메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 18, Issue 2, 2001, Pages 79-101

Moral facts and best explanations

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0040623233     PISSN: 02650525     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/s0265052500002910     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (43)

References (125)
  • 1
    • 0040272386 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I will use the terms "moral properties" and "moral facts" interchangeably in what follows. So, for example, one might say that inflicting gratuitous pain on a sentient creature has the property (or feature) of being morally wrong, or one might say that it is a (moral) fact that the infliction of such pain is morally wrong.
  • 2
    • 0003771786 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, chap. 1
    • See, e.g., Jerry Fodor's defense of the reality of the attitudes in Jerry Fodor, Psychosemantics (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987), chap. 1; and Richard Boyd's defense of scientific realism in, e.g., Richard Boyd, "Scientific Realism and Naturalistic Epistemology," in Peter D. Asquith and Ronald N. Giere, eds., PSA 1980, vol. 2 (East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, 1982).
    • (1987) Psychosemantics
    • Fodor, J.1
  • 3
    • 0039088381 scopus 로고
    • Scientific realism and naturalistic epistemology
    • Peter D. Asquith and Ronald N. Giere, eds., East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association
    • See, e.g., Jerry Fodor's defense of the reality of the attitudes in Jerry Fodor, Psychosemantics (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987), chap. 1; and Richard Boyd's defense of scientific realism in, e.g., Richard Boyd, "Scientific Realism and Naturalistic Epistemology," in Peter D. Asquith and Ronald N. Giere, eds., PSA 1980, vol. 2 (East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, 1982).
    • (1982) PSA 1980 , vol.2
    • Boyd, R.1
  • 4
    • 0004269702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Gilbert Harman, The Nature of Morality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1977); Nicholas Sturgeon, "Moral Explanations," reprinted in Geoffrey Sayre-McCord, ed., Essays on Moral Realism (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1988); Gilbert Harman, "Moral Explanations of Natural Facts - Can Moral Claims Be Tested against Moral Reality?" Southern Journal of Philosophy 24, supplement (1986): 57-68; Nicholas Sturgeon, "Harman on Moral Explanations of Natural Facts," Southern Journal of Philosophy 24, supplement (1986): 69-78. In later work, Sturgeon has argued, with some plausibility, that "nonmoral explanations do not always appear to undermine moral ones." Nicholas Sturgeon, "Nonmoral Explanations," Philosophical Perspectives 6 (1992): 111-12. This point, however, even if correct, has no bearing on the argument of this essay, which supposes that the question is not whether nonmoral explanations undermine moral ones, but which explanations are best.
    • (1977) The Nature of Morality
    • Harman, G.1
  • 5
    • 0040866616 scopus 로고
    • Moral explanations
    • reprinted in Geoffrey Sayre-McCord, ed., Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press
    • Gilbert Harman, The Nature of Morality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1977); Nicholas Sturgeon, "Moral Explanations," reprinted in Geoffrey Sayre-McCord, ed., Essays on Moral Realism (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1988); Gilbert Harman, "Moral Explanations of Natural Facts - Can Moral Claims Be Tested against Moral Reality?" Southern Journal of Philosophy 24, supplement (1986): 57-68; Nicholas Sturgeon, "Harman on Moral Explanations of Natural Facts," Southern Journal of Philosophy 24, supplement (1986): 69-78. In later work, Sturgeon has argued, with some plausibility, that "nonmoral explanations do not always appear to undermine moral ones." Nicholas Sturgeon, "Nonmoral Explanations," Philosophical Perspectives 6 (1992): 111-12. This point, however, even if correct, has no bearing on the argument of this essay, which supposes that the question is not whether nonmoral explanations undermine moral ones, but which explanations are best.
    • (1988) Essays on Moral Realism
    • Sturgeon, N.1
  • 6
    • 84979447951 scopus 로고
    • Moral explanations of natural facts - Can moral claims be tested against moral reality?
    • Gilbert Harman, The Nature of Morality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1977); Nicholas Sturgeon, "Moral Explanations," reprinted in Geoffrey Sayre-McCord, ed., Essays on Moral Realism (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1988); Gilbert Harman, "Moral Explanations of Natural Facts - Can Moral Claims Be Tested against Moral Reality?" Southern Journal of Philosophy 24, supplement (1986): 57-68; Nicholas Sturgeon, "Harman on Moral Explanations of Natural Facts," Southern Journal of Philosophy 24, supplement (1986): 69-78. In later work, Sturgeon has argued, with some plausibility, that "nonmoral explanations do not always appear to undermine moral ones." Nicholas Sturgeon, "Nonmoral Explanations," Philosophical Perspectives 6 (1992): 111-12. This point, however, even if correct, has no bearing on the argument of this essay, which supposes that the question is not whether nonmoral explanations undermine moral ones, but which explanations are best.
    • (1986) Southern Journal of Philosophy , vol.24 , Issue.SUPPL. , pp. 57-68
    • Harman, G.1
  • 7
    • 84979403372 scopus 로고
    • Harman on moral explanations of natural facts
    • Gilbert Harman, The Nature of Morality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1977); Nicholas Sturgeon, "Moral Explanations," reprinted in Geoffrey Sayre-McCord, ed., Essays on Moral Realism (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1988); Gilbert Harman, "Moral Explanations of Natural Facts - Can Moral Claims Be Tested against Moral Reality?" Southern Journal of Philosophy 24, supplement (1986): 57-68; Nicholas Sturgeon, "Harman on Moral Explanations of Natural Facts," Southern Journal of Philosophy 24, supplement (1986): 69-78. In later work, Sturgeon has argued, with some plausibility, that "nonmoral explanations do not always appear to undermine moral ones." Nicholas Sturgeon, "Nonmoral Explanations," Philosophical Perspectives 6 (1992): 111-12. This point, however, even if correct, has no bearing on the argument of this essay, which supposes that the question is not whether nonmoral explanations undermine moral ones, but which explanations are best.
    • (1986) Southern Journal of Philosophy , vol.24 , Issue.SUPPL. , pp. 69-78
    • Sturgeon, N.1
  • 8
    • 0040272289 scopus 로고
    • Nonmoral explanations
    • Gilbert Harman, The Nature of Morality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1977); Nicholas Sturgeon, "Moral Explanations," reprinted in Geoffrey Sayre-McCord, ed., Essays on Moral Realism (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1988); Gilbert Harman, "Moral Explanations of Natural Facts - Can Moral Claims Be Tested against Moral Reality?" Southern Journal of Philosophy 24, supplement (1986): 57-68; Nicholas Sturgeon, "Harman on Moral Explanations of Natural Facts," Southern Journal of Philosophy 24, supplement (1986): 69-78. In later work, Sturgeon has argued, with some plausibility, that "nonmoral explanations do not always appear to undermine moral ones." Nicholas Sturgeon, "Nonmoral Explanations," Philosophical Perspectives 6 (1992): 111-12. This point, however, even if correct, has no bearing on the argument of this essay, which supposes that the question is not whether nonmoral explanations undermine moral ones, but which explanations are best.
