메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 108, Issue 8, 1999, Pages 2215-2235

Transitions

(1)  Levinson, Sanford a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0041541752     PISSN: 00440094     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/797386     Document Type: Review
Times cited : (13)

References (96)
  • 2
    • 0008221469 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • forthcoming (studying transitional regimes, particularly in Latin America and Eastern Europe)
    • Ruti Teitel, Transitional Jurisprudence: The Role of Law in Political Transformation, 106 YALE L.J. 2009, 2009 (1997); see also RUTI TEITEL, TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE (forthcoming 1999) (studying transitional regimes, particularly in Latin America and Eastern Europe).
    • (1999) TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE
    • Teitel, R.1
  • 3
    • 0041556239 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1-3 TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE: How EMERGING DEMOCRACIES RECKON WITH FORMER REGIMES (Neil J. Kritz ed., 1995) [hereinafter EMERGING DEMOCRACIES]; see also TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE AND THE RULE OF LAW IN NEW DEMOCRACIES (A. James McAdams ed., 1997) (describing various transitions, including those in Greece, Hungary, Bolivia, South Africa, Argentina, Chile, East Germany, and Poland)
    • 1-3 TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE: How EMERGING DEMOCRACIES RECKON WITH FORMER REGIMES (Neil J. Kritz ed., 1995) [hereinafter EMERGING DEMOCRACIES]; see also TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE AND THE RULE OF LAW IN NEW DEMOCRACIES (A. James McAdams ed., 1997) (describing various transitions, including those in Greece, Hungary, Bolivia, South Africa, Argentina, Chile, East Germany, and Poland).
  • 4
    • 0042558318 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Foreword to supra note 2, at
    • See Nelson Mandela, Foreword to 1 EMERGING DEMOCRACIES, supra note 2, at xi, xi.
    • Emerging Democracies , vol.1
    • Mandela, N.1
  • 5
    • 0003444750 scopus 로고
    • at bookjacket
    • I am also an unabashed admirer of Ackerman's general enterprise, as evidenced by my comment, on the back jacket of the first volume of We the People, describing Ackerman's work as "[t]he most important project now underway in the entire field of constitutional theory." 1 BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: FOUNDATIONS at bookjacket (1991). No one has had more influence on my own work over the past decade. See, for example, RESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION: THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT (Sanford Levinson ed., 1995) [hereinafter RESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION], which was distinctly inspired by Ackerman's (and his colleague Akhil Amar's) critiques of the conventional understanding of constitutional amendment within the American system.
    • (1991) We the People: Foundations
    • Ackerman, B.1
  • 6
    • 0009276890 scopus 로고
    • Sanford Levinson ed., [hereinafter RESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION], which was distinctly inspired by Ackerman's (and his colleague Akhil Amar's) critiques of the conventional understanding of constitutional amendment within the American system
    • I am also an unabashed admirer of Ackerman's general enterprise, as evidenced by my comment, on the back jacket of the first volume of We the People, describing Ackerman's work as "[t]he most important project now underway in the entire field of constitutional theory." 1 BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: FOUNDATIONS at bookjacket (1991). No one has had more influence on my own work over the past decade. See, for example, RESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION: THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT (Sanford Levinson ed., 1995) [hereinafter RESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION], which was distinctly inspired by Ackerman's (and his colleague Akhil Amar's) critiques of the conventional understanding of constitutional amendment within the American system.
    • (1995) Responding to Imperfection: The Theory and Practice of Constitutional Amendment
  • 8
    • 0007199581 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I also greatly admire, and have been influenced by, the work of Stephen Griffin, who asks, especially at the empirical level, similar questions. See STEPHEN M. GRIFFIN, AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONALISM (1996); Stephen M. Griffin, Constitutional Theory Transformed, 108 YALE L.J. 2115 (1999).
    • (1996) American Constitutionalism
    • Griffin, S.M.1
  • 9
    • 0041541753 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • YALE L.J.
    • I also greatly admire, and have been influenced by, the work of Stephen Griffin, who asks, especially at the empirical level, similar questions. See STEPHEN M. GRIFFIN, AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONALISM (1996); Stephen M. Griffin, Constitutional Theory Transformed, 108 YALE L.J. 2115 (1999).
    • (1999) Constitutional Theory Transformed , vol.108 , pp. 2115
    • Griffin, S.M.1
  • 10
    • 0041556430 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ackermania or uncomfortable truths?
    • Lucas Powe questions the progressive narrative in his own review of Ackerman. See L.A. Powe, Jr., Ackermania or Uncomfortable Truths?, 15 CONST. COMMENTARY 547, 560-61 (1998) (reviewing 2 BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: TRANSFORMATIONS (1998)).
    • (1998) Const. Commentary , vol.15 , pp. 547
    • Powe L.A., Jr.1
  • 11
    • 0043059208 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Lucas Powe questions the progressive narrative in his own review of Ackerman. See L.A. Powe, Jr., Ackermania or Uncomfortable Truths?, 15 CONST. COMMENTARY 547, 560-61 (1998) (reviewing 2 BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: TRANSFORMATIONS (1998)).
    • (1998) We the People: Transformations , vol.2
    • Ackerman, B.1
  • 12
    • 0041556217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • At least when "American" is taken to mean persons within the United States who fixate exclusively on the history of the United States
    • At least when "American" is taken to mean persons within the United States who fixate exclusively on the history of the United States.
  • 13
    • 0042057445 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 7, at 212, 463 n.8
    • 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 7, at 212, 463 n.8 (1998).
    • (1998)
    • Ackerman1
  • 14
    • 0042558307 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 71 U.S. 333 (1867)
    • 71 U.S. 333 (1867).
  • 15
    • 0042057464 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 71 U.S. 277 (1867)
    • 71 U.S. 277 (1867).
  • 16
    • 0042057439 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ackerman in fact scants the deep constitutional issues at the heart of the secession issue, taking as a (relative) given the illegitimacy of secession. For what it is worth, I think there is substantial merit in the Southern position and that the war was justified by the injustice (rather than the illegality per se) of the Confederate regime
    • Ackerman in fact scants the deep constitutional issues at the heart of the secession issue, taking as a (relative) given the illegitimacy of secession. For what it is worth, I think there is substantial merit in the Southern position and that the war was justified by the injustice (rather than the illegality per se) of the Confederate regime.
  • 17
    • 0042057447 scopus 로고
    • supra note 5, at 72
    • ACKERMAN, supra note 5, at 72 (1992); see also Steven R. Ratner, New Democracies, Old Atrocities: An Inquiry in International Law, 87 GEO. L.J. 707, 709 (1999) (discussing the tension between international-law norms demanding accountability for violations of human rights and the possible necessity, on the part of transitional democracies, to sacrifice such accountability in order to safeguard fragile democratic institutions).
    • (1992)
    • Ackerman1
  • 18
    • 0346246796 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • GEO. L.J. (discussing the tension between international-law norms demanding accountability for violations of human rights and the possible necessity, on the part of transitional democracies, to sacrifice such accountability in order to safeguard fragile democratic institutions)
    • ACKERMAN, supra note 5, at 72 (1992); see also Steven R. Ratner, New Democracies, Old Atrocities: An Inquiry in International Law, 87 GEO. L.J. 707, 709 (1999) (discussing the tension between international-law norms demanding accountability for violations of human rights and the possible necessity, on the part of transitional democracies, to sacrifice such accountability in order to safeguard fragile democratic institutions).
