메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 108, Issue 8, 1999, Pages 2115-2161

Constitutional theory transformed

(1)  Griffin, Stephen M a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0041541753     PISSN: 00440094     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.2307/797384     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (27)

References (352)
  • 1
    • 0003444750 scopus 로고
    • Bruce Ackerman and Lawrence Lessig are two prominent theorists who have undertaken the project of understanding the Constitution as a whole. See 1 BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: FOUNDATIONS (1991); BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: TRANSFORMATIONS (1998); RESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION: THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT (Sanford Levinson ed., 1995); Lawrence Lessig, Fidelity and Constraint, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 1365 (1997); Lawrence Lessig, Translating Federalism: United States v. Lopez, 1995 SUP. CT. REV. 125 (1995); Lawrence Lessig, Understanding Changed Readings: Fidelity and Theory, 47 STAN. L. REV. 395 (1995) [hereinafter Lessig, Understanding]; Lawrence Lessig, Fidelity in Translation, 71 TEX. L. REV. 1165 (1993) [hereinafter Lessig, Fidelity]; Symposium, Fidelity in Constitutional Theory, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 1247 (1997). set out my own theory of constitutional change in STEPHEN M. GRIFFIN, AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONALISM: FROM THEORY TO POLITICS 9-19, 26-58, 68-87 (1996).
    • (1991) We the People: Foundations
    • Ackerman, B.1
  • 2
    • 0003444752 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bruce Ackerman and Lawrence Lessig are two prominent theorists who have undertaken the project of understanding the Constitution as a whole. See 1 BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: FOUNDATIONS (1991); BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: TRANSFORMATIONS (1998); RESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION: THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT (Sanford Levinson ed., 1995); Lawrence Lessig, Fidelity and Constraint, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 1365 (1997); Lawrence Lessig, Translating Federalism: United States v. Lopez, 1995 SUP. CT. REV. 125 (1995); Lawrence Lessig, Understanding Changed Readings: Fidelity and Theory, 47 STAN. L. REV. 395 (1995) [hereinafter Lessig, Understanding]; Lawrence Lessig, Fidelity in Translation, 71 TEX. L. REV. 1165 (1993) [hereinafter Lessig, Fidelity]; Symposium, Fidelity in Constitutional Theory, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 1247 (1997). set out my own theory of constitutional change in STEPHEN M. GRIFFIN, AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONALISM: FROM THEORY TO POLITICS 9-19, 26-58, 68-87 (1996).
    • (1998) We the People: Transformations
    • Ackerman, B.1
  • 3
    • 0009276890 scopus 로고
    • Sanford Levinson ed.
    • Bruce Ackerman and Lawrence Lessig are two prominent theorists who have undertaken the project of understanding the Constitution as a whole. See 1 BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: FOUNDATIONS (1991); BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: TRANSFORMATIONS (1998); RESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION: THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT (Sanford Levinson ed., 1995); Lawrence Lessig, Fidelity and Constraint, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 1365 (1997); Lawrence Lessig, Translating Federalism: United States v. Lopez, 1995 SUP. CT. REV. 125 (1995); Lawrence Lessig, Understanding Changed Readings: Fidelity and Theory, 47 STAN. L. REV. 395 (1995) [hereinafter Lessig, Understanding]; Lawrence Lessig, Fidelity in Translation, 71 TEX. L. REV. 1165 (1993) [hereinafter Lessig, Fidelity]; Symposium, Fidelity in Constitutional Theory, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 1247 (1997). set out my own theory of constitutional change in STEPHEN M. GRIFFIN, AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONALISM: FROM THEORY TO POLITICS 9-19, 26-58, 68-87 (1996).
    • (1995) Responding to Imperfection: The Theory and Practice of Constitutional Amendment
  • 4
    • 0042560075 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fidelity and constraint
    • Bruce Ackerman and Lawrence Lessig are two prominent theorists who have undertaken the project of understanding the Constitution as a whole. See 1 BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: FOUNDATIONS (1991); BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: TRANSFORMATIONS (1998); RESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION: THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT (Sanford Levinson ed., 1995); Lawrence Lessig, Fidelity and Constraint, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 1365 (1997); Lawrence Lessig, Translating Federalism: United States v. Lopez, 1995 SUP. CT. REV. 125 (1995); Lawrence Lessig, Understanding Changed Readings: Fidelity and Theory, 47 STAN. L. REV. 395 (1995) [hereinafter Lessig, Understanding]; Lawrence Lessig, Fidelity in Translation, 71 TEX. L. REV. 1165 (1993) [hereinafter Lessig, Fidelity]; Symposium, Fidelity in Constitutional Theory, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 1247 (1997). set out my own theory of constitutional change in STEPHEN M. GRIFFIN, AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONALISM: FROM THEORY TO POLITICS 9-19, 26-58, 68-87 (1996).
    • (1997) Fordham L. Rev. , vol.65 , pp. 1365
    • Lessig, L.1
  • 5
    • 0040373276 scopus 로고
    • Translating federalism: United States v. Lopez
    • Bruce Ackerman and Lawrence Lessig are two prominent theorists who have undertaken the project of understanding the Constitution as a whole. See 1 BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: FOUNDATIONS (1991); BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: TRANSFORMATIONS (1998); RESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION: THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT (Sanford Levinson ed., 1995); Lawrence Lessig, Fidelity and Constraint, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 1365 (1997); Lawrence Lessig, Translating Federalism: United States v. Lopez, 1995 SUP. CT. REV. 125 (1995); Lawrence Lessig, Understanding Changed Readings: Fidelity and Theory, 47 STAN. L. REV. 395 (1995) [hereinafter Lessig, Understanding]; Lawrence Lessig, Fidelity in Translation, 71 TEX. L. REV. 1165 (1993) [hereinafter Lessig, Fidelity]; Symposium, Fidelity in Constitutional Theory, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 1247 (1997). set out my own theory of constitutional change in STEPHEN M. GRIFFIN, AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONALISM: FROM THEORY TO POLITICS 9-19, 26-58, 68-87 (1996).
    • (1995) Sup. Ct. Rev. , vol.1995 , pp. 125
    • Lessig, L.1
  • 6
    • 43549104222 scopus 로고
    • Understanding changed readings: Fidelity and theory
    • hereinafter Lessig, Understanding
    • Bruce Ackerman and Lawrence Lessig are two prominent theorists who have undertaken the project of understanding the Constitution as a whole. See 1 BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: FOUNDATIONS (1991); BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: TRANSFORMATIONS (1998); RESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION: THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT (Sanford Levinson ed., 1995); Lawrence Lessig, Fidelity and Constraint, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 1365 (1997); Lawrence Lessig, Translating Federalism: United States v. Lopez, 1995 SUP. CT. REV. 125 (1995); Lawrence Lessig, Understanding Changed Readings: Fidelity and Theory, 47 STAN. L. REV. 395 (1995) [hereinafter Lessig, Understanding]; Lawrence Lessig, Fidelity in Translation, 71 TEX. L. REV. 1165 (1993) [hereinafter Lessig, Fidelity]; Symposium, Fidelity in Constitutional Theory, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 1247 (1997). set out my own theory of constitutional change in STEPHEN M. GRIFFIN, AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONALISM: FROM THEORY TO POLITICS 9-19, 26-58, 68-87 (1996).
    • (1995) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.47 , pp. 395
    • Lessig, L.1
  • 7
    • 77954490901 scopus 로고
    • Fidelity in translation
    • hereinafter Lessig, Fidelity
    • Bruce Ackerman and Lawrence Lessig are two prominent theorists who have undertaken the project of understanding the Constitution as a whole. See 1 BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: FOUNDATIONS (1991); BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: TRANSFORMATIONS (1998); RESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION: THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT (Sanford Levinson ed., 1995); Lawrence Lessig, Fidelity and Constraint, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 1365 (1997); Lawrence Lessig, Translating Federalism: United States v. Lopez, 1995 SUP. CT. REV. 125 (1995); Lawrence Lessig, Understanding Changed Readings: Fidelity and Theory, 47 STAN. L. REV. 395 (1995) [hereinafter Lessig, Understanding]; Lawrence Lessig, Fidelity in Translation, 71 TEX. L. REV. 1165 (1993) [hereinafter Lessig, Fidelity]; Symposium, Fidelity in Constitutional Theory, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 1247 (1997). set out my own theory of constitutional change in STEPHEN M. GRIFFIN, AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONALISM: FROM THEORY TO POLITICS 9-19, 26-58, 68-87 (1996).
    • (1993) Tex. L. Rev. , vol.71 , pp. 1165
    • Lessig, L.1
  • 8
    • 0041557926 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Fidelity in constitutional theory
    • Bruce Ackerman and Lawrence Lessig are two prominent theorists who have undertaken the project of understanding the Constitution as a whole. See 1 BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: FOUNDATIONS (1991); BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: TRANSFORMATIONS (1998); RESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION: THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT (Sanford Levinson ed., 1995); Lawrence Lessig, Fidelity and Constraint, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 1365 (1997); Lawrence Lessig, Translating Federalism: United States v. Lopez, 1995 SUP. CT. REV. 125 (1995); Lawrence Lessig, Understanding Changed Readings: Fidelity and Theory, 47 STAN. L. REV. 395 (1995) [hereinafter Lessig, Understanding]; Lawrence Lessig, Fidelity in Translation, 71 TEX. L. REV. 1165 (1993) [hereinafter Lessig, Fidelity]; Symposium, Fidelity in Constitutional Theory, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 1247 (1997). set out my own theory of constitutional change in STEPHEN M. GRIFFIN, AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONALISM: FROM THEORY TO POLITICS 9-19, 26-58, 68-87 (1996).
    • (1997) Fordham L. Rev. , vol.65 , pp. 1247
  • 9
    • 0003983215 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Bruce Ackerman and Lawrence Lessig are two prominent theorists who have undertaken the project of understanding the Constitution as a whole. See 1 BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: FOUNDATIONS (1991); BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: TRANSFORMATIONS (1998); RESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION: THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT (Sanford Levinson ed., 1995); Lawrence Lessig, Fidelity and Constraint, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 1365 (1997); Lawrence Lessig, Translating Federalism: United States v. Lopez, 1995 SUP. CT. REV. 125 (1995); Lawrence Lessig, Understanding Changed Readings: Fidelity and Theory, 47 STAN. L. REV. 395 (1995) [hereinafter Lessig, Understanding]; Lawrence Lessig, Fidelity in Translation, 71 TEX. L. REV. 1165 (1993) [hereinafter Lessig, Fidelity]; Symposium, Fidelity in Constitutional Theory, 65 FORDHAM L. REV. 1247 (1997). set out my own theory of constitutional change in STEPHEN M. GRIFFIN, AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONALISM: FROM THEORY TO POLITICS 9-19, 26-58, 68-87 (1996).
    • (1996) American Constitutionalism: From Theory to Politics , pp. 9-19
    • Griffin, S.M.1
  • 10
    • 0009276372 scopus 로고
    • An eighteenth century presidency in a twenty-first century world
    • It would thus be unwise to assume at the outset that a single branch of government, such as the Supreme Court, has been the sole source of important constitutional changes. It is unlikely that the Court has initiated or is responsible for all of the significant changes that have occurred with respect to the political branches. It seems intuitive, for example, that the nation's presidents have had something to do with changes in their office. For a recent brief treatment of constitutional changes in the presidency, see Cass R. Sunstein, An Eighteenth Century Presidency in a Twenty-First Century World, 48 ARK. L. REV. 1 (1994).
    • (1994) Ark. L. Rev. , vol.48 , pp. 1
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 11
    • 0042560041 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • See 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 1; 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1.
    • Ackerman , vol.1
  • 12
    • 0041557925 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • See 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 1; 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1.
    • Ackerman , vol.2
  • 13
    • 15744389689 scopus 로고
    • United States v. Lopez, opinion of Kennedy, J., concurring
    • My theory of constitutional change does not begin with the Court, but rather with the idea that all of the branches are likely to have initiated significant constitutional changes at one time or another. Further, I do not begin with the Court in a methodological sense; that is, I do not assume that the kind of legalistic interpretation that characterizes the Court's opinions necessarily prevails in the other branches. I see no reason to assume that constitutional change in the political branches is fundamentally a matter of interpreting the Constitution. Change may happen through interpretation, but it also may not. Since ordinary political change often happens as a result of power struggles, electoral victories, interest group pressure, and so on, it seems unlikely that changes in the constitutional structure of the political branches would be driven solely by legalistic interpretation. Justices Kennedy and O'Connor recently made this point in United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549, 577-78 (1995) (opinion of Kennedy, J., concurring).
    • (1995) U.S. , vol.514 , pp. 549
  • 14
    • 0043060901 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Here and elsewhere in this essay, I use "interpretive" and "interpretation" in the very specific sense of legal interpretation. I do not mean to refer to the much different debate of whether the social sciences should be pursued through an interpretive method.
  • 15
    • 0042560074 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • How is the idea of "change" to be understood? What counts as a change? Some might imagine that I must use an originalist notion of change, according to which change in the Constitution is to be measured against a baseline of the Framers' intent. In this and in my earlier work, however, I am not using an originalist baseline, but an historicist one. The baseline for determining whether a constitutional change has occurred is not a relatively discrete set of statements by important members of the Founding generation issued during the period surrounding the adoption of the Constitution, as well as statements by Framers of its subsequent amendments. It is rather the historical context in which those statements were made. More specifically, the baseline for assessing change is composed of the institutional structures and state capacities created by the Constitution. We can study constitutional change by observing the continuities and discontinuities as these structures develop over time.
  • 16
    • 0004212175 scopus 로고
    • Peter B. Evans et al. eds.
    • For representative works, see BRINGING THE STATE BACK IN (Peter B. Evans et al. eds., 1985); JAMES G. MARCH & JOHAN P. OLSEN, REDISCOVERING INSTITUTIONS: THE ORGANIZATIONAL BASIS OF POLITICS (1989); ERIC A. NORDLINGER, ON THE AUTONOMY OF THE DEMOCRATIC STATE (1981); MARTIN SHEFTER, POLITICAL PARTIES AND THE STATE: THE AMERICAN HISTORICAL EXPERIENCE (1994); and STEPHEN SKOWRONEK, BUILDING A NEW AMERICAN STATE: THE EXPANSION OF NATIONAL ADMINISTRATIVE CAPACITIES, 1877-1920 (1982). See also Karen Orren & Stephen Skowronek, Institutions and Intercurrence: Theory Building in the Fullness of Time, in POLITICAL ORDER 111 (Ian Shapiro & Russell Hardin eds., 1996); Polity Forum: Institutions and Institutionalism, 28 POLITY 84 (1995); Rogers M. Smith, Science, Non-Science, and Politics, in THE HISTORIC TURN IN THE HUMAN SCIENCES 119 (Terrence J. McDonald ed., 1996); Rogers M. Smith, Still Blowing in the Wind: The American Quest for a Democratic, Scientific Political Science, 126 DAEDALUS 253 (1997) [hereinafter Smith, Still Blowing in the Wind].
    • (1985) Bringing the State Back In
  • 17
    • 0003713160 scopus 로고
    • For representative works, see BRINGING THE STATE BACK IN (Peter B. Evans et al. eds., 1985); JAMES G. MARCH & JOHAN P. OLSEN, REDISCOVERING INSTITUTIONS: THE ORGANIZATIONAL BASIS OF POLITICS (1989); ERIC A. NORDLINGER, ON THE AUTONOMY OF THE DEMOCRATIC STATE (1981); MARTIN SHEFTER, POLITICAL PARTIES AND THE STATE: THE AMERICAN HISTORICAL EXPERIENCE (1994); and STEPHEN SKOWRONEK, BUILDING A NEW AMERICAN STATE: THE EXPANSION OF NATIONAL ADMINISTRATIVE CAPACITIES, 1877-1920 (1982). See also Karen Orren & Stephen Skowronek, Institutions and Intercurrence: Theory Building in the Fullness of Time, in POLITICAL ORDER 111 (Ian Shapiro & Russell Hardin eds., 1996); Polity Forum: Institutions and Institutionalism, 28 POLITY 84 (1995); Rogers M. Smith, Science, Non-Science, and Politics, in THE HISTORIC TURN IN THE HUMAN SCIENCES 119 (Terrence J. McDonald ed., 1996); Rogers M. Smith, Still Blowing in the Wind: The American Quest for a Democratic, Scientific Political Science, 126 DAEDALUS 253 (1997) [hereinafter Smith, Still Blowing in the Wind].
    • (1989) Rediscovering Institutions: the Organizational Basis of Politics
    • March, J.G.1    Olsen, J.P.2
  • 18
    • 0004181643 scopus 로고
    • For representative works, see BRINGING THE STATE BACK IN (Peter B. Evans et al. eds., 1985); JAMES G. MARCH & JOHAN P. OLSEN, REDISCOVERING INSTITUTIONS: THE ORGANIZATIONAL BASIS OF POLITICS (1989); ERIC A. NORDLINGER, ON THE AUTONOMY OF THE DEMOCRATIC STATE (1981); MARTIN SHEFTER, POLITICAL PARTIES AND THE STATE: THE AMERICAN HISTORICAL EXPERIENCE (1994); and STEPHEN SKOWRONEK, BUILDING A NEW AMERICAN STATE: THE EXPANSION OF NATIONAL ADMINISTRATIVE CAPACITIES, 1877-1920 (1982). See also Karen Orren & Stephen Skowronek, Institutions and Intercurrence: Theory Building in the Fullness of Time, in POLITICAL ORDER 111 (Ian Shapiro & Russell Hardin eds., 1996); Polity Forum: Institutions and Institutionalism, 28 POLITY 84 (1995); Rogers M. Smith, Science, Non-Science, and Politics, in THE HISTORIC TURN IN THE HUMAN SCIENCES 119 (Terrence J. McDonald ed., 1996); Rogers M. Smith, Still Blowing in the Wind: The American Quest for a Democratic, Scientific Political Science, 126 DAEDALUS 253 (1997) [hereinafter Smith, Still Blowing in the Wind].
    • (1981) On the Autonomy of the Democratic State
    • Nordlinger, E.A.1
  • 19
    • 0003498466 scopus 로고
    • For representative works, see BRINGING THE STATE BACK IN (Peter B. Evans et al. eds., 1985); JAMES G. MARCH & JOHAN P. OLSEN, REDISCOVERING INSTITUTIONS: THE ORGANIZATIONAL BASIS OF POLITICS (1989); ERIC A. NORDLINGER, ON THE AUTONOMY OF THE DEMOCRATIC STATE (1981); MARTIN SHEFTER, POLITICAL PARTIES AND THE STATE: THE AMERICAN HISTORICAL EXPERIENCE (1994); and STEPHEN SKOWRONEK, BUILDING A NEW AMERICAN STATE: THE EXPANSION OF NATIONAL ADMINISTRATIVE CAPACITIES, 1877-1920 (1982). See also Karen Orren & Stephen Skowronek, Institutions and Intercurrence: Theory Building in the Fullness of Time, in POLITICAL ORDER 111 (Ian Shapiro & Russell Hardin eds., 1996); Polity Forum: Institutions and Institutionalism, 28 POLITY 84 (1995); Rogers M. Smith, Science, Non-Science, and Politics, in THE HISTORIC TURN IN THE HUMAN SCIENCES 119 (Terrence J. McDonald ed., 1996); Rogers M. Smith, Still Blowing in the Wind: The American Quest for a Democratic, Scientific Political Science, 126 DAEDALUS 253 (1997) [hereinafter Smith, Still Blowing in the Wind].
    • (1994) Political Parties and the State: The American Historical Experience
    • Shefter, M.1
  • 20
    • 0004070748 scopus 로고
    • For representative works, see BRINGING THE STATE BACK IN (Peter B. Evans et al. eds., 1985); JAMES G. MARCH & JOHAN P. OLSEN, REDISCOVERING INSTITUTIONS: THE ORGANIZATIONAL BASIS OF POLITICS (1989); ERIC A. NORDLINGER, ON THE AUTONOMY OF THE DEMOCRATIC STATE (1981); MARTIN SHEFTER, POLITICAL PARTIES AND THE STATE: THE AMERICAN HISTORICAL EXPERIENCE (1994); and STEPHEN SKOWRONEK, BUILDING A NEW AMERICAN STATE: THE EXPANSION OF NATIONAL ADMINISTRATIVE CAPACITIES, 1877-1920 (1982). See also Karen Orren & Stephen Skowronek, Institutions and Intercurrence: Theory Building in the Fullness of Time, in POLITICAL ORDER 111 (Ian Shapiro & Russell Hardin eds., 1996); Polity Forum: Institutions and Institutionalism, 28 POLITY 84 (1995); Rogers M. Smith, Science, Non-Science, and Politics, in THE HISTORIC TURN IN THE HUMAN SCIENCES 119 (Terrence J. McDonald ed., 1996); Rogers M. Smith, Still Blowing in the Wind: The American Quest for a Democratic, Scientific Political Science, 126 DAEDALUS 253 (1997) [hereinafter Smith, Still Blowing in the Wind].
    • (1982) Building a New American State: The Expansion of National Administrative Capacities , pp. 1877-1920
    • Skowronek, S.1
  • 21
    • 0011338691 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Institutions and intercurrence: Theory building in the fullness of time
    • Ian Shapiro & Russell Hardin eds.
    • For representative works, see BRINGING THE STATE BACK IN (Peter B. Evans et al. eds., 1985); JAMES G. MARCH & JOHAN P. OLSEN, REDISCOVERING INSTITUTIONS: THE ORGANIZATIONAL BASIS OF POLITICS (1989); ERIC A. NORDLINGER, ON THE AUTONOMY OF THE DEMOCRATIC STATE (1981); MARTIN SHEFTER, POLITICAL PARTIES AND THE STATE: THE AMERICAN HISTORICAL EXPERIENCE (1994); and STEPHEN SKOWRONEK, BUILDING A NEW AMERICAN STATE: THE EXPANSION OF NATIONAL ADMINISTRATIVE CAPACITIES, 1877-1920 (1982). See also Karen Orren & Stephen Skowronek, Institutions and Intercurrence: Theory Building in the Fullness of Time, in POLITICAL ORDER 111 (Ian Shapiro & Russell Hardin eds., 1996); Polity Forum: Institutions and Institutionalism, 28 POLITY 84 (1995); Rogers M. Smith, Science, Non-Science, and Politics, in THE HISTORIC TURN IN THE HUMAN SCIENCES 119 (Terrence J. McDonald ed., 1996); Rogers M. Smith, Still Blowing in the Wind: The American Quest for a Democratic, Scientific Political Science, 126 DAEDALUS 253 (1997) [hereinafter Smith, Still Blowing in the Wind].
    • (1996) Political Order , pp. 111
    • Orren, K.1    Skowronek, S.2
  • 22
    • 0040707006 scopus 로고
    • Polity forum: Institutions and institutionalism
    • For representative works, see BRINGING THE STATE BACK IN (Peter B. Evans et al. eds., 1985); JAMES G. MARCH & JOHAN P. OLSEN, REDISCOVERING INSTITUTIONS: THE ORGANIZATIONAL BASIS OF POLITICS (1989); ERIC A. NORDLINGER, ON THE AUTONOMY OF THE DEMOCRATIC STATE (1981); MARTIN SHEFTER, POLITICAL PARTIES AND THE STATE: THE AMERICAN HISTORICAL EXPERIENCE (1994); and STEPHEN SKOWRONEK, BUILDING A NEW AMERICAN STATE: THE EXPANSION OF NATIONAL ADMINISTRATIVE CAPACITIES, 1877-1920 (1982). See also Karen Orren & Stephen Skowronek, Institutions and Intercurrence: Theory Building in the Fullness of Time, in POLITICAL ORDER 111 (Ian Shapiro & Russell Hardin eds., 1996); Polity Forum: Institutions and Institutionalism, 28 POLITY 84 (1995); Rogers M. Smith, Science, Non-Science, and Politics, in THE HISTORIC TURN IN THE HUMAN SCIENCES 119 (Terrence J. McDonald ed., 1996); Rogers M. Smith, Still Blowing in the Wind: The American Quest for a Democratic, Scientific Political Science, 126 DAEDALUS 253 (1997) [hereinafter Smith, Still Blowing in the Wind].
    • (1995) Polity , vol.28 , pp. 84
  • 23
    • 0001067941 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Science, non-science, and politics
    • Terrence J. McDonald ed.