    • (1992) Philosophical Perspectives , vol.6 , pp. 111-112
    • Sturgeon, N.1
  • 9
    • 0003687747 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • See, e.g., David O. Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 187 ff., which discusses the issue in terms of explanatory "relevance" and "irrelevance."
    • (1989) Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics
    • Brink, D.O.1
  • 10
    • 38949150097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral theory and explanatory impotence
    • Sayre-McCord, ed.
    • See Geoffrey Sayre-McCord, "Moral Theory and Explanatory Impotence," in Sayre-McCord, ed., Essays on Moral Realism, 272-74.
    • Essays on Moral Realism , pp. 272-274
    • Sayre-McCord, G.1
  • 11
    • 0039680601 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The "Cornell realists" are defenders of moral realism such as Richard Boyd and Nicholas Sturgeon (who teach at Cornell), as well as their students, such as David Brink.
  • 12
    • 0008350673 scopus 로고
    • The natural ontological attitude
    • Jarrett Leplin, ed., Berkeley: University of California Press
    • As noted above, the IBE arguments for realism claim that we are entitled to infer the real existence of those facts that figure in the best explanation of our experience. Arthur Fine has argued that as a defense of realism, IBE begs the question, which is precisely about the legitimacy of such an inference (namely, the IBE by which scientists posit unobservable entities). Bas van Fraassen, in contrast, has asked why we should think that what happens to be our best explanation should warrant an inference to truth. See Arthur Fine, "The Natural Ontological Attitude," in Jarrett Leplin, ed., Scientific Realism (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984), 84-91; and Bas van Fraassen, Laws and Symmetry (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989), 142-49.
    • (1984) Scientific Realism , pp. 84-91
    • Fine, A.1
  • 13
    • 0004268348 scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • As noted above, the IBE arguments for realism claim that we are entitled to infer the real existence of those facts that figure in the best explanation of our experience. Arthur Fine has argued that as a defense of realism, IBE begs the question, which is precisely about the legitimacy of such an inference (namely, the IBE by which scientists posit unobservable entities). Bas van Fraassen, in contrast, has asked why we should think that what happens to be our best explanation should warrant an inference to truth. See Arthur Fine, "The Natural Ontological Attitude," in Jarrett Leplin, ed., Scientific Realism (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984), 84-91; and Bas van Fraassen, Laws and Symmetry (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989), 142-49.
    • (1989) Laws and Symmetry , pp. 142-149
    • Van Fraassen, B.1
  • 15
    • 0001443553 scopus 로고
    • Moral realism
    • Peter Railton, "Moral Realism," Philosophical Review 95, no. 2 (1986): 172. Note that none of this constitutes a bar to realism; Railton's realist program, for example - in both ethics and philosophy of science - eschews IBE. See also Peter Railton, "Explanation and Metaphysical Controversy," in Philip Kitcher and Wesley Salmon, eds., Scientific Explanation (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1989).
    • (1986) Philosophical Review , vol.95 , Issue.2 , pp. 172
    • Railton, P.1
  • 16
    • 0012771394 scopus 로고
    • Explanation and metaphysical controversy
    • Philip Kitcher and Wesley Salmon, eds., Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press
    • Peter Railton, "Moral Realism," Philosophical Review 95, no. 2 (1986): 172. Note that none of this constitutes a bar to realism; Railton's realist program, for example - in both ethics and philosophy of science - eschews IBE. See also Peter Railton, "Explanation and Metaphysical Controversy," in Philip Kitcher and Wesley Salmon, eds., Scientific Explanation (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1989).
    • (1989) Scientific Explanation
    • Railton, P.1
  • 17
    • 0002085351 scopus 로고
    • The best explanation: Criteria for theory choice
    • Paul Thagard, "The Best Explanation: Criteria for Theory Choice," Journal of Philosophy 75, no. 2 (1978): 76-92. ignore a third criterion Thagard introduces, that of analogy. This is the thought that "other things being equal [i.e., without sacrificing consilience or simplicity], the explanations afforded by a theory are better explanations if the theory is familiar, that is, introduces mechanisms, entities, or concepts that are used in established explanations" (ibid., 91). This criterion is more contentious than are the other two, and is arguably more obviously inhospitable to moral explanations.
    • (1978) Journal of Philosophy , vol.75 , Issue.2 , pp. 76-92
    • Thagard, P.1
  • 18
    • 0039088371 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Paul Thagard, "The Best Explanation: Criteria for Theory Choice," Journal of Philosophy 75, no. 2 (1978): 76-92. ignore a third criterion Thagard introduces, that of analogy. This is the thought that "other things being equal [i.e., without sacrificing consilience or simplicity], the explanations afforded by a theory are better explanations if the theory is familiar, that is, introduces mechanisms, entities, or concepts that are used in established explanations" (ibid., 91). This criterion is more contentious than are the other two, and is arguably more obviously inhospitable to moral explanations.
    • Journal of Philosophy , pp. 91
  • 21
    • 0040272381 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The simplicity criterion is, then, a relative of Ockham's razor
    • The simplicity criterion is, then, a relative of Ockham's razor.
  • 22
    • 0039680599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This objection, especially with respect to consilience, was urged on me in conversation by Julia Annas
    • This objection, especially with respect to consilience, was urged on me in conversation by Julia Annas.
  • 23
    • 0002630828 scopus 로고
    • Explanation and scientific understanding
    • See Michael Friedman, "Explanation and Scientific Understanding," Journal of Philosophy 71, no. 1 (1974): 5-19.
    • (1974) Journal of Philosophy , vol.71 , Issue.1 , pp. 5-19
    • Friedman, M.1
  • 24
    • 0040272319 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Good vibrations
    • review of The Elegant Universe, by Brian Greene, March 30
    • That Thagard has accurately captured these criteria is nicely illustrated by this passage written by a mathematician reviewing a book by a physicist: The great ambition of scientists is to grasp the far from obvious nature of the physical world at ever more fundamental levels, and in doing so, to unify our understanding of phenomena that had previously appeared to be disparate. We have been enormously successful in this, demonstrating that complex objects are made from simpler components, and they in turn are made of even simpler ones. . . . [U]nderlying the immense complexity of life is a simplicity of microscopic composition. George Ellis, "Good Vibrations," review of The Elegant Universe, by Brian Greene, London Review of Books, March 30, 2000, 14.
    • (2000) London Review of Books , pp. 14
    • Ellis, G.1
  • 25
    • 0003678815 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Cf. Crispin Wright, Truth and Objectivity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992).
    • (1992) Truth and Objectivity
    • Wright, C.1
  • 26
    • 0040866606 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cf. Sturgeon, "Moral Explanations," 245: "I do not believe that Hitler would have done all he did if he had not been morally depraved. . . ."