    • (1999) New Democracies, Old Atrocities: An Inquiry in International Law , vol.87 , pp. 707
    • Ratner, S.R.1
  • 19
    • 0042057446 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 5, at 72. (emphasis added)
    • ACKERMAN, supra note 5, at 72. (emphasis added).
    • Ackerman1
  • 20
    • 0043059207 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 73
    • Id. at 73.
  • 21
    • 0043059209 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 22
    • 0041556229 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 81
    • Id. at 81
  • 23
    • 0042558321 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 24
    • 0042057449 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 98
    • Id. at 98
  • 25
    • 0041556228 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 28
    • 0042057461 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 18 (disclosing the identity of an individual's brother as an informant)
    • See id. at 18 (disclosing the identity of an individual's brother as an informant).
  • 29
    • 0041556227 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. (detailing Vera Wollenberger's discovery that her husband - whom she subsequently divorced - had been informing on her to the Stasi)
    • See id. (detailing Vera Wollenberger's discovery that her husband - whom she subsequently divorced - had been informing on her to the Stasi).
  • 30
    • 0042558322 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 31
    • 0043059210 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 200-01
    • Id. at 200-01.
  • 32
    • 0042057452 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 7, at 7
    • 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 7, at 7.
    • Ackerman1
  • 35
    • 0042558320 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 5, at 74
    • ACKERMAN, supra note 5, at 74.
    • Ackerman1
  • 36
    • 0041556225 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (emphasis added)
    • Id. (emphasis added).
  • 37
    • 0043059218 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 38
    • 0004066016 scopus 로고
    • (describing the political and economic philosophies that prevailed in the United States between 1919 and 1933)
    • See generally ARTHUR M. SCHLESINGER, JR., THE CRISIS OF THE OLD ORDER (1957) (describing the political and economic philosophies that prevailed in the United States between 1919 and 1933).
    • (1957) The Crisis of the Old Order
    • Schlesinger A.M., Jr.1
  • 39
    • 84944600281 scopus 로고
    • Civil war
    • Eric Foner & John A. Garrity eds.
    • "[A]t least 620,000 American soldiers lost their lives...." James M. McPherson, Civil War, in THE READER'S COMPANION TO AMERICAN HISTORY, 182, 185 (Eric Foner & John A. Garrity eds., 1991). The total population of the United States in 1860 was approximately 31,513,000. See HISTORICAL STATISTICS OF THE UNITED STATES: COLONIAL TIMES TO 1970, at 8. The population of males 15 and over in 1860 was approximately 9.5 million, 8.5 million of whom were white. See id. at 16-17. Thus, notes McPherson, the war "killed one-quarter of the Confederacy's white men of military age." McPherson, supra, at 185. Though the percentage was necessarily less for the much more populous Union states, there can be no doubt that "[t]he Civil War was the great trauma and tragedy of American history." Id. Ackerman is undoubtedly aware of all of these facts, but it is precisely the "trauma" and "tragedy" that tend to be absent in his account.
    • (1991) The Reader's Companion to American History , pp. 182
    • McPherson, J.M.1
  • 40
    • 29144522688 scopus 로고
    • "[A]t least 620,000 American soldiers lost their lives...." James M. McPherson, Civil War, in THE READER'S COMPANION TO AMERICAN HISTORY, 182, 185 (Eric Foner & John A. Garrity eds., 1991). The total population of the United States in 1860 was approximately 31,513,000. See HISTORICAL STATISTICS OF THE UNITED STATES: COLONIAL TIMES TO 1970, at 8. The population of males 15 and over in 1860 was approximately 9.5 million, 8.5 million of whom were white. See id. at 16-17. Thus, notes McPherson, the war "killed one-quarter of the Confederacy's white men of military age." McPherson, supra, at 185. Though the percentage was necessarily less for the much more populous Union states, there can be no doubt that "[t]he Civil War was the great trauma and tragedy of American history." Id. Ackerman is undoubtedly aware of all of these facts, but it is precisely the "trauma" and "tragedy" that tend to be absent in his account.
    • (1970) Historical Statistics of the United States: Colonial Times to , pp. 8
  • 41
    • 0013120997 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (detailing contemporary controversies involving monuments to Confederate leaders)
    • It is worth noting, though, that analogous passions can certainly be seen in regard to the memorialization of these long-dead Confederates. See generally SANFORD LEVINSON, WRITTEN IN STONE: PUBLIC MONUMENTS IN CHANGING SOCIETIES (1998) (detailing contemporary controversies involving monuments to Confederate leaders).
    • (1998) Written in Stone: Public Monuments in Changing Societies
    • Levinson, S.1
  • 42
    • 0041556238 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (reviewing §§ 352-60 of the Indian Constitution);
    • See V.N. SHUKLA, THE CONSTITUTION OF INDIA 564-73 (reviewing §§ 352-60 of the Indian Constitution); CONSTITUTIONS THAT MADE HISTORY 367 (reprinting the text of Article 48 of the German Constitution of 1919) (Albert P. Blaustein & lay A. Sigler eds., 1988).
    • The Constitution of India , pp. 564-573
    • Shukla, V.N.1
  • 43
    • 0042558336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • (reprinting the text of Article 48 of the German Constitution of 1919) (Albert P. Blaustein & lay A. Sigler eds., 1988)
    • See V.N. SHUKLA, THE CONSTITUTION OF INDIA 564-73 (reviewing §§ 352-60 of the Indian Constitution); CONSTITUTIONS THAT MADE HISTORY 367 (reprinting the text of Article 48 of the German Constitution of 1919) (Albert P. Blaustein & lay A. Sigler eds., 1988).