    • For representative works, see BRINGING THE STATE BACK IN (Peter B. Evans et al. eds., 1985); JAMES G. MARCH & JOHAN P. OLSEN, REDISCOVERING INSTITUTIONS: THE ORGANIZATIONAL BASIS OF POLITICS (1989); ERIC A. NORDLINGER, ON THE AUTONOMY OF THE DEMOCRATIC STATE (1981); MARTIN SHEFTER, POLITICAL PARTIES AND THE STATE: THE AMERICAN HISTORICAL EXPERIENCE (1994); and STEPHEN SKOWRONEK, BUILDING A NEW AMERICAN STATE: THE EXPANSION OF NATIONAL ADMINISTRATIVE CAPACITIES, 1877-1920 (1982). See also Karen Orren & Stephen Skowronek, Institutions and Intercurrence: Theory Building in the Fullness of Time, in POLITICAL ORDER 111 (Ian Shapiro & Russell Hardin eds., 1996); Polity Forum: Institutions and Institutionalism, 28 POLITY 84 (1995); Rogers M. Smith, Science, Non-Science, and Politics, in THE HISTORIC TURN IN THE HUMAN SCIENCES 119 (Terrence J. McDonald ed., 1996); Rogers M. Smith, Still Blowing in the Wind: The American Quest for a Democratic, Scientific Political Science, 126 DAEDALUS 253 (1997) [hereinafter Smith, Still Blowing in the Wind].
    • (1996) The Historic Turn in the Human Sciences , pp. 119
    • Smith, R.M.1
  • 24
    • 0038770237 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Still blowing in the wind: The American quest for a democratic, scientific political science
    • hereinafter Smith, Still Blowing in the Wind
    • For representative works, see BRINGING THE STATE BACK IN (Peter B. Evans et al. eds., 1985); JAMES G. MARCH & JOHAN P. OLSEN, REDISCOVERING INSTITUTIONS: THE ORGANIZATIONAL BASIS OF POLITICS (1989); ERIC A. NORDLINGER, ON THE AUTONOMY OF THE DEMOCRATIC STATE (1981); MARTIN SHEFTER, POLITICAL PARTIES AND THE STATE: THE AMERICAN HISTORICAL EXPERIENCE (1994); and STEPHEN SKOWRONEK, BUILDING A NEW AMERICAN STATE: THE EXPANSION OF NATIONAL ADMINISTRATIVE CAPACITIES, 1877-1920 (1982). See also Karen Orren & Stephen Skowronek, Institutions and Intercurrence: Theory Building in the Fullness of Time, in POLITICAL ORDER 111 (Ian Shapiro & Russell Hardin eds., 1996); Polity Forum: Institutions and Institutionalism, 28 POLITY 84 (1995); Rogers M. Smith, Science, Non-Science, and Politics, in THE HISTORIC TURN IN THE HUMAN SCIENCES 119 (Terrence J. McDonald ed., 1996); Rogers M. Smith, Still Blowing in the Wind: The American Quest for a Democratic, Scientific Political Science, 126 DAEDALUS 253 (1997) [hereinafter Smith, Still Blowing in the Wind].
    • (1997) Daedalus , vol.126 , pp. 253
    • Smith, R.M.1
  • 25
    • 84928617581 scopus 로고
    • The very idea of an autonomous national state presupposes the capacity to make effective decisions and have them enforced. See, e.g., KENNETH FINEGOLD & THEDA SKOCPOL, STATE AND PARTY IN AMERICA'S NEW DEAL 50-59 (1995). In the case of the American state, this capacity has been acquired over time, leading to the focus, characteristic of historical institutionalism, on state building. See, e.g., SKOWRONEK, supra note 7. At the most abstract level, historical institutionalists speak of "weak" or "strong" states. Strong states are relatively autonomous of civil society, while weak states are dependent on societal interests to make decisions and implement policies. There are a number of more specific opposing terms that go along with the terms weak or strong. Weak states can be so because their departments and agencies are fragmented instead of coordinated. Or state agencies can be decentralized at different levels of government rather than centralized at the national level. Further, states have various capacities for action. A state with a competent, adequately funded bureaucracy, for example, is more likely to have the infrastructural capacity "to penetrate society and to organize social relations." JOHN A. HALL & G. JOHN IKENBERRY, THE STATE 13 (1989). With this richer vocabulary, we can reach a more precise understanding of the development of state institutions, which then enables us to achieve a more dynamic view of the course of constitutional change. See generally Stephen D. Krasner, Approaches to the State: Alternative Conceptions and Historical Dynamics, 16 COMP. POL. 223 (1984).
    • (1995) State and Party in America's New Deal , pp. 50-59
    • Finegold, K.1    Skocpol, T.2
  • 26
    • 0041557923 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 7.
    • The very idea of an autonomous national state presupposes the capacity to make effective decisions and have them enforced. See, e.g., KENNETH FINEGOLD & THEDA SKOCPOL, STATE AND PARTY IN AMERICA'S NEW DEAL 50-59 (1995). In the case of the American state, this capacity has been acquired over time, leading to the focus, characteristic of historical institutionalism, on state building. See, e.g., SKOWRONEK, supra note 7. At the most abstract level, historical institutionalists speak of "weak" or "strong" states. Strong states are relatively autonomous of civil society, while weak states are dependent on societal interests to make decisions and implement policies. There are a number of more specific opposing terms that go along with the terms weak or strong. Weak states can be so because their departments and agencies are fragmented instead of coordinated. Or state agencies can be decentralized at different levels of government rather than centralized at the national level. Further, states have various capacities for action. A state with a competent, adequately funded bureaucracy, for example, is more likely to have the infrastructural capacity "to penetrate society and to organize social relations." JOHN A. HALL & G. JOHN IKENBERRY, THE STATE 13 (1989). With this richer vocabulary, we can reach a more precise understanding of the development of state institutions, which then enables us to achieve a more dynamic view of the course of constitutional change. See generally Stephen D. Krasner, Approaches to the State: Alternative Conceptions and Historical Dynamics, 16 COMP. POL. 223 (1984).
    • Skowronek1
  • 27
    • 0004243985 scopus 로고
    • The very idea of an autonomous national state presupposes the capacity to make effective decisions and have them enforced. See, e.g., KENNETH FINEGOLD & THEDA SKOCPOL, STATE AND PARTY IN AMERICA'S NEW DEAL 50-59 (1995). In the case of the American state, this capacity has been acquired over time, leading to the focus, characteristic of historical institutionalism, on state building. See, e.g., SKOWRONEK, supra note 7. At the most abstract level, historical institutionalists speak of "weak" or "strong" states. Strong states are relatively autonomous of civil society, while weak states are dependent on societal interests to make decisions and implement policies. There are a number of more specific opposing terms that go along with the terms weak or strong. Weak states can be so because their departments and agencies are fragmented instead of coordinated. Or state agencies can be decentralized at different levels of government rather than centralized at the national level. Further, states have various capacities for action. A state with a competent, adequately funded bureaucracy, for example, is more likely to have the infrastructural capacity "to penetrate society and to organize social relations." JOHN A. HALL & G. JOHN IKENBERRY, THE STATE 13 (1989). With this richer vocabulary, we can reach a more precise understanding of the development of state institutions, which then enables us to achieve a more dynamic view of the course of constitutional change. See generally Stephen D. Krasner, Approaches to the State: Alternative Conceptions and Historical Dynamics, 16 COMP. POL. 223 (1984).
    • (1989) The State , pp. 13
    • Hall, J.A.1    Ikenberry, G.J.2
  • 28
    • 0007029184 scopus 로고
    • Approaches to the state: Alternative conceptions and historical dynamics
    • The very idea of an autonomous national state presupposes the capacity to make effective decisions and have them enforced. See, e.g., KENNETH FINEGOLD & THEDA SKOCPOL, STATE AND PARTY IN AMERICA'S NEW DEAL 50-59 (1995). In the case of the American state, this capacity has been acquired over time, leading to the focus, characteristic of historical institutionalism, on state building. See, e.g., SKOWRONEK, supra note 7. At the most abstract level, historical institutionalists speak of "weak" or "strong" states. Strong states are relatively autonomous of civil society, while weak states are dependent on societal interests to make decisions and implement policies. There are a number of more specific opposing terms that go along with the terms weak or strong. Weak states can be so because their departments and agencies are fragmented instead of coordinated. Or state agencies can be decentralized at different levels of government rather than centralized at the national level. Further, states have various capacities for action. A state with a competent, adequately funded bureaucracy, for example, is more likely to have the infrastructural capacity "to penetrate society and to organize social relations." JOHN A. HALL & G. JOHN IKENBERRY, THE STATE 13 (1989). With this richer vocabulary, we can reach a more precise understanding of the development of state institutions, which then enables us to achieve a more dynamic view of the course of constitutional change. See generally Stephen D. Krasner, Approaches to the State: Alternative Conceptions and Historical Dynamics, 16 COMP. POL. 223 (1984).
    • (1984) Comp. Pol. , vol.16 , pp. 223
    • Krasner, S.D.1
  • 30
    • 0043060848 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 8
    • See generally Krasner, supra note 8. For a discussion in the New Deal context, see FINEGOLD & SKOCPOL, supra note 8, at 50-59.
    • Krasner1
  • 31
    • 0042560038 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 8, at 50-59
    • See generally Krasner, supra note 8. For a discussion in the New Deal context, see FINEGOLD & SKOCPOL, supra note 8, at 50-59.
    • Finegold1    Skocpol2
  • 32
    • 0043060819 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 42; see also 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 259.
    • Ackerman , vol.2 , pp. 42
  • 33
    • 0043060818 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 42; see also 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 259.
    • Ackerman , vol.2 , pp. 259
  • 34
    • 84900147193 scopus 로고
    • Foreword: Revolutions?
    • This was demonstrated by the critical reaction to Ackerman's argument. See, e.g., Charles Fried, Foreword: Revolutions?, 109 HARV. L. REV. 13 (1995); Laurence H. Tribe, Taking Text and Structure Seriously: Reflections on Free-Form Method in Constitutional Interpretation, 108 HARV. L. REV. 1223 (1995).
    • (1995) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.109 , pp. 13
    • Fried, C.1
  • 35
    • 11944274591 scopus 로고
    • Taking text and structure seriously: Reflections on free-form method in constitutional interpretation
    • This was demonstrated by the critical reaction to Ackerman's argument. See, e.g., Charles Fried, Foreword: Revolutions?, 109 HARV. L. REV. 13 (1995); Laurence H. Tribe, Taking Text and Structure Seriously: Reflections on Free-Form Method in Constitutional Interpretation, 108 HARV. L. REV. 1223 (1995).
    • (1995) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.108 , pp. 1223
    • Tribe, L.H.1
  • 36
    • 33749833618 scopus 로고
    • 17 U.S. (4 Wheat.) 316 (1819).
    • (1819) U.S. (4 Wheat.) , vol.17 , pp. 316
  • 37
    • 33749867922 scopus 로고
    • 22 U.S. (9 Wheat.) 1 (1824).
    • (1824) U.S. (9 Wheat.) , vol.22 , pp. 1
  • 38
    • 0042560037 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • See 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1.
    • Ackerman , vol.2
  • 39
    • 0041557924 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • On the role of history and historicism, see 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 16-33; and GRIFFIN, supra note 1 at 164-69.
    • Ackerman , vol.1 , pp. 16-33
  • 40
    • 0043060882 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1 at 164-69
    • On the role of history and historicism, see 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 16-33; and GRIFFIN, supra note 1 at 164-69.
    • Griffin1
  • 41
    • 0043061016 scopus 로고
    • Abstract democracy: A review of Ackerman's we the people
    • reviewing 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 1
    • See, e.g., Terrance Sandalow, Abstract Democracy: A Review of Ackerman's We The People, 9 CONST. COMMENTARY 309 (1992) (reviewing 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 1); Suzanna Sherry, The Ghost of Liberalism Past, 105 HARV. L. REV. 918 (1992) (same); Richard A. Posner, This Magic Moment, THE NEW REPUBLIC, Apr. 6, 1998, at 32 (reviewing 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1).
    • (1992) Const. Commentary , vol.9 , pp. 309
    • Sandalow, T.1
  • 42
    • 84933495141 scopus 로고
    • The ghost of liberalism past
    • same
    • See, e.g., Terrance Sandalow, Abstract Democracy: A Review of Ackerman's We The People, 9 CONST. COMMENTARY 309 (1992) (reviewing 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 1); Suzanna Sherry, The Ghost of Liberalism Past, 105 HARV. L. REV. 918 (1992) (same); Richard A. Posner, This Magic Moment, THE NEW REPUBLIC, Apr. 6, 1998, at 32 (reviewing 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1).
    • (1992) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.105 , pp. 918
    • Sherry, S.1
  • 43
    • 0042560028 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This magic moment
    • Apr. 6, reviewing 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1
    • See, e.g., Terrance Sandalow, Abstract Democracy: A Review of Ackerman's We The People, 9 CONST. COMMENTARY 309 (1992) (reviewing 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 1); Suzanna Sherry, The Ghost of Liberalism Past, 105 HARV. L. REV. 918 (1992) (same); Richard A. Posner, This Magic Moment, THE NEW REPUBLIC, Apr. 6, 1998, at 32 (reviewing 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1).
    • (1998) The New Republic , pp. 32
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 44
    • 0042560027 scopus 로고
    • Historicism in legal scholarship
    • In a widely noted article, Robert Gordon argued that historicism, which he defined as "the recognition of the historical and cultural contingency of law," still had not been absorbed by legal scholars because it was a threat to the standard ways of doing legal scholarship. Robert W. Gordon, Historicism in Legal Scholarship, 90 YALE L.J. 1017, 1017 (1981); see also Robert W. Gordon, The Past as Authority and as Social Critic: Stabilizing and Destabilizing Functions of History in Legal Argument, in THE HISTORIC TURN IN THE HUMAN SCIENCES 339 (Terrence J. McDonald ed., 1996) [hereinafter Gordon, The Past as Authority]. Gordon contended that the evasion of this threat had limited the "intellectual options and imaginative range" of legal scholarship. Gordon, Historicism in Legal Scholarship, supra, at 1017. Although Gordon used some examples drawn from constitutional law, he did not explore in any detail the consequences of his thesis for constitutional theory. I believe that Gordon was largely correct.
    • (1981) Yale L.J. , vol.90 , pp. 1017
    • Gordon, R.W.1
  • 45
    • 0042059167 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The past as authority and as social critic: Stabilizing and destabilizing functions of history in legal argument
    • Terrence J. McDonald ed., hereinafter Gordon, The Past as Authority
    • In a widely noted article, Robert Gordon argued that historicism, which he defined as "the recognition of the historical and cultural contingency of law," still had not been absorbed by legal scholars because it was a threat to the standard ways of doing legal scholarship. Robert W. Gordon, Historicism in Legal Scholarship, 90 YALE L.J. 1017, 1017 (1981); see also Robert W. Gordon, The Past as Authority and as Social Critic: Stabilizing and Destabilizing Functions of History in Legal Argument, in THE HISTORIC TURN IN THE HUMAN SCIENCES 339 (Terrence J. McDonald ed., 1996) [hereinafter Gordon, The Past as Authority]. Gordon contended that the evasion of this threat had limited the "intellectual options and imaginative range" of legal scholarship. Gordon, Historicism in Legal Scholarship, supra, at 1017. Although Gordon used some examples drawn from constitutional law, he did not explore in any detail the consequences of his thesis for constitutional theory. I believe that Gordon was largely correct.
    • (1996) The Historic Turn in the Human Sciences , pp. 339
    • Gordon, R.W.1
  • 46
    • 0042059116 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra
    • In a widely noted article, Robert Gordon argued that historicism, which he defined as "the recognition of the historical and cultural contingency of law," still had not been absorbed by legal scholars because it was a threat to the standard ways of doing legal scholarship. Robert W. Gordon, Historicism in Legal Scholarship, 90 YALE L.J. 1017, 1017 (1981); see also Robert W. Gordon, The Past as Authority and as Social Critic: Stabilizing and Destabilizing Functions of History in Legal Argument, in THE HISTORIC TURN IN THE HUMAN SCIENCES 339 (Terrence J. McDonald ed., 1996) [hereinafter Gordon, The Past as Authority]. Gordon contended that the evasion of this threat had limited the "intellectual options and imaginative range" of legal scholarship. Gordon, Historicism in Legal Scholarship, supra, at 1017. Although Gordon used some examples drawn from constitutional law, he did not explore in any detail the consequences of his thesis for constitutional theory. I believe that Gordon was largely correct.
    • Historicism in Legal Scholarship , pp. 1017
    • Gordon1
  • 47
    • 33749867922 scopus 로고
    • 22 U.S. (9 Wheat.) 1 (1824).
    • (1824) U.S. (9 Wheat.) , vol.22 , pp. 1
  • 48
    • 33749833618 scopus 로고
    • 17 U.S. (4 Wheat.) 316 (1819).
    • (1819) U.S. (4 Wheat.) , vol.17 , pp. 316
  • 49
    • 0041018635 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • art. I, § 8, cl. 3
    • U.S. CONST, art. I, § 8, cl. 3.
    • U.S. Const
  • 50
    • 0041557869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gibbons
    • Gibbons, 22 U.S. at 196.
    • U.S. , vol.22 , pp. 196
  • 51
    • 0041557869 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • U.S. , vol.22 , pp. 196
  • 52
    • 0042559977 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 197.
    • U.S. , pp. 197
  • 53
    • 0004060897 scopus 로고
    • See PETER H. IRONS, THE NEW DEAL LAWYERS 137-38 (1982). Irons himself appears to accept the restoration thesis. See id. at 47. For a Court opinion that emphasizes the plenary nature of the power established in Gibbons, see Hodel v. Virginia Surface Mining & Reclamation Ass'n, 452 U.S. 264, 276 (1981).
    • (1982) The New Deal Lawyers , pp. 137-138
    • Irons, P.H.1
  • 54
    • 0043060881 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See PETER H. IRONS, THE NEW DEAL LAWYERS 137-38 (1982). Irons himself appears to accept the restoration thesis. See id. at 47. For a Court opinion that emphasizes the plenary nature of the power established in Gibbons, see Hodel v. Virginia Surface Mining & Reclamation Ass'n, 452 U.S. 264, 276 (1981).
    • The New Deal Lawyers , pp. 47
  • 55
    • 33750590644 scopus 로고
    • Hodel v. Virginia Surface Mining & Reclamation Ass'n
    • See PETER H. IRONS, THE NEW DEAL LAWYERS 137-38 (1982). Irons himself appears to accept the restoration thesis. See id. at 47. For a Court opinion that emphasizes the plenary nature of the power established in Gibbons, see Hodel v. Virginia Surface Mining & Reclamation Ass'n, 452 U.S. 264, 276 (1981).
    • (1981) U.S. , vol.452 , pp. 264
  • 56
    • 0042560030 scopus 로고
    • That commerce which concerns more states than one
    • Robert L. Stern, That Commerce Which Concerns More States Than One, 47 HARV. L. REV. 1335, 1337 (1934).
    • (1934) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.47 , pp. 1335
    • Stern, R.L.1
  • 57
    • 0043060878 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 25, at 92-93, 137-38, 295
    • See IRONS, supra note 25, at 92-93, 137-38, 295.
    • Irons1
  • 58
    • 0007331895 scopus 로고
    • emphasis added
    • ROBERT H. JACKSON, THE STRUGGLE FOR JUDICIAL SUPREMACY: A STUDY OF A CRISIS IN AMERICAN POWER POLITICS xiv-xv (1941) (emphasis added). For further evidence of the prominence of the restoration thesis in the late 1930s and 1940s, see PAUL L. MURPHY, THE CONSTITUTION IN CRISIS TIMES, 1918-1969, at 167-68 (1972). See also Hugh Evander Willis, Gibbons v. Ogden Then and Now, 28 KY. L.J. 280, 286, 302 (1940).
    • (1941) The Struggle for Judicial Supremacy: A Study of a Crisis in American Power Politics
    • Jackson, R.H.1
  • 59
    • 0011600470 scopus 로고
    • ROBERT H. JACKSON, THE STRUGGLE FOR JUDICIAL SUPREMACY: A STUDY OF A CRISIS IN AMERICAN POWER POLITICS xiv-xv (1941) (emphasis added). For further evidence of the prominence of the restoration thesis in the late 1930s and 1940s, see PAUL L. MURPHY, THE CONSTITUTION IN CRISIS TIMES, 1918-1969, at 167-68 (1972). See also Hugh Evander Willis, Gibbons v. Ogden Then and Now, 28 KY. L.J. 280, 286, 302 (1940).
    • (1972) The Constitution in Crisis Times, 1918-1969 , pp. 167-168
    • Murphy, P.L.1
  • 60
    • 0042059114 scopus 로고
    • Gibbons v. Ogden Then and Now
    • ROBERT H. JACKSON, THE STRUGGLE FOR JUDICIAL SUPREMACY: A STUDY OF A CRISIS IN AMERICAN POWER POLITICS xiv-xv (1941) (emphasis added). For further evidence of the prominence of the restoration thesis in the late 1930s and 1940s, see PAUL L. MURPHY, THE CONSTITUTION IN CRISIS TIMES, 1918-1969, at 167-68 (1972). See also Hugh Evander Willis, Gibbons v. Ogden Then and Now, 28 KY. L.J. 280, 286, 302 (1940).
    • (1940) Ky. L.J. , vol.28 , pp. 280
    • Willis, H.E.1
  • 61
    • 33745247331 scopus 로고
    • 312 U.S. 100 (1941).
    • (1941) U.S. , vol.312 , pp. 100
  • 62
    • 0042059125 scopus 로고
    • 247 U.S. 251 (1918).
    • (1918) U.S. , vol.247 , pp. 251
  • 63
    • 0042059124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 312 U.S. at 115.
    • U.S. , vol.312 , pp. 115
  • 64
    • 0042059124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id.
    • U.S. , vol.312 , pp. 115
  • 65
    • 33745243578 scopus 로고
    • 317 U.S. 111 (1942).
    • (1942) U.S. , vol.317 , pp. 111
  • 66
    • 0043060870 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 120.
    • U.S. , pp. 120
  • 67
    • 0043060871 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 122.
    • U.S. , pp. 122
  • 68
    • 84862608492 scopus 로고
    • 379 U.S. 241 (1964).
    • (1964) U.S. , vol.379 , pp. 241
  • 69
    • 0043060874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 254-55.
    • U.S. , pp. 254-255
  • 70
    • 0043060872 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 251.
    • U.S. , pp. 251
  • 71
    • 84862608492 scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • (1964) U.S. , vol.379 , pp. 241
  • 72
    • 33745281175 scopus 로고
    • 402 U.S. 146 (1971).
    • (1971) U.S. , vol.402 , pp. 146
  • 73
    • 0041557921 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 150-51.
    • U.S. , pp. 150-151
  • 74
    • 0041557919 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 151.
    • U.S. , pp. 151
  • 77
    • 0042059168 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 12, at 33
    • Fried, supra note 12, at 33.
    • Fried1
  • 78
    • 0042560034 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 12, at 1295
    • Tribe, supra note 12, at 1295.
    • Tribe1
  • 79
    • 33750032622 scopus 로고
    • 14 U.S. (1 Wheat.) 304 (1816).
    • (1816) U.S. (1 Wheat.) , vol.14 , pp. 304
  • 80
    • 84873815593 scopus 로고
    • 19 U.S. (6 Wheat.) 264 (1821).
    • (1821) U.S. (6 Wheat.) , vol.19 , pp. 264
  • 81
    • 33749833618 scopus 로고
    • 17 U.S. (4 Wheat.) 316 (1819).
    • (1819) U.S. (4 Wheat.) , vol.17 , pp. 316
  • 82
    • 33749867922 scopus 로고
    • 22 U.S. (9 Wheat.) 1 (1824).
    • (1824) U.S. (9 Wheat.) , vol.22 , pp. 1
  • 86
    • 0041557922 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • See 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 62.
    • Ackerman , vol.1 , pp. 62
  • 87
    • 0042560033 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 50, at 519
    • WHITE supra note 50, at 519. The most recent biographies of Marshall and Justice Joseph Story agree with this assessment. See R. KENT NEWMYER, SUPREME COURT JUSTICE JOSEPH STORY: STATESMAN OF THE OLD REPUBLIC 148-49 (1985); JEAN EDWARD SMITH, JOHN MARSHALL: DEFINER OF A NATION 445 (1996); see also Michael Les Benedict, Preserving Federalism: Reconstruction and the Waite Court, 1978 SUP. CT. REV. 39, 42-44 (1979).
    • White1
  • 88
    • 0043060866 scopus 로고
    • WHITE supra note 50, at 519. The most recent biographies of Marshall and Justice Joseph Story agree with this assessment. See R. KENT NEWMYER, SUPREME COURT JUSTICE JOSEPH STORY: STATESMAN OF THE OLD REPUBLIC 148-49 (1985); JEAN EDWARD SMITH, JOHN MARSHALL: DEFINER OF A NATION 445 (1996); see also Michael Les Benedict, Preserving Federalism: Reconstruction and the Waite Court, 1978 SUP. CT. REV. 39, 42-44 (1979).
    • (1985) Supreme Court Justice Joseph Story: Statesman of the Old Republic , pp. 148-149
    • Newmyer, R.K.1
  • 89
    • 0009228239 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • WHITE supra note 50, at 519. The most recent biographies of Marshall and Justice Joseph Story agree with this assessment. See R. KENT NEWMYER, SUPREME COURT JUSTICE JOSEPH STORY: STATESMAN OF THE OLD REPUBLIC 148-49 (1985); JEAN EDWARD SMITH, JOHN MARSHALL: DEFINER OF A NATION 445 (1996); see also Michael Les Benedict, Preserving Federalism: Reconstruction and the Waite Court, 1978 SUP. CT. REV. 39, 42-44 (1979).