    • Moral Explanations , pp. 245
    • Sturgeon1
  • 29
    • 0040866607 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The paradox of fatalism and self-creation in Nietzsche
    • Christopher Janaway, ed., Oxford: Clarendon Press
    • For Nietzsche's version of these kinds of naturalistic arguments, see the discussion in Brian Leiter, "The Paradox of Fatalism and Self-Creation in Nietzsche," in Christopher Janaway, ed., Willing and Nothingness: Schopenhauer as Nietzsche's Educator (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998), esp. 230-35; and in Brian Leiter, "One Health, One Earth, One Sun: Nietzsche's Respect for Natural Science," Times Literary Supplement, October 2, 1998, 30-31. For a longer treatment, see Brian Leiter, Nietzsche on Morality (London: Routledge, 2001). Nietzsche's and Freud's approaches are compared in the book and in the TLS article. For Freud's naturalistic explanation of moral judgment, see especially Sigmund Freud, "The Dissection of the Psychical Personality," in Freud, New Introductory Lectures in Psychoanalysis, ed. and trans. James Strachey (New York: Norton, 1965).
    • (1998) Willing and Nothingness: Schopenhauer as Nietzsche's Educator , pp. 230-235
    • Leiter, B.1
  • 30
    • 0039680594 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • One health, one earth, one sun: Nietzsche's respect for natural science
    • October 2
    • For Nietzsche's version of these kinds of naturalistic arguments, see the discussion in Brian Leiter, "The Paradox of Fatalism and Self-Creation in Nietzsche," in Christopher Janaway, ed., Willing and Nothingness: Schopenhauer as Nietzsche's Educator (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998), esp. 230-35; and in Brian Leiter, "One Health, One Earth, One Sun: Nietzsche's Respect for Natural Science," Times Literary Supplement, October 2, 1998, 30-31. For a longer treatment, see Brian Leiter, Nietzsche on Morality (London: Routledge, 2001). Nietzsche's and Freud's approaches are compared in the book and in the TLS article. For Freud's naturalistic explanation of moral judgment, see especially Sigmund Freud, "The Dissection of the Psychical Personality," in Freud, New Introductory Lectures in Psychoanalysis, ed. and trans. James Strachey (New York: Norton, 1965).
    • (1998) Times Literary Supplement , pp. 30-31
    • Leiter, B.1
  • 31
    • 0040272380 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge
    • For Nietzsche's version of these kinds of naturalistic arguments, see the discussion in Brian Leiter, "The Paradox of Fatalism and Self-Creation in Nietzsche," in Christopher Janaway, ed., Willing and Nothingness: Schopenhauer as Nietzsche's Educator (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998), esp. 230-35; and in Brian Leiter, "One Health, One Earth, One Sun: Nietzsche's Respect for Natural Science," Times Literary Supplement, October 2, 1998, 30-31. For a longer treatment, see Brian Leiter, Nietzsche on Morality (London: Routledge, 2001). Nietzsche's and Freud's approaches are compared in the book and in the TLS article. For Freud's naturalistic explanation of moral judgment, see especially Sigmund Freud, "The Dissection of the Psychical Personality," in Freud, New Introductory Lectures in Psychoanalysis, ed. and trans. James Strachey (New York: Norton, 1965).
    • (2001) Nietzsche on Morality
    • Leiter, B.1
  • 32
    • 0040589059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The dissection of the psychical personality
    • Freud, ed. and trans. James Strachey New York: Norton
    • For Nietzsche's version of these kinds of naturalistic arguments, see the discussion in Brian Leiter, "The Paradox of Fatalism and Self-Creation in Nietzsche," in Christopher Janaway, ed., Willing and Nothingness: Schopenhauer as Nietzsche's Educator (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998), esp. 230-35; and in Brian Leiter, "One Health, One Earth, One Sun: Nietzsche's Respect for Natural Science," Times Literary Supplement, October 2, 1998, 30-31. For a longer treatment, see Brian Leiter, Nietzsche on Morality (London: Routledge, 2001). Nietzsche's and Freud's approaches are compared in the book and in the TLS article. For Freud's naturalistic explanation of moral judgment, see especially Sigmund Freud, "The Dissection of the Psychical Personality," in Freud, New Introductory Lectures in Psychoanalysis, ed. and trans. James Strachey (New York: Norton, 1965).
    • (1965) New Introductory Lectures in Psychoanalysis
    • Freud, S.1
  • 33
    • 84974487470 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press
    • I am assuming - not uncontroversially these days - that Freud's theory is basically true, or at least that the part of the theory concerned with explaining the nature of and capacity for moral judgment and conscience is true. The standard reference point for the contrary view is Adolf Grünbaum, The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Critique (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984). (Strictly speaking, Grünbaum argues only that Freud's theory is not warranted by the evidence adduced, not that it is false.) Frederick Crews's shrill polemics notwithstanding, Grünbaum's critique has itself been demolished in a series of papers, of which the most important are Arthur Fine and Mickey Forbes, "Grünbaum on Freud: Three Grounds for Dissent," Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9, no. 2 (1986): 237-38; Jim Hopkins, "Epistemology and Depth Psychology: Critical Notes on The Foundations of Psychoanalysis," in Peter Clark and Crispin Wright, eds., Mind, Psychoanalysis, and Science (Oxford: Blackwell, 1988); David Sachs, "In Fairness to Freud: A Critical Notice of The Foundations of Psychoanalysis by Adolf Grünbaum," Philosophical Review 98, no. 3 (1989): 349-78; and Richard Wollheim, "Desire, Belief, and Professor Grünbaum's Freud," in Wollheim, The Mind and Its Depths (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993). Empirical confirmation of aspects of Freudian theory from nonclinical settings is presented, among other places, in Henry E. Adams, Lester W. Wright, Jr., and Bethany A. Lohr, "Is Homophobia Associated with Homosexual Arousal?" Journal of Abnormal Psychology 105, no. 3 (1996): 440-45, in which the authors report experimental evidence of the role of reaction formations in homophobia.
    • (1984) The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Critique
    • Grünbaum, A.1
  • 34
    • 84974487470 scopus 로고
    • Grünbaum on Freud: Three grounds for dissent
    • I am assuming - not uncontroversially these days - that Freud's theory is basically true, or at least that the part of the theory concerned with explaining the nature of and capacity for moral judgment and conscience is true. The standard reference point for the contrary view is Adolf Grünbaum, The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Critique (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984). (Strictly speaking, Grünbaum argues only that Freud's theory is not warranted by the evidence adduced, not that it is false.) Frederick Crews's shrill polemics notwithstanding, Grünbaum's critique has itself been demolished in a series of papers, of which the most important are Arthur Fine and Mickey Forbes, "Grünbaum on Freud: Three Grounds for Dissent," Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9, no. 2 (1986): 237-38; Jim Hopkins, "Epistemology and Depth Psychology: Critical Notes on The Foundations of Psychoanalysis," in Peter Clark and Crispin Wright, eds., Mind, Psychoanalysis, and Science (Oxford: Blackwell, 1988); David Sachs, "In Fairness to Freud: A Critical Notice of The Foundations of Psychoanalysis by Adolf Grünbaum," Philosophical Review 98, no. 3 (1989): 349-78; and Richard Wollheim, "Desire, Belief, and Professor Grünbaum's Freud," in Wollheim, The Mind and Its Depths (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993). Empirical confirmation of aspects of Freudian theory from nonclinical settings is presented, among other places, in Henry E. Adams, Lester W. Wright, Jr., and Bethany A. Lohr, "Is Homophobia Associated with Homosexual Arousal?" Journal of Abnormal Psychology 105, no. 3 (1996): 440-45, in which the authors report experimental evidence of the role of reaction formations in homophobia.