    • Constitutions that Made History , pp. 367
  • 44
    • 0003508294 scopus 로고
    • Perhaps the most relevant citation, in terms of intellectual stature, is the German (and Nazi) legal theorist Carl Schmitt. See, e.g., JOSEPH W. BENDERSKY, CARL SCHMITT, THEORIST FOR THE REICH (1983); PETER C. CALDWELL, POPULAR SOVEREIGNTY AND THE CRISIS OF GERMAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW: THE THEORY & PRACTICE OF WEIMAR CONSTITUTIONALISM (1997); DAVID DYZENHAUS, LEGALITY AND LEGITIMACY: CARL SCHMITT, HANS KELSEN AND HERMANN HELLER IN WEIMAR (1997); Ellen Kennedy, The Politics of Law in Weimar Germany, 77 TEX. L. REV. 1079 (1999) (reviewing CALDWELL, supra & DYZENHAUS, supra); Neil MacCormick, Jurisprudence, Democracy, and the Death of the Weimar Republic, 77 TEX. L. REV 1095 (1999) (same); G.L. Ulmen, "Integrative Jurisprudence" and Other Misdemeanors, 77 TEX. L. REV. 1107 (1999) (same); see also Izhak Englard, Nazi Criticism Against the Normativist Theory of Hans Kelsen: Its Intellectual Bias and Post-Modern Tendencies, 32 ISRAEL L. REV. 183, 194 (setting out Carl Schmitt's theory of "decisionism"). My colleague Hans Baade has stated in conversation that he views Ackerman as altogether Schmittian insofar as Ackerman ultimately assigns to existential decisions emanating from "We the People" a higher rank than the specific provisions of the Constitution as written. See, e.g., 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 15 ("In America, . . . it is the People who are the source of rights"). Ackerman would, for example, have no hesitation in accepting as constitutionally legitimate, albeit normatively dreadful, a repeal of the present First Amendment and its replacement by a new amendment stating that "Christianity is established as the state religion of the American people, and the public worship of other gods is hereby forbidden." Id. at 14. Another colleague, Willy Forbath, has told me that a German friend has indicated that the German translation of We the People is creating quite a stir, precisely because of its perceived Schmittian affinities. The heart of the controversy involves the meaning of popular sovereignty. If, after all, "the voice of the people is the voice of God," ALCUS, EPISTLES (c. 800), quoted in H.L. MENCKEN, A NEW DICTIONARY OF QUOTATIONS ON HISTORICAL PRINCIPLES FROM ANCIENT AND MODERN SOURCES 901 (1966), at least in the sense that the same obeisance must be paid to the "voice of the people" just because it is the popular voice - I take it this is the defining characteristic of all theories of popular sovereignty - then this necessarily constitutes a kind of normless "decisionism" associated with Schmitt and, perhaps, all forms of sovereignty-oriented positivism. One notes that the very sovereignty of God generated the basic conundrum of whether God can be bound by norms of justice. See, e.g., Fletcher v. Peck, 10 U.S. (6 Cranch) 87, 143 (1810) (Johnson, J., concurring) ("I do not hesitate to declare, that a state does not possess the power of revoking its own grants. But I do it, on a general principle, on the reason and nature of things; a principle which will impose laws even on the Deity . . . ."). This suggests that God lives within a "foundationalist" (and thus limiting) universe, a theologically controversial assertion. In any event, Ackerman clearly rejects foundauonalism insofar as the sovereign People are concerned. See 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 15.
    • (1983) Carl Schmitt, Theorist for the Reich
    • Bendersky, J.W.1
  • 45
    • 0003851086 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Perhaps the most relevant citation, in terms of intellectual stature, is the German (and Nazi) legal theorist Carl Schmitt. See, e.g., JOSEPH W. BENDERSKY, CARL SCHMITT, THEORIST FOR THE REICH (1983); PETER C. CALDWELL, POPULAR SOVEREIGNTY AND THE CRISIS OF GERMAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW: THE THEORY & PRACTICE OF WEIMAR CONSTITUTIONALISM (1997); DAVID DYZENHAUS, LEGALITY AND LEGITIMACY: CARL SCHMITT, HANS KELSEN AND HERMANN HELLER IN WEIMAR (1997); Ellen Kennedy, The Politics of Law in Weimar Germany, 77 TEX. L. REV. 1079 (1999) (reviewing CALDWELL, supra & DYZENHAUS, supra); Neil MacCormick, Jurisprudence, Democracy, and the Death of the Weimar Republic, 77 TEX. L. REV 1095 (1999) (same); G.L. Ulmen, "Integrative Jurisprudence" and Other Misdemeanors, 77 TEX. L. REV. 1107 (1999) (same); see also Izhak Englard, Nazi Criticism Against the Normativist Theory of Hans Kelsen: Its Intellectual Bias and Post-Modern Tendencies, 32 ISRAEL L. REV. 183, 194 (setting out Carl Schmitt's theory of "decisionism"). My colleague Hans Baade has stated in conversation that he views Ackerman as altogether Schmittian insofar as Ackerman ultimately assigns to existential decisions emanating from "We the People" a higher rank than the specific provisions of the Constitution as written. See, e.g., 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 15 ("In America, . . . it is the People who are the source of rights"). Ackerman would, for example, have no hesitation in accepting as constitutionally legitimate, albeit normatively dreadful, a repeal of the present First Amendment and its replacement by a new amendment stating that "Christianity is established as the state religion of the American people, and the public worship of other gods is hereby forbidden." Id. at 14. Another colleague, Willy Forbath, has told me that a German friend has indicated that the German translation of We the People is creating quite a stir, precisely because of its perceived Schmittian affinities. The heart of the controversy involves the meaning of popular sovereignty. If, after all, "the voice of the people is the voice of God," ALCUS, EPISTLES (c. 800), quoted in H.L. MENCKEN, A NEW DICTIONARY OF QUOTATIONS ON HISTORICAL PRINCIPLES FROM ANCIENT AND MODERN SOURCES 901 (1966), at least in the sense that the same obeisance must be paid to the "voice of the people" just because it is the popular voice - I take it this is the defining characteristic of all theories of popular sovereignty - then this necessarily constitutes a kind of normless "decisionism" associated with Schmitt and, perhaps, all forms of sovereignty-oriented positivism. One notes that the very sovereignty of God generated the basic conundrum of whether God can be bound by norms of justice. See, e.g., Fletcher v. Peck, 10 U.S. (6 Cranch) 87, 143 (1810) (Johnson, J., concurring) ("I do not hesitate to declare, that a state does not possess the power of revoking its own grants. But I do it, on a general principle, on the reason and nature of things; a principle which will impose laws even on the Deity . . . ."). This suggests that God lives within a "foundationalist" (and thus limiting) universe, a theologically controversial assertion. In any event, Ackerman clearly rejects foundauonalism insofar as the sovereign People are concerned. See 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 15.
    • (1997) Popular Sovereignty and the Crisis of German Constitutional Law: The Theory & Practice of Weimar Constitutionalism
    • Caldwell, P.C.1
  • 46
    • 0007434250 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Perhaps the most relevant citation, in terms of intellectual stature, is the German (and Nazi) legal theorist Carl Schmitt. See, e.g., JOSEPH W. BENDERSKY, CARL SCHMITT, THEORIST FOR THE REICH (1983); PETER C. CALDWELL, POPULAR SOVEREIGNTY AND THE CRISIS OF GERMAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW: THE THEORY & PRACTICE OF WEIMAR CONSTITUTIONALISM (1997); DAVID DYZENHAUS, LEGALITY AND LEGITIMACY: CARL SCHMITT, HANS KELSEN AND HERMANN HELLER IN WEIMAR (1997); Ellen Kennedy, The Politics of Law in Weimar Germany, 77 TEX. L. REV. 1079 (1999) (reviewing CALDWELL, supra & DYZENHAUS, supra); Neil MacCormick, Jurisprudence, Democracy, and the Death of the Weimar Republic, 77 TEX. L. REV 1095 (1999) (same); G.L. Ulmen, "Integrative Jurisprudence" and Other Misdemeanors, 77 TEX. L. REV. 1107 (1999) (same); see also Izhak Englard, Nazi Criticism Against the Normativist Theory of Hans Kelsen: Its Intellectual Bias and Post-Modern Tendencies, 32 ISRAEL L. REV. 183, 194 (setting out Carl Schmitt's theory of "decisionism"). My colleague Hans Baade has stated in conversation that he views Ackerman as altogether Schmittian insofar as Ackerman ultimately assigns to existential decisions emanating from "We the People" a higher rank than the specific provisions of the Constitution as written. See, e.g., 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 15 ("In America, . . . it is the People who are the source of rights"). Ackerman would, for example, have no hesitation in accepting as constitutionally legitimate, albeit normatively dreadful, a repeal of the present First Amendment and its replacement by a new amendment stating that "Christianity is established as the state religion of the American people, and the public worship of other gods is hereby forbidden." Id. at 14. Another colleague, Willy Forbath, has told me that a German friend has indicated that the German translation of We the People is creating quite a stir, precisely because of its perceived Schmittian affinities. The heart of the controversy involves the meaning of popular sovereignty. If, after all, "the voice of the people is the voice of God," ALCUS, EPISTLES (c. 800), quoted in H.L. MENCKEN, A NEW DICTIONARY OF QUOTATIONS ON HISTORICAL PRINCIPLES FROM ANCIENT AND MODERN SOURCES 901 (1966), at least in the sense that the same obeisance must be paid to the "voice of the people" just because it is the popular voice - I take it this is the defining characteristic of all theories of popular sovereignty - then this necessarily constitutes a kind of normless "decisionism" associated with Schmitt and, perhaps, all forms of sovereignty-oriented positivism. One notes that the very sovereignty of God generated the basic conundrum of whether God can be bound by norms of justice. See, e.g., Fletcher v. Peck, 10 U.S. (6 Cranch) 87, 143 (1810) (Johnson, J., concurring) ("I do not hesitate to declare, that a state does not possess the power of revoking its own grants. But I do it, on a general principle, on the reason and nature of things; a principle which will impose laws even on the Deity . . . ."). This suggests that God lives within a "foundationalist" (and thus limiting) universe, a theologically controversial assertion. In any event, Ackerman clearly rejects foundauonalism insofar as the sovereign People are concerned. See 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 15.