    • (1996) John Marshall: Definer of a Nation , pp. 445
    • Smith, J.E.1
  • 90
    • 0002302217 scopus 로고
    • Preserving federalism: Reconstruction and the Waite Court
    • WHITE supra note 50, at 519. The most recent biographies of Marshall and Justice Joseph Story agree with this assessment. See R. KENT NEWMYER, SUPREME COURT JUSTICE JOSEPH STORY: STATESMAN OF THE OLD REPUBLIC 148-49 (1985); JEAN EDWARD SMITH, JOHN MARSHALL: DEFINER OF A NATION 445 (1996); see also Michael Les Benedict, Preserving Federalism: Reconstruction and the Waite Court, 1978 SUP. CT. REV. 39, 42-44 (1979).
    • (1979) Sup. Ct. Rev. , vol.1978 , pp. 39
    • Benedict, M.L.1
  • 95
    • 0042059121 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • footnote omitted
    • Id. (footnote omitted). With respect to Gibbons, Hobson notes that while it "has often been cited as a landmark judicial precedent for extensive national power. . . the principal significance of Gibbons lay not so much in building up and centralizing federal power as in circumscribing state power." Id. at 139.
    • The Great Chief Justice: John Marshall and the Rule of Law
  • 96
    • 0042059121 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. (footnote omitted). With respect to Gibbons, Hobson notes that while it "has often been cited as a landmark judicial precedent for extensive national power. . . the principal significance of Gibbons lay not so much in building up and centralizing federal power as in circumscribing state power." Id. at 139.
    • The Great Chief Justice: John Marshall and the Rule of Law , pp. 139
  • 97
    • 84970466084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Judicial review, nationalism, and the commerce clause: Contrasting Antebellum and Postbellum Supreme Court decision making
    • Gillman's article is part of his exchange with Robert Lowry Clinton and Wallace Mendelson, who defend the traditional restorationist position. For the progress of this debate, see Roben Lowry Clinton, Judicial Review, Nationalism, and the Commerce Clause: Contrasting Antebellum and Postbellum Supreme Court Decision Making, 47 POL. RES Q. 857 (1994); Howard Gillman, The Struggle over Marshall and the Politics of Constitutional History, 41 POL. RES. Q. 877 (1994); Robert Lowry Clinton, John Marshall's Federalism: A Reply to Professor Gillman, 47 POL. RES. Q. 887 (1994); Wallace Mendelson, John Marshall and the Sugar Trust - A Reply to Professor Gillman, 49 POL. RES. Q. 405 (1996); Howard Gillman, More on the Origins of the Fuller Court's Jurisprudence: Reexamining the Scope of Federal Power over Commerce and Manufacturing in Nineteenth-Century Constitutional Law, 49 POL. RES. Q. 415 (1996); and Wallace Mendelson, Nullification via Dual Federalism: A Second Response to Professor Gillman, 49 POL. RES. Q. 439 (1996).
    • (1994) Pol. Res Q. , vol.47 , pp. 857
    • Clinton, R.L.1
  • 98
    • 84970305703 scopus 로고
    • The struggle over Marshall and the politics of constitutional history
    • Gillman's article is part of his exchange with Robert Lowry Clinton and Wallace Mendelson, who defend the traditional restorationist position. For the progress of this debate, see Roben Lowry Clinton, Judicial Review, Nationalism, and the Commerce Clause: Contrasting Antebellum and Postbellum Supreme Court Decision Making, 47 POL. RES Q. 857 (1994); Howard Gillman, The Struggle over Marshall and the Politics of Constitutional History, 41 POL. RES. Q. 877 (1994); Robert Lowry Clinton, John Marshall's Federalism: A Reply to Professor Gillman, 47 POL. RES. Q. 887 (1994); Wallace Mendelson, John Marshall and the Sugar Trust - A Reply to Professor Gillman, 49 POL. RES. Q. 405 (1996); Howard Gillman, More on the Origins of the Fuller Court's Jurisprudence: Reexamining the Scope of Federal Power over Commerce and Manufacturing in Nineteenth-Century Constitutional Law, 49 POL. RES. Q. 415 (1996); and Wallace Mendelson, Nullification via Dual Federalism: A Second Response to Professor Gillman, 49 POL. RES. Q. 439 (1996).
    • (1994) Pol. Res. Q. , vol.41 , pp. 877
    • Gillman, H.1
  • 99
    • 84973182745 scopus 로고
    • John Marshall's federalism: A reply to professor Gillman
    • Gillman's article is part of his exchange with Robert Lowry Clinton and Wallace Mendelson, who defend the traditional restorationist position. For the progress of this debate, see Roben Lowry Clinton, Judicial Review, Nationalism, and the Commerce Clause: Contrasting Antebellum and Postbellum Supreme Court Decision Making, 47 POL. RES Q. 857 (1994); Howard Gillman, The Struggle over Marshall and the Politics of Constitutional History, 41 POL. RES. Q. 877 (1994); Robert Lowry Clinton, John Marshall's Federalism: A Reply to Professor Gillman, 47 POL. RES. Q. 887 (1994); Wallace Mendelson, John Marshall and the Sugar Trust - A Reply to Professor Gillman, 49 POL. RES. Q. 405 (1996); Howard Gillman, More on the Origins of the Fuller Court's Jurisprudence: Reexamining the Scope of Federal Power over Commerce and Manufacturing in Nineteenth-Century Constitutional Law, 49 POL. RES. Q. 415 (1996); and Wallace Mendelson, Nullification via Dual Federalism: A Second Response to Professor Gillman, 49 POL. RES. Q. 439 (1996).
    • (1994) Pol. Res. Q. , vol.47 , pp. 887
    • Clinton, R.L.1
  • 100
    • 0030553504 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John Marshall and the sugar trust -a reply to professor Gillman
    • Gillman's article is part of his exchange with Robert Lowry Clinton and Wallace Mendelson, who defend the traditional restorationist position. For the progress of this debate, see Roben Lowry Clinton, Judicial Review, Nationalism, and the Commerce Clause: Contrasting Antebellum and Postbellum Supreme Court Decision Making, 47 POL. RES Q. 857 (1994); Howard Gillman, The Struggle over Marshall and the Politics of Constitutional History, 41 POL. RES. Q. 877 (1994); Robert Lowry Clinton, John Marshall's Federalism: A Reply to Professor Gillman, 47 POL. RES. Q. 887 (1994); Wallace Mendelson, John Marshall and the Sugar Trust -A Reply to Professor Gillman, 49 POL. RES. Q. 405 (1996); Howard Gillman, More on the Origins of the Fuller Court's Jurisprudence: Reexamining the Scope of Federal Power over Commerce and Manufacturing in Nineteenth-Century Constitutional Law, 49 POL. RES. Q. 415 (1996); and Wallace Mendelson, Nullification via Dual Federalism: A Second Response to Professor Gillman, 49 POL. RES. Q. 439 (1996).
    • (1996) Pol. Res. Q. , vol.49 , pp. 405
    • Mendelson, W.1
  • 101
    • 0041195242 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • More on the origins of the Fuller Court's jurisprudence: Reexamining the scope of federal power over commerce and manufacturing in nineteenth-century constitutional law
    • Gillman's article is part of his exchange with Robert Lowry Clinton and Wallace Mendelson, who defend the traditional restorationist position. For the progress of this debate, see Roben Lowry Clinton, Judicial Review, Nationalism, and the Commerce Clause: Contrasting Antebellum and Postbellum Supreme Court Decision Making, 47 POL. RES Q. 857 (1994); Howard Gillman, The Struggle over Marshall and the Politics of Constitutional History, 41 POL. RES. Q. 877 (1994); Robert Lowry Clinton, John Marshall's Federalism: A Reply to Professor Gillman, 47 POL. RES. Q. 887 (1994); Wallace Mendelson, John Marshall and the Sugar Trust - A Reply to Professor Gillman, 49 POL. RES. Q. 405 (1996); Howard Gillman, More on the Origins of the Fuller Court's Jurisprudence: Reexamining the Scope of Federal Power over Commerce and Manufacturing in Nineteenth-Century Constitutional Law, 49 POL. RES. Q. 415 (1996); and Wallace Mendelson, Nullification via Dual Federalism: A Second Response to Professor Gillman, 49 POL. RES. Q. 439 (1996).
    • (1996) Pol. Res. Q. , vol.49 , pp. 415
    • Gillman, H.1
  • 102
    • 84970466084 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Nullification via dual federalism: A second response to professor Gillman
    • Gillman's article is part of his exchange with Robert Lowry Clinton and Wallace Mendelson, who defend the traditional restorationist position. For the progress of this debate, see Roben Lowry Clinton, Judicial Review, Nationalism, and the Commerce Clause: Contrasting Antebellum and Postbellum Supreme Court Decision Making, 47 POL. RES Q. 857 (1994); Howard Gillman, The Struggle over Marshall and the Politics of Constitutional History, 41 POL. RES. Q. 877 (1994); Robert Lowry Clinton, John Marshall's Federalism: A Reply to Professor Gillman, 47 POL. RES. Q. 887 (1994); Wallace Mendelson, John Marshall and the Sugar Trust - A Reply to Professor Gillman, 49 POL. RES. Q. 405 (1996); Howard Gillman, More on the Origins of the Fuller Court's Jurisprudence: Reexamining the Scope of Federal Power over Commerce and Manufacturing in Nineteenth-Century Constitutional Law, 49 POL. RES. Q. 415 (1996); and Wallace Mendelson, Nullification via Dual Federalism: A Second Response to Professor Gillman, 49 POL. RES. Q. 439 (1996).
    • (1996) Pol. Res. Q. , vol.49 , pp. 439
    • Mendelson, W.1
  • 103
    • 33749867922 scopus 로고
    • Gibbons v. Ogden
    • Gibbons v. Ogden, 22 U.S. (9 Wheat.) 1, 194 (1824).
    • (1824) U.S. (9 Wheat.) , vol.22 , pp. 1
  • 107
    • 0043060820 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • See 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 62.
    • Ackerman , vol.1 , pp. 62
  • 108
    • 0004315670 scopus 로고
    • See LEONARD D. WHITE, THE FEDERALISTS: A STUDY IN ADMINISTRATIVE HISTORY (1948); LEONARD D. WHITE, THE JACKSONIANS: A STUDY IN ADMINISTRATIVE HISTORY 1829- 1861 (1954); LEONARD D. WHITE, THE JEFFERSONIANS: A STUDY IN ADMINISTRATIVE HISTORY 1801-1829 (1951).
    • (1948) The Federalists: A Study in Administrative History
    • White, L.D.1
  • 112
    • 0041557872 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 7
    • See SKOWRONEK, supra note 7.
    • Skowronek1
  • 113
    • 0003651220 scopus 로고
    • As historian Charles Sellers describes: Except in matters of diplomacy and war, [the federal government's] only direct services to citizens were the lightly used postal system, the federal courts, a National Road, and scattered lighthouses and navigational aids. . . . In 1815 the President paid out of his own pocket the single secretary who assisted him; the Attorney General had neither clerk nor office; the Supreme Court convened for two months a year in a Capitol Hill boarding house; and during the summer only the clerks and bureau chiefs remained in the muggy capital to keep the wheels of state slowly turning. CHARLES SELLERS, THE MARKET REVOLUTION: JACKSONIAN AMERICA 1815-1846, at 36-37 (1991).
    • (1991) The Market Revolution: Jacksonian America 1815-1846 , pp. 36-37
    • Sellers, C.1
  • 114
    • 0043060868 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 7, at 24
    • SKOWRONEK, supra note 7, at 24.
    • Skowronek1
  • 115
    • 0011296293 scopus 로고
    • The state in the United States during the nineteenth century
    • Charles Bright & Susan Harding, eds.
    • Charles C. Bright, The State in the United States During the Nineteenth Century, in STATEMAKING AND SOCIAL MOVEMENTS 121, 121 (Charles Bright & Susan Harding, eds.) (1984).
    • (1984) Statemaking and Social Movements , pp. 121
    • Bright, C.C.1
  • 116
    • 0007733342 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., DANIEL FELLER, THE JACKSONIAN PROMISE: AMERICA 1815-1840, at 53-60, 66-75, 162-68; SELLERS, supra note 69, at 70-84, 149-52, 312-31. Calhoun, of course, eventually turned against the American System and the federal power it represented. See SELLERS, supra, at 305-06.
    • The Jacksonian Promise: America 1815-1840 , pp. 53-60
    • Feller, D.1
  • 117
    • 0042059118 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 69, at 70-84, 149-52, 312-31
    • See, e.g., DANIEL FELLER, THE JACKSONIAN PROMISE: AMERICA 1815-1840, at 53-60, 66-75, 162-68; SELLERS, supra note 69, at 70-84, 149-52, 312-31. Calhoun, of course, eventually turned against the American System and the federal power it represented. See SELLERS, supra, at 305-06.
    • Sellers1
  • 118
    • 0041556729 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra, at 305-06
    • See, e.g., DANIEL FELLER, THE JACKSONIAN PROMISE: AMERICA 1815-1840, at 53-60, 66-75, 162-68; SELLERS, supra note 69, at 70-84, 149-52, 312-31. Calhoun, of course, eventually turned against the American System and the federal power it represented. See SELLERS, supra, at 305-06.
    • Sellers1
  • 119
    • 0041557873 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 72, at 168
    • FELLER, supra note 72, at 168.
    • Feller1
  • 120
    • 0042059164 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 167
    • See id. at 167.
  • 121
    • 0031489933 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • State resistance to authority in federal unions: The early United States (1790-1860) and the European community (1958-94)
    • See Leslie Friedman Goldstein, State Resistance to Authority in Federal Unions: The Early United States (1790-1860) and the European Community (1958-94), 11 STUD. AM. POL. DEV. 149 (1997); Mark A. Graber, The Passive-Aggressive Virtues: Cohens v. Virginia and the Problematic Establishment of Judicial Power, 12 CONST. COMMENTARY 67 (1995).
    • (1997) Stud. Am. Pol. Dev. , vol.11 , pp. 149
    • Goldstein, L.F.1
  • 122
    • 0031489933 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The passive-aggressive virtues: Cohens v. Virginia and the problematic establishment of judicial power
    • See Leslie Friedman Goldstein, State Resistance to Authority in Federal Unions: The Early United States (1790-1860) and the European Community (1958-94), 11 STUD. AM. POL. DEV. 149 (1997); Mark A. Graber, The Passive-Aggressive Virtues: Cohens v. Virginia and the Problematic Establishment of Judicial Power, 12 CONST. COMMENTARY 67 (1995).
    • (1995) Const. Commentary , vol.12 , pp. 67
    • Graber, M.A.1
  • 123
    • 0042560173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • What's a constitution for anyway? of history and theory, Bruce Ackerman and the new deal
    • See, e.g., Larry Kramer, What's a Constitution For Anyway? Of History and Theory, Bruce Ackerman and the New Deal, 46 CASE W. RES. L. REV. 885, 916-24 (1996).
    • (1996) Case W. Res. L. Rev. , vol.46 , pp. 885
    • Kramer, L.1
  • 124
    • 0039343077 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Processes of statemaking and popular protest
    • supra note 71
    • Historical institutionalists emphasize the importance of crises for state-building efforts. See Charles Bright & Susan Harding, Processes of Statemaking and Popular Protest, in STATEMAKING AND SOCIAL MOVEMENTS, supra note 71, at 1, 14; SKOWRONEK, supra note 7, at 10-12.
    • Statemaking and Social Movements , pp. 1
    • Bright, C.1    Harding, S.2
  • 125
    • 0042560029 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 7, at 10-12
    • Historical institutionalists emphasize the importance of crises for state-building efforts. See Charles Bright & Susan Harding, Processes of Statemaking and Popular Protest, in STATEMAKING AND SOCIAL MOVEMENTS, supra note 71, at 1, 14; SKOWRONEK, supra note 7, at 10-12.
    • Skowronek1
  • 126
    • 0043060862 scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., JOHN A. GARRATY, THE GREAT DEPRESSION (1986); WILLIAM E. LEUCHTENBURG, FRANKLIN D. ROOSEVELT AND THE NEW DEAL, 1932-1940 (1963).
    • (1986) The Great Depression
    • Garraty, J.A.1
  • 128
    • 0043060867 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • There is an obvious affinity here with the argument that Ackerman makes with respect to the New Deal. See 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 279-382.
    • Ackerman , vol.2 , pp. 279-382
  • 131
    • 84883284736 scopus 로고
    • invalidating the Railroad Retirement Act
    • 295 U.S. 330 (1935) (invalidating the Railroad Retirement Act).
    • (1935) U.S. , vol.295 , pp. 330
  • 132
    • 33645943220 scopus 로고
    • invalidating the National Industrial Recovery Act
    • 295 U.S. 495 (1935) (invalidating the National Industrial Recovery Act).
    • (1935) U.S. , vol.295 , pp. 495
  • 133
    • 84858217879 scopus 로고
    • invalidating the Agricultural Adjustment Act
    • 297 U.S. 1 (1936) (invalidating the Agricultural Adjustment Act).
    • (1936) U.S. , vol.297 , pp. 1
  • 134
    • 84858239105 scopus 로고
    • invalidating the Guffey Coal Act
    • 298 U S 238 (1936) (invalidating the Guffey Coal Act).
    • (1936) U S , vol.298 , pp. 238
  • 135
    • 0004112235 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This story has been told many times and lately a dispute has broken out over how the "switch" occurred. For contrasting views, compare BARRY CUSHMAN, RETHINKING THE NEW DEAL COURT: THE STRUCTURE OF A CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION (1998), and Richard D. Friedman, Switching Time and Other Thought Experiments: The Hughes Court and Constitutional Transformation, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1891 (1994), with WILLIAM E. LEUCHTENBURG, THE SUPREME COURT REBORN: THE CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION IN THE AGE OF ROOSEVELT (1995), and David A. Pepper, Against Legalism: Rebutting an Anachronistic Account of 1937, 82 MARQ. L. REV. 63 (1998). For other important discussions see MICHAEL E. PARRISH, ANXIOUS DECADES: AMERICA IN PROSPERITY AND DEPRESSION, 1920-1941, at 364-76 (1992); Michael Ariens, A Thrice-Told Tale, or Felix the Cat, 107 HARV. L. REV. 620 (1994); John W. Chambers, The Big Switch: Justice Roberts and the Minimum-Wage Cases, 10 LABOR HIST. 44 (1969); Richard D. Friedman, A Reaffirmation: The Authenticity of the Roberts Memorandum, or Felix the Non-Forger, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1985 (1994); Michael E. Parrish, The Great Depression, the New Deal, and the American Legal Order, 59 WASH. L. REV. 723 (1984) [hereinafter Parrish, The Great Depression]; Michael E. Parrish, The Hughes Court, the Great Depression, and the Historians, 40 HISTORIAN 286 (1978) [hereinafter Parrish, The Hughes Court]. have serious reservations about Cushman's narrowly doctrinal account of the Court's 1937 switch. While space does not permit setting out my objections in detail, it is important to point out that many reputable scholars have in effect taken the position that purely doctrinal explanations of the votes of Chief Justice Hughes and Justice Roberts in the various New Deal cases are implausible because they took inconsistent positions. Their positions were inconsistent with respect to their allegiance to broad constitutional values such as federalism, as set forth in pre- 1937 decisions. The most plausible explanation for their votes is therefore that they changed their minds about the relative importance of various constitutional values. The context for their change in view was: (1) the hostile, bipartisan reaction to Morehead v. Tipaldo, 298 U.S. 587 (1936), which held unconstitutional a New York statute mandating a minimum wage for women and minors (only relevant to Roberts); (2) FDR's overwhelming victory in the 1936 election; and (3) FDR's Court-packing plan (only relevant to some 1937 decsions). Cushman's tendentious distinction between "internal" or doctrinal explanations and "external" or political explanations means that he never comes to grips with the most persuasive version of the "external" account, one that is, in fact, an internal explanation to the extent that it focuses on the motives of Hughes and Roberts. See CUSHMAN, supra, at 4.
    • (1998) Rethinking the New Deal Court: The Structure of a Constitutional Revolution
    • Cushman, B.1
  • 136
    • 84896188144 scopus 로고
    • Switching time and other thought experiments: The Hughes Court and constitutional transformation
    • This story has been told many times and lately a dispute has broken out over how the "switch" occurred. For contrasting views, compare BARRY CUSHMAN, RETHINKING THE NEW DEAL COURT: THE STRUCTURE OF A CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION (1998), and Richard D. Friedman, Switching Time and Other Thought Experiments: The Hughes Court and Constitutional Transformation, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1891 (1994), with WILLIAM E. LEUCHTENBURG, THE SUPREME COURT REBORN: THE CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION IN THE AGE OF ROOSEVELT (1995), and David A. Pepper, Against Legalism: Rebutting an Anachronistic Account of 1937, 82 MARQ. L. REV. 63 (1998). For other important discussions see MICHAEL E. PARRISH, ANXIOUS DECADES: AMERICA IN PROSPERITY AND DEPRESSION, 1920-1941, at 364-76 (1992); Michael Ariens, A Thrice-Told Tale, or Felix the Cat, 107 HARV. L. REV. 620 (1994); John W. Chambers, The Big Switch: Justice Roberts and the Minimum-Wage Cases, 10 LABOR HIST. 44 (1969); Richard D. Friedman, A Reaffirmation: The Authenticity of the Roberts Memorandum, or Felix the Non-Forger, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1985 (1994); Michael E. Parrish, The Great Depression, the New Deal, and the American Legal Order, 59 WASH. L. REV. 723 (1984) [hereinafter Parrish, The Great Depression]; Michael E. Parrish, The Hughes Court, the Great Depression, and the Historians, 40 HISTORIAN 286 (1978) [hereinafter Parrish, The Hughes Court]. have serious reservations about Cushman's narrowly doctrinal account of the Court's 1937 switch. While space does not permit setting out my objections in detail, it is important to point out that many reputable scholars have in effect taken the position that purely doctrinal explanations of the votes of Chief Justice Hughes and Justice Roberts in the various New Deal cases are implausible because they took inconsistent positions. Their positions were inconsistent with respect to their allegiance to broad constitutional values such as federalism, as set forth in pre- 1937 decisions. The most plausible explanation for their votes is therefore that they changed their minds about the relative importance of various constitutional values. The context for their change in view was: (1) the hostile, bipartisan reaction to Morehead v. Tipaldo, 298 U.S. 587 (1936), which held unconstitutional a New York statute mandating a minimum wage for women and minors (only relevant to Roberts); (2) FDR's
    • (1994) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.142 , pp. 1891
    • Friedman, R.D.1
  • 137
    • 0003789339 scopus 로고
    • This story has been told many times and lately a dispute has broken out over how the "switch" occurred. For contrasting views, compare BARRY CUSHMAN, RETHINKING THE NEW DEAL COURT: THE STRUCTURE OF A CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION (1998), and Richard D. Friedman, Switching Time and Other Thought Experiments: The Hughes Court and Constitutional Transformation, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1891 (1994), with WILLIAM E. LEUCHTENBURG, THE SUPREME COURT REBORN: THE CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION IN THE AGE OF ROOSEVELT (1995), and David A. Pepper, Against Legalism: Rebutting an Anachronistic Account of 1937, 82 MARQ. L. REV. 63 (1998). For other important discussions see MICHAEL E. PARRISH, ANXIOUS DECADES: AMERICA IN PROSPERITY AND DEPRESSION, 1920-1941, at 364-76 (1992); Michael Ariens, A Thrice-Told Tale, or Felix the Cat, 107 HARV. L. REV. 620 (1994); John W. Chambers, The Big Switch: Justice Roberts and the Minimum-Wage Cases, 10 LABOR HIST. 44 (1969); Richard D. Friedman, A Reaffirmation: The Authenticity of the Roberts Memorandum, or Felix the Non-Forger, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1985 (1994); Michael E. Parrish, The Great Depression, the New Deal, and the American Legal Order, 59 WASH. L. REV. 723 (1984) [hereinafter Parrish, The Great Depression]; Michael E. Parrish, The Hughes Court, the Great Depression, and the Historians, 40 HISTORIAN 286 (1978) [hereinafter Parrish, The Hughes Court]. have serious reservations about Cushman's narrowly doctrinal account of the Court's 1937 switch. While space does not permit setting out my objections in detail, it is important to point out that many reputable scholars have in effect taken the position that purely doctrinal explanations of the votes of Chief Justice Hughes and Justice Roberts in the various New Deal cases are implausible because they took inconsistent positions. Their positions were inconsistent with respect to their allegiance to broad constitutional values such as federalism, as set forth in pre- 1937 decisions. The most plausible explanation for their votes is therefore that they changed their minds about the relative importance of various constitutional values. The context for their change in view was: (1) the hostile, bipartisan reaction to Morehead v. Tipaldo, 298 U.S. 587 (1936), which held unconstitutional a New York statute mandating a minimum wage for women and minors (only relevant to Roberts); (2) FDR's overwhelming victory in the 1936 election; and (3) FDR's Court-packing plan (only relevant to some 1937 decsions). Cushman's tendentious distinction between "internal" or doctrinal explanations and "external" or political explanations means that he never comes to grips with the most persuasive version of the "external" account, one that is, in fact, an internal explanation to the extent that it focuses on the motives of Hughes and Roberts. See CUSHMAN, supra, at 4.