    • (1986) Behavioral and Brain Sciences , vol.9 , Issue.2 , pp. 237-238
    • Fine, A.1    Forbes, M.2
  • 35
    • 84974487470 scopus 로고
    • Epistemology and depth psychology: Critical notes on the foundations of psychoanalysis
    • Peter Clark and Crispin Wright, eds., Oxford: Blackwell
    • I am assuming - not uncontroversially these days - that Freud's theory is basically true, or at least that the part of the theory concerned with explaining the nature of and capacity for moral judgment and conscience is true. The standard reference point for the contrary view is Adolf Grünbaum, The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Critique (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984). (Strictly speaking, Grünbaum argues only that Freud's theory is not warranted by the evidence adduced, not that it is false.) Frederick Crews's shrill polemics notwithstanding, Grünbaum's critique has itself been demolished in a series of papers, of which the most important are Arthur Fine and Mickey Forbes, "Grünbaum on Freud: Three Grounds for Dissent," Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9, no. 2 (1986): 237-38; Jim Hopkins, "Epistemology and Depth Psychology: Critical Notes on The Foundations of Psychoanalysis," in Peter Clark and Crispin Wright, eds., Mind, Psychoanalysis, and Science (Oxford: Blackwell, 1988); David Sachs, "In Fairness to Freud: A Critical Notice of The Foundations of Psychoanalysis by Adolf Grünbaum," Philosophical Review 98, no. 3 (1989): 349-78; and Richard Wollheim, "Desire, Belief, and Professor Grünbaum's Freud," in Wollheim, The Mind and Its Depths (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993). Empirical confirmation of aspects of Freudian theory from nonclinical settings is presented, among other places, in Henry E. Adams, Lester W. Wright, Jr., and Bethany A. Lohr, "Is Homophobia Associated with Homosexual Arousal?" Journal of Abnormal Psychology 105, no. 3 (1996): 440-45, in which the authors report experimental evidence of the role of reaction formations in homophobia.
    • (1988) Mind, Psychoanalysis, and Science
    • Hopkins, J.1
  • 36
    • 84974487470 scopus 로고
    • In fairness to Freud: A critical notice of the foundations of psychoanalysis by Adolf Grünbaum
    • I am assuming - not uncontroversially these days - that Freud's theory is basically true, or at least that the part of the theory concerned with explaining the nature of and capacity for moral judgment and conscience is true. The standard reference point for the contrary view is Adolf Grünbaum, The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Critique (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984). (Strictly speaking, Grünbaum argues only that Freud's theory is not warranted by the evidence adduced, not that it is false.) Frederick Crews's shrill polemics notwithstanding, Grünbaum's critique has itself been demolished in a series of papers, of which the most important are Arthur Fine and Mickey Forbes, "Grünbaum on Freud: Three Grounds for Dissent," Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9, no. 2 (1986): 237-38; Jim Hopkins, "Epistemology and Depth Psychology: Critical Notes on The Foundations of Psychoanalysis," in Peter Clark and Crispin Wright, eds., Mind, Psychoanalysis, and Science (Oxford: Blackwell, 1988); David Sachs, "In Fairness to Freud: A Critical Notice of The Foundations of Psychoanalysis by Adolf Grünbaum," Philosophical Review 98, no. 3 (1989): 349-78; and Richard Wollheim, "Desire, Belief, and Professor Grünbaum's Freud," in Wollheim, The Mind and Its Depths (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993). Empirical confirmation of aspects of Freudian theory from nonclinical settings is presented, among other places, in Henry E. Adams, Lester W. Wright, Jr., and Bethany A. Lohr, "Is Homophobia Associated with Homosexual Arousal?" Journal of Abnormal Psychology 105, no. 3 (1996): 440-45, in which the authors report experimental evidence of the role of reaction formations in homophobia.
    • (1989) Philosophical Review , vol.98 , Issue.3 , pp. 349-378
    • Sachs, D.1
  • 37
    • 84974487470 scopus 로고
    • Desire, belief, and professor Grünbaum's Freud
    • Wollheim, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • I am assuming - not uncontroversially these days - that Freud's theory is basically true, or at least that the part of the theory concerned with explaining the nature of and capacity for moral judgment and conscience is true. The standard reference point for the contrary view is Adolf Grünbaum, The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Critique (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984). (Strictly speaking, Grünbaum argues only that Freud's theory is not warranted by the evidence adduced, not that it is false.) Frederick Crews's shrill polemics notwithstanding, Grünbaum's critique has itself been demolished in a series of papers, of which the most important are Arthur Fine and Mickey Forbes, "Grünbaum on Freud: Three Grounds for Dissent," Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9, no. 2 (1986): 237-38; Jim Hopkins, "Epistemology and Depth Psychology: Critical Notes on The Foundations of Psychoanalysis," in Peter Clark and Crispin Wright, eds., Mind, Psychoanalysis, and Science (Oxford: Blackwell, 1988); David Sachs, "In Fairness to Freud: A Critical Notice of The Foundations of Psychoanalysis by Adolf Grünbaum," Philosophical Review 98, no. 3 (1989): 349-78; and Richard Wollheim, "Desire, Belief, and Professor Grünbaum's Freud," in Wollheim, The Mind and Its Depths (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993). Empirical confirmation of aspects of Freudian theory from nonclinical settings is presented, among other places, in Henry E. Adams, Lester W. Wright, Jr., and Bethany A. Lohr, "Is Homophobia Associated with Homosexual Arousal?" Journal of Abnormal Psychology 105, no. 3 (1996): 440-45, in which the authors report experimental evidence of the role of reaction formations in homophobia.
    • (1993) The Mind and Its Depths
    • Wollheim, R.1
  • 38
    • 0029737764 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Is homophobia associated with homosexual arousal?
    • I am assuming - not uncontroversially these days - that Freud's theory is basically true, or at least that the part of the theory concerned with explaining the nature of and capacity for moral judgment and conscience is true. The standard reference point for the contrary view is Adolf Grünbaum, The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Critique (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984). (Strictly speaking, Grünbaum argues only that Freud's theory is not warranted by the evidence adduced, not that it is false.) Frederick Crews's shrill polemics notwithstanding, Grünbaum's critique has itself been demolished in a series of papers, of which the most important are Arthur Fine and Mickey Forbes, "Grünbaum on Freud: Three Grounds for Dissent," Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9, no. 2 (1986): 237-38; Jim Hopkins, "Epistemology and Depth Psychology: Critical Notes on The Foundations of Psychoanalysis," in Peter Clark and Crispin Wright, eds., Mind, Psychoanalysis, and Science (Oxford: Blackwell, 1988); David Sachs, "In Fairness to Freud: A Critical Notice of The Foundations of Psychoanalysis by Adolf Grünbaum," Philosophical Review 98, no. 3 (1989): 349-78; and Richard Wollheim, "Desire, Belief, and Professor Grünbaum's Freud," in Wollheim, The Mind and Its Depths (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993). Empirical confirmation of aspects of Freudian theory from nonclinical settings is presented, among other places, in Henry E. Adams, Lester W. Wright, Jr., and Bethany A. Lohr, "Is Homophobia Associated with Homosexual Arousal?" Journal of Abnormal Psychology 105, no. 3 (1996): 440-45, in which the authors report experimental evidence of the role of reaction formations in homophobia.