    • (1997) Legality and Legitimacy: Carl Schmitt, Hans Kelsen and Hermann Heller in Weimar
    • Dyzenhaus, D.1
  • 47
    • 22644452478 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The politics of law in Weimar Germany
    • (reviewing CALDWELL, supra & DYZENHAUS, supra);
    • Perhaps the most relevant citation, in terms of intellectual stature, is the German (and Nazi) legal theorist Carl Schmitt. See, e.g., JOSEPH W. BENDERSKY, CARL SCHMITT, THEORIST FOR THE REICH (1983); PETER C. CALDWELL, POPULAR SOVEREIGNTY AND THE CRISIS OF GERMAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW: THE THEORY & PRACTICE OF WEIMAR CONSTITUTIONALISM (1997); DAVID DYZENHAUS, LEGALITY AND LEGITIMACY: CARL SCHMITT, HANS KELSEN AND HERMANN HELLER IN WEIMAR (1997); Ellen Kennedy, The Politics of Law in Weimar Germany, 77 TEX. L. REV. 1079 (1999) (reviewing CALDWELL, supra & DYZENHAUS, supra); Neil MacCormick, Jurisprudence, Democracy, and the Death of the Weimar Republic, 77 TEX. L. REV 1095 (1999) (same); G.L. Ulmen, "Integrative Jurisprudence" and Other Misdemeanors, 77 TEX. L. REV. 1107 (1999) (same); see also Izhak Englard, Nazi Criticism Against the Normativist Theory of Hans Kelsen: Its Intellectual Bias and Post-Modern Tendencies, 32 ISRAEL L. REV. 183, 194 (setting out Carl Schmitt's theory of "decisionism"). My colleague Hans Baade has stated in conversation that he views Ackerman as altogether Schmittian insofar as Ackerman ultimately assigns to existential decisions emanating from "We the People" a higher rank than the specific provisions of the Constitution as written. See, e.g., 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 15 ("In America, . . . it is the People who are the source of rights"). Ackerman would, for example, have no hesitation in accepting as constitutionally legitimate, albeit normatively dreadful, a repeal of the present First Amendment and its replacement by a new amendment stating that "Christianity is established as the state religion of the American people, and the public worship of other gods is hereby forbidden." Id. at 14. Another colleague, Willy Forbath, has told me that a German friend has indicated that the German translation of We the People is creating quite a stir, precisely because of its perceived Schmittian affinities. The heart of the controversy involves the meaning of popular sovereignty. If, after all, "the voice of the people is the voice of God," ALCUS, EPISTLES (c. 800), quoted in H.L. MENCKEN, A NEW DICTIONARY OF QUOTATIONS ON HISTORICAL PRINCIPLES FROM ANCIENT AND MODERN SOURCES 901 (1966), at least in the sense that the same obeisance must be paid to the "voice of the people" just because it is the popular voice - I take it this is the defining characteristic of all theories of popular sovereignty - then this necessarily constitutes a kind of normless "decisionism" associated with Schmitt and, perhaps, all forms of sovereignty-oriented positivism. One notes that the very sovereignty of God generated the basic conundrum of whether God can be bound by norms of justice. See, e.g., Fletcher v. Peck, 10 U.S. (6 Cranch) 87, 143 (1810) (Johnson, J., concurring) ("I do not hesitate to declare, that a state does not possess the power of revoking its own grants. But I do it, on a general principle, on the reason and nature of things; a principle which will impose laws even on the Deity . . . ."). This suggests that God lives within a "foundationalist" (and thus limiting) universe, a theologically controversial assertion. In any event, Ackerman clearly rejects foundauonalism insofar as the sovereign People are concerned. See 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 15.
    • (1999) Tex. L. Rev. , vol.77 , pp. 1079
    • Kennedy, E.1
  • 48
    • 22644448555 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Jurisprudence, democracy, and the death of the Weimar Republic
    • (same)
    • Perhaps the most relevant citation, in terms of intellectual stature, is the German (and Nazi) legal theorist Carl Schmitt. See, e.g., JOSEPH W. BENDERSKY, CARL SCHMITT, THEORIST FOR THE REICH (1983); PETER C. CALDWELL, POPULAR SOVEREIGNTY AND THE CRISIS OF GERMAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW: THE THEORY & PRACTICE OF WEIMAR CONSTITUTIONALISM (1997); DAVID DYZENHAUS, LEGALITY AND LEGITIMACY: CARL SCHMITT, HANS KELSEN AND HERMANN HELLER IN WEIMAR (1997); Ellen Kennedy, The Politics of Law in Weimar Germany, 77 TEX. L. REV. 1079 (1999) (reviewing CALDWELL, supra & DYZENHAUS, supra); Neil MacCormick, Jurisprudence, Democracy, and the Death of the Weimar Republic, 77 TEX. L. REV 1095 (1999) (same); G.L. Ulmen, "Integrative Jurisprudence" and Other Misdemeanors, 77 TEX. L. REV. 1107 (1999) (same); see also Izhak Englard, Nazi Criticism Against the Normativist Theory of Hans Kelsen: Its Intellectual Bias and Post-Modern Tendencies, 32 ISRAEL L. REV. 183, 194 (setting out Carl Schmitt's theory of "decisionism"). My colleague Hans Baade has stated in conversation that he views Ackerman as altogether Schmittian insofar as Ackerman ultimately assigns to existential decisions emanating from "We the People" a higher rank than the specific provisions of the Constitution as written. See, e.g., 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 15 ("In America, . . . it is the People who are the source of rights"). Ackerman would, for example, have no hesitation in accepting as constitutionally legitimate, albeit normatively dreadful, a repeal of the present First Amendment and its replacement by a new amendment stating that "Christianity is established as the state religion of the American people, and the public worship of other gods is hereby forbidden." Id. at 14. Another colleague, Willy Forbath, has told me that a German friend has indicated that the German translation of We the People is creating quite a stir, precisely because of its perceived Schmittian affinities. The heart of the controversy involves the meaning of popular sovereignty. If, after all, "the voice of the people is the voice of God," ALCUS, EPISTLES (c. 800), quoted in H.L. MENCKEN, A NEW DICTIONARY OF QUOTATIONS ON HISTORICAL PRINCIPLES FROM ANCIENT AND MODERN SOURCES 901 (1966), at least in the sense that the same obeisance must be paid to the "voice of the people" just because it is the popular voice - I take it this is the defining characteristic of all theories of popular sovereignty - then this necessarily constitutes a kind of normless "decisionism" associated with Schmitt and, perhaps, all forms of sovereignty-oriented positivism. One notes that the very sovereignty of God generated the basic conundrum of whether God can be bound by norms of justice. See, e.g., Fletcher v. Peck, 10 U.S. (6 Cranch) 87, 143 (1810) (Johnson, J., concurring) ("I do not hesitate to declare, that a state does not possess the power of revoking its own grants. But I do it, on a general principle, on the reason and nature of things; a principle which will impose laws even on the Deity . . . ."). This suggests that God lives within a "foundationalist" (and thus limiting) universe, a theologically controversial assertion. In any event, Ackerman clearly rejects foundauonalism insofar as the sovereign People are concerned. See 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 15.