    • (1995) The Supreme Court Reborn: The Constitutional Revolution in the Age of Roosevelt
    • Leuchtenburg, W.E.1
  • 138
    • 0042059260 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Against legalism: Rebutting an anachronistic account of 1937
    • This story has been told many times and lately a dispute has broken out over how the "switch" occurred. For contrasting views, compare BARRY CUSHMAN, RETHINKING THE NEW DEAL COURT: THE STRUCTURE OF A CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION (1998), and Richard D. Friedman, Switching Time and Other Thought Experiments: The Hughes Court and Constitutional Transformation, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1891 (1994), with WILLIAM E. LEUCHTENBURG, THE SUPREME COURT REBORN: THE CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION IN THE AGE OF ROOSEVELT (1995), and David A. Pepper, Against Legalism: Rebutting an Anachronistic Account of 1937, 82 MARQ. L. REV. 63 (1998). For other important discussions see MICHAEL E. PARRISH, ANXIOUS DECADES: AMERICA IN PROSPERITY AND DEPRESSION, 1920-1941, at 364-76 (1992); Michael Ariens, A Thrice-Told Tale, or Felix the Cat, 107 HARV. L. REV. 620 (1994); John W. Chambers, The Big Switch: Justice Roberts and the Minimum-Wage Cases, 10 LABOR HIST. 44 (1969); Richard D. Friedman, A Reaffirmation: The Authenticity of the Roberts Memorandum, or Felix the Non-Forger, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1985 (1994); Michael E. Parrish, The Great Depression, the New Deal, and the American Legal Order, 59 WASH. L. REV. 723 (1984) [hereinafter Parrish, The Great Depression]; Michael E. Parrish, The Hughes Court, the Great Depression, and the Historians, 40 HISTORIAN 286 (1978) [hereinafter Parrish, The Hughes Court]. have serious reservations about Cushman's narrowly doctrinal account of the Court's 1937 switch. While space does not permit setting out my objections in detail, it is important to point out that many reputable scholars have in effect taken the position that purely doctrinal explanations of the votes of Chief Justice Hughes and Justice Roberts in the various New Deal cases are implausible because they took inconsistent positions. Their positions were inconsistent with respect to their allegiance to broad constitutional values such as federalism, as set forth in pre- 1937 decisions. The most plausible explanation for their votes is therefore that they changed their minds about the relative importance of various constitutional values. The context for their change in view was: (1) the hostile, bipartisan reaction to Morehead v. Tipaldo, 298 U.S. 587 (1936), which held unconstitutional a New York statute mandating a minimum wage for women and minors (only relevant to Roberts); (2) FDR's overwhelming victory in the 1936 election; and (3) FDR's Court-packing plan (only relevant to some 1937 decsions). Cushman's tendentious distinction between "internal" or doctrinal explanations and "external" or political explanations means that he never comes to grips with the most persuasive version of the "external" account, one that is, in fact, an internal explanation to the extent that it focuses on the motives of Hughes and Roberts. See CUSHMAN, supra, at 4.
    • (1998) Marq. L. Rev. , vol.82 , pp. 63
    • Pepper, D.A.1
  • 139
    • 0003940421 scopus 로고
    • This story has been told many times and lately a dispute has broken out over how the "switch" occurred. For contrasting views, compare BARRY CUSHMAN, RETHINKING THE NEW DEAL COURT: THE STRUCTURE OF A CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION (1998), and Richard D. Friedman, Switching Time and Other Thought Experiments: The Hughes Court and Constitutional Transformation, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1891 (1994), with WILLIAM E. LEUCHTENBURG, THE SUPREME COURT REBORN: THE CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION IN THE AGE OF ROOSEVELT (1995), and David A. Pepper, Against Legalism: Rebutting an Anachronistic Account of 1937, 82 MARQ. L. REV. 63 (1998). For other important discussions see MICHAEL E. PARRISH, ANXIOUS DECADES: AMERICA IN PROSPERITY AND DEPRESSION, 1920-1941, at 364-76 (1992); Michael Ariens, A Thrice-Told Tale, or Felix the Cat, 107 HARV. L. REV. 620 (1994); John W. Chambers, The Big Switch: Justice Roberts and the Minimum-Wage Cases, 10 LABOR HIST. 44 (1969); Richard D. Friedman, A Reaffirmation: The Authenticity of the Roberts Memorandum, or Felix the Non-Forger, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1985 (1994); Michael E. Parrish, The Great Depression, the New Deal, and the American Legal Order, 59 WASH. L. REV. 723 (1984) [hereinafter Parrish, The Great Depression]; Michael E. Parrish, The Hughes Court, the Great Depression, and the Historians, 40 HISTORIAN 286 (1978) [hereinafter Parrish, The Hughes Court]. have serious reservations about Cushman's narrowly doctrinal account of the Court's 1937 switch. While space does not permit setting out my objections in detail, it is important to point out that many reputable scholars have in effect taken the position that purely doctrinal explanations of the votes of Chief Justice Hughes and Justice Roberts in the various New Deal cases are implausible because they took inconsistent positions. Their positions were inconsistent with respect to their allegiance to broad constitutional values such as federalism, as set forth in pre- 1937 decisions. The most plausible explanation for their votes is therefore that they changed their minds about the relative importance of various constitutional values. The context for their change in view was: (1) the hostile, bipartisan reaction to Morehead v. Tipaldo, 298 U.S. 587 (1936), which held unconstitutional a New York statute mandating a minimum wage for women and minors (only relevant to Roberts); (2) FDR's overwhelming victory in the 1936 election; and (3) FDR's Court-packing plan (only relevant to some 1937 decsions). Cushman's tendentious distinction between "internal" or doctrinal explanations and "external" or political explanations means that he never comes to grips with the most persuasive version of the "external" account, one that is, in fact, an internal explanation to the extent that it focuses on the motives of Hughes and Roberts. See CUSHMAN, supra, at 4.
    • (1992) Anxious Decades: America in Prosperity and Depression, 1920-1941 , pp. 364-376
    • Parrish, M.E.1
  • 140
    • 0039727883 scopus 로고
    • A thrice-told tale, or Felix the cat
    • This story has been told many times and lately a dispute has broken out over how the "switch" occurred. For contrasting views, compare BARRY CUSHMAN, RETHINKING THE NEW DEAL COURT: THE STRUCTURE OF A CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION (1998), and Richard D. Friedman, Switching Time and Other Thought Experiments: The Hughes Court and Constitutional Transformation, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1891 (1994), with WILLIAM E. LEUCHTENBURG, THE SUPREME COURT REBORN: THE CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION IN THE AGE OF ROOSEVELT (1995), and David A. Pepper, Against Legalism: Rebutting an Anachronistic Account of 1937, 82 MARQ. L. REV. 63 (1998). For other important discussions see MICHAEL E. PARRISH, ANXIOUS DECADES: AMERICA IN PROSPERITY AND DEPRESSION, 1920-1941, at 364-76 (1992); Michael Ariens, A Thrice-Told Tale, or Felix the Cat, 107 HARV. L. REV. 620 (1994); John W. Chambers, The Big Switch: Justice Roberts and the Minimum-Wage Cases, 10 LABOR HIST. 44 (1969); Richard D. Friedman, A Reaffirmation: The Authenticity of the Roberts Memorandum, or Felix the Non-Forger, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1985 (1994); Michael E. Parrish, The Great Depression, the New Deal, and the American Legal Order, 59 WASH. L. REV. 723 (1984) [hereinafter Parrish, The Great Depression]; Michael E. Parrish, The Hughes Court, the Great Depression, and the Historians, 40 HISTORIAN 286 (1978) [hereinafter Parrish, The Hughes Court]. have serious reservations about Cushman's narrowly doctrinal account of the Court's 1937 switch. While space does not permit setting out my objections in detail, it is important to point out that many reputable scholars have in effect taken the position that purely doctrinal explanations of the votes of Chief Justice Hughes and Justice Roberts in the various New Deal cases are implausible because they took inconsistent positions. Their positions were inconsistent with respect to their allegiance to broad constitutional values such as federalism, as set forth in pre- 1937 decisions. The most plausible explanation for their votes is therefore that they changed their minds about the relative importance of various constitutional values. The context for their change in view was: (1) the hostile, bipartisan reaction to Morehead v. Tipaldo, 298 U.S. 587 (1936), which held unconstitutional a New York statute mandating a minimum wage for women and minors (only relevant to Roberts); (2) FDR's overwhelming victory in the 1936 election; and (3) FDR's Court-packing plan (only relevant to some 1937 decsions). Cushman's tendentious distinction between "internal" or doctrinal explanations and "external" or political explanations means that he never comes to grips with the most persuasive version of the "external" account, one that is, in fact, an internal explanation to the extent that it focuses on the motives of Hughes and Roberts. See CUSHMAN, supra, at 4.
    • (1994) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.107 , pp. 620
    • Ariens, M.1
  • 141
    • 0041557915 scopus 로고
    • The big switch: Justice Roberts and the minimum-wage cases
    • This story has been told many times and lately a dispute has broken out over how the "switch" occurred. For contrasting views, compare BARRY CUSHMAN, RETHINKING THE NEW DEAL COURT: THE STRUCTURE OF A CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION (1998), and Richard D. Friedman, Switching Time and Other Thought Experiments: The Hughes Court and Constitutional Transformation, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1891 (1994), with WILLIAM E. LEUCHTENBURG, THE SUPREME COURT REBORN: THE CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION IN THE AGE OF ROOSEVELT (1995), and David A. Pepper, Against Legalism: Rebutting an Anachronistic Account of 1937, 82 MARQ. L. REV. 63 (1998). For other important discussions see MICHAEL E. PARRISH, ANXIOUS DECADES: AMERICA IN PROSPERITY AND DEPRESSION, 1920-1941, at 364-76 (1992); Michael Ariens, A Thrice-Told Tale, or Felix the Cat, 107 HARV. L. REV. 620 (1994); John W. Chambers, The Big Switch: Justice Roberts and the Minimum-Wage Cases, 10 LABOR HIST. 44 (1969); Richard D. Friedman, A Reaffirmation: The Authenticity of the Roberts Memorandum, or Felix the Non-Forger, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1985 (1994); Michael E. Parrish, The Great Depression, the New Deal, and the American Legal Order, 59 WASH. L. REV. 723 (1984) [hereinafter Parrish, The Great Depression]; Michael E. Parrish, The Hughes Court, the Great Depression, and the Historians, 40 HISTORIAN 286 (1978) [hereinafter Parrish, The Hughes Court]. have serious reservations about Cushman's narrowly doctrinal account of the Court's 1937 switch. While space does not permit setting out my objections in detail, it is important to point out that many reputable scholars have in effect taken the position that purely doctrinal explanations of the votes of Chief Justice Hughes and Justice Roberts in the various New Deal cases are implausible because they took inconsistent positions. Their positions were inconsistent with respect to their allegiance to broad constitutional values such as federalism, as set forth in pre- 1937 decisions. The most plausible explanation for their votes is therefore that they changed their minds about the relative importance of various constitutional values. The context for their change in view was: (1) the hostile, bipartisan reaction to Morehead v. Tipaldo, 298 U.S. 587 (1936), which held unconstitutional a New York statute mandating a minimum wage for women and minors (only relevant to Roberts); (2) FDR's overwhelming victory in the 1936 election; and (3) FDR's Court-packing plan (only relevant to some 1937 decsions). Cushman's tendentious distinction between "internal" or doctrinal explanations and "external" or political explanations means that he never comes to grips with the most persuasive version of the "external" account, one that is, in fact, an internal explanation to the extent that it focuses on the motives of Hughes and Roberts. See CUSHMAN, supra, at 4.
    • (1969) Labor Hist. , vol.10 , pp. 44
    • Chambers, J.W.1
  • 142
    • 84937303220 scopus 로고
    • A reaffirmation: The authenticity of the Roberts memorandum, or Felix the non-forger
    • This story has been told many times and lately a dispute has broken out over how the "switch" occurred. For contrasting views, compare BARRY CUSHMAN, RETHINKING THE NEW DEAL COURT: THE STRUCTURE OF A CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION (1998), and Richard D. Friedman, Switching Time and Other Thought Experiments: The Hughes Court and Constitutional Transformation, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1891 (1994), with WILLIAM E. LEUCHTENBURG, THE SUPREME COURT REBORN: THE CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION IN THE AGE OF ROOSEVELT (1995), and David A. Pepper, Against Legalism: Rebutting an Anachronistic Account of 1937, 82 MARQ. L. REV. 63 (1998). For other important discussions see MICHAEL E. PARRISH, ANXIOUS DECADES: AMERICA IN PROSPERITY AND DEPRESSION, 1920-1941, at 364-76 (1992); Michael Ariens, A Thrice-Told Tale, or Felix the Cat, 107 HARV. L. REV. 620 (1994); John W. Chambers, The Big Switch: Justice Roberts and the Minimum-Wage Cases, 10 LABOR HIST. 44 (1969); Richard D. Friedman, A Reaffirmation: The Authenticity of the Roberts Memorandum, or Felix the Non-Forger, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1985 (1994); Michael E. Parrish, The Great Depression, the New Deal, and the American Legal Order, 59 WASH. L. REV. 723 (1984) [hereinafter Parrish, The Great Depression]; Michael E. Parrish, The Hughes Court, the Great Depression, and the Historians, 40 HISTORIAN 286 (1978) [hereinafter Parrish, The Hughes Court]. have serious reservations about Cushman's narrowly doctrinal account of the Court's 1937 switch. While space does not permit setting out my objections in detail, it is important to point out that many reputable scholars have in effect taken the position that purely doctrinal explanations of the votes of Chief Justice Hughes and Justice Roberts in the various New Deal cases are implausible because they took inconsistent positions. Their positions were inconsistent with respect to their allegiance to broad constitutional values such as federalism, as set forth in pre- 1937 decisions. The most plausible explanation for their votes is therefore that they changed their minds about the relative importance of various constitutional values. The context for their change in view was: (1) the hostile, bipartisan reaction to Morehead v. Tipaldo, 298 U.S. 587 (1936), which held unconstitutional a New York statute mandating a minimum wage for women and minors (only relevant to Roberts); (2) FDR's overwhelming victory in the 1936 election; and (3) FDR's Court-packing plan (only relevant to some 1937 decsions). Cushman's tendentious distinction between "internal" or doctrinal explanations and "external" or political explanations means that he never comes to grips with the most persuasive version of the "external" account, one that is, in fact, an internal explanation to the extent that it focuses on the motives of Hughes and Roberts. See CUSHMAN, supra, at 4.
    • (1994) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.142 , pp. 1985
    • Friedman, R.D.1
  • 143
    • 84927455608 scopus 로고
    • The great depression, the new deal, and the American legal order
    • hereinafter Parrish, The Great Depression
    • This story has been told many times and lately a dispute has broken out over how the "switch" occurred. For contrasting views, compare BARRY CUSHMAN, RETHINKING THE NEW DEAL COURT: THE STRUCTURE OF A CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION (1998), and Richard D. Friedman, Switching Time and Other Thought Experiments: The Hughes Court and Constitutional Transformation, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1891 (1994), with WILLIAM E. LEUCHTENBURG, THE SUPREME COURT REBORN: THE CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION IN THE AGE OF ROOSEVELT (1995), and David A. Pepper, Against Legalism: Rebutting an Anachronistic Account of 1937, 82 MARQ. L. REV. 63 (1998). For other important discussions see MICHAEL E. PARRISH, ANXIOUS DECADES: AMERICA IN PROSPERITY AND DEPRESSION, 1920-1941, at 364-76 (1992); Michael Ariens, A Thrice-Told Tale, or Felix the Cat, 107 HARV. L. REV. 620 (1994); John W. Chambers, The Big Switch: Justice Roberts and the Minimum-Wage Cases, 10 LABOR HIST. 44 (1969); Richard D. Friedman, A Reaffirmation: The Authenticity of the Roberts Memorandum, or Felix the Non-Forger, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1985 (1994); Michael E. Parrish, The Great Depression, the New Deal, and the American Legal Order, 59 WASH. L. REV. 723 (1984) [hereinafter Parrish, The Great Depression]; Michael E. Parrish, The Hughes Court, the Great Depression, and the Historians, 40 HISTORIAN 286 (1978) [hereinafter Parrish, The Hughes Court]. have serious reservations about Cushman's narrowly doctrinal account of the Court's 1937 switch. While space does not permit setting out my objections in detail, it is important to point out that many reputable scholars have in effect taken the position that purely doctrinal explanations of the votes of Chief Justice Hughes and Justice Roberts in the various New Deal cases are implausible because they took inconsistent positions. Their positions were inconsistent with respect to their allegiance to broad constitutional values such as federalism, as set forth in pre- 1937 decisions. The most plausible explanation for their votes is therefore that they changed their minds about the relative importance of various constitutional values. The context for their change in view was: (1) the hostile, bipartisan reaction to Morehead v. Tipaldo, 298 U.S. 587 (1936), which held unconstitutional a New York statute mandating a minimum wage for women and minors (only relevant to Roberts); (2) FDR's overwhelming victory in the 1936 election; and (3) FDR's Court-packing plan (only relevant to some 1937 decsions). Cushman's tendentious distinction between "internal" or doctrinal explanations and "external" or political explanations means that he never comes to grips with the most persuasive version of the "external" account, one that is, in fact, an internal explanation to the extent that it focuses on the motives of Hughes and Roberts. See CUSHMAN, supra, at 4.
    • (1984) Wash. L. Rev. , vol.59 , pp. 723
    • Parrish, M.E.1
  • 144
    • 84977367647 scopus 로고
    • The Hughes Court, the great depression, and the historians
    • hereinafter Parrish, The Hughes Court
    • This story has been told many times and lately a dispute has broken out over how the "switch" occurred. For contrasting views, compare BARRY CUSHMAN, RETHINKING THE NEW DEAL COURT: THE STRUCTURE OF A CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION (1998), and Richard D. Friedman, Switching Time and Other Thought Experiments: The Hughes Court and Constitutional Transformation, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1891 (1994), with WILLIAM E. LEUCHTENBURG, THE SUPREME COURT REBORN: THE CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION IN THE AGE OF ROOSEVELT (1995), and David A. Pepper, Against Legalism: Rebutting an Anachronistic Account of 1937, 82 MARQ. L. REV. 63 (1998). For other important discussions see MICHAEL E. PARRISH, ANXIOUS DECADES: AMERICA IN PROSPERITY AND DEPRESSION, 1920-1941, at 364-76 (1992); Michael Ariens, A Thrice-Told Tale, or Felix the Cat, 107 HARV. L. REV. 620 (1994); John W. Chambers, The Big Switch: Justice Roberts and the Minimum-Wage Cases, 10 LABOR HIST. 44 (1969); Richard D. Friedman, A Reaffirmation: The Authenticity of the Roberts Memorandum, or Felix the Non-Forger, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1985 (1994); Michael E. Parrish, The Great Depression, the New Deal, and the American Legal Order, 59 WASH. L. REV. 723 (1984) [hereinafter Parrish, The Great Depression]; Michael E. Parrish, The Hughes Court, the Great Depression, and the Historians, 40 HISTORIAN 286 (1978) [hereinafter Parrish, The Hughes Court]. have serious reservations about Cushman's narrowly doctrinal account of the Court's 1937 switch. While space does not permit setting out my objections in detail, it is important to point out that many reputable scholars have in effect taken the position that purely doctrinal explanations of the votes of Chief Justice Hughes and Justice Roberts in the various New Deal cases are implausible because they took inconsistent positions. Their positions were inconsistent with respect to their allegiance to broad constitutional values such as federalism, as set forth in pre- 1937 decisions. The most plausible explanation for their votes is therefore that they changed their minds about the relative importance of various constitutional values. The context for their change in view was: (1) the hostile, bipartisan reaction to Morehead v. Tipaldo, 298 U.S. 587 (1936), which held unconstitutional a New York statute mandating a minimum wage for women and minors (only relevant to Roberts); (2) FDR's overwhelming victory in the 1936 election; and (3) FDR's Court-packing plan (only relevant to some 1937 decsions). Cushman's tendentious distinction between "internal" or doctrinal explanations and "external" or political explanations means that he never comes to grips with the most persuasive version of the "external" account, one that is, in fact, an internal explanation to the extent that it focuses on the motives of Hughes and Roberts. See CUSHMAN, supra, at 4.
    • (1978) Historian , vol.40 , pp. 286
    • Parrish, M.E.1
  • 145
    • 84862604221 scopus 로고
    • Morehead v. Tipaldo
    • This story has been told many times and lately a dispute has broken out over how the "switch" occurred. For contrasting views, compare BARRY CUSHMAN, RETHINKING THE NEW DEAL COURT: THE STRUCTURE OF A CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION (1998), and Richard D. Friedman, Switching Time and Other Thought Experiments: The Hughes Court and Constitutional Transformation, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1891 (1994), with WILLIAM E. LEUCHTENBURG, THE SUPREME COURT REBORN: THE CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION IN THE AGE OF ROOSEVELT (1995), and David A. Pepper, Against Legalism: Rebutting an Anachronistic Account of 1937, 82 MARQ. L. REV. 63 (1998). For other important discussions see MICHAEL E. PARRISH, ANXIOUS DECADES: AMERICA IN PROSPERITY AND DEPRESSION, 1920-1941, at 364-76 (1992); Michael Ariens, A Thrice-Told Tale, or Felix the Cat, 107 HARV. L. REV. 620 (1994); John W. Chambers, The Big Switch: Justice Roberts and the Minimum-Wage Cases, 10 LABOR HIST. 44 (1969); Richard D. Friedman, A Reaffirmation: The Authenticity of the Roberts Memorandum, or Felix the Non-Forger, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1985 (1994); Michael E. Parrish, The Great Depression, the New Deal, and the American Legal Order, 59 WASH. L. REV. 723 (1984) [hereinafter Parrish, The Great Depression]; Michael E. Parrish, The Hughes Court, the Great Depression, and the Historians, 40 HISTORIAN 286 (1978) [hereinafter Parrish, The Hughes Court]. have serious reservations about Cushman's narrowly doctrinal account of the Court's 1937 switch. While space does not permit setting out my objections in detail, it is important to point out that many reputable scholars have in effect taken the position that purely doctrinal explanations of the votes of Chief Justice Hughes and Justice Roberts in the various New Deal cases are implausible because they took inconsistent positions. Their positions were inconsistent with respect to their allegiance to broad constitutional values such as federalism, as set forth in pre-1937 decisions. The most plausible explanation for their votes is therefore that they changed their minds about the relative importance of various constitutional values. The context for their change in view was: (1) the hostile, bipartisan reaction to Morehead v. Tipaldo, 298 U.S. 587 (1936), which held unconstitutional a New York statute mandating a minimum wage for women and minors (only relevant to Roberts); (2) FDR's overwhelming victory in the 1936 election; and (3) FDR's Court-packing plan (only relevant to some 1937 decsions). Cushman's tendentious distinction between "internal" or doctrinal explanations and "external" or political explanations means that he never comes to grips with the most persuasive version of the "external" account, one that is, in fact, an internal explanation to the extent that it focuses on the motives of Hughes and Roberts. See CUSHMAN, supra, at 4.