    • (1996) Journal of Abnormal Psychology , vol.105 , Issue.3 , pp. 440-445
    • Adams, H.E.1    Wright L.W., Jr.2    Lohr, B.A.3
  • 39
    • 0040589059 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Freud writes, "With his abandonment of the Oedipus complex a child must . . . renounce the intense object-cathexes which he has deposited with his parents, and it is as a compensation for this loss of objects that there is such a strong intensification of the identifications with his parents which have probably long been present in his ego." Freud, "The Dissection of the Psychical Personality," 57.
    • The Dissection of the Psychical Personality , pp. 57
  • 40
    • 0004242613 scopus 로고
    • ed. and trans. James Strachey New York: Norton
    • Freud writes, "His aggressiveness is introjected, internalized; it is, in point of fact, sent back to where it came from - that is, it is directed towards his own ego. There it is taken over by a portion of the ego as super-ego, and which now, in the form of 'conscience,' is ready to put into action the ego the same harsh aggressiveness that the ego would have liked to satisfy upon other, extraneous individuals. . . . Civilization, therefore, obtains mastery over the individual's dangerous desire for aggression by weakening and disarming it and by setting up an agency within him to watch over it, like a garrison in a conquered city." Sigmund Freud, Civilization and Its Discontents, ed. and trans. James Strachey (New York: Norton, 1961), 78-79. This account mirrors the account Nietzsche presents in the second essay of Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morality (1887).
    • (1961) Civilization and Its Discontents , pp. 78-79
    • Freud, S.1
  • 41
    • 0003730309 scopus 로고
    • Freud writes, "His aggressiveness is introjected, internalized; it is, in point of fact, sent back to where it came from - that is, it is directed towards his own ego. There it is taken over by a portion of the ego as super-ego, and which now, in the form of 'conscience,' is ready to put into action the ego the same harsh aggressiveness that the ego would have liked to satisfy upon other, extraneous individuals. . . . Civilization, therefore, obtains mastery over the individual's dangerous desire for aggression by weakening and disarming it and by setting up an agency within him to watch over it, like a garrison in a conquered city." Sigmund Freud, Civilization and Its Discontents, ed. and trans. James Strachey (New York: Norton, 1961), 78-79. This account mirrors the account Nietzsche presents in the second essay of Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morality (1887).
    • (1887) On the Genealogy of Morality
    • Nietzsche, F.1
  • 42
    • 0039680593 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Remarks on some difficulties in Freud's theory of moral development
    • reprinted in Deigh, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • John Deigh, "Remarks on Some Difficulties in Freud's Theory of Moral Development," reprinted in Deigh, The Sources of Moral Agency (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 66.
    • (1996) The Sources of Moral Agency , pp. 66
    • Deigh, J.1
  • 43
    • 0039088368 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Freud, naturalism, and modern moral philosophy
    • reprinted in Deigh
    • John Deigh, "Freud, Naturalism, and Modern Moral Philosophy," reprinted in Deigh, The Sources of Moral Agency, 127.
    • The Sources of Moral Agency , pp. 127
    • Deigh, J.1
  • 45
    • 0004256881 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press, chap. 5
    • Recent years have witnessed an odd marriage of Freudian insights and Kantian strictures in the work of some Anglo-American moral philosophers, including Deigh. See also Samuel Scheffler, Human Morality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), chap. 5; and J. David Velleman, "A Rational Superego," Philosophical Review (forthcoming). These writers believe that Freud's theory can be divested of Freud's explicitly antirationalist interpretation. Deigh, for example, complains that "the belief that [moral] judgment has motivational force solely in virtue of its being invested with instinctual force is not philosophically innocent" and that Freud simply begs the question against the rationalist who denies that premise. Deigh, "Freud, Naturalism, and Modern Moral Philosophy," 129. The difficulty, of course, is that for Freud this is an empirical question, not a philosophical one, and the empirical evidence favors his interpretation - or so Freud believes. (Oddly, Deigh makes the conclusory assertion that Freud did not have "evidence to support [his interpretation]" [ibid., 130], but gives no argument or discussion on this point.)
    • (1992) Human Morality
    • Scheffler, S.1
  • 46
    • 85047284008 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • A rational superego
    • forthcoming
    • Recent years have witnessed an odd marriage of Freudian insights and Kantian strictures in the work of some Anglo-American moral philosophers, including Deigh. See also Samuel Scheffler, Human Morality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), chap. 5; and J. David Velleman, "A Rational Superego," Philosophical Review (forthcoming). These writers believe that Freud's theory can be divested of Freud's explicitly antirationalist interpretation. Deigh, for example, complains that "the belief that [moral] judgment has motivational force solely in virtue of its being invested with instinctual force is not philosophically innocent" and that Freud simply begs the question against the rationalist who denies that premise. Deigh, "Freud, Naturalism, and Modern Moral Philosophy," 129. The difficulty, of course, is that for Freud this is an empirical question, not a philosophical one, and the empirical evidence favors his interpretation - or so Freud believes. (Oddly, Deigh makes the conclusory assertion that Freud did not have "evidence to support [his interpretation]" [ibid., 130], but gives no argument or discussion on this point.)
    • Philosophical Review
    • Velleman, J.D.1
  • 47
    • 0039088376 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Recent years have witnessed an odd marriage of Freudian insights and Kantian strictures in the work of some Anglo-American moral philosophers, including Deigh. See also Samuel Scheffler, Human Morality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), chap. 5; and J. David Velleman, "A Rational Superego," Philosophical Review (forthcoming). These writers believe that Freud's theory can be divested of Freud's explicitly antirationalist interpretation. Deigh, for example, complains that "the belief that [moral] judgment has motivational force solely in virtue of its being invested with instinctual force is not philosophically innocent" and that Freud simply begs the question against the rationalist who denies that premise. Deigh, "Freud, Naturalism, and Modern Moral Philosophy," 129. The difficulty, of course, is that for Freud this is an empirical question, not a philosophical one, and the empirical evidence favors his interpretation - or so Freud believes. (Oddly, Deigh makes the conclusory assertion that Freud did not have "evidence to support [his interpretation]" [ibid., 130], but gives no argument or discussion on this point.)
    • Freud, Naturalism, and Modern Moral Philosophy , pp. 129
    • Deigh1
  • 48
    • 0039088377 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Recent years have witnessed an odd marriage of Freudian insights and Kantian strictures in the work of some Anglo-American moral philosophers, including Deigh. See also Samuel Scheffler, Human Morality (New York: Oxford University Press, 1992), chap. 5; and J. David Velleman, "A Rational Superego," Philosophical Review (forthcoming). These writers believe that Freud's theory can be divested of Freud's explicitly antirationalist interpretation. Deigh, for example, complains that "the belief that [moral] judgment has motivational force solely in virtue of its being invested with instinctual force is not philosophically innocent" and that Freud simply begs the question against the rationalist who denies that premise. Deigh, "Freud, Naturalism, and Modern Moral Philosophy," 129. The difficulty, of course, is that for Freud this is an empirical question, not a philosophical one, and the empirical evidence favors his interpretation - or so Freud believes. (Oddly, Deigh makes the conclusory assertion that Freud did not have "evidence to support [his interpretation]" [ibid., 130], but gives no argument or discussion on this point.)