    • (1999) Tex. L. Rev , vol.77 , pp. 1095
    • MacCormick, N.1
  • 49
    • 22644451336 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • "Integrative jurisprudence" and other misdemeanors
    • (same)
    • Perhaps the most relevant citation, in terms of intellectual stature, is the German (and Nazi) legal theorist Carl Schmitt. See, e.g., JOSEPH W. BENDERSKY, CARL SCHMITT, THEORIST FOR THE REICH (1983); PETER C. CALDWELL, POPULAR SOVEREIGNTY AND THE CRISIS OF GERMAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW: THE THEORY & PRACTICE OF WEIMAR CONSTITUTIONALISM (1997); DAVID DYZENHAUS, LEGALITY AND LEGITIMACY: CARL SCHMITT, HANS KELSEN AND HERMANN HELLER IN WEIMAR (1997); Ellen Kennedy, The Politics of Law in Weimar Germany, 77 TEX. L. REV. 1079 (1999) (reviewing CALDWELL, supra & DYZENHAUS, supra); Neil MacCormick, Jurisprudence, Democracy, and the Death of the Weimar Republic, 77 TEX. L. REV 1095 (1999) (same); G.L. Ulmen, "Integrative Jurisprudence" and Other Misdemeanors, 77 TEX. L. REV. 1107 (1999) (same); see also Izhak Englard, Nazi Criticism Against the Normativist Theory of Hans Kelsen: Its Intellectual Bias and Post-Modern Tendencies, 32 ISRAEL L. REV. 183, 194 (setting out Carl Schmitt's theory of "decisionism"). My colleague Hans Baade has stated in conversation that he views Ackerman as altogether Schmittian insofar as Ackerman ultimately assigns to existential decisions emanating from "We the People" a higher rank than the specific provisions of the Constitution as written. See, e.g., 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 15 ("In America, . . . it is the People who are the source of rights"). Ackerman would, for example, have no hesitation in accepting as constitutionally legitimate, albeit normatively dreadful, a repeal of the present First Amendment and its replacement by a new amendment stating that "Christianity is established as the state religion of the American people, and the public worship of other gods is hereby forbidden." Id. at 14. Another colleague, Willy Forbath, has told me that a German friend has indicated that the German translation of We the People is creating quite a stir, precisely because of its perceived Schmittian affinities. The heart of the controversy involves the meaning of popular sovereignty. If, after all, "the voice of the people is the voice of God," ALCUS, EPISTLES (c. 800), quoted in H.L. MENCKEN, A NEW DICTIONARY OF QUOTATIONS ON HISTORICAL PRINCIPLES FROM ANCIENT AND MODERN SOURCES 901 (1966), at least in the sense that the same obeisance must be paid to the "voice of the people" just because it is the popular voice - I take it this is the defining characteristic of all theories of popular sovereignty - then this necessarily constitutes a kind of normless "decisionism" associated with Schmitt and, perhaps, all forms of sovereignty-oriented positivism. One notes that the very sovereignty of God generated the basic conundrum of whether God can be bound by norms of justice. See, e.g., Fletcher v. Peck, 10 U.S. (6 Cranch) 87, 143 (1810) (Johnson, J., concurring) ("I do not hesitate to declare, that a state does not possess the power of revoking its own grants. But I do it, on a general principle, on the reason and nature of things; a principle which will impose laws even on the Deity . . . ."). This suggests that God lives within a "foundationalist" (and thus limiting) universe, a theologically controversial assertion. In any event, Ackerman clearly rejects foundauonalism insofar as the sovereign People are concerned. See 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 15.
    • (1999) Tex. L. Rev. , vol.77 , pp. 1107
    • Ulmen, G.L.1
  • 50
    • 85016311672 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nazi criticism against the normativist theory of Hans Kelsen: Its intellectual bias and post-modern tendencies
    • (setting out Carl Schmitt's theory of "decisionism")
    • Perhaps the most relevant citation, in terms of intellectual stature, is the German (and Nazi) legal theorist Carl Schmitt. See, e.g., JOSEPH W. BENDERSKY, CARL SCHMITT, THEORIST FOR THE REICH (1983); PETER C. CALDWELL, POPULAR SOVEREIGNTY AND THE CRISIS OF GERMAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW: THE THEORY & PRACTICE OF WEIMAR CONSTITUTIONALISM (1997); DAVID DYZENHAUS, LEGALITY AND LEGITIMACY: CARL SCHMITT, HANS KELSEN AND HERMANN HELLER IN WEIMAR (1997); Ellen Kennedy, The Politics of Law in Weimar Germany, 77 TEX. L. REV. 1079 (1999) (reviewing CALDWELL, supra & DYZENHAUS, supra); Neil MacCormick, Jurisprudence, Democracy, and the Death of the Weimar Republic, 77 TEX. L. REV 1095 (1999) (same); G.L. Ulmen, "Integrative Jurisprudence" and Other Misdemeanors, 77 TEX. L. REV. 1107 (1999) (same); see also Izhak Englard, Nazi Criticism Against the Normativist Theory of Hans Kelsen: Its Intellectual Bias and Post-Modern Tendencies, 32 ISRAEL L. REV. 183, 194 (setting out Carl Schmitt's theory of "decisionism"). My colleague Hans Baade has stated in conversation that he views Ackerman as altogether Schmittian insofar as Ackerman ultimately assigns to existential decisions emanating from "We the People" a higher rank than the specific provisions of the Constitution as written. See, e.g., 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 15 ("In America, . . . it is the People who are the source of rights"). Ackerman would, for example, have no hesitation in accepting as constitutionally legitimate, albeit normatively dreadful, a repeal of the present First Amendment and its replacement by a new amendment stating that "Christianity is established as the state religion of the American people, and the public worship of other gods is hereby forbidden." Id. at 14. Another colleague, Willy Forbath, has told me that a German friend has indicated that the German translation of We the People is creating quite a stir, precisely because of its perceived Schmittian affinities. The heart of the controversy involves the meaning of popular sovereignty. If, after all, "the voice of the people is the voice of God," ALCUS, EPISTLES (c. 800), quoted in H.L. MENCKEN, A NEW DICTIONARY OF QUOTATIONS ON HISTORICAL PRINCIPLES FROM ANCIENT AND MODERN SOURCES 901 (1966), at least in the sense that the same obeisance must be paid to the "voice of the people" just because it is the popular voice - I take it this is the defining characteristic of all theories of popular sovereignty - then this necessarily constitutes a kind of normless "decisionism" associated with Schmitt and, perhaps, all forms of sovereignty-oriented positivism. One notes that the very sovereignty of God generated the basic conundrum of whether God can be bound by norms of justice. See, e.g., Fletcher v. Peck, 10 U.S. (6 Cranch) 87, 143 (1810) (Johnson, J., concurring) ("I do not hesitate to declare, that a state does not possess the power of revoking its own grants. But I do it, on a general principle, on the reason and nature of things; a principle which will impose laws even on the Deity . . . ."). This suggests that God lives within a "foundationalist" (and thus limiting) universe, a theologically controversial assertion. In any event, Ackerman clearly rejects foundauonalism insofar as the sovereign People are concerned. See 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 15.