    • (1936) U.S. , vol.298 , pp. 587
  • 146
    • 0043060824 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra, at 4
    • This story has been told many times and lately a dispute has broken out over how the "switch" occurred. For contrasting views, compare BARRY CUSHMAN, RETHINKING THE NEW DEAL COURT: THE STRUCTURE OF A CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION (1998), and Richard D. Friedman, Switching Time and Other Thought Experiments: The Hughes Court and Constitutional Transformation, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1891 (1994), with WILLIAM E. LEUCHTENBURG, THE SUPREME COURT REBORN: THE CONSTITUTIONAL REVOLUTION IN THE AGE OF ROOSEVELT (1995), and David A. Pepper, Against Legalism: Rebutting an Anachronistic Account of 1937, 82 MARQ. L. REV. 63 (1998). For other important discussions see MICHAEL E. PARRISH, ANXIOUS DECADES: AMERICA IN PROSPERITY AND DEPRESSION, 1920-1941, at 364-76 (1992); Michael Ariens, A Thrice-Told Tale, or Felix the Cat, 107 HARV. L. REV. 620 (1994); John W. Chambers, The Big Switch: Justice Roberts and the Minimum-Wage Cases, 10 LABOR HIST. 44 (1969); Richard D. Friedman, A Reaffirmation: The Authenticity of the Roberts Memorandum, or Felix the Non-Forger, 142 U. PA. L. REV. 1985 (1994); Michael E. Parrish, The Great Depression, the New Deal, and the American Legal Order, 59 WASH. L. REV. 723 (1984) [hereinafter Parrish, The Great Depression]; Michael E. Parrish, The Hughes Court, the Great Depression, and the Historians, 40 HISTORIAN 286 (1978) [hereinafter Parrish, The Hughes Court]. have serious reservations about Cushman's narrowly doctrinal account of the Court's 1937 switch. While space does not permit setting out my objections in detail, it is important to point out that many reputable scholars have in effect taken the position that purely doctrinal explanations of the votes of Chief Justice Hughes and Justice Roberts in the various New Deal cases are implausible because they took inconsistent positions. Their positions were inconsistent with respect to their allegiance to broad constitutional values such as federalism, as set forth in pre- 1937 decisions. The most plausible explanation for their votes is therefore that they changed their minds about the relative importance of various constitutional values. The context for their change in view was: (1) the hostile, bipartisan reaction to Morehead v. Tipaldo, 298 U.S. 587 (1936), which held unconstitutional a New York statute mandating a minimum wage for women and minors (only relevant to Roberts); (2) FDR's overwhelming victory in the 1936 election; and (3) FDR's Court-packing plan (only relevant to some 1937 decsions). Cushman's tendentious distinction between "internal" or doctrinal explanations and "external" or political explanations means that he never comes to grips with the most persuasive version of the "external" account, one that is, in fact, an internal explanation to the extent that it focuses on the motives of Hughes and Roberts. See CUSHMAN, supra, at 4.
    • Cushman1
  • 147
    • 0043060858 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • Cf. 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 286-89 (discussing NIRA's replacement of market capitalism with a corporatist structure).
    • Ackerman , vol.2 , pp. 286-289
  • 148
    • 0042059162 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 8, at 20
    • FINEGOLD AND SKOCPOL, supra note 8, at 20.
    • Finegold1    Skocpol2
  • 149
    • 84883284736 scopus 로고
    • Railroad Retirement Bd. v. Alton R.R. Co.
    • See Railroad Retirement Bd. v. Alton R.R. Co., 295 U.S. 330, 367-68 (1935); Butler, 297 U.S. at 63-64, 68-78; Carter Coal, 298 U.S. at 297-310.
    • (1935) U.S. , vol.295 , pp. 330
  • 150
    • 0042059131 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Butler
    • See Railroad Retirement Bd. v. Alton R.R. Co., 295 U.S. 330, 367-68 (1935); Butler, 297 U.S. at 63-64, 68-78; Carter Coal, 298 U.S. at 297-310.
    • U.S. , vol.297 , pp. 63-64
  • 151
    • 0042059129 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Carter coal
    • See Railroad Retirement Bd. v. Alton R.R. Co., 295 U.S. 330, 367-68 (1935); Butler, 297 U.S. at 63-64, 68-78; Carter Coal, 298 U.S. at 297-310.
    • U.S. , vol.298 , pp. 297-310
  • 152
    • 33645943220 scopus 로고
    • A.L.A. Schechter Poultry Corp. v. United States
    • In A.L.A. Schechter Poultry Corp. v. United States, 295 U.S. 495 (1935), for example, Chief Justice Hughes stated: In determining how far the federal government may go in controlling intrastate transactions upon the ground that they "affect" interstate commerce, there is a necessary and well-established distinction between direct and indirect effects. . . . If the commerce clause were construed to reach all enterprises and transactions which could be said to have an indirect effect upon interstate commerce, the federal authority would embrace practically all the activities of the people, and the authority of the state over its domestic concerns would exist only by sufferance of the federal government. . . . . The distinction between direct and indirect effects of intrastate commerce must be recognized as a fundamental one, essential to the maintenance of our constitutional system. Otherwise, as we have said, there would be virtually no limit to the federal power and for all practical purposes we should have a completely centralized government. Id. at 546, 548.
    • (1935) U.S. , vol.295 , pp. 495
  • 153
    • 0042559983 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In A.L.A. Schechter Poultry Corp. v. United States, 295 U.S. 495 (1935), for example, Chief Justice Hughes stated: In determining how far the federal government may go in controlling intrastate transactions upon the ground that they "affect" interstate commerce, there is a necessary and well-established distinction between direct and indirect effects. . . . If the commerce clause were construed to reach all enterprises and transactions which could be said to have an indirect effect upon interstate commerce, the federal authority would embrace practically all the activities of the people, and the authority of the state over its domestic concerns would exist only by sufferance of the federal government. . . . . The distinction between direct and indirect effects of intrastate commerce must be recognized as a fundamental one, essential to the maintenance of our constitutional system. Otherwise, as we have said, there would be virtually no limit to the federal power and for all practical purposes we should have a completely centralized government. Id. at 546, 548.
    • U.S. , pp. 546
  • 154
    • 33846381848 scopus 로고
    • 301 U.S. 1 (1937).
    • (1937) U.S. , vol.301 , pp. 1
  • 155
    • 0043060860 scopus 로고
    • 312 U.S. 657 (1941).
    • (1941) U.S. , vol.312 , pp. 657
  • 156
    • 33745243578 scopus 로고
    • 317 U.S. 111 (1942).
    • (1942) U.S. , vol.317 , pp. 111
  • 157
    • 0041557916 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at 81-85
    • Since I have provided more detail on the presidency and federalism in my book, my discussion here is brief. I should note, however, that the presidency was affected just as much by the changes that occurred in the Cold War as the developments during FDR's terms in office. See GRIFFIN, supra note 1, at 81-85.
    • Griffin1
  • 158
    • 0042059163 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 86, at 1-34
    • See LEUCHTENBURG, supra note 86, at 1-34; SIDNEY M. MILKIS, THE PRESIDENT AND THE PARTIES: THE TRANSFORMATION OF THE AMERICAN PARTY SYSTEM SINCE THE NEW DEAL 150-51 (1993).
    • Leuchtenburg1
  • 160
    • 0042560025 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 86, internal citations omitted
    • See Parrish, The Great Depression, supra note 86, at 727 (internal citations omitted).
    • The Great Depression , pp. 727
    • Parrish1
  • 161
    • 0347873667 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. For a recent treatment from a doctrinal perspective, see Stephen Gardbaum, New Deal Constitutionalism and the Unshackling of the States, 64 U. CHI. L. REV. 483 (1997). Gardbaum's analysis is useful to the extent that he reminds us that the end of the "no go zone" in due process jurisprudence necessarily meant that the states came out of the New Deal with greatly expanded regulatory powers. But Gardbaum's article also shows the inherent limits of doctrinal history: He never assumes an institutionalist perspective, that is, he never tells us what the states did with their new powers. As I suggest in the text, at least with respect to unemployment and poor relief, they were not able to do very much.
    • The Great Depression
  • 162
    • 0347873667 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New deal constitutionalism and the unshackling of the states
    • See id. For a recent treatment from a doctrinal perspective, see Stephen Gardbaum, New Deal Constitutionalism and the Unshackling of the States, 64 U. CHI. L. REV. 483 (1997). Gardbaum's analysis is useful to the extent that he reminds us that the end of the "no go zone" in due process jurisprudence necessarily meant that the states came out of the New Deal with greatly expanded regulatory powers. But Gardbaum's article also shows the inherent limits of doctrinal history: He never assumes an institutionalist perspective, that is, he never tells us what the states did with their new powers. As I suggest in the text, at least with respect to unemployment and poor relief, they were not able to do very much.
    • (1997) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.64 , pp. 483
    • Gardbaum, S.1
  • 164
    • 0042560026 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at 41-42
    • See GRIFFIN, supra note 1, at 41-42.
    • Griffin1
  • 165
    • 0041557914 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 86, at 6
    • This list of assumptions is an extremely compressed summary of recent historical work on the constitutional ideology that prevailed between the Civil War and the New Deal. See, e.g., CUSHMAN, supra note 86, at 6; HOWARD GILLMAN, THE CONSTITUTION BESIEGED: THE RISE AND DEMISE OF LOCHNER ERA POLICE POWERS JURISPRUDENCE (1993); Benedict, supra note 54; see also JAMES W. ELY, JR., THE CHIEF JUSTICESHIP OF MELVILLE W. FULLER, 1888-1910 (1995) ; OWEN M. FISS, TROUBLED BEGINNINGS OF THE MODERN STATE, 1888-1910 (1993); MORTON J. HORWITZ, THE TRANSFORMATION OF AMERICAN LAW, 1870-1960 (1992); HERBERT HOVENKAMP, ENTERPRISE AND AMERICAN LAW 1836-1937 (1991); WILLIAM E. NELSON, THE ROOTS OF AMERICAN BUREAUCRACY, 1830-1900 (1982); WILLIAM M. WIECEK, THE LOST WORLD OF CLASSICAL LEGAL THOUGHT (1998); Michael Les Benedict, Laissez-Faire and Liberty: A Re-Evaluation of the Meaning and Origins of Laissez-Faire Constitutionalism, 3 LEGAL HIST. REV. 293 (1985); Stephen A. Siegel, Lochner Era Jurisprudence and the American Constitutional Tradition, 70 N.C. L. REV. 1 (1991).
    • Cushman1
  • 166
    • 0007338440 scopus 로고
    • This list of assumptions is an extremely compressed summary of recent historical work on the constitutional ideology that prevailed between the Civil War and the New Deal. See, e.g., CUSHMAN, supra note 86, at 6; HOWARD GILLMAN, THE CONSTITUTION BESIEGED: THE RISE AND DEMISE OF LOCHNER ERA POLICE POWERS JURISPRUDENCE (1993); Benedict, supra note 54; see also JAMES W. ELY, JR., THE CHIEF JUSTICESHIP OF MELVILLE W. FULLER, 1888-1910 (1995) ; OWEN M. FISS, TROUBLED BEGINNINGS OF THE MODERN STATE, 1888-1910 (1993); MORTON J. HORWITZ, THE TRANSFORMATION OF AMERICAN LAW, 1870-1960 (1992); HERBERT HOVENKAMP, ENTERPRISE AND AMERICAN LAW 1836-1937 (1991); WILLIAM E. NELSON, THE ROOTS OF AMERICAN BUREAUCRACY, 1830-1900 (1982); WILLIAM M. WIECEK, THE LOST WORLD OF CLASSICAL LEGAL THOUGHT (1998); Michael Les Benedict, Laissez-Faire and Liberty: A Re-Evaluation of the Meaning and Origins of Laissez-Faire Constitutionalism, 3 LEGAL HIST. REV. 293 (1985); Stephen A. Siegel, Lochner Era Jurisprudence and the American Constitutional Tradition, 70 N.C. L. REV. 1 (1991).
    • (1993) The Constitution Besieged: The Rise and Demise of Lochner Era Police Powers Jurisprudence
    • Gillman, H.1
  • 167
    • 0043060859 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 54
    • This list of assumptions is an extremely compressed summary of recent historical work on the constitutional ideology that prevailed between the Civil War and the New Deal. See, e.g., CUSHMAN, supra note 86, at 6; HOWARD GILLMAN, THE CONSTITUTION BESIEGED: THE RISE AND DEMISE OF LOCHNER ERA POLICE POWERS JURISPRUDENCE (1993); Benedict, supra note 54; see also JAMES W. ELY, JR., THE CHIEF JUSTICESHIP OF MELVILLE W. FULLER, 1888-1910 (1995) ; OWEN M. FISS, TROUBLED BEGINNINGS OF THE MODERN STATE, 1888-1910 (1993); MORTON J. HORWITZ, THE TRANSFORMATION OF AMERICAN LAW, 1870-1960 (1992); HERBERT HOVENKAMP, ENTERPRISE AND AMERICAN LAW 1836-1937 (1991); WILLIAM E. NELSON, THE ROOTS OF AMERICAN BUREAUCRACY, 1830-1900 (1982); WILLIAM M. WIECEK, THE LOST WORLD OF CLASSICAL LEGAL THOUGHT (1998); Michael Les Benedict, Laissez-Faire and Liberty: A Re-Evaluation of the Meaning and Origins of Laissez-Faire Constitutionalism, 3 LEGAL HIST. REV. 293 (1985); Stephen A. Siegel, Lochner Era Jurisprudence and the American Constitutional Tradition, 70 N.C. L. REV. 1 (1991).
    • Benedict1
  • 168
    • 0002184077 scopus 로고
    • This list of assumptions is an extremely compressed summary of recent historical work on the constitutional ideology that prevailed between the Civil War and the New Deal. See, e.g., CUSHMAN, supra note 86, at 6; HOWARD GILLMAN, THE CONSTITUTION BESIEGED: THE RISE AND DEMISE OF LOCHNER ERA POLICE POWERS JURISPRUDENCE (1993); Benedict, supra note 54; see also JAMES W. ELY, JR., THE CHIEF JUSTICESHIP OF MELVILLE W. FULLER, 1888-1910 (1995) ; OWEN M. FISS, TROUBLED BEGINNINGS OF THE MODERN STATE, 1888-1910 (1993); MORTON J. HORWITZ, THE TRANSFORMATION OF AMERICAN LAW, 1870-1960 (1992); HERBERT HOVENKAMP, ENTERPRISE AND AMERICAN LAW 1836-1937 (1991); WILLIAM E. NELSON, THE ROOTS OF AMERICAN BUREAUCRACY, 1830-1900 (1982); WILLIAM M. WIECEK, THE LOST WORLD OF CLASSICAL LEGAL THOUGHT (1998); Michael Les Benedict, Laissez-Faire and Liberty: A Re-Evaluation of the Meaning and Origins of Laissez-Faire Constitutionalism, 3 LEGAL HIST. REV. 293 (1985); Stephen A. Siegel, Lochner Era Jurisprudence and the American Constitutional Tradition, 70 N.C. L. REV. 1 (1991).
    • (1995) The Chief Justiceship of Melville W. Fuller, 1888-1910
    • Ely J.W., Jr.1
  • 169
    • 0011532163 scopus 로고
    • This list of assumptions is an extremely compressed summary of recent historical work on the constitutional ideology that prevailed between the Civil War and the New Deal. See, e.g., CUSHMAN, supra note 86, at 6; HOWARD GILLMAN, THE CONSTITUTION BESIEGED: THE RISE AND DEMISE OF LOCHNER ERA POLICE POWERS JURISPRUDENCE (1993); Benedict, supra note 54; see also JAMES W. ELY, JR., THE CHIEF JUSTICESHIP OF MELVILLE W. FULLER, 1888-1910 (1995) ; OWEN M. FISS, TROUBLED BEGINNINGS OF THE MODERN STATE, 1888-1910 (1993); MORTON J. HORWITZ, THE TRANSFORMATION OF AMERICAN LAW, 1870-1960 (1992); HERBERT HOVENKAMP, ENTERPRISE AND AMERICAN LAW 1836-1937 (1991); WILLIAM E. NELSON, THE ROOTS OF AMERICAN BUREAUCRACY, 1830-1900 (1982); WILLIAM M. WIECEK, THE LOST WORLD OF CLASSICAL LEGAL THOUGHT (1998); Michael Les Benedict, Laissez-Faire and Liberty: A Re-Evaluation of the Meaning and Origins of Laissez-Faire Constitutionalism, 3 LEGAL HIST. REV. 293 (1985); Stephen A. Siegel, Lochner Era Jurisprudence and the American Constitutional Tradition, 70 N.C. L. REV. 1 (1991).
    • (1993) Troubled Beginnings of the Modern State, 1888-1910
    • Fiss, O.M.1
  • 170
    • 0003476039 scopus 로고
    • This list of assumptions is an extremely compressed summary of recent historical work on the constitutional ideology that prevailed between the Civil War and the New Deal. See, e.g., CUSHMAN, supra note 86, at 6; HOWARD GILLMAN, THE CONSTITUTION BESIEGED: THE RISE AND DEMISE OF LOCHNER ERA POLICE POWERS JURISPRUDENCE (1993); Benedict, supra note 54; see also JAMES W. ELY, JR., THE CHIEF JUSTICESHIP OF MELVILLE W. FULLER, 1888-1910 (1995) ; OWEN M. FISS, TROUBLED BEGINNINGS OF THE MODERN STATE, 1888-1910 (1993); MORTON J. HORWITZ, THE TRANSFORMATION OF AMERICAN LAW, 1870-1960 (1992); HERBERT HOVENKAMP, ENTERPRISE AND AMERICAN LAW 1836-1937 (1991); WILLIAM E. NELSON, THE ROOTS OF AMERICAN BUREAUCRACY, 1830-1900 (1982); WILLIAM M. WIECEK, THE LOST WORLD OF CLASSICAL LEGAL THOUGHT (1998); Michael Les Benedict, Laissez-Faire and Liberty: A Re-Evaluation of the Meaning and Origins of Laissez-Faire Constitutionalism, 3 LEGAL HIST. REV. 293 (1985); Stephen A. Siegel, Lochner Era Jurisprudence and the American Constitutional Tradition, 70 N.C. L. REV. 1 (1991).
    • (1992) The Transformation of American Law, 1870-1960
    • Horwitz, M.J.1
  • 171
    • 0003759668 scopus 로고
    • This list of assumptions is an extremely compressed summary of recent historical work on the constitutional ideology that prevailed between the Civil War and the New Deal. See, e.g., CUSHMAN, supra note 86, at 6; HOWARD GILLMAN, THE CONSTITUTION BESIEGED: THE RISE AND DEMISE OF LOCHNER ERA POLICE POWERS JURISPRUDENCE (1993); Benedict, supra note 54; see also JAMES W. ELY, JR., THE CHIEF JUSTICESHIP OF MELVILLE W. FULLER, 1888-1910 (1995) ; OWEN M. FISS, TROUBLED BEGINNINGS OF THE MODERN STATE, 1888-1910 (1993); MORTON J. HORWITZ, THE TRANSFORMATION OF AMERICAN LAW, 1870-1960 (1992); HERBERT HOVENKAMP, ENTERPRISE AND AMERICAN LAW 1836-1937 (1991); WILLIAM E. NELSON, THE ROOTS OF AMERICAN BUREAUCRACY, 1830-1900 (1982); WILLIAM M. WIECEK, THE LOST WORLD OF CLASSICAL LEGAL THOUGHT (1998); Michael Les Benedict, Laissez-Faire and Liberty: A Re-Evaluation of the Meaning and Origins of Laissez-Faire Constitutionalism, 3 LEGAL HIST. REV. 293 (1985); Stephen A. Siegel, Lochner Era Jurisprudence and the American Constitutional Tradition, 70 N.C. L. REV. 1 (1991).
    • (1991) Enterprise and American Law 1836-1937
    • Hovenkamp, H.1
  • 172
    • 0009851062 scopus 로고
    • This list of assumptions is an extremely compressed summary of recent historical work on the constitutional ideology that prevailed between the Civil War and the New Deal. See, e.g., CUSHMAN, supra note 86, at 6; HOWARD GILLMAN, THE CONSTITUTION BESIEGED: THE RISE AND DEMISE OF LOCHNER ERA POLICE POWERS JURISPRUDENCE (1993); Benedict, supra note 54; see also JAMES W. ELY, JR., THE CHIEF JUSTICESHIP OF MELVILLE W. FULLER, 1888-1910 (1995) ; OWEN M. FISS, TROUBLED BEGINNINGS OF THE MODERN STATE, 1888-1910 (1993); MORTON J. HORWITZ, THE TRANSFORMATION OF AMERICAN LAW, 1870-1960 (1992); HERBERT HOVENKAMP, ENTERPRISE AND AMERICAN LAW 1836-1937 (1991); WILLIAM E. NELSON, THE ROOTS OF AMERICAN BUREAUCRACY, 1830-1900 (1982); WILLIAM M. WIECEK, THE LOST WORLD OF CLASSICAL LEGAL THOUGHT (1998); Michael Les Benedict, Laissez-Faire and Liberty: A Re-Evaluation of the Meaning and Origins of Laissez-Faire Constitutionalism, 3 LEGAL HIST. REV. 293 (1985); Stephen A. Siegel, Lochner Era Jurisprudence and the American Constitutional Tradition, 70 N.C. L. REV. 1 (1991).
    • (1982) The Roots of American Bureaucracy, 1830-1900
    • Nelson, W.E.1
  • 173
    • 0040874708 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This list of assumptions is an extremely compressed summary of recent historical work on the constitutional ideology that prevailed between the Civil War and the New Deal. See, e.g., CUSHMAN, supra note 86, at 6; HOWARD GILLMAN, THE CONSTITUTION BESIEGED: THE RISE AND DEMISE OF LOCHNER ERA POLICE POWERS JURISPRUDENCE (1993); Benedict, supra note 54; see also JAMES W. ELY, JR., THE CHIEF JUSTICESHIP OF MELVILLE W. FULLER, 1888-1910 (1995) ; OWEN M. FISS, TROUBLED BEGINNINGS OF THE MODERN STATE, 1888-1910 (1993); MORTON J. HORWITZ, THE TRANSFORMATION OF AMERICAN LAW, 1870-1960 (1992); HERBERT HOVENKAMP, ENTERPRISE AND AMERICAN LAW 1836-1937 (1991); WILLIAM E. NELSON, THE ROOTS OF AMERICAN BUREAUCRACY, 1830-1900 (1982); WILLIAM M. WIECEK, THE LOST WORLD OF CLASSICAL LEGAL THOUGHT (1998); Michael Les Benedict, Laissez-Faire and Liberty: A Re-Evaluation of the Meaning and Origins of Laissez-Faire Constitutionalism, 3 LEGAL HIST. REV. 293 (1985); Stephen A. Siegel, Lochner Era Jurisprudence and the American Constitutional Tradition, 70 N.C. L. REV. 1 (1991).
    • (1998) The Lost World of Classical Legal Thought
    • Wiecek, W.M.1
  • 174
    • 0011531909 scopus 로고
    • Laissez-Faire and liberty: A re-evaluation of the meaning and origins of Laissez-Faire constitutionalism
    • This list of assumptions is an extremely compressed summary of recent historical work on the constitutional ideology that prevailed between the Civil War and the New Deal. See, e.g., CUSHMAN, supra note 86, at 6; HOWARD GILLMAN, THE CONSTITUTION BESIEGED: THE RISE AND DEMISE OF LOCHNER ERA POLICE POWERS JURISPRUDENCE (1993); Benedict, supra note 54; see also JAMES W. ELY, JR., THE CHIEF JUSTICESHIP OF MELVILLE W. FULLER, 1888-1910 (1995) ; OWEN M. FISS, TROUBLED BEGINNINGS OF THE MODERN STATE, 1888-1910 (1993); MORTON J. HORWITZ, THE TRANSFORMATION OF AMERICAN LAW, 1870-1960 (1992); HERBERT HOVENKAMP, ENTERPRISE AND AMERICAN LAW 1836-1937 (1991); WILLIAM E. NELSON, THE ROOTS OF AMERICAN BUREAUCRACY, 1830-1900 (1982); WILLIAM M. WIECEK, THE LOST WORLD OF CLASSICAL LEGAL THOUGHT (1998); Michael Les Benedict, Laissez-Faire and Liberty: A Re-Evaluation of the Meaning and Origins of Laissez-Faire Constitutionalism, 3 LEGAL HIST. REV. 293 (1985); Stephen A. Siegel, Lochner Era Jurisprudence and the American Constitutional Tradition, 70 N.C. L. REV. 1 (1991).
    • (1985) Legal Hist. Rev. , vol.3 , pp. 293
    • Les Benedict, M.1
  • 175
    • 0039465021 scopus 로고
    • Lochner Era jurisprudence and the American constitutional tradition
    • This list of assumptions is an extremely compressed summary of recent historical work on the constitutional ideology that prevailed between the Civil War and the New Deal. See, e.g., CUSHMAN, supra note 86, at 6; HOWARD GILLMAN, THE CONSTITUTION BESIEGED: THE RISE AND DEMISE OF LOCHNER ERA POLICE POWERS JURISPRUDENCE (1993); Benedict, supra note 54; see also JAMES W. ELY, JR., THE CHIEF JUSTICESHIP OF MELVILLE W. FULLER, 1888-1910 (1995) ; OWEN M. FISS, TROUBLED BEGINNINGS OF THE MODERN STATE, 1888-1910 (1993); MORTON J. HORWITZ, THE TRANSFORMATION OF AMERICAN LAW, 1870-1960 (1992); HERBERT HOVENKAMP, ENTERPRISE AND AMERICAN LAW 1836-1937 (1991); WILLIAM E. NELSON, THE ROOTS OF AMERICAN BUREAUCRACY, 1830-1900 (1982); WILLIAM M. WIECEK, THE LOST WORLD OF CLASSICAL LEGAL THOUGHT (1998); Michael Les Benedict, Laissez-Faire and Liberty: A Re-Evaluation of the Meaning and Origins of Laissez-Faire Constitutionalism, 3 LEGAL HIST. REV. 293 (1985); Stephen A. Siegel, Lochner Era Jurisprudence and the American Constitutional Tradition, 70 N.C. L. REV. 1 (1991).