    • Freud, Naturalism, and Modern Moral Philosophy , pp. 130
  • 49
    • 84985379575 scopus 로고
    • How to be an ethical antirealist
    • Simon Blackburn, "How to Be an Ethical Antirealist," Midwest Studies in Philosophy 12 (1988): 361-76; Allan Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990). See also Gilbert Harman, "Explaining Value," Social Philosophy and Policy 11, no. 1 (1994): 229-48, esp. 238-39. For skepticism about such evolutionary accounts, see Nicholas L. Sturgeon, "Critical Study of Gibbard's Wise Choices, Apt Feelings," in Noûs 29, no. 3 (1995): 402-24, esp. 415-18.
    • (1988) Midwest Studies in Philosophy , vol.12 , pp. 361-376
    • Blackburn, S.1
  • 50
    • 84985379575 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Simon Blackburn, "How to Be an Ethical Antirealist," Midwest Studies in Philosophy 12 (1988): 361-76; Allan Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990). See also Gilbert Harman, "Explaining Value," Social Philosophy and Policy 11, no. 1 (1994): 229-48, esp. 238-39. For skepticism about such evolutionary accounts, see Nicholas L. Sturgeon, "Critical Study of Gibbard's Wise Choices, Apt Feelings," in Noûs 29, no. 3 (1995): 402-24, esp. 415-18.
    • (1990) Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment
    • Gibbard, A.1
  • 51
    • 84974400000 scopus 로고
    • Explaining value
    • Simon Blackburn, "How to Be an Ethical Antirealist," Midwest Studies in Philosophy 12 (1988): 361-76; Allan Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990). See also Gilbert Harman, "Explaining Value," Social Philosophy and Policy 11, no. 1 (1994): 229-48, esp. 238-39. For skepticism about such evolutionary accounts, see Nicholas L. Sturgeon, "Critical Study of Gibbard's Wise Choices, Apt Feelings," in Noûs 29, no. 3 (1995): 402-24, esp. 415-18.
    • (1994) Social Philosophy and Policy , vol.11 , Issue.1 , pp. 229-248
    • Harman, G.1
  • 52
    • 84985379575 scopus 로고
    • Critical study of Gibbard's wise choices, apt feelings
    • Simon Blackburn, "How to Be an Ethical Antirealist," Midwest Studies in Philosophy 12 (1988): 361-76; Allan Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings: A Theory of Normative Judgment (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1990). See also Gilbert Harman, "Explaining Value," Social Philosophy and Policy 11, no. 1 (1994): 229-48, esp. 238-39. For skepticism about such evolutionary accounts, see Nicholas L. Sturgeon, "Critical Study of Gibbard's Wise Choices, Apt Feelings," in Noûs 29, no. 3 (1995): 402-24, esp. 415-18.
    • (1995) Noûs , vol.29 , Issue.3 , pp. 402-424
    • Sturgeon, N.L.1
  • 53
    • 0003541293 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings, 108, 116. Among Sturgeon's more interesting objections to the speculative evolutionary story is the following: "[Gibbard] believes . . . that humans evolved biologically to have a separate motivational faculty, a 'language-infused' norm-acceptance system that emerged as we became language-users. . . . [E]valuative language thus emerged to play a special role, that of expressing the norms so accepted." Sturgeon, "Gibbard's Wise Choices, Apt Feelings," 407. The puzzle, then, is why "we don't now find natural languages better adapted to the function Gibbard identifies." Ibid. In other words, why didn't evolution also select for language with a noncognitive surface grammar, instead of the cognitive surface grammar that noncognitivists must work so hard to reinterpret? In the speculative evolutionary mode of thinking that this objection invites, some answers do suggest themselves. For example, it was probably advantageous in terms of facilitating successful coordination and cooperation for humans to employ a language with a uniform syntax rather than to have evolved many specialized syntaxes, especially since evolution has no reason to take sides in the debate between realism and antirealism (or cognitivism and noncognitivism). Indeed, a cognitive-looking syntax may have enhanced the value of normative talk for coordination. Only the claim that there are no moral facts - a claim on which, to repeat, evolution is utterly neutral - creates a dilemma for the philosophical interpretation of normative talk. Recall that a primary motivation for noncognitivism is the thought that if there are no moral facts and we take the syntax of normative discourse at face value, then it is mysterious why normative talk persists: why would a putatively fact-stating discourse that states no facts have held on for so long? Noncognitivism vindicates the point of normative talk even in the absence of normative facts.
    • Wise Choices, Apt Feelings , pp. 108
    • Gibbard1
  • 54
    • 0040866605 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings, 108, 116. Among Sturgeon's more interesting objections to the speculative evolutionary story is the following: "[Gibbard] believes . . . that humans evolved biologically to have a separate motivational faculty, a 'language-infused' norm-acceptance system that emerged as we became language-users. . . . [E]valuative language thus emerged to play a special role, that of expressing the norms so accepted." Sturgeon, "Gibbard's Wise Choices, Apt Feelings," 407. The puzzle, then, is why "we don't now find natural languages better adapted to the function Gibbard identifies." Ibid. In other words, why didn't evolution also select for language with a noncognitive surface grammar, instead of the cognitive surface grammar that noncognitivists must work so hard to reinterpret? In the speculative evolutionary mode of thinking that this objection invites, some answers do suggest themselves. For example, it was probably advantageous in terms of facilitating successful coordination and cooperation for humans to employ a language with a uniform syntax rather than to have evolved many specialized syntaxes, especially since evolution has no reason to take sides in the debate between realism and antirealism (or cognitivism and noncognitivism). Indeed, a cognitive-looking syntax may have enhanced the value of normative talk for coordination. Only the claim that there are no moral facts - a claim on which, to repeat, evolution is utterly neutral - creates a dilemma for the philosophical interpretation of normative talk. Recall that a primary motivation for noncognitivism is the thought that if there are no moral facts and we take the syntax of normative discourse at face value, then it is mysterious why normative talk persists: why would a putatively fact-stating discourse that states no facts have held on for so long? Noncognitivism vindicates the point of normative talk even in the absence of normative facts.
    • Gibbard's Wise Choices, Apt Feelings , pp. 407
    • Sturgeon1
  • 56
    • 0039088380 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • I will assume, plausibly, that altruism is central to morality, so that we have explained a lot about morality when we have explained why we prize altruism. Altruism is, of course, central to a number of influential moral philosophies - from Schopenhauer's to Thomas Nagel's - and it enjoys pride of place in commonsense moral thinking as well.
  • 59
    • 0003002521 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The origin of altruism
    • review of Sober and Wilson's
    • See, e.g., John Maynard Smith, "The Origin of Altruism," review of Sober and Wilson's Unto Others, Nature 393, no. 6686 (1998): 639-40; or the polemic in Richard C. Lewontin, "Survival of the Nicest?" review of Sober and Wilson's Unto Others, New York Review of Books, October 22, 1998, 59-63.