    • Israel L. Rev. , vol.32 , pp. 183
    • Englard, I.1
  • 51
    • 0042558317 scopus 로고
    • note
    • Perhaps the most relevant citation, in terms of intellectual stature, is the German (and Nazi) legal theorist Carl Schmitt. See, e.g., JOSEPH W. BENDERSKY, CARL SCHMITT, THEORIST FOR THE REICH (1983); PETER C. CALDWELL, POPULAR SOVEREIGNTY AND THE CRISIS OF GERMAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW: THE THEORY & PRACTICE OF WEIMAR CONSTITUTIONALISM (1997); DAVID DYZENHAUS, LEGALITY AND LEGITIMACY: CARL SCHMITT, HANS KELSEN AND HERMANN HELLER IN WEIMAR (1997); Ellen Kennedy, The Politics of Law in Weimar Germany, 77 TEX. L. REV. 1079 (1999) (reviewing CALDWELL, supra & DYZENHAUS, supra); Neil MacCormick, Jurisprudence, Democracy, and the Death of the Weimar Republic, 77 TEX. L. REV 1095 (1999) (same); G.L. Ulmen, "Integrative Jurisprudence" and Other Misdemeanors, 77 TEX. L. REV. 1107 (1999) (same); see also Izhak Englard, Nazi Criticism Against the Normativist Theory of Hans Kelsen: Its Intellectual Bias and Post-Modern Tendencies, 32 ISRAEL L. REV. 183, 194 (setting out Carl Schmitt's theory of "decisionism"). My colleague Hans Baade has stated in conversation that he views Ackerman as altogether Schmittian insofar as Ackerman ultimately assigns to existential decisions emanating from "We the People" a higher rank than the specific provisions of the Constitution as written. See, e.g., 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 15 ("In America, . . . it is the People who are the source of rights"). Ackerman would, for example, have no hesitation in accepting as constitutionally legitimate, albeit normatively dreadful, a repeal of the present First Amendment and its replacement by a new amendment stating that "Christianity is established as the state religion of the American people, and the public worship of other gods is hereby forbidden." Id. at 14. Another colleague, Willy Forbath, has told me that a German friend has indicated that the German translation of We the People is creating quite a stir, precisely because of its perceived Schmittian affinities. The heart of the controversy involves the meaning of popular sovereignty. If, after all, "the voice of the people is the voice of God," ALCUS, EPISTLES (c. 800), quoted in H.L. MENCKEN, A NEW DICTIONARY OF QUOTATIONS ON HISTORICAL PRINCIPLES FROM ANCIENT AND MODERN SOURCES 901 (1966), at least in the sense that the same obeisance must be paid to the "voice of the people" just because it is the popular voice - I take it this is the defining characteristic of all theories of popular sovereignty - then this necessarily constitutes a kind of normless "decisionism" associated with Schmitt and, perhaps, all forms of sovereignty-oriented positivism. One notes that the very sovereignty of God generated the basic conundrum of whether God can be bound by norms of justice. See, e.g., Fletcher v. Peck, 10 U.S. (6 Cranch) 87, 143 (1810) (Johnson, J., concurring) ("I do not hesitate to declare, that a state does not possess the power of revoking its own grants. But I do it, on a general principle, on the reason and nature of things; a principle which will impose laws even on the Deity . . . ."). This suggests that God lives within a "foundationalist" (and thus limiting) universe, a theologically controversial assertion. In any event, Ackerman clearly rejects foundauonalism insofar as the sovereign People are concerned. See 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 15.
    • (1966) A New Dictionary of Quotations on Historical Principles from Ancient and Modern Sources , pp. 901
    • Mencken, H.L.1
  • 52
    • 0042057454 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 4, at 115
    • 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 115.
    • Ackerman1
  • 53
    • 0043059217 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 1 id at 116. Professor Powe, who is generally sympathetic to Ackerman's specific narrative of Reconstruction events, nonetheless finds a War Powers justification far more persuasive than Ackerman's. See Powe, supra note 7, at 562-64
    • 1 id at 116. Professor Powe, who is generally sympathetic to Ackerman's specific narrative of Reconstruction events, nonetheless finds a War Powers justification far more persuasive than Ackerman's. See Powe, supra note 7, at 562-64.
  • 54
    • 0011599744 scopus 로고
    • (arguing that "playing by the rules" entails that one accept the cost of "suboptimal outcomes" that could, perhaps, be avoided by ignoring the rules in favor of seeking the best result in any given case)
    • FREDERICK SCHAUER, PLAYING BY THE RULES: A PHILOSOPHICAL EXAMINATION OF RULE-BASED DECISION-MAKING IN LAW AND LIFE 100-02 (1991) (arguing that "playing by the rules" entails that one accept the cost of "suboptimal outcomes" that could, perhaps, be avoided by ignoring the rules in favor of seeking the best result in any given case).
    • (1991) Playing by the Rules: A Philosophical Examination of Rule-based Decision-making in Law and Life , pp. 100-102
    • Schauer, F.1
  • 55
    • 0042057440 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Truth & Reconciliation Comm'n v. Du Preez & Another, 1996 (3) SALR 997, 1009-10 (Cape Provincial Div.) (rejecting the claim of a party accused of human rights violations that the party had a right to be notified of the general elements of the accusation for which the party was called to answer), overruled by 1997 (3) SALR 204 (A). The two cases come to conflicting conclusions concerning the meaning of "fairness" in regard to persons identified by ostensible victims as the perpetrators of the injustices against them. In particular, the Appellate Division held that alleged perpetrators are entitled to prior notice "of the substance of the allegations against him or her, with sufficient detail to know what the case is all about," Du Preez, 1997 (3) SALR at 234, though the court acknowledged the ability of the Commission, when necessary, to withhold disclosing the identity of particular witnesses. See id. at 235, 236
    • See Truth & Reconciliation Comm'n v. Du Preez & Another, 1996 (3) SALR 997, 1009-10 (Cape Provincial Div.) (rejecting the claim of a party accused of human rights violations that the party had a right to be notified of the general elements of the accusation for which the party was called to answer), overruled by 1997 (3) SALR 204 (A). The two cases come to conflicting conclusions concerning the meaning of "fairness" in regard to persons identified by ostensible victims as the perpetrators of the injustices against them. In particular, the Appellate Division held that alleged perpetrators are entitled to prior notice "of the substance of the allegations against him or her, with sufficient detail to know what the case is all about," Du Preez, 1997 (3) SALR at 234, though the court acknowledged the ability of the Commission, when necessary, to withhold disclosing the identity of particular witnesses. See id. at 235, 236.