    • (1991) N.C. L. Rev. , vol.70 , pp. 1
    • Siegel, S.A.1
  • 176
    • 0041557912 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 100
    • See, e.g., GILLMAN, supra note 100.
    • Gillman1
  • 177
    • 0042560023 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 100, at 124-26
    • See, e.g., WIECEK, supra note 100, at 124-26.
    • Wiecek1
  • 178
    • 0042560022 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 132
    • See id. at 132.
  • 179
    • 0043060855 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 54, at 41-42 Id. at 42
    • See Benedict, supra note 54, at 41-42. This is the doctrine of "dual federalism" or "states' rights." Benedict comments that "[t]hose who advocated broad expansion of the national role from the Progressive to the New Deal eras. . . argued that this doctrine of dual federalism had subverted the nationalistic principles expounded by the Marshall Court. But in reality, most Americans had accepted dual federalism as implicit in those principles." Id. at 42.
    • Benedict1
  • 180
    • 0043060856 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 25, at 92-93
    • Peter Irons notes, for example, that some NRA lawyers found even the strong restorationist argument advanced by Robert Stern to be too timid. See IRONS, supra note 25, at 92-93.
    • Irons1
  • 181
    • 0031319994 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The collapse of constitutional originalism and the rise of the notion of the 'Living Constitution' in the course of American state-building
    • See, e.g., Howard Gillman, The Collapse of Constitutional Originalism and the Rise of the Notion of the 'Living Constitution' in the Course of American State-Building, 11 STUD. AM. POL. DEV. 191 (1997); G. Edward White, The "Constitutional Revolution" as a Crisis in Adaptivity, 48 HASTINGS L.J. 867 (1997).
    • (1997) Stud. Am. Pol. Dev. , vol.11 , pp. 191
    • Gillman, H.1
  • 182
    • 0346880120 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The "Constitutional Revolution" as a crisis in adaptivity
    • See, e.g., Howard Gillman, The Collapse of Constitutional Originalism and the Rise of the Notion of the 'Living Constitution' in the Course of American State-Building, 11 STUD. AM. POL. DEV. 191 (1997); G. Edward White, The "Constitutional Revolution" as a Crisis in Adaptivity, 48 HASTINGS L.J. 867 (1997).
    • (1997) Hastings L.J. , vol.48 , pp. 867
    • White, G.E.1
  • 183
    • 0042560024 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 25, at 52-54, 93
    • See IRONS, supra note 25, at 52-54, 93.
    • Irons1
  • 184
    • 0041557910 scopus 로고
    • "A concert of action, based on a fair and just concert of interests," address at Jefferson Day Dinner, St. Paul, Minn. (April 18, 1932)
    • See Franklin D. Roosevelt, "A Concert of Action, Based on a Fair and Just Concert of Interests," Address at Jefferson Day Dinner, St. Paul, Minn. (April 18, 1932), in 1 THE PUBLIC PAPERS AND ADDRESSES OF FRANKLIN D. ROOSEVELT 627, 631 (1938).
    • (1938) The Public Papers and Addresses of Franklin D. Roosevelt , vol.1 , pp. 627
    • Roosevelt, F.D.1
  • 188
  • 189
    • 0043060852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 86, at 35-75
    • See BARRY D. KARL, THE UNEASY STATE: THE UNITED STATES FROM 1915 TO 1945, at 119-21 (1983); LEUCHTENBURG, supra note 86, at 35-75; Michal R. Belknap, The New Deal and the Emergency Powers Doctrine, 62 TEX. L. REV. 67 (1983).
    • Leuchtenburg1
  • 190
    • 84926273288 scopus 로고
    • The new deal and the emergency powers doctrine
    • See BARRY D. KARL, THE UNEASY STATE: THE UNITED STATES FROM 1915 TO 1945, at 119-21 (1983); LEUCHTENBURG, supra note 86, at 35-75; Michal R. Belknap, The New Deal and the Emergency Powers Doctrine, 62 TEX. L. REV. 67 (1983).
    • (1983) Tex. L. Rev. , vol.62 , pp. 67
    • Belknap, M.R.1
  • 191
    • 0042059160 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 54
    • In the Civil War, it was the doctrine of state sovereignty and its corollaries of interposition, nullification, and secession that were discredited. See Benedict, supra note 54.
    • Benedict1
  • 192
    • 0043060853 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at 81-85
    • See GRIFFIN, supra note 1, at 81-85; KARL, supra note 112.
    • Griffin1
  • 193
    • 0042559989 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 112
    • See GRIFFIN, supra note 1, at 81-85; KARL, supra note 112.
    • Karl1
  • 194
    • 0042059132 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Roosevelt did say in his inaugural address that the Constitution was adequate to meet the crisis. This remark was made, however, within the framework provided by the wartime analogy, which should have been unnecessary had Roosevelt really accepted some version of restorationism.
  • 195
    • 0041557875 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 12
    • See, e.g., Fried, supra note 12; Tribe, supra note 12.
    • Fried1
  • 196
    • 0042559988 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 12
    • See, e.g., Fried, supra note 12; Tribe, supra note 12.
    • Tribe1
  • 197
    • 0042059134 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 100, at 201-02
    • See GILLMAN, supra note 100, at 201-02.
    • Gillman1
  • 198
    • 0042560019 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 76, at 916-24
    • But see Kramer, supra note 76, at 916-24.
    • Kramer1
  • 199
    • 0042059161 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 112, at 119
    • As Barry Karl notes. [T]he mechanisms for giving the federal government control over a centralized, nationalized industrial system simply did not exist. A skilled federal bureaucracy was not available, and, even had it been, it is doubtful that a managerial army would have been acceptable to most Americans, accustomed as they were to looking on active government as a threat. KARL, supra note 112, at 119; see also GRIFFIN, supra note 1, at 80-81 (noting that Congress had long been reluctant to give up control over the federal bureaucracy).
    • Karl1
  • 200
    • 0043060854 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at 80-81
    • As Barry Karl notes. [T]he mechanisms for giving the federal government control over a centralized, nationalized industrial system simply did not exist. A skilled federal bureaucracy was not available, and, even had it been, it is doubtful that a managerial army would have been acceptable to most Americans, accustomed as they were to looking on active government as a threat. KARL, supra note 112, at 119; see also GRIFFIN, supra note 1, at 80-81 (noting that Congress had long been reluctant to give up control over the federal bureaucracy).
    • Griffin1
  • 201
    • 0042059159 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 8, at 58-59
    • Finegold and Skocpol argue that in a few particular areas, such as agriculture, there was substantial capacity to administer the programs of the New Deal. See FINEGOLD & SKOCPOL, supra note 8, at 58-59. However, in general, Finegold and Skocpol agree with the majority of scholars that the U.S. national state was weak prior to the New Deal. See id. at 53-57.
    • Finegold1    Skocpol2
  • 202
    • 0041557908 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 53-57
    • Finegold and Skocpol argue that in a few particular areas, such as agriculture, there was substantial capacity to administer the programs of the New Deal. See FINEGOLD & SKOCPOL, supra note 8, at 58-59. However, in general, Finegold and Skocpol agree with the majority of scholars that the U.S. national state was weak prior to the New Deal. See id. at 53-57.
  • 203
    • 0042560011 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at 26-58
    • In this Section, I summarize the theory of constitutional change that is presented in much greater detail in GRIFFIN, supra note 1, at 26-58.
    • Griffin1
  • 204
    • 0041557909 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at 81-87, 194-201
    • See GRIFFIN, supra note 1, at 81-87, 194-201.
    • Griffin1
  • 205
    • 31544470175 scopus 로고
    • Marbury v. Madison
    • See Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137 (1803).
    • (1803) U.S. (1 Cranch) , vol.5 , pp. 137
  • 207
    • 84972487467 scopus 로고
    • The nonmajoritarian difficulty: Legislative deference to the judiciary
    • The exception, of course, is in the area of civil liberties and civil rights. Even here, however, most of the Court's jurisprudence concerned actions of the state governments, not the national government. Furthermore, in the new democratic context produced by the New Deal, it is a mistake to say simply that the Court responded by increasing its power to oversee the other branches in the area of rights. The question should rather be posed as follows: Why was it in the interest of the national state for the Court to handle these kinds of issues? For an interesting discussion, see Mark A. Graber, The Nonmajoritarian Difficulty: Legislative Deference to the Judiciary, 7 STUD. AM. POL. DEV. 35 (1993).
    • (1993) Stud. Am. Pol. Dev. , vol.7 , pp. 35
    • Graber, M.A.1
  • 208
    • 0041557874 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • See the brief remarks to this effect in Lessig, Fidelity, supra note 1, at 1268.
    • Fidelity , pp. 1268
    • Lessig1
  • 209
    • 0042560016 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hereinafter, just "rules."
    • Hereinafter, just "rules."
  • 210
    • 0003496214 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This may appear to be an implausible conclusion, given that I have dealt only with restorationism. But restorationism is the theory that results from the most common modes of constitutional interpretation: appeals to text and intent. The other major approach to constitutional interpretation focuses on the abstract character of the text. See, e.g., RONALD DWORKIN, FREEDOM'S LAW: THE MORAL READING OF THE AMERICAN CONSTITUTION (1996). While Dworkin has not discussed the legitimacy of the New Deal, Lawrence Lessig has presented a Dworkin-like theory that attempts to justify the New Deal. I criticize Lessig's theory infra note 182.
    • (1996) Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 211
    • 0043060828 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 76, at 915-17
    • See Kramer, supra note 76, at 915-17; Sherry, supra note 17, at 923-28.
    • Kramer1
  • 212
    • 0042059135 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 17, at 923-28
    • See Kramer, supra note 76, at 915-17; Sherry, supra note 17, at 923-28.
    • Sherry1
  • 213
    • 0042560017 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • See 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 58-130.
    • Ackerman , vol.1 , pp. 58-130
  • 214
    • 0041557924 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 1 id. at 16-33. Ackerman's historicism of course includes not only his treatment of Lochner, as I note below, but his rejection of restorationism. Unfortunately, Ackerman's critics have largely missed these points, especially the last. This is shown by two common criticisms of Ackerman's first volume. One, advanced by Terrance Sandalow and others, was that Ackerman was trying to rehabilitate Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905), one of the most criticized decisions of what Ackerman calls the "Middle Republic." To conventional scholars, this was heresy. See, e.g., Sandalow, supra note 17, at 333- 34. From their point of view, Lochner was wrong at the moment it was decided and there is no reasonable contemporary justification for the judicial philosophy that it represented. Ackerman, however, stated quite clearly that he wanted legal scholars to view Lochner in a "legally detached way," which is to say from an historicist point of view. 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 66. Ackerman was trying to put Lochner in context, an Ackermanian context to be sure, but an historical context nonetheless. See 1 id. at 58-67, 99-103. From this perspective, it is pointless to condemn Lochner as wrong (or praise it as right). The task is to understand how the result and reasoning in Lochner was plausible within the context of its own time. A second common criticism is that Ackerman's theory is difficult to implement because it gives judges the role of deciding when constitutional moments have occurred. See, e.g., Posner, supra note 17, at 34. Not only does this criticism misunderstand completely the thrust of Ackerman's theory, it demonstrates unwittingly the kind of Court-centered focus Ackerman labors to correct. Constitutional moments are the kind of events about which everyone tends to agree. Everyone recognizes that something has happened. The moment creates a new constitutional reality, as it were, and there is no real possibility of the Court doing anything else but ratifying it.
    • Ackerman , vol.1 , pp. 16-33
  • 215
    • 32144462476 scopus 로고
    • Lochner v. New York
    • See 1 id. at 16-33. Ackerman's historicism of course includes not only his treatment of Lochner, as I note below, but his rejection of restorationism. Unfortunately, Ackerman's critics have largely missed these points, especially the last. This is shown by two common criticisms of Ackerman's first volume. One, advanced by Terrance Sandalow and others, was that Ackerman was trying to rehabilitate Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905), one of the most criticized decisions of what Ackerman calls the "Middle Republic." To conventional scholars, this was heresy. See, e.g., Sandalow, supra note 17, at 333- 34. From their point of view, Lochner was wrong at the moment it was decided and there is no reasonable contemporary justification for the judicial philosophy that it represented. Ackerman, however, stated quite clearly that he wanted legal scholars to view Lochner in a "legally detached way," which is to say from an historicist point of view. 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 66. Ackerman was trying to put Lochner in context, an Ackermanian context to be sure, but an historical context nonetheless. See 1 id. at 58-67, 99-103. From this perspective, it is pointless to condemn Lochner as wrong (or praise it as right). The task is to understand how the result and reasoning in Lochner was plausible within the context of its own time. A second common criticism is that Ackerman's theory is difficult to implement because it gives judges the role of deciding when constitutional moments have occurred. See, e.g., Posner, supra note 17, at 34. Not only does this criticism misunderstand completely the thrust of Ackerman's theory, it demonstrates unwittingly the kind of Court-centered focus Ackerman labors to correct. Constitutional moments are the kind of events about which everyone tends to agree. Everyone recognizes that something has happened. The moment creates a new constitutional reality, as it were, and there is no real possibility of the Court doing anything else but ratifying it.
    • (1905) U.S. , vol.198 , pp. 45
  • 216
    • 0042560014 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 17, at 333-34
    • See 1 id. at 16-33. Ackerman's historicism of course includes not only his treatment of Lochner, as I note below, but his rejection of restorationism. Unfortunately, Ackerman's critics have largely missed these points, especially the last. This is shown by two common criticisms of Ackerman's first volume. One, advanced by Terrance Sandalow and others, was that Ackerman was trying to rehabilitate Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905), one of the most criticized decisions of what Ackerman calls the "Middle Republic." To conventional scholars, this was heresy. See, e.g., Sandalow, supra note 17, at 333-34. From their point of view, Lochner was wrong at the moment it was decided and there is no reasonable contemporary justification for the judicial
    • Sandalow1
  • 217
    • 0041557906 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • See 1 id. at 16-33. Ackerman's historicism of course includes not only his treatment of Lochner, as I note below, but his rejection of restorationism. Unfortunately, Ackerman's critics have largely missed these points, especially the last. This is shown by two common criticisms of Ackerman's first volume. One, advanced by Terrance Sandalow and others, was that Ackerman was trying to rehabilitate Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905), one of the most criticized decisions of what Ackerman calls the "Middle Republic." To conventional scholars, this was heresy. See, e.g., Sandalow, supra note 17, at 333- 34. From their point of view, Lochner was wrong at the moment it was decided and there is no reasonable contemporary justification for the judicial philosophy that it represented. Ackerman, however, stated quite clearly that he wanted legal scholars to view Lochner in a "legally detached way," which is to say from an historicist point of view. 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 66. Ackerman was trying to put Lochner in context, an Ackermanian context to be sure, but an historical context nonetheless. See 1 id. at 58-67, 99-103. From this perspective, it is pointless to condemn Lochner as wrong (or praise it as right). The task is to understand how the result and reasoning in Lochner was plausible within the context of its own time. A second common criticism is that Ackerman's theory is difficult to implement because it gives judges the role of deciding when constitutional moments have occurred. See, e.g., Posner, supra note 17, at 34. Not only does this criticism misunderstand completely the thrust of Ackerman's theory, it demonstrates unwittingly the kind of Court-centered focus Ackerman labors to correct. Constitutional moments are the kind of events about which everyone tends to agree. Everyone recognizes that something has happened. The moment creates a new constitutional reality, as it were, and there is no real possibility of the Court doing anything else but ratifying it.
    • Ackerman , vol.1 , pp. 66
  • 218
    • 0042059136 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 1 id. at 16-33. Ackerman's historicism of course includes not only his treatment of Lochner, as I note below, but his rejection of restorationism. Unfortunately, Ackerman's critics have largely missed these points, especially the last. This is shown by two common criticisms of Ackerman's first volume. One, advanced by Terrance Sandalow and others, was that Ackerman was trying to rehabilitate Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905), one of the most criticized decisions of what Ackerman calls the "Middle Republic." To conventional scholars, this was heresy. See, e.g., Sandalow, supra note 17, at 333- 34. From their point of view, Lochner was wrong at the moment it was decided and there is no reasonable contemporary justification for the judicial philosophy that it represented. Ackerman, however, stated quite clearly that he wanted legal scholars to view Lochner in a "legally detached way," which is to say from an historicist point of view. 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 66. Ackerman was trying to put Lochner in context, an Ackermanian context to be sure, but an historical context nonetheless. See 1 id. at 58-67, 99-103. From this perspective, it is pointless to condemn Lochner as wrong (or praise it as right). The task is to understand how the result and reasoning in Lochner was plausible within the context of its own time. A second common criticism is that Ackerman's theory is difficult to implement because it gives judges the role of deciding when constitutional moments have occurred. See, e.g., Posner, supra note 17, at 34. Not only does this criticism misunderstand completely the thrust of Ackerman's theory, it demonstrates unwittingly the kind of Court-centered focus Ackerman labors to correct. Constitutional moments are the kind of events about which everyone tends to agree. Everyone recognizes that something has happened. The moment creates a new constitutional reality, as it were, and there is no real possibility of the Court doing anything else but ratifying it.
    • Ackerman , vol.1 , pp. 58-67
  • 219
    • 0041557899 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 17, at 34
    • See 1 id. at 16-33. Ackerman's historicism of course includes not only his treatment of Lochner, as I note below, but his rejection of restorationism. Unfortunately, Ackerman's critics have largely missed these points, especially the last. This is shown by two common criticisms of Ackerman's first volume. One, advanced by Terrance Sandalow and others, was that Ackerman was trying to rehabilitate Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905), one of the most criticized decisions of what Ackerman calls the "Middle Republic." To conventional scholars, this was heresy. See, e.g., Sandalow, supra note 17, at 333- 34. From their point of view, Lochner was wrong at the moment it was decided and there is no reasonable contemporary justification for the judicial philosophy that it represented. Ackerman, however, stated quite clearly that he wanted legal scholars to view Lochner in a "legally detached way," which is to say from an historicist point of view. 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 66. Ackerman was trying to put Lochner in context, an Ackermanian context to be sure, but an historical context nonetheless. See 1 id. at 58-67, 99-103. From this perspective, it is pointless to condemn Lochner as wrong (or praise it as right). The task is to understand how the result and reasoning in Lochner was plausible within the context of its own time. A second common criticism is that Ackerman's theory is difficult to implement because it gives judges the role of deciding when constitutional moments have occurred. See, e.g., Posner, supra note 17, at 34. Not only does this criticism misunderstand completely the thrust of Ackerman's theory, it demonstrates unwittingly the kind of Court-centered focus Ackerman labors to correct. Constitutional moments are the kind of events about which everyone tends to agree. Everyone recognizes that something has happened. The moment creates a new constitutional reality, as it were, and there is no real possibility of the Court doing anything else but ratifying it.
    • Posner1
  • 220
    • 0043060849 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • See 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 71-95.
    • Ackerman , vol.2 , pp. 71-95
  • 221
    • 0042059133 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • See 1 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 165-99.
    • Ackerman , vol.1 , pp. 165-199
  • 222
    • 0042559991 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • See 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 12, 66-68.
    • Ackerman , vol.2 , pp. 12
  • 223
    • 84918572973 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 2 id. at 11-12.
    • Ackerman , vol.2 , pp. 11-12
  • 224
    • 0041557907 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 2 id. at 70, 115.
    • Ackerman , vol.2 , pp. 70
  • 225
    • 0042059157 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2 id. at 12.
    • Ackerman , vol.2 , pp. 12
  • 226
    • 0041557905 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2 id. at 26.
    • Ackerman , vol.2 , pp. 26
  • 227
    • 0042059154 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • I realize that Ackerman argues that Article V does not offer much certainty. See id. at 69-95. I am merely pointing out here that his arguments are not likely to be persuasive because they threaten larger concerns shared by most lawyers, judges, and scholars.
    • Ackerman , pp. 69-95
  • 228
    • 0041557901 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, e.g., 2 id. at 91-95.
    • Ackerman , vol.2 , pp. 91-95
  • 229
    • 84937262171 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The canons of constitutional law
    • On the idea of the canon, see J.M. Balkin & Sanford Levinson, The Canons of Constitutional Law, 111 HARV. L. REV. 963 (1998).
    • (1998) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.111 , pp. 963
    • Balkin, J.M.1    Levinson, S.2
  • 230
    • 0346982591 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • How many times has the United States constitution been amended?
    • supra note 1
    • This is why I am not attracted to the idea of understanding change outside Article V by unpacking the meaning of "amendment." See Sanford Levinson, How Many Times Has the United States Constitution Been Amended?, in RESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION, supra note 1, at 13. This enterprise makes two assumptions I see no reason to make: that change outside Article V must necessarily be legalistic in order to be constitutional, and that constitutional change is a matter of offering new legal interpretations of the Constitution. These assumptions may be true, but they may not. We should not assume that they are true before embarking on an investigation of constitutional change.
    • Responding to Imperfection , pp. 13
    • Levinson, S.1
  • 232
    • 0043060829 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, footnote omitted
    • 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 50 (footnote omitted). In the case of Madison, Ackerman notes that since other Convention delegates did not encourage his concern with the legality of their proceedings, "it is not surprising that Madison abandoned his legalisms when defending the Convention's triggering decision in public." 2 id. at 430 n.63.
    • Ackerman , vol.2 , pp. 50
  • 233
    • 0042559992 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 50 (footnote omitted). In the case of Madison, Ackerman notes that since other Convention delegates did not encourage his concern with the legality of their proceedings, "it is not surprising that Madison abandoned his legalisms when defending the Convention's triggering decision in public." 2 id. at 430 n.63.
    • Ackerman , vol.2 , Issue.63 , pp. 430
  • 234
    • 0042059137 scopus 로고
    • Max Farrand ed.
    • 1 THE RECORDS OF THE FEDERAL CONVENTION OF 1787, at 255 (Max Farrand ed., 1937), quoted in id. at 50. See also the discussion in RAKOVE, supra note 64, at 102-30.
    • (1937) The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787 , vol.1 , pp. 255
  • 235
    • 0042059155 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • quoted
    • 1 THE RECORDS OF THE FEDERAL CONVENTION OF 1787, at 255 (Max Farrand ed., 1937), quoted in id. at 50. See also the discussion in RAKOVE, supra note 64, at 102-30.
    • The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787 , pp. 50
  • 236
    • 0043060847 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 64, at 102-30
    • 1 THE RECORDS OF THE FEDERAL CONVENTION OF 1787, at 255 (Max Farrand ed., 1937), quoted in id. at 50. See also the discussion in RAKOVE, supra note 64, at 102-30.
    • Rakove1
  • 237
    • 0043061174 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 116.
    • Ackerman , vol.2 , pp. 116
  • 238
    • 0042560003 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Constitutional history and constitutional theory: Bruce Ackerman on reconstruction and the transformation of the American constitution
    • My argument here largely accords with that of Les Benedict. See Michael Les Benedict, Constitutional History and Constitutional Theory: Bruce Ackerman on Reconstruction and the Transformation of the American Constitution, 108 YALE L.J. 2028-29 (1999).
    • (1999) Yale L.J. , vol.108 , pp. 2028-2029
    • Les Benedict, M.1
  • 239
    • 0041557902 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • See 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 113-14.
    • Ackerman , vol.2 , pp. 113-114
  • 240
    • 0042560002 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 2 id. at 99-113.
    • Ackerman , vol.2 , pp. 99-113
  • 241
    • 0042560013 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See 2 id. at 120-252.
    • Ackerman , vol.2 , pp. 120-252
  • 245
    • 0041557904 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1, at 115.
    • Ackerman , vol.2 , pp. 115
  • 246
    • 0041557877 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Compare Ackerman: "All that the victory of the Union army established was the failure of secession. It did not establish the terms for reunion, and certainly did not establish that most Americans supported a move beyond the Thirteenth Amendment." 2 id. at 22. I disagree with this judgment for the reasons stated in the text.
    • Ackerman , vol.2 , pp. 22
  • 247
    • 0042560005 scopus 로고
    • Constitutionalism in the United States: From theory to politics
    • Indeed, I made the argument that the forced acceptance of these amendments was an important clue to the nature of American constitutionalism in Stephen M. Griffin, Constitutionalism in the United States: From Theory to Politics, 10 OXFORD J. LEGAL STUD. 200, 209 (1990).
    • (1990) Oxford J. Legal Stud. , vol.10 , pp. 200
    • Griffin, S.M.1
  • 248
    • 0346333608 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Madison's audience
    • Larry D. Kramer, Madison's Audience, 112 HARV. L. REV. 611, 677 (1999).
    • (1999) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.112 , pp. 611
    • Kramer, L.D.1
  • 249
    • 0347419788 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Integrating normative and descriptive constitutional theory: The case of original meaning
    • See, e.g., Michael C. Dorf, Integrating Normative and Descriptive Constitutional Theory: The Case of Original Meaning, 85 GEO. L.J. 1765 (1997).