    • (1998) Unto Others, Nature , vol.393 , Issue.6686 , pp. 639-640
    • Smith, J.M.1
  • 60
    • 0040272369 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Survival of the nicest?
    • review of Sober and Wilson's October 22
    • See, e.g., John Maynard Smith, "The Origin of Altruism," review of Sober and Wilson's Unto Others, Nature 393, no. 6686 (1998): 639-40; or the polemic in Richard C. Lewontin, "Survival of the Nicest?" review of Sober and Wilson's Unto Others, New York Review of Books, October 22, 1998, 59-63.
    • (1998) Unto Others, New York Review of Books , pp. 59-63
    • Lewontin, R.C.1
  • 61
    • 0001742381 scopus 로고
    • The evolution of altruistic behavior
    • The theory is first sketched in W. D. Hamilton, "The Evolution of Altruistic Behavior," American Naturalist 97, no. 896 (1963): 354-56. It receives its classic formal expression in W. D. Hamilton, "The Genetical Evolution of Social Behavior I," Journal of Theoretical Biology 7 (1964): 1-16; and W. D. Hamilton, "The Genetical Evolution of Social Behavior II," Journal of Theoretical Biology 7 (1964): 17-52. All these papers are reprinted in W. D. Hamilton, Narrow Roads of Gene Land (Oxford: W. H. Freeman, 1996); future references to them will use the reprint pagination. In a 1975 paper, Hamilton himself displays some sympathy for a kind of group selectionism, though he does so on the basis of formal modeling reasons that would take us far afield. See W. D. Hamilton, "Innate Social Aptitudes of Man: An Approach from Evolutionary Genetics," reprinted in Hamilton, Narrow Roads of Gene Land, esp. 337.
    • (1963) American Naturalist , vol.97 , Issue.896 , pp. 354-356
    • Hamilton, W.D.1
  • 62
    • 0013770258 scopus 로고
    • The genetical evolution of social behavior I
    • The theory is first sketched in W. D. Hamilton, "The Evolution of Altruistic Behavior," American Naturalist 97, no. 896 (1963): 354-56. It receives its classic formal expression in W. D. Hamilton, "The Genetical Evolution of Social Behavior I," Journal of Theoretical Biology 7 (1964): 1-16; and W. D. Hamilton, "The Genetical Evolution of Social Behavior II," Journal of Theoretical Biology 7 (1964): 17-52. All these papers are reprinted in W. D. Hamilton, Narrow Roads of Gene Land (Oxford: W. H. Freeman, 1996); future references to them will use the reprint pagination. In a 1975 paper, Hamilton himself displays some sympathy for a kind of group selectionism, though he does so on the basis of formal modeling reasons that would take us far afield. See W. D. Hamilton, "Innate Social Aptitudes of Man: An Approach from Evolutionary Genetics," reprinted in Hamilton, Narrow Roads of Gene Land, esp. 337.
    • (1964) Journal of Theoretical Biology , vol.7 , pp. 1-16
    • Hamilton, W.D.1
  • 63
    • 0013770278 scopus 로고
    • The genetical evolution of social behavior II
    • The theory is first sketched in W. D. Hamilton, "The Evolution of Altruistic Behavior," American Naturalist 97, no. 896 (1963): 354-56. It receives its classic formal expression in W. D. Hamilton, "The Genetical Evolution of Social Behavior I," Journal of Theoretical Biology 7 (1964): 1-16; and W. D. Hamilton, "The Genetical Evolution of Social Behavior II," Journal of Theoretical Biology 7 (1964): 17-52. All these papers are reprinted in W. D. Hamilton, Narrow Roads of Gene Land (Oxford: W. H. Freeman, 1996); future references to them will use the reprint pagination. In a 1975 paper, Hamilton himself displays some sympathy for a kind of group selectionism, though he does so on the basis of formal modeling reasons that would take us far afield. See W. D. Hamilton, "Innate Social Aptitudes of Man: An Approach from Evolutionary Genetics," reprinted in Hamilton, Narrow Roads of Gene Land, esp. 337.
    • (1964) Journal of Theoretical Biology , vol.7 , pp. 17-52
    • Hamilton, W.D.1
  • 64
    • 0003866685 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: W. H. Freeman
    • The theory is first sketched in W. D. Hamilton, "The Evolution of Altruistic Behavior," American Naturalist 97, no. 896 (1963): 354-56. It receives its classic formal expression in W. D. Hamilton, "The Genetical Evolution of Social Behavior I," Journal of Theoretical Biology 7 (1964): 1-16; and W. D. Hamilton, "The Genetical Evolution of Social Behavior II," Journal of Theoretical Biology 7 (1964): 17-52. All these papers are reprinted in W. D. Hamilton, Narrow Roads of Gene Land (Oxford: W. H. Freeman, 1996); future references to them will use the reprint pagination. In a 1975 paper, Hamilton himself displays some sympathy for a kind of group selectionism, though he does so on the basis of formal modeling reasons that would take us far afield. See W. D. Hamilton, "Innate Social Aptitudes of Man: An Approach from Evolutionary Genetics," reprinted in Hamilton, Narrow Roads of Gene Land, esp. 337.
    • (1996) Narrow Roads of Gene Land
    • Hamilton, W.D.1
  • 65
    • 0342879308 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Innate social aptitudes of man: An approach from evolutionary genetics
    • reprinted in Hamilton
    • The theory is first sketched in W. D. Hamilton, "The Evolution of Altruistic Behavior," American Naturalist 97, no. 896 (1963): 354-56. It receives its classic formal expression in W. D. Hamilton, "The Genetical Evolution of Social Behavior I," Journal of Theoretical Biology 7 (1964): 1-16; and W. D. Hamilton, "The Genetical Evolution of Social Behavior II," Journal of Theoretical Biology 7 (1964): 17-52. All these papers are reprinted in W. D. Hamilton, Narrow Roads of Gene Land (Oxford: W. H. Freeman, 1996); future references to them will use the reprint pagination. In a 1975 paper, Hamilton himself displays some sympathy for a kind of group selectionism, though he does so on the basis of formal modeling reasons that would take us far afield. See W. D. Hamilton, "Innate Social Aptitudes of Man: An Approach from Evolutionary Genetics," reprinted in Hamilton, Narrow Roads of Gene Land, esp. 337.
    • Narrow Roads of Gene Land , pp. 337
    • Hamilton, W.D.1
  • 66
    • 0039680587 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Hamilton puts the point as follows: [T]he ultimate criterion which determines whether [gene] G will spread is not whether the behavior is to the benefit of the behaver but whether it is to the benefit of the gene G; and this will be the case if the average net result of the behavior is to add to the gene pool a handful of genes containing G in a higher concentration than does the gene pool itself. With altruism this will happen only if the affected individual is a relative of the altruist, therefore having an increased chance of carrying the gene, and if the advantage conferred is large enough compared to the personal disadvantage to offset the regression, or 'dilution,' of the altruist's genotype in the relative in question. Hamilton, "The Evolution of Altruistic Behavior," 7.