  • 56
    • 84934014784 scopus 로고
    • The storrs lectures: Discovering the constitution
    • See, e.g., Bruce Ackerman, The Storrs Lectures: Discovering the Constitution, 93 YALE L.J. 1013 (1984); see also 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 458-80 (1991) (discussing the Founding, Reconstruction, and the New Deal as key constitutional transitions).
    • (1984) Yale L.J. , vol.93 , pp. 1013
    • Ackerman, B.1
  • 57
    • 0043059213 scopus 로고
    • supra note 4, at 458-80 (discussing the Founding, Reconstruction, and the New Deal as key constitutional transitions)
    • See, e.g., Bruce Ackerman, The Storrs Lectures: Discovering the Constitution, 93 YALE L.J. 1013 (1984); see also 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 458-80 (1991) (discussing the Founding, Reconstruction, and the New Deal as key constitutional transitions).
    • (1991)
    • Ackerman1
  • 59
    • 0042059549 scopus 로고
    • The forgotten constitutional moment
    • The notion of "constitutional moments" is well-articulated in Michael McConnell, The Forgotten Constitutional Moment, 11 CONST. COMMENTARY 115, 121-22 (1994).
    • (1994) Const. Commentary , vol.11 , pp. 115
    • McConnell, M.1
  • 60
    • 0042558333 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 122-40 (1994). Ackerman replies to McConnell in 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 7, at 471-74 n.126. Professor Powe offers another example of a most unfortunate constitutional moment that occurred in the 1950s: McCarthyism. See Powe, supra note 7, at 566 n.29
    • See id. at 122-40 (1994). Ackerman replies to McConnell in 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 7, at 471-74 n.126. Professor Powe offers another example of a most unfortunate constitutional moment that occurred in the 1950s: McCarthyism. See Powe, supra note 7, at 566 n.29.
  • 62
    • 0042558323 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • PUERTO RICO, AMERICAN EXPANSIONISM, AND THE CONSTITUTION Christine Duffy Burnett & Burke Marshall eds., forthcoming
    • See, e.g., Downes v. Bidwell, 182 U.S. 244 (1901); see also OWEN M. FISS, 8 THE OLIVER WENDELL HOLMES DEVISE HISTORY OF THE SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES: TROUBLED BEGINNINGS OF THE MODERN STATE, 1888-1910, at 225-56 (1993); "FOREIGN IN A DOMESTIC SENSE": PUERTO RICO, AMERICAN EXPANSIONISM, AND THE CONSTITUTION (Christine Duffy Burnett & Burke Marshall eds., forthcoming 2000).
    • (2000) Foreign in a Domestic Sense
  • 63
    • 0041558124 scopus 로고
    • Is NAFTA constitutional?
    • (discussing the history of the Treaty Clause and its implications for the constitutionality of NAFTA)
    • See generally Bruce Ackerman & David Golove, Is NAFTA Constitutional?, 108 HARV. L. REV. 799 (1995) (discussing the history of the Treaty Clause and its implications for the constitutionality of NAFTA).
    • (1995) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.108 , pp. 799
    • Ackerman, B.1    Golove, D.2
  • 64
    • 0041556230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • On Ackerman's identification of the distinctive "constitutional regime" as "the basic unit of analysis," see 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 59. Thus, Ackerman titles a chapter of his volume, One Constitution, Three Regimes. Id. at 58. Ackerman also refers to these separate "regimes" as "republics." Id. at 62-63 (discussing the "early," "middle," and "modern republics"). I owe this point to Jim Fleming, who, commenting on an earlier draft, argued that Ackerman's emphasis on distinctive "regimes" means that he has not in fact adopted the view that I ascribe to him in the text as to the presence of additional constitutional moments beyond the three that form the topic of Transformations. Perhaps the answer is to distinguish between "strong" and "weaker" constitutional moments that differ in the degree to which they transform the regime and nonetheless recognize that all of them involve significant constitutional changes that cannot be explained by the standard-model of Article V (or, of course, by the Supreme Court's simply discovering what was, though unrecognized, already in the Constitution to be discovered by the skilled interpreter).
  • 66
    • 0042558331 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Amicus Brief for the United States at 6, Brown v. Board of Educ., 347 U.S. 483 (1954) [(docket No. ?)], reprinted in 49 LANDMARK BRIEFS AND ARGUMENTS OF THE SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES 113, 121 (Philip B. Kurland & Gerhard Casper eds., 1975)
    • Amicus Brief for the United States at 6, Brown v. Board of Educ., 347 U.S. 483 (1954) [(docket No. ?)], reprinted in 49 LANDMARK BRIEFS AND ARGUMENTS OF THE SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES 113, 121 (Philip B. Kurland & Gerhard Casper eds., 1975).
  • 67
    • 0043059215 scopus 로고
    • (describing the creation, objectives, and activities of the Commission)
    • See generally FOSTER RHEA DULLES, THE CIVIL RIGHTS COMMISSION: 1957-1965 (1968) (describing the creation, objectives, and activities of the Commission).
    • (1968) The Civil Rights Commission: 1957-1965
    • Dulles, F.R.1
  • 68
    • 0042558319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nor was the Supreme Court necessarily helpful. See. e.g., Screws v. United States, 325 U.S. 91, 98 (1945) (requiring proof of "knowing" and "willful" deprivation of constitutionally Protected civil rights in order to sustain a conviction of a Southern sheriff who had killed an African-American prisoner in his custody)
    • Nor was the Supreme Court necessarily helpful. See. e.g., Screws v. United States, 325 U.S. 91, 98 (1945) (requiring proof of "knowing" and "willful" deprivation of constitutionally Protected civil rights in order to sustain a conviction of a Southern sheriff who had killed an African-American prisoner in his custody).
  • 69
    • 0003472531 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • They might have been able to argue even more eloquently if they had had the opportunity to read the work of Akhil Amar concerning the essential role of juries as a procedural safeguard against what local majorities perceive as governmental overreaching. See AKHIL REED AMAR, THE BILL OF RIGHTS: CREATION AND RECONSTRUCTION 84-88 (1998).
    • (1998) The Bill of Rights: Creation and Reconstruction , pp. 84-88
    • Amar, A.R.1
  • 70
    • 0041556231 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Hannah v. Larche, 363 U.S. 420, 425 (1960) (noting the decision of the Commission to hold hearings in Shreveport beginning on July 13, 1959)
    • See Hannah v. Larche, 363 U.S. 420, 425 (1960) (noting the decision of the Commission to hold hearings in Shreveport beginning on July 13, 1959).
  • 71
    • 0042057456 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 428
    • Id. at 428.
  • 72
    • 0041556232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 422
    • See id. at 422.
  • 73
    • 0043059214 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 440
    • Id. at 440.
  • 74
    • 0042558326 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 442
    • Id. at 442.
  • 75
    • 0042558327 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 453
    • See id. at 453.
  • 76
    • 0042558329 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 442
    • Id. at 442.
  • 77
    • 0041556233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 443
    • Id. at 443.
  • 78
    • 0042057460 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 79
    • 0042558328 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 454-85
    • id. at 454-85.
