis Kasper, “Frank Knight's Case for Laissez-Faire: The Patrimony of the Social Philosophy of the Chicago School,” History of Political Economy 25 (1993): 413-33.
    • (1993) “The Role of Principles in Economics and Politics,” , pp. 413-433
    • Knight, F.1
  • 16
    • 85022745502 scopus 로고
    • It is clear from their account that the era of “reigning Keynesian social planners,” as described by Heckman, was relatively short lived as a dominant theoretical project and subject to almost immediate contestation by antistatist neoclassicists. See Screpanti and Zamagni, An Outline of the History of Economic Thought (New York: Oxford University Press).
    • Ernesto Screpanti and Stefano Zamagni have written a very good treatment of the demise of Keynesianism at the hands of neoclassicists ranging from Lionel Robbins to Milton Friedman. It is clear from their account that the era of “reigning Keynesian social planners,” as described by Heckman, was relatively short lived as a dominant theoretical project and subject to almost immediate contestation by antistatist neoclassicists. See Screpanti and Zamagni, An Outline of the History of Economic Thought (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993).
    • (1993) Ernesto Screpanti and Stefano Zamagni have written a very good treatment of the demise of Keynesianism at the hands of neoclassicists ranging from Lionel Robbins to Milton Friedman
  • 17
    • 85022827928 scopus 로고
    • According to their chronology, the “Austrian theoretical approach joined the mainstream of the neoclassical system in the 1920's and 's.” See Ernesto Screpanti and Stefano Zamagni have written a very good treatment of the demise of Keynesianism at the hands of neoclassicists ranging from Lionel Robbins to Milton Friedman.
    • Screpanti and Zamagni give a detailed account of Austrian influences on “mainstream” economics. According to their chronology, the “Austrian theoretical approach joined the mainstream of the neoclassical system in the 1920's and 1930's.” See Ernesto Screpanti and Stefano Zamagni have written a very good treatment of the demise of Keynesianism at the hands of neoclassicists ranging from Lionel Robbins to Milton Friedman., 196.
    • (1930) Screpanti and Zamagni give a detailed account of Austrian influences on “mainstream” economics , pp. 196
  • 18
    • 85022352220 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Coase's recognition of his intellectual debt to F. A. Hayek and the institutional role Hayek played in establishing law and neoclassical economics studies at the University of Chicago is illustrative of this point. Hackney, 284, n. 42, 306, n. 141.
    • Coase's recognition of his intellectual debt to F. A. Hayek and the institutional role Hayek played in establishing law and neoclassical economics studies at the University of Chicago is illustrative of this point. Hackney, “Law and Neoclassical Economics,” 284, n. 42, 306, n. 141.
    • “Law and Neoclassical Economics,”
  • 19
    • 85022898649 scopus 로고
    • ed. Edmund W. Kitch, Journal of Law and Economics 26 : 163 (roundtable discussion of principal founders of law and neoclassical economics at the University of Chicago).
    • See “The Fire of Truth: A Remembrance of Law and Economics at Chicago, 1932-1970,” ed. Edmund W. Kitch, Journal of Law and Economics 26 (1983): 163 (roundtable discussion of principal founders of law and neoclassical economics at the University of Chicago).
    • (1983) “The Fire of Truth: A Remembrance of Law and Economics at Chicago, 1932-1970,”
  • 20
    • 85022770618 scopus 로고
    • For a discussion of this and their motives for doing so, see John P. Henderson, “The History of Thought in the Development of the Chicago Paradigm,” in The Chicago School of Political Economy, ed. Warren J. Samuels (New Brunswick: Transaction)
    • University of Chicago economists have had a tradition of paying particular attention to the intellectual history of their field. For a discussion of this and their motives for doing so, see John P. Henderson, “The History of Thought in the Development of the Chicago Paradigm,” in The Chicago School of Political Economy, ed. Warren J. Samuels (New Brunswick: Transaction, 1976), 341.
    • (1976) University of Chicago economists have had a tradition of paying particular attention to the intellectual history of their field , pp. 341
  • 22
    • 85022839553 scopus 로고
    • 1780-1860 (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1977) and The Transformation of American Law, 1870-1960 (New York: Oxford University Press) would be essential points of departure for such a study.
    • Morton Horwitz's The Transformation of American Law, 1780-1860 (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1977) and The Transformation of American Law, 1870-1960 (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992) would be essential points of departure for such a study.
    • (1992) Morton Horwitz's The Transformation of American Law
  • 24
    • 85022744451 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is obviously a major contribution to our understanding of the subject. However, I would not be the first to note that he “does not look closely enough into particular fields.” See Robert Gordon, “Book Review of Patterns of American Jurisprudence,” Georgetown Law Journal 84 : 2225. While Gordon's criticism was limited to Duxbury's study of the legal realists, I believe it is generally illustrative. It does not hold true so much for Duxbury's cogent analysis of law and neoclassical economics contributions to antitrust law but certainly applies to his discussion of tort law contributions, which lacks doctrinal focus and text analysis.
    • I never meant to cast any aspersions on Duxbury's exemplary account of law and neoclassical economics. It is obviously a major contribution to our understanding of the subject. However, I would not be the first to note that he “does not look closely enough into particular fields.” See Robert Gordon, “Book Review of Patterns of American Jurisprudence,” Georgetown Law Journal 84 (1996): 2225. While Gordon's criticism was limited to Duxbury's study of the legal realists, I believe it is generally illustrative. It does not hold true so much for Duxbury's cogent analysis of law and neoclassical economics contributions to antitrust law but certainly applies to his discussion of tort law contributions, which lacks doctrinal focus and text analysis.
    • (1996) I never meant to cast any aspersions on Duxbury's exemplary account of law and neoclassical economics
  • 26
    • 85022781418 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 323. Whether such analyses fall under the rubric of “rigorous revisionism” or “something more sophisticated” is a matter of semantics. “Haskins Lectures,”.
    • Duxbury, “Law and Economics, Science and Politics,” 323. Whether such analyses fall under the rubric of “rigorous revisionism” or “something more sophisticated” is a matter of semantics. “Haskins Lectures,”., 324.
    • “Law and Economics, Science and Politics,” , pp. 324
    • Duxbury1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.