    • (1997) Geo. L.J. , vol.85 , pp. 1765
    • Dorf, M.C.1
  • 250
    • 0041557892 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Unoriginalism's law without meaning
    • "[H]istory and originalism either sink or swim together. . . ." (reviewing RAKOVE, supra note 64)
    • For a recent illustration of this view, see Saikrishna B. Prakash, Unoriginalism's Law Without Meaning, 15 CONST. COMMENTARY 529, 535 (1998) ("[H]istory and originalism either sink or swim together. . . .") (reviewing RAKOVE, supra note 64). As I argue, originalism and historicism have little to do with each other. Prakash's failure to understand this results in a review that completely ignores Rakove's important insights into the Founding period. Rakove's book won the Pulitzer prize for history, but one would never know why from this review.
    • (1998) Const. Commentary , vol.15 , pp. 529
    • Prakash, S.B.1
  • 251
    • 0003509777 scopus 로고
    • For recent general works that provide insight on the craft of history and the historicist perspective, see JOYCE APPLEBY ET AL., TELLING THE TRUTH ABOUT HISTORY (1994); PAUL A. COHEN, HISTORY IN THREE KEYS: THE BOXERS AS EVENT, EXPERIENCE, AND MYTH (1997); PETER NOVICK, THAT NOBLE DREAM: OBJECTIVITY AND THE AMERICAN HISTORICAL PROFESSION (1989).
    • (1994) Telling the Truth About History
    • Appleby, J.1
  • 252
    • 0003730563 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For recent general works that provide insight on the craft of history and the historicist perspective, see JOYCE APPLEBY ET AL., TELLING THE TRUTH ABOUT HISTORY (1994); PAUL A. COHEN, HISTORY IN THREE KEYS: THE BOXERS AS EVENT, EXPERIENCE, AND MYTH (1997); PETER NOVICK, THAT NOBLE DREAM: OBJECTIVITY AND THE AMERICAN HISTORICAL PROFESSION (1989).
    • (1997) History in Three Keys: The Boxers as Event, Experience, and Myth
    • Cohen, P.A.1
  • 253
    • 0004048248 scopus 로고
    • For recent general works that provide insight on the craft of history and the historicist perspective, see JOYCE APPLEBY ET AL., TELLING THE TRUTH ABOUT HISTORY (1994); PAUL A. COHEN, HISTORY IN THREE KEYS: THE BOXERS AS EVENT, EXPERIENCE, AND MYTH (1997); PETER NOVICK, THAT NOBLE DREAM: OBJECTIVITY AND THE AMERICAN HISTORICAL PROFESSION (1989).
    • (1989) That Noble Dream: Objectivity and the American Historical Profession
    • Novick, P.1
  • 256
    • 0042059140 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Why not the New Deal? Because, of course, lawyers and scholars think they know what happened during the New Deal - it was merely a restoration of the Founding, by way of the Marshall Court.
  • 265
    • 37949000852 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Clio and the Court: An illicit love affair
    • See the original critique of "law-office" history by Alfred H. Kelly, Clio and the Court: An Illicit Love Affair, 1965 SUP. CT. REV. 119. In recent years, Kelly's argument has been updated and confirmed by other scholars. See, e.g., Neil M. Richards, Clio and the Court: A Reassessment of the Supreme Court's Uses of History, 13 J.L. & POL. 809 (1997); William M. Wiecek, Clio as Hostage: The United States Supreme Court and the Uses of History, 24 CAL. W. L. REV. 227 (1988).
    • Sup. Ct. Rev. , vol.1965 , pp. 119
    • Kelly, A.H.1
  • 266
    • 0041557891 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Clio and the Court: A reassessment of the Supreme Court's uses of history
    • See the original critique of "law-office" history by Alfred H. Kelly, Clio and the Court: An Illicit Love Affair, 1965 SUP. CT. REV. 119. In recent years, Kelly's argument has been updated and confirmed by other scholars. See, e.g., Neil M. Richards, Clio and the Court: A Reassessment of the Supreme Court's Uses of History, 13 J.L. & POL. 809 (1997); William M. Wiecek, Clio as Hostage: The United States Supreme Court and the Uses of History, 24 CAL. W. L. REV. 227 (1988).
    • (1997) J.L. & Pol. , vol.13 , pp. 809
    • Richards, N.M.1
  • 267
    • 0042059143 scopus 로고
    • Clio as hostage: The United States Supreme Court and the uses of history
    • See the original critique of "law-office" history by Alfred H. Kelly, Clio and the Court: An Illicit Love Affair, 1965 SUP. CT. REV. 119. In recent years, Kelly's argument has been updated and confirmed by other scholars. See, e.g., Neil M. Richards, Clio and the Court: A Reassessment of the Supreme Court's Uses of History, 13 J.L. & POL. 809 (1997); William M. Wiecek, Clio as Hostage: The United States Supreme Court and the Uses of History, 24 CAL. W. L. REV. 227 (1988).
    • (1988) Cal. W. L. Rev. , vol.24 , pp. 227
    • Wiecek, W.M.1
  • 268
    • 0041557884 scopus 로고
    • The Supreme Court's legal history
    • Eric Foner, The Supreme Court's Legal History, 23 RUTGERS L.J. 243, 243-44 (1992).
    • (1992) Rutgers L.J. , vol.23 , pp. 243
    • Foner, E.1
  • 269
    • 33644650824 scopus 로고
    • 505 U.S. 833 (1992).
    • (1992) U.S. , vol.505 , pp. 833
  • 270
    • 0043060839 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 861-64.
    • U.S. , pp. 861-864
  • 271
    • 0041557898 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id. at 861-62.
    • U.S. , pp. 861-862
  • 272
    • 0004201389 scopus 로고
    • 163 U.S. 537 (1896).
    • (1896) U.S. , vol.163 , pp. 537
  • 273
    • 19844380853 scopus 로고
    • 347 U.S. 483 (1954).
    • (1954) U.S. , vol.347 , pp. 483
  • 274
    • 0043060843 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Casey
    • Casey, 505 U.S. at 863.
    • U.S. , vol.505 , pp. 863
  • 275
    • 0043060843 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id.
    • U.S. , vol.505 , pp. 863
  • 276
    • 0345880245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • This fallacy is one of the key problems with Lessig's theory of translation. Like Ackerman and myself, Lessig rejects restorationism as a way to understand how constitutional change occurred legitimately in the New Deal. See Lessig, Understanding, supra note 1, at 446-48. Lessig contends, however, that changes in the facts can justify the New Deal decisions. He quotes Chief Justice Hughes's opinion in West Coast Hotel v. Parrish, 300 U.S. 379 (1937), to show the role of changed facts. Hughes refers to "recent economic experience" which has revealed the "exploitation" of workers who occupy an "unequal" economic position and are "relatively defenceless." Id. at 399 (quoted in Lessig, Understanding, supra note 1, at 460) . He takes judicial notice of the Depression and says there is no need to provide a subsidy to "unconscionable employers." Id. The state has the right "to correct the abuse which springs from their selfish disregard of the public interest." Id. These are facts? At the very least Hughes's argument turns on a mixture of facts and values. Almost all the terms Hughes uses are unambiguously value-laden. Why is it so important for Lessig to avoid the idea that historical change involves changes in values? Lessig wants to show that the Court can maintain fidelity with the past even in areas where constitutional law has undergone drastic shifts without the benefit of Article V amendments. As he sees it, the key to maintaining fidelity is to make sure that the Framers' values are brought up to date through a process of translation that compares their background context with our own. The problem here is that the Framers' values, even the general ones that they embodied in the Constitution, were part of a larger historical worldview that no longer exists. See William W. Fisher III, Texts and Contexts: The Application to American Legal History of the Methodologies of Intellectual History, 49 STAN. L. REV. 1065, 1106-07 (1997) (arguing that when shifts in "ideology" or "world view" are involved, "then equivalence of the sort Lessig celebrates seems chimerical"). As I showed in Part I, the context surrounding Marshall's interpretation of the Commerce Clause included a commitment to an extremely limited federal role in regulating the economy. Given this value commitment, there is no possibility of maintaining true fidelity with the Marshall Court. If we include all of Marshall's values in our translation effort, we will not be able to justify the New Deal. On the other hand, if we selectively edit the past to remove those values that are antithetical to the modern regulatory state, we have given the game away. Deciding on our own which past values to keep and which to discard does not maintain "fidelity" with those values.
    • Understanding , pp. 446-448
    • Lessig1
  • 277
    • 0345880245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • West Coast Hotel v. Parrish
    • This fallacy is one of the key problems with Lessig's theory of translation. Like Ackerman and myself, Lessig rejects restorationism as a way to understand how constitutional change occurred legitimately in the New Deal. See Lessig, Understanding, supra note 1, at 446- 48. Lessig contends, however, that changes in the facts can justify the New Deal decisions. He quotes Chief Justice Hughes's opinion in West Coast Hotel v. Parrish, 300 U.S. 379 (1937), to show the role of changed facts. Hughes refers to "recent economic experience" which has revealed the "exploitation" of workers who occupy an "unequal" economic position and are "relatively defenceless." Id. at 399 (quoted in Lessig, Understanding, supra note 1, at 460) . He takes judicial notice of the Depression and says there is no need to provide a subsidy to "unconscionable employers." Id. The state has the right "to correct the abuse which springs from their selfish disregard of the public interest." Id. These are facts? At the very least Hughes's argument turns on a mixture of facts and values. Almost all the terms Hughes uses are unambiguously value-laden. Why is it so important for Lessig to avoid the idea that historical change involves changes in values? Lessig wants to show that the Court can maintain fidelity with the past even in areas where constitutional law has undergone drastic shifts without the benefit of Article V amendments. As he sees it, the key to maintaining fidelity is to make sure that the Framers' values are brought up to date through a process of translation that compares their background context with our own. The problem here is that the Framers' values, even the general ones that they embodied in the Constitution, were part of a larger historical worldview that no longer exists. See William W. Fisher III, Texts and Contexts: The Application to American Legal History of the Methodologies of Intellectual History, 49 STAN. L. REV. 1065, 1106-07 (1997) (arguing that when shifts in "ideology" or "world view" are involved, "then equivalence of the sort Lessig celebrates seems chimerical"). As I showed in Part I, the context surrounding Marshall's interpretation of the Commerce Clause included a commitment to an extremely limited federal role in regulating the economy. Given this value commitment, there is no possibility of maintaining true fidelity with the Marshall Court. If we include all of Marshall's values in our translation effort, we will not be able to justify the New Deal. On the other hand, if we selectively edit the past to remove those values that are antithetical to the modern regulatory state, we have given the game away. Deciding on our own which past values to keep and which to discard does not maintain "fidelity" with those values.
    • (1937) U.S. , vol.300 , pp. 379
  • 278
    • 0345880245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This fallacy is one of the key problems with Lessig's theory of translation. Like Ackerman and myself, Lessig rejects restorationism as a way to understand how constitutional change occurred legitimately in the New Deal. See Lessig, Understanding, supra note 1, at 446- 48. Lessig contends, however, that changes in the facts can justify the New Deal decisions. He quotes Chief Justice Hughes's opinion in West Coast Hotel v. Parrish, 300 U.S. 379 (1937), to show the role of changed facts. Hughes refers to "recent economic experience" which has revealed the "exploitation" of workers who occupy an "unequal" economic position and are "relatively defenceless." Id. at 399 (quoted in Lessig, Understanding, supra note 1, at 460) . He takes judicial notice of the Depression and says there is no need to provide a subsidy to "unconscionable employers." Id. The state has the right "to correct the abuse which springs from their selfish disregard of the public interest." Id. These are facts? At the very least Hughes's argument turns on a mixture of facts and values. Almost all the terms Hughes uses are unambiguously value-laden. Why is it so important for Lessig to avoid the idea that historical change involves changes in values? Lessig wants to show that the Court can maintain fidelity with the past even in areas where constitutional law has undergone drastic shifts without the benefit of Article V amendments. As he sees it, the key to maintaining fidelity is to make sure that the Framers' values are brought up to date through a process of translation that compares their background context with our own. The problem here is that the Framers' values, even the general ones that they embodied in the Constitution, were part of a larger historical worldview that no longer exists. See William W. Fisher III, Texts and Contexts: The Application to American Legal History of the Methodologies of Intellectual History, 49 STAN. L. REV. 1065, 1106-07 (1997) (arguing that when shifts in "ideology" or "world view" are involved, "then equivalence of the sort Lessig celebrates seems chimerical"). As I showed in Part I, the context surrounding Marshall's interpretation of the Commerce Clause included a commitment to an extremely limited federal role in regulating the economy. Given this value commitment, there is no possibility of maintaining true fidelity with the Marshall Court. If we include all of Marshall's values in our translation effort, we will not be able to justify the New Deal. On the other hand, if we selectively edit the past to remove those values that are antithetical to the modern regulatory state, we have given the game away. Deciding on our own which past values to keep and which to discard does not maintain "fidelity" with those values.
    • U.S. , pp. 399
  • 279
    • 0345880245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • quoted supra note 1
    • This fallacy is one of the key problems with Lessig's theory of translation. Like Ackerman and myself, Lessig rejects restorationism as a way to understand how constitutional change occurred legitimately in the New Deal. See Lessig, Understanding, supra note 1, at 446- 48. Lessig contends, however, that changes in the facts can justify the New Deal decisions. He quotes Chief Justice Hughes's opinion in West Coast Hotel v. Parrish, 300 U.S. 379 (1937), to show the role of changed facts. Hughes refers to "recent economic experience" which has revealed the "exploitation" of workers who occupy an "unequal" economic position and are "relatively defenceless." Id. at 399 (quoted in Lessig, Understanding, supra note 1, at 460) . He takes judicial notice of the Depression and says there is no need to provide a subsidy to "unconscionable employers." Id. The state has the right "to correct the abuse which springs from their selfish disregard of the public interest." Id. These are facts? At the very least Hughes's argument turns on a mixture of facts and values. Almost all the terms Hughes uses are unambiguously value-laden. Why is it so important for Lessig to avoid the idea that historical change involves changes in values? Lessig wants to show that the Court can maintain fidelity with the past even in areas where constitutional law has undergone drastic shifts without the benefit of Article V amendments. As he sees it, the key to maintaining fidelity is to make sure that the Framers' values are brought up to date through a process of translation that compares their background context with our own. The problem here is that the Framers' values, even the general ones that they embodied in the Constitution, were part of a larger historical worldview that no longer exists. See William W. Fisher III, Texts and Contexts: The Application to American Legal History of the Methodologies of Intellectual History, 49 STAN. L. REV. 1065, 1106-07 (1997) (arguing that when shifts in "ideology" or "world view" are involved, "then equivalence of the sort Lessig celebrates seems chimerical"). As I showed in Part I, the context surrounding Marshall's interpretation of the Commerce Clause included a commitment to an extremely limited federal role in regulating the economy. Given this value commitment, there is no possibility of maintaining true fidelity with the Marshall Court. If we include all of Marshall's values in our translation effort, we will not be able to justify the New Deal. On the other hand, if we selectively edit the past to remove those values that are antithetical to the modern regulatory state, we have given the game away. Deciding on our own which past values to keep and which to discard does not maintain "fidelity" with those values.
    • Understanding , pp. 460
    • Lessig1
  • 280
    • 0345880245 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Texts and contexts: The application to American legal history of the methodologies of intellectual history
    • arguing that when shifts in "ideology" or "world view" are involved, "then equivalence of the sort Lessig celebrates seems chimerical"
    • This fallacy is one of the key problems with Lessig's theory of translation. Like Ackerman and myself, Lessig rejects restorationism as a way to understand how constitutional change occurred legitimately in the New Deal. See Lessig, Understanding, supra note 1, at 446- 48. Lessig contends, however, that changes in the facts can justify the New Deal decisions. He quotes Chief Justice Hughes's opinion in West Coast Hotel v. Parrish, 300 U.S. 379 (1937), to show the role of changed facts. Hughes refers to "recent economic experience" which has revealed the "exploitation" of workers who occupy an "unequal" economic position and are "relatively defenceless." Id. at 399 (quoted in Lessig, Understanding, supra note 1, at 460) . He takes judicial notice of the Depression and says there is no need to provide a subsidy to "unconscionable employers." Id. The state has the right "to correct the abuse which springs from their selfish disregard of the public interest." Id. These are facts? At the very least Hughes's argument turns on a mixture of facts and values. Almost all the terms Hughes uses are unambiguously value-laden. Why is it so important for Lessig to avoid the idea that historical change involves changes in values? Lessig wants to show that the Court can maintain fidelity with the past even in areas where constitutional law has undergone drastic shifts without the benefit of Article V amendments. As he sees it, the key to maintaining fidelity is to make sure that the Framers' values are brought up to date through a process of translation that compares their background context with our own. The problem here is that the Framers' values, even the general ones that they embodied in the Constitution, were part of a larger historical worldview that no longer exists. See William W. Fisher III, Texts and Contexts: The Application to American Legal History of the Methodologies of Intellectual History, 49 STAN. L. REV. 1065, 1106-07 (1997) (arguing that when shifts in "ideology" or "world view" are involved, "then equivalence of the sort Lessig celebrates seems chimerical"). As I showed in Part I, the context surrounding Marshall's interpretation of the Commerce Clause included a commitment to an extremely limited federal role in regulating the economy. Given this value commitment, there is no possibility of maintaining true fidelity with the Marshall Court. If we include all of Marshall's values in our translation effort, we will not be able to justify the New Deal. On the other hand, if we selectively edit the past to remove those values that are antithetical to the modern regulatory state, we have given the game away. Deciding on our own which past values to keep and which to discard does not maintain "fidelity" with those values.
    • (1997) Stan. L. Rev. , vol.49 , pp. 1065
    • Fisher W.W. III1
  • 281
    • 0041557895 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See the sources cited supra note 100 on the history of the Due Process Clause and Commerce Clause between the Civil War and the New Deal
    • See the sources cited supra note 100 on the history of the Due Process Clause and Commerce Clause between the Civil War and the New Deal.
  • 282
    • 0347758703 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Race and the Court in the progressive era
    • See Michael J. Klarman, Race and the Court in the Progressive Era, 51 VAND. L. REV. 881, 886-95 (1998).
    • (1998) Vand. L. Rev. , vol.51 , pp. 881
    • Klarman, M.J.1
  • 283
    • 0004201389 scopus 로고
    • Plessy
    • See Plessy, 163 U.S. 537, 551-52 (1896).
    • (1896) U.S. , vol.163 , pp. 537
  • 284
    • 0038927689 scopus 로고
    • The Supreme court, 1992 term - foreword: The constitution of change: Legal fundamentality without fundamentalism
    • Morton J. Horwitz, The Supreme court, 1992 Term - Foreword: The Constitution of Change: Legal Fundamentality Without Fundamentalism, 107 HARV. L. REV. 32, 92 (1993); see also id. at 71-92 (criticizing Casey).
    • (1993) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.107 , pp. 32
    • Horwitz, M.J.1
  • 285
    • 84906890735 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • criticizing Casey
    • Morton J. Horwitz, The Supreme court, 1992 Term - Foreword: The Constitution of Change: Legal Fundamentality Without Fundamentalism, 107 HARV. L. REV. 32, 92 (1993); see also id. at 71-92 (criticizing Casey).
    • Harv. L. Rev. , pp. 71-92
  • 286
    • 0041557894 scopus 로고
    • The idea of a useable past
    • See, e.g., Cass R. Sunstein, The Idea of a Useable Past, 95 COLUM. L. REV. 601 (1995).
    • (1995) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.95 , pp. 601
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 288
    • 84923752433 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • emphasis in original
    • Id. (emphasis in original). Sunstein's statement illustrates what I mean when I say that constitutional lawyers and scholars use history to produce narratives of continuity.
    • Colum. L. Rev.
  • 292
    • 0042559994 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See sources cited supra note 173
    • See sources cited supra note 173.
  • 293
    • 0042559990 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Legal liberalism at Yale
    • reviewing LAURA KALMAN, THE STRANGE CAREER OF LEGAL LIBERALISM (1996)
    • See Stephen M. Griffin, Legal Liberalism at Yale, 14 CONST. COMMENTARY 535, 546-49 (1997) (reviewing LAURA KALMAN, THE STRANGE CAREER OF LEGAL LIBERALISM (1996))
    • (1997) Const. Commentary , vol.14 , pp. 535
    • Griffin, S.M.1
  • 294
    • 0042559987 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 187, at 604
    • Sunstein, supra note 187, at 604.
    • Sunstein1
  • 295
    • 0042059142 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. at 605
    • See id. at 605.
  • 296
    • 0042560008 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id. 198
    • See id. 198. For a similar criticism of Sunstein, see Fisher, supra note 182, at 1108.
  • 297
    • 0042559984 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 182, at 1108
    • See id. 198. For a similar criticism of Sunstein, see Fisher, supra note 182, at 1108.
    • Fisher1
  • 298
    • 0007131920 scopus 로고
    • Reflections on the bicentennial of the United States constitution
    • Thurgood Marshall, Reflections on the Bicentennial of the United States Constitution, 101 HARV. L. REV. 1, 2 (1987). For relevant commentary, see Raymond T. Diamond, No Call to Glory: Thurgood Marshall's Thesis on the Intent of a Pro-Slavery Constitution 42 VAND. L. REV. 93 (1989).
    • (1987) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.101 , pp. 1
    • Marshall, T.1
  • 299
    • 0347905709 scopus 로고
    • No call to glory: Thurgood Marshall's thesis on the intent of a pro-slavery constitution
    • Thurgood Marshall, Reflections on the Bicentennial of the United States Constitution, 101 HARV. L. REV. 1, 2 (1987). For relevant commentary, see Raymond T. Diamond, No Call to Glory: Thurgood Marshall's Thesis on the Intent of a Pro-Slavery Constitution 42 VAND. L. REV. 93 (1989).
    • (1989) Vand. L. Rev. , vol.42 , pp. 93
    • Diamond, R.T.1
  • 300
    • 0042059141 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • In drawing the distinctions in this Section, I do not wish to be misunderstood. I am not arguing that historians engage in description without the need to assume a normative point of view. The difference between historians and lawyers is not that the former are interested solely in description or explanation while the latter are interested solely in prescription. While historians do focus on description and explanation, the crucial difference is that they bring a much broader normative perspective to bear on historical evidence. To oversimplify, lawyers are interested in resolving cases by building narratives of continuity. Historians are not so limited and often focus on discontinuities between the present and the past.
  • 301
    • 0041557882 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 194, at 180 (footnote omitted)
    • KALMAN, supra note 194, at 180 (footnote omitted).
    • Kalman1
  • 303
    • 0041557886 scopus 로고
    • What is constitutional theory? the newer theory and the decline of the learned tradition
    • outlining a new paradigm of rigorous constitutional theory
    • See generally Stephen M. Griffin, What Is Constitutional Theory? The Newer Theory and the Decline of the Learned Tradition, 62 S. CAL. L. REV. 493 (1989) (outlining a new paradigm of rigorous constitutional theory).
    • (1989) S. Cal. L. Rev. , vol.62 , pp. 493
    • Griffin, S.M.1
  • 305
    • 0003761763 scopus 로고
    • See JURGEN HABERMAS, LEGITIMATION CRISIS 107-08 (1975). See also the views of Rogers Smith, who recently provided a statement of his own ideal of scholarship with respect to his home discipline of political science: I have come to favor a Socratic view of our professional mission. I think we are at our best when we are intellectual gadflies, rigorously questioning and testing accepted political truths, exploring ignored possibilities, courting unpopularity by offering suggestions that markets are not likely to reward and that people in power are not likely to approve. Smith, Still Blowing in the Wind, supra note 7, at 278.
    • (1975) Legitimation Crisis , pp. 107-108
    • Habermas, J.1
  • 306
    • 0041557881 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 7
    • See JURGEN HABERMAS, LEGITIMATION CRISIS 107-08 (1975). See also the views of Rogers Smith, who recently provided a statement of his own ideal of scholarship with respect to his home discipline of political science: I have come to favor a Socratic view of our professional mission. I think we are at our best when we are intellectual gadflies, rigorously questioning and testing accepted political truths, exploring ignored possibilities, courting unpopularity by offering suggestions that markets are not likely to reward and that people in power are not likely to approve. Smith, Still Blowing in the Wind, supra note 7, at 278.
    • Still Blowing in the Wind , pp. 278
    • Smith1
  • 307
    • 0032361236 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Against constitutional theory
    • Recently, Judge Richard Posner defined constitutional theory as "the effort to develop a generally accepted theory to guide the interpretation of the Constitution of the United States." Richard A. Posner, Against Constitutional Theory, 73 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1, 1 (1998). I have explained elsewhere why this common definition is far too narrow. See GRIFFIN, supra note 1, at 3-4. We do not gain much by general definitions, but properly understood, constitutional theory concerns any theoretical issue raised by the distinctive practice of American constitutionalism. See id. at 4. More helpfully, Judge Posner calls for a greater degree of attention to the empirical issues pertaining to constitutionalism. See Posner, supra, at 11-12. As I argued 10 years ago, these issues are certainly relevant to constitutional theory, and it is unfortunate that constitutional scholars have neglected them. See Griffin, supra note 203. But Posner does not use this gesture toward empiricism as an opportunity to rethink the nature of constitutional theory. The historicist perspective I have described in this Essay offers us a better chance to do this.