  • 80
    • 0042057457 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The earliest example given in the Court's appendix is an 1800 investigation, by the Senate Committee of Privileges, of charges that William Duane had published articles in his newspaper that defamed the Senate. See id. at 478. Far more importantly, the Joint Committee on the Conduct of the Civil War was established in 1861, which, the Court tells us, "frequently centered on the allegedly derelict conduct of specific individuals." Id. at 481. Other pre-New Deal investigations include the House Committee to Investigate the Electric Boat Company of New Jersey (1908), and the House Committee to Investigate Violations of the Antitrust Laws by the American Sugar Refining Company (1911). See id. at 482.
  • 82
    • 0043059212 scopus 로고
    • House un-American activities committee
    • Eric Foner & John A. Garraty eds.
    • See House Un-American Activities Committee, in THE READER'S COMPANION TO AMERICAN HISTORY 519 (Eric Foner & John A. Garraty eds., 1991).
    • (1991) The Reader's Companion to American History , pp. 519
  • 83
    • 0042558335 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id.
    • See id.
  • 84
    • 0042558324 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Many of the particular individuals bringing suit would probably not be punished by the "court of public opinion" inasmuch as they were the front soldiers of the attempt to maintain the traditional racial order. Perhaps this helps to explain why Chief Justice Warren, perhaps especially sensitive to the Southern "massive resistance" to any attempts to implement Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.S. 483 (1954), found the claims of harm merely "conjectural."
    • Many of the particular individuals bringing suit would probably not be punished by the "court of public opinion" inasmuch as they were the front soldiers of the attempt to maintain the traditional racial order. Perhaps this helps to explain why Chief Justice Warren, perhaps especially sensitive to the Southern "massive resistance" to any attempts to implement Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.S. 483 (1954), found the claims of harm merely "conjectural."
  • 85
    • 0041556235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hannah v. Larche, 363 U.S. 420, 497 (1960)
    • Hannah v. Larche, 363 U.S. 420, 497 (1960).
  • 86
    • 0042057455 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ackerman acknowledges as a democratic reality that, even in the United States, liberal norms of due process have not been accorded a status any more transcendent than that of institutional norms (like the allocation of power between the President and Congress). See 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 320-21 (suggesting but questioning the ultimate efficacy of entrenching fundamental liberties against future transformations through the ratification of a new, unamendable Bill of Rights). He may, however, carry in his mind some idealized, immutable notion of due process by which he judges the actuality of any given legal order
    • Ackerman acknowledges as a democratic reality that, even in the United States, liberal norms of due process have not been accorded a status any more transcendent than that of institutional norms (like the allocation of power between the President and Congress). See 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 4, at 320-21 (suggesting but questioning the ultimate efficacy of entrenching fundamental liberties against future transformations through the ratification of a new, unamendable Bill of Rights). He may, however, carry in his mind some idealized, immutable notion of due process by which he judges the actuality of any given legal order.
  • 87
    • 0039668702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • It is obvious that these issues are no longer as current as they were when I initially wrote this Article in late 1998. That said, it is still helpful, I believe, to note the particular stance taken by Ackerman and its possible relevance to his overall theory. I should also note that Ackerman's most important intervention was his argument, initially presented to the House Judiciary Committee and then published as a book, BRUCE ACKERMAN, THE CASE AGAINST LAMEDUCK IMPEACHMENT (1999), that any impeachment resolution voted upon by the lameduck House of Representatives expired at the end of the legislative session and thus could not be presented to the Senate without a new vote by the successor House. I think there is substantial merit in Ackerman's argument and very much wish that it had been taken far more seriously than it was. Ironically, the very fact that it was basically brushed aside, presented neither by the President's own lawyers nor by any member of the Senate, could be interpreted as a decision by "We the People" to adopt and make part of our settled constitutional doctrine an anti-Ackermanian understanding of the Constitution.
    • (1999) The Case Against Lameduck Impeachment
    • Ackerman, B.1
  • 88
    • 0042057448 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Would the framers impeach President Clinton?
    • Fall
    • See, e.g., Scott Gerber, Would the Framers Impeach President Clinton?, in LAW AND COURTS: NEWSLETTER OF THE LAW AND COURTS SECTION OF THE AMERICAN POLITICAL SCIENCE ASSOCIATION 4-6 (Fall 1998). My own view is that the answer to this question ought to be of no interest to anyone contemplating the merits of impeaching President Clinton. See Sanford Levinson, Clinton and Impeachment: Some Reflections, in LAW AND COURTS: NEWSLETTER OF THE LAW AND COURTS SECTION OF THE AMERICAN POLITICAL SCIENCE ASSOCIATION, Fall 1998, at 7.
    • (1998) Law and Courts: Newsletter of the Law and Courts Section of the American Political Science Association , pp. 4-6
    • Gerber, S.1
  • 89
    • 0042057442 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Clinton and impeachment: Some reflections
    • Fall
    • See, e.g., Scott Gerber, Would the Framers Impeach President Clinton?, in LAW AND COURTS: NEWSLETTER OF THE LAW AND COURTS SECTION OF THE AMERICAN POLITICAL SCIENCE ASSOCIATION 4-6 (Fall 1998). My own view is that the answer to this question ought to be of no interest to anyone contemplating the merits of impeaching President Clinton. See Sanford Levinson, Clinton and Impeachment: Some Reflections, in LAW AND COURTS: NEWSLETTER OF THE LAW AND COURTS SECTION OF THE AMERICAN POLITICAL SCIENCE ASSOCIATION, Fall 1998, at 7.
    • (1998) Law and Courts: Newsletter of the Law and Courts Section of the American Political Science Association , pp. 7
    • Levinson, S.1
  • 90
    • 4243456524 scopus 로고
    • What Ken starr neglected to tell us
    • Editorial, Sept. 14
    • Bruce Ackerman, Editorial, What Ken Starr Neglected To Tell Us, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 14, 1988, at A33.
    • (1988) N.Y. Times
    • Ackerman, B.1
  • 91
    • 0004156984 scopus 로고
    • (providing a critical history of the development of the modern Presidency)
    • See, e.g., JEFFREY TULIS, THE RHETORICAL PRESIDENCY (1987) (providing a critical history of the development of the modern Presidency).
    • (1987) The Rhetorical Presidency
    • Tulis, J.1
  • 93
    • 0042558332 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 74, at A33
    • Ackerman, supra note 74, at A33.
    • Ackerman1
  • 94
    • 0042057458 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • Id.
  • 95
    • 84855587044 scopus 로고
    • Is the presidential succession law constitutional?
    • See Akhil Reed Amar & Vikram David Amar, Is the Presidential Succession Law Constitutional?, 48 STAN. L. REV. 113 (1995).
    • (1995) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.48 , pp. 113
    • Amar, A.R.1    Amar, V.D.2
  • 96
    • 0041558043 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Living in a constitutional moment?: Lopez and constitutional theory
    • (discussing the difficulty of ascertaining a proper response when one realizes that one is living in a possible constitutional moment)
    • See Mark Tushnet, Living in a Constitutional Moment?: Lopez and Constitutional Theory, 46 CASE W. RES. L. REV. 845 (1996) (discussing the difficulty of ascertaining a proper response when one realizes that one is living in a possible constitutional moment).
    • (1996) Case W. Res. L. Rev. , vol.46 , pp. 845
    • Tushnet, M.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.