    • (1998) N.Y.U. L. Rev. , vol.73 , pp. 1
    • Posner, R.A.1
  • 308
    • 0042059151 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at 3-4
    • Recently, Judge Richard Posner defined constitutional theory as "the effort to develop a generally accepted theory to guide the interpretation of the Constitution of the United States." Richard A. Posner, Against Constitutional Theory, 73 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1, 1 (1998). I have explained elsewhere why this common definition is far too narrow. See GRIFFIN, supra note 1, at 3-4. We do not gain much by general definitions, but properly understood, constitutional theory concerns any theoretical issue raised by the distinctive practice of American constitutionalism. See id. at 4. More helpfully, Judge Posner calls for a greater degree of attention to the empirical issues pertaining to constitutionalism. See Posner, supra, at 11-12. As I argued 10 years ago, these issues are certainly relevant to constitutional theory, and it is unfortunate that constitutional scholars have neglected them. See Griffin, supra note 203. But Posner does not use this gesture toward empiricism as an opportunity to rethink the nature of constitutional theory. The historicist perspective I have described in this Essay offers us a better chance to do this.
    • Griffin1
  • 309
    • 0042059150 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • id. at 4
    • Recently, Judge Richard Posner defined constitutional theory as "the effort to develop a generally accepted theory to guide the interpretation of the Constitution of the United States." Richard A. Posner, Against Constitutional Theory, 73 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1, 1 (1998). I have explained elsewhere why this common definition is far too narrow. See GRIFFIN, supra note 1, at 3-4. We do not gain much by general definitions, but properly understood, constitutional theory concerns any theoretical issue raised by the distinctive practice of American constitutionalism. See id. at 4. More helpfully, Judge Posner calls for a greater degree of attention to the empirical issues pertaining to constitutionalism. See Posner, supra, at 11-12. As I argued 10 years ago, these issues are certainly relevant to constitutional theory, and it is unfortunate that constitutional scholars have neglected them. See Griffin, supra note 203. But Posner does not use this gesture toward empiricism as an opportunity to rethink the nature of constitutional theory. The historicist perspective I have described in this Essay offers us a better chance to do this.
  • 310
    • 0043060841 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra, at 11-12
    • Recently, Judge Richard Posner defined constitutional theory as "the effort to develop a generally accepted theory to guide the interpretation of the Constitution of the United States." Richard A. Posner, Against Constitutional Theory, 73 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1, 1 (1998). I have explained elsewhere why this common definition is far too narrow. See GRIFFIN, supra note 1, at 3-4. We do not gain much by general definitions, but properly understood, constitutional theory concerns any theoretical issue raised by the distinctive practice of American constitutionalism. See id. at 4. More helpfully, Judge Posner calls for a greater degree of attention to the empirical issues pertaining to constitutionalism. See Posner, supra, at 11-12. As I argued 10 years ago, these issues are certainly relevant to constitutional theory, and it is unfortunate that constitutional scholars have neglected them. See Griffin, supra note 203. But Posner does not use this gesture toward empiricism as an opportunity to rethink the nature of constitutional theory. The historicist perspective I have described in this Essay offers us a better chance to do this.
    • Posner1
  • 311
    • 0042559996 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 203
    • Recently, Judge Richard Posner defined constitutional theory as "the effort to develop a generally accepted theory to guide the interpretation of the Constitution of the United States." Richard A. Posner, Against Constitutional Theory, 73 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1, 1 (1998). I have explained elsewhere why this common definition is far too narrow. See GRIFFIN, supra note 1, at 3-4. We do not gain much by general definitions, but properly understood, constitutional theory concerns any theoretical issue raised by the distinctive practice of American constitutionalism. See id. at 4. More helpfully, Judge Posner calls for a greater degree of attention to the empirical issues pertaining to constitutionalism. See Posner, supra, at 11-12. As I argued 10 years ago, these issues are certainly relevant to constitutional theory, and it is unfortunate that constitutional scholars have neglected them. See Griffin, supra note 203. But Posner does not use this gesture toward empiricism as an opportunity to rethink the nature of constitutional theory. The historicist perspective I have described in this Essay offers us a better chance to do this.
    • Griffin1
  • 312
    • 84937259429 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • We the unconventional American people
    • reviewing 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1
    • For an example of the unconventional view that the theory of constitutional interpretation comes first, see James E. Fleming, We the Unconventional American People, 65 U. CHI. L. REV. 1513 (1998) (reviewing 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1). Fleming criticizes Ackerman for not offering a theory of constitutional interpretation. See 2 id. at 1522, 1537. What Fleming does not see is that the task of constructing a theory of constitutional change necessarily comes first. It is only through a better understanding of constitutional change that unrealistic narratives of continuity can be avoided.
    • (1998) U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.65 , pp. 1513
    • Fleming, J.E.1
  • 313
    • 0043060840 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • For an example of the unconventional view that the theory of constitutional interpretation comes first, see James E. Fleming, We the Unconventional American People, 65 U. CHI. L. REV. 1513 (1998) (reviewing 2 ACKERMAN, supra note 1). Fleming criticizes Ackerman for not offering a theory of constitutional interpretation. See 2 id. at 1522, 1537. What Fleming does not see is that the task of constructing a theory of constitutional change necessarily comes first. It is only through a better understanding of constitutional change that unrealistic narratives of continuity can be avoided.
    • U. Chi. L. Rev. , vol.2 , pp. 1522
  • 314
    • 37949017146 scopus 로고
    • Rules for originalists
    • See H. Jefferson Powell, Rules for Originalists, 73 VA. L. REV. 659, 662-66 (1987).
    • (1987) Va. L. Rev. , vol.73 , pp. 659
    • Powell, H.J.1
  • 315
    • 0042098790 scopus 로고
    • A neo-federalist view of article III: Separating the two tiers of federal jurisdiction
    • finding no constitutional mandate to create any lower federal courts
    • See, e.g., Akhil Reed Amar, A Neo-Federalist View of Article III: Separating the Two Tiers of Federal Jurisdiction, 65 B.U. L. REV. 205, 212 (1985) (finding no constitutional mandate to create any lower federal courts); Cass R. Sunstein, Constitutionalism After the New Deal, 101 HARV. L. REV. 421, 467 (1987) (criticizing Chevron v. NRDC on the ground that it contradicts Marbury v. Madison).
    • (1985) B.U. L. Rev. , vol.65 , pp. 205
    • Amar, A.R.1
  • 316
    • 66749133192 scopus 로고
    • Constitutionalism after the new deal
    • criticizing Chevron v. NRDC on the ground that it contradicts Marbury v. Madison
    • See, e.g., Akhil Reed Amar, A Neo-Federalist View of Article III: Separating the Two Tiers of Federal Jurisdiction, 65 B.U. L. REV. 205, 212 (1985) (finding no constitutional mandate to create any lower federal courts); Cass R. Sunstein, Constitutionalism After the New Deal, 101 HARV. L. REV. 421, 467 (1987) (criticizing Chevron v. NRDC on the ground that it contradicts Marbury v. Madison).
    • (1987) Harv. L. Rev. , vol.101 , pp. 421
    • Sunstein, C.R.1
  • 317
    • 0042559998 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 206, at 6
    • See Posner, supra note 206, at 6.
    • Posner1
  • 318
    • 0042059147 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Id
    • Id.
  • 319
    • 0042559999 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See id
    • See id.
  • 320
    • 0042560001 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 186, at 57-65
    • See Horwitz, supra note 186, at 57-65.
    • Horwitz1
  • 321
    • 0043060833 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at 63-66
    • For how the argument regarding judicial review should proceed given this historical approach, see GRIFFIN, supra note 1, at 63-66.
    • Griffin1
  • 322
    • 0041557880 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • See 1 ACKERMAN. supra note 1, at 64-66.
    • Ackerman , vol.1 , pp. 64-66
  • 323
    • 23844549426 scopus 로고
    • 410 U.S. 113 (1973).
    • (1973) U.S. , vol.410 , pp. 113
  • 324
    • 0042059144 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1, at 143-52
    • For discussion of this model, which I have called the pluralist theory of constitutional interpretation, see GRIFFIN, supra note 1, at 143-52.
    • Griffin1
  • 325
    • 0041557893 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 128
    • See, e.g., DWORKIN, supra note 128; RONALD DWORKIN. LAW'S EMPIRE (1986).
    • Dworkin1
  • 327
    • 0043060837 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 80
    • See SEIDMAN & TUSHNET, supra note 80.
    • Seidman1    Tushnet2
  • 328
    • 0348199092 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Rethinking the civil rights and civil liberties revolutions
    • hereinafter Klarman, Rethinking
    • See Michael J. Klarman, Rethinking the Civil Rights and Civil Liberties Revolutions, 82 VA. L. REV. 1 (1996) [hereinafter Klarman, Rethinking]; see also Michael J. Klarman, How Brown Changed Race Relations: The Backlash Thesis, 81 J. AM. HIST. 81 (1994).
    • (1996) Va. L. Rev. , vol.82 , pp. 1
    • Klarman, M.J.1
  • 329
    • 84962994467 scopus 로고
    • How brown changed race relations: The backlash thesis
    • See Michael J. Klarman, Rethinking the Civil Rights and Civil Liberties Revolutions, 82 VA. L. REV. 1 (1996) [hereinafter Klarman, Rethinking]; see also Michael J. Klarman, How Brown Changed Race Relations: The Backlash Thesis, 81 J. AM. HIST. 81 (1994).
    • (1994) J. Am. Hist. , vol.81 , pp. 81
    • Klarman, M.J.1
  • 330
    • 0041557890 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 1
    • See, e.g., RESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION, supra note 1; Sanford Levinson, The Specious Morality of the Law, HARPER'S, May 1977, at 35. Levinson's seminal article somehow anticipated both the "republican revival" of the 1980s and the future importance of the issue of constitutional change.
    • Responding to Imperfection
  • 331
    • 0043060831 scopus 로고
    • The specious morality of the law
    • May
    • See, e.g., RESPONDING TO IMPERFECTION, supra note 1; Sanford Levinson, The Specious Morality of the Law, HARPER'S, May 1977, at 35. Levinson's seminal article somehow anticipated both the "republican revival" of the 1980s and the future importance of the issue of constitutional change.
    • (1977) Harper's , pp. 35
    • Levinson, S.1
  • 332
    • 0040877577 scopus 로고
    • History "Lite" in modern American constitutionalism
    • See Martin S. Flaherty, History "Lite" in Modern American Constitutionalism, 95 COLUM. L. REV. 523 (1995); Martin S. Flaherty, The Most Dangerous Branch, 105 YALE L.J. 1725 (1996).
    • (1995) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.95 , pp. 523
    • Flaherty, M.S.1
  • 333
    • 0041557883 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The most dangerous branch
    • See Martin S. Flaherty, History "Lite" in Modern American Constitutionalism, 95 COLUM. L. REV. 523 (1995); Martin S. Flaherty, The Most Dangerous Branch, 105 YALE L.J. 1725 (1996).
    • (1996) Yale L.J. , vol.105 , pp. 1725
    • Flaherty, M.S.1
  • 334
    • 0032385485 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The history of the countermajoritarian difficulty, part one: The road to judicial supremacy
    • See Barry Friedman, The History of the Countermajoritarian Difficulty, Part One: The Road to Judicial Supremacy, 73 N.Y.U. L. REV. 333 (1998); Barry Friedman & Scott B. Smith, The Sedimentary Constitution, 147 U. PA. L. REV. 1 (1998).
    • (1998) N.Y.U. L. Rev. , vol.73 , pp. 333
    • Friedman, B.1
  • 335
    • 0346785696 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The sedimentary constitution
    • See Barry Friedman, The History of the Countermajoritarian Difficulty, Part One: The Road to Judicial Supremacy, 73 N.Y.U. L. REV. 333 (1998); Barry Friedman & Scott B. Smith, The Sedimentary Constitution, 147 U. PA. L. REV. 1 (1998).
    • (1998) U. Pa. L. Rev. , vol.147 , pp. 1
    • Friedman, B.1    Smith, S.B.2
  • 336
    • 84887348081 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 220
    • Klarman, Rethinking, supra note 220, at 31-32.
    • Rethinking , pp. 31-32
    • Klarman1
  • 338
    • 0042059138 scopus 로고
    • A response to professor McConnell
    • See also the instructive exchange between Klarman and Michael McConnell on the constitutionality of school segregation in the nineteenth century. From my point of view, Klarman argues as a slightly puzzled historicist against McConnell's aggressive legalist position. See Michael J. Klarman, A Response to Professor McConnell, 81 VA. L. REV. 1881 (1995); Michael W. McConnell, A Reply to Professor Klarman, 81 VA. L. REV. 1937 (1995). Klarman is responding to McConnell's earlier article, Michael W. McConnell, Originalism and the Desegregation Decisions, 81 VA. L. REV. 947 (1995).
    • (1995) Va. L. Rev. , vol.81 , pp. 1881
    • Klarman, M.J.1
  • 339
    • 0042059148 scopus 로고
    • A reply to professor Klarman
    • See also the instructive exchange between Klarman and Michael McConnell on the constitutionality of school segregation in the nineteenth century. From my point of view, Klarman argues as a slightly puzzled historicist against McConnell's aggressive legalist position. See Michael J. Klarman, A Response to Professor McConnell, 81 VA. L. REV. 1881 (1995); Michael W. McConnell, A Reply to Professor Klarman, 81 VA. L. REV. 1937 (1995). Klarman is responding to McConnell's earlier article, Michael W. McConnell, Originalism and the Desegregation Decisions, 81 VA. L. REV. 947 (1995).
    • (1995) Va. L. Rev. , vol.81 , pp. 1937
    • McConnell, M.W.1
  • 340
    • 21844488029 scopus 로고
    • Originalism and the desegregation decisions
    • See also the instructive exchange between Klarman and Michael McConnell on the constitutionality of school segregation in the nineteenth century. From my point of view, Klarman argues as a slightly puzzled historicist against McConnell's aggressive legalist position. See Michael J. Klarman, A Response to Professor McConnell, 81 VA. L. REV. 1881 (1995); Michael W. McConnell, A Reply to Professor Klarman, 81 VA. L. REV. 1937 (1995). Klarman is responding to McConnell's earlier article, Michael W. McConnell, Originalism and the Desegregation Decisions, 81 VA. L. REV. 947 (1995).
    • (1995) Va. L. Rev. , vol.81 , pp. 947
    • McConnell, M.W.1
  • 341
    • 0003673312 scopus 로고
    • Among recent works by historical institutionalists, the two that are most suggestive for future constitutional theory are STEPHEN SKOWRONEK, THE POLITICS PRESIDENTS MAKE: LEADERSHIP FROM JOHN ADAMS TO GEORGE BUSH (1993) and ROGERS M. SMITH, CIVIC IDEALS: CONFLICTING VISIONS OF CITIZENSHIP IN U.S. HISTORY (1997). Smith's book is particularly relevant to what I have argued here in that it shows that American constitutionalism cannot be reasonably represented as a narrative of continuity. For other works by political scientists that are relevant to the project of a contextualized constitutional theory, see GILLMAN, supra note 100; SKOWRONEK, supra note 7; and Graber, supra note 125 . See also the following recent works: MARK A. BRANDON, FREE IN THE WORLD: AMERICAN SLAVERY AND CONSTITUTIONAL FAILURE (1998); WAYNE D. MOORE, CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHTS AND POWERS OF THE PEOPLE (1996); and KEITH E. WHITTINGTON, CONSTITUTIONAL CONSTRUCTION: DIVIDED POWERS AND CONSTITUTIONAL MEANING (forthcoming 1999).
    • (1993) The Politics Presidents Make: Leadership from John Adams to George Bush
    • Skowronek, S.1
  • 342
    • 0003589489 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Among recent works by historical institutionalists, the two that are most suggestive for future constitutional theory are STEPHEN SKOWRONEK, THE POLITICS PRESIDENTS MAKE: LEADERSHIP FROM JOHN ADAMS TO GEORGE BUSH (1993) and ROGERS M. SMITH, CIVIC IDEALS: CONFLICTING VISIONS OF CITIZENSHIP IN U.S. HISTORY (1997). Smith's book is particularly relevant to what I have argued here in that it shows that American constitutionalism cannot be reasonably represented as a narrative of continuity. For other works by political scientists that are relevant to the project of a contextualized constitutional theory, see GILLMAN, supra note 100; SKOWRONEK, supra note 7; and Graber, supra note 125 . See also the following recent works: MARK A. BRANDON, FREE IN THE WORLD: AMERICAN SLAVERY AND CONSTITUTIONAL FAILURE (1998); WAYNE D. MOORE, CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHTS AND POWERS OF THE PEOPLE (1996); and KEITH E. WHITTINGTON, CONSTITUTIONAL CONSTRUCTION: DIVIDED POWERS AND CONSTITUTIONAL MEANING (forthcoming 1999).
    • (1997) Civic Ideals: Conflicting Visions of Citizenship in U.S. History
    • Smith, R.M.1
  • 343
    • 0042059149 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 100
    • Among recent works by historical institutionalists, the two that are most suggestive for future constitutional theory are STEPHEN SKOWRONEK, THE POLITICS PRESIDENTS MAKE: LEADERSHIP FROM JOHN ADAMS TO GEORGE BUSH (1993) and ROGERS M. SMITH, CIVIC IDEALS: CONFLICTING VISIONS OF CITIZENSHIP IN U.S. HISTORY (1997). Smith's book is particularly relevant to what I have argued here in that it shows that American constitutionalism cannot be reasonably represented as a narrative of continuity. For other works by political scientists that are relevant to the project of a contextualized constitutional theory, see GILLMAN, supra note 100; SKOWRONEK, supra note 7; and Graber, supra note 125 . See also the following recent works: MARK A. BRANDON, FREE IN THE WORLD: AMERICAN SLAVERY AND CONSTITUTIONAL FAILURE (1998); WAYNE D. MOORE, CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHTS AND POWERS OF THE PEOPLE (1996); and KEITH E. WHITTINGTON, CONSTITUTIONAL CONSTRUCTION: DIVIDED POWERS AND CONSTITUTIONAL MEANING (forthcoming 1999).
    • Gillman1
  • 344
    • 0041557888 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 7
    • Among recent works by historical institutionalists, the two that are most suggestive for future constitutional theory are STEPHEN SKOWRONEK, THE POLITICS PRESIDENTS MAKE: LEADERSHIP FROM JOHN ADAMS TO GEORGE BUSH (1993) and ROGERS M. SMITH, CIVIC IDEALS: CONFLICTING VISIONS OF CITIZENSHIP IN U.S. HISTORY (1997). Smith's book is particularly relevant to what I have argued here in that it shows that American constitutionalism cannot be reasonably represented as a narrative of continuity. For other works by political scientists that are relevant to the project of a contextualized constitutional theory, see GILLMAN, supra note 100; SKOWRONEK, supra note 7; and Graber, supra note 125 . See also the following recent works: MARK A. BRANDON, FREE IN THE WORLD: AMERICAN SLAVERY AND CONSTITUTIONAL FAILURE (1998); WAYNE D. MOORE, CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHTS AND POWERS OF THE PEOPLE (1996); and KEITH E. WHITTINGTON, CONSTITUTIONAL CONSTRUCTION: DIVIDED POWERS AND CONSTITUTIONAL MEANING (forthcoming 1999).
    • Skowronek1
  • 345
    • 0043060836 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • supra note 125
    • Among recent works by historical institutionalists, the two that are most suggestive for future constitutional theory are STEPHEN SKOWRONEK, THE POLITICS PRESIDENTS MAKE: LEADERSHIP FROM JOHN ADAMS TO GEORGE BUSH (1993) and ROGERS M. SMITH, CIVIC IDEALS: CONFLICTING VISIONS OF CITIZENSHIP IN U.S. HISTORY (1997). Smith's book is particularly relevant to what I have argued here in that it shows that American constitutionalism cannot be reasonably represented as a narrative of continuity. For other works by political scientists that are relevant to the project of a contextualized constitutional theory, see GILLMAN, supra note 100; SKOWRONEK, supra note 7; and Graber, supra note 125 . See also the following recent works: MARK A. BRANDON, FREE IN THE WORLD: AMERICAN SLAVERY AND CONSTITUTIONAL FAILURE (1998); WAYNE D. MOORE, CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHTS AND POWERS OF THE PEOPLE (1996); and KEITH E. WHITTINGTON, CONSTITUTIONAL CONSTRUCTION: DIVIDED POWERS AND CONSTITUTIONAL MEANING (forthcoming 1999).
    • Graber1
  • 346
    • 0002310422 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Among recent works by historical institutionalists, the two that are most suggestive for future constitutional theory are STEPHEN SKOWRONEK, THE POLITICS PRESIDENTS MAKE: LEADERSHIP FROM JOHN ADAMS TO GEORGE BUSH (1993) and ROGERS M. SMITH, CIVIC IDEALS: CONFLICTING VISIONS OF CITIZENSHIP IN U.S. HISTORY (1997). Smith's book is particularly relevant to what I have argued here in that it shows that American constitutionalism cannot be reasonably represented as a narrative of continuity. For other works by political scientists that are relevant to the project of a contextualized constitutional theory, see GILLMAN, supra note 100; SKOWRONEK, supra note 7; and Graber, supra note 125 . See also the following recent works: MARK A. BRANDON, FREE IN THE WORLD: AMERICAN SLAVERY AND CONSTITUTIONAL FAILURE (1998); WAYNE D. MOORE, CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHTS AND POWERS OF THE PEOPLE (1996); and KEITH E. WHITTINGTON, CONSTITUTIONAL CONSTRUCTION: DIVIDED POWERS AND CONSTITUTIONAL MEANING (forthcoming 1999).
    • (1998) Free in the World: American Slavery and Constitutional Failure
    • Brandon, M.A.1
  • 347
    • 0007073124 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Among recent works by historical institutionalists, the two that are most suggestive for future constitutional theory are STEPHEN SKOWRONEK, THE POLITICS PRESIDENTS MAKE: LEADERSHIP FROM JOHN ADAMS TO GEORGE BUSH (1993) and ROGERS M. SMITH, CIVIC IDEALS: CONFLICTING VISIONS OF CITIZENSHIP IN U.S. HISTORY (1997). Smith's book is particularly relevant to what I have argued here in that it shows that American constitutionalism cannot be reasonably represented as a narrative of continuity. For other works by political scientists that are relevant to the project of a contextualized constitutional theory, see GILLMAN, supra note 100; SKOWRONEK, supra note 7; and Graber, supra note 125 . See also the following recent works: MARK A. BRANDON, FREE IN THE WORLD: AMERICAN SLAVERY AND CONSTITUTIONAL FAILURE (1998); WAYNE D. MOORE, CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHTS AND POWERS OF THE PEOPLE (1996); and KEITH E. WHITTINGTON, CONSTITUTIONAL CONSTRUCTION: DIVIDED POWERS AND CONSTITUTIONAL MEANING (forthcoming 1999).
    • (1996) Constitutional Rights and Powers of the People
    • Moore, W.D.1
  • 348
    • 0004136172 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • forthcoming
    • Among recent works by historical institutionalists, the two that are most suggestive for future constitutional theory are STEPHEN SKOWRONEK, THE POLITICS PRESIDENTS MAKE: LEADERSHIP FROM JOHN ADAMS TO GEORGE BUSH (1993) and ROGERS M. SMITH, CIVIC IDEALS: CONFLICTING VISIONS OF CITIZENSHIP IN U.S. HISTORY (1997). Smith's book is particularly relevant to what I have argued here in that it shows that American constitutionalism cannot be reasonably represented as a narrative of continuity. For other works by political scientists that are relevant to the project of a contextualized constitutional theory, see GILLMAN, supra note 100; SKOWRONEK, supra note 7; and Graber, supra note 125 . See also the following recent works: MARK A. BRANDON, FREE IN THE WORLD: AMERICAN SLAVERY AND CONSTITUTIONAL FAILURE (1998); WAYNE D. MOORE, CONSTITUTIONAL RIGHTS AND POWERS OF THE PEOPLE (1996); and KEITH E. WHITTINGTON, CONSTITUTIONAL CONSTRUCTION: DIVIDED POWERS AND CONSTITUTIONAL MEANING (forthcoming 1999).
    • (1999) Constitutional Construction: Divided Powers and Constitutional Meaning
    • Whittington, K.E.1
  • 352
    • 0346155286 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A constitution of democratic experimentalism
    • See Stephen L. Elkin, Constitutionalism: Old and New, in id. at 20 . Also exemplary in this regard is the important recent article by Michael C. Dorf and Charles F. Sabel, A Constitution of Democratic Experimentalism, 98 COLUM. L. REV. 267 (1998).
    • (1998) Colum. L. Rev. , vol.98 , pp. 267
    • Dorf, M.C.1    Sabel, C.F.2


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.