    • The Evolution of Altruistic Behavior , pp. 7
    • Hamilton1
  • 67
    • 0039088372 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • If no NE works, then moral explanations of moral belief and judgment might seem to win by default. Even this strikes me as doubtful, however. Why should moral explanations be the default position, when they play a role only in parts of folk explanations (and the speculations of various moral realist philosophers) and have been utterly neglected by all serious empirical researchers? Psychoanalytic explanations (more controversially) and evolutionary explanations (uncontroversially) have established their explanatory credentials in many domains, even if details of their accounts of moral judgment might be disputed.
  • 70
    • 84934452631 scopus 로고
    • Explanation and justification in ethics
    • For examples of this approach, see Sayre-McCord, "Moral Theory and Explanatory Impotence"; and David Copp, "Explanation and Justification in Ethics," Ethics 100, no. 2 (1990): 237-58.
    • (1990) Ethics , vol.100 , Issue.2 , pp. 237-258
    • Copp, D.1
  • 71
    • 0040866602 scopus 로고
    • Naturalism and prescriptivity
    • Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller, Jr., and Jeffrey Paul, eds., Oxford: Blackwell
    • See Peter Railton, "Naturalism and Prescriptivity," in Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller, Jr., and Jeffrey Paul, eds., Foundations of Moral and Political Philosophy (Oxford: Blackwell, 1990).
    • (1990) Foundations of Moral and Political Philosophy
    • Railton, P.1
  • 73
    • 0004207980 scopus 로고
    • New York: Oxford University Press
    • Thomas Nagel, The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), 144. A very interesting and important critique of Nagel's metaethical views in this regard can be found in Sigrún Svavarsdóttir, "Objective Values: Does Metaethics Rest on a Mistake?" in Brian Leiter, ed., Objectivity in Law and Morals (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001). Ronald Dworkin has recently objected to the "best explanation" test in terms similar to Nagel's; see Ronald Dworkin, "Objectivity and Truth: You'd Better Believe It," Philosophy and Public Affairs 25, no. 2 (1996): 87-139. Dworkin's views are described and criticized in detail in Brian Leiter, "Objectivity, Morality, and Adjudication," in Leiter, ed., Objectivity in Law and Morals.
    • (1986) The View from Nowhere , pp. 144
    • Nagel, T.1
  • 74
    • 26144461173 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Objective values: Does metaethics rest on a mistake?
    • Brian Leiter, ed., New York: Cambridge University Press
    • Thomas Nagel, The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), 144. A very interesting and important critique of Nagel's metaethical views in this regard can be found in Sigrún Svavarsdóttir, "Objective Values: Does Metaethics Rest on a Mistake?" in Brian Leiter, ed., Objectivity in Law and Morals (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001). Ronald Dworkin has recently objected to the "best explanation" test in terms similar to Nagel's; see Ronald Dworkin, "Objectivity and Truth: You'd Better Believe It," Philosophy and Public Affairs 25, no. 2 (1996): 87-139. Dworkin's views are described and criticized in detail in Brian Leiter, "Objectivity, Morality, and Adjudication," in Leiter, ed., Objectivity in Law and Morals.
    • (2001) Objectivity in Law and Morals
    • Svavarsdóttir, S.1
  • 75
    • 0010915611 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Objectivity and truth: You'd better believe it
    • Thomas Nagel, The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), 144. A very interesting and important critique of Nagel's metaethical views in this regard can be found in Sigrún Svavarsdóttir, "Objective Values: Does Metaethics Rest on a Mistake?" in Brian Leiter, ed., Objectivity in Law and Morals (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001). Ronald Dworkin has recently objected to the "best explanation" test in terms similar to Nagel's; see Ronald Dworkin, "Objectivity and Truth: You'd Better Believe It," Philosophy and Public Affairs 25, no. 2 (1996): 87-139. Dworkin's views are described and criticized in detail in Brian Leiter, "Objectivity, Morality, and Adjudication," in Leiter, ed., Objectivity in Law and Morals.
    • (1996) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.25 , Issue.2 , pp. 87-139
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 76
    • 0039039967 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Objectivity, morality, and adjudication
    • Leiter, ed.
    • Thomas Nagel, The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986), 144. A very interesting and important critique of Nagel's metaethical views in this regard can be found in Sigrún Svavarsdóttir, "Objective Values: Does Metaethics Rest on a Mistake?" in Brian Leiter, ed., Objectivity in Law and Morals (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001). Ronald Dworkin has recently objected to the "best explanation" test in terms similar to Nagel's; see Ronald Dworkin, "Objectivity and Truth: You'd Better Believe It," Philosophy and Public Affairs 25, no. 2 (1996): 87-139. Dworkin's views are described and criticized in detail in Brian Leiter, "Objectivity, Morality, and Adjudication," in Leiter, ed., Objectivity in Law and Morals.
    • Objectivity in Law and Morals
    • Leiter, B.1
  • 77
    • 0040272368 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Pathetic ethics
    • Leiter, ed.
    • John McDowell has built a whole realist program around a sometimes glib contempt for naturalistic constraints, and, not surprisingly, his is a promiscuous ontology, including moral, aesthetic, and comical facts, among others. The plausibility of McDowell's grounds for dismissing naturalistic constraints - grounds that are not always easy to discern -requires examination. For doubts about McDowell's program, see David Sosa, "Pathetic Ethics," in Leiter, ed., Objectivity in Law and Morals; and Leiter, "Objectivity, Morality, and Adjudication," pt. 4.
    • Objectivity in Law and Morals
    • Sosa, D.1
  • 78
    • 0040866599 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • John McDowell has built a whole realist program around a sometimes glib contempt for naturalistic constraints, and, not surprisingly, his is a promiscuous ontology, including moral, aesthetic, and comical facts, among others. The plausibility of McDowell's grounds for dismissing naturalistic constraints - grounds that are not always easy to discern - requires examination. For doubts about McDowell's program, see David Sosa, "Pathetic Ethics," in Leiter, ed., Objectivity in Law and Morals; and Leiter, "Objectivity, Morality, and Adjudication," pt. 4.
    • Objectivity, Morality, and Adjudication , Issue.4 PT
    • Leiter1
  • 79
    • 0346997749 scopus 로고
    • Replies to Brian Leiter and Jules Coleman
    • Hilary Putnam, "Replies to Brian Leiter and Jules Coleman," Legal Theory 1, no. 1 (1995):
    • (1995) Legal Theory , vol.1 , Issue.1
    • Putnam, H.1
  • 80
    • 38949150097 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sayre-McCord, "Moral Theory and Explanatory Impotence," 274-75; for a similar point, see Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics, 193. Gibbard, it should be noted, agrees on this point, saying that "[e]ven if I am right that normative judgments have coordination as their biological function, that does not by itself show that there is no kind of fact . . . to which these judgments are adapted to correspond. One might imagine a program of 'normative realism' that proposes a kind of fact to do the job. . . . I, myself, though, have found no kind of fact that works . . ." Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings, 116.
    • Moral Theory and Explanatory Impotence , pp. 274-275
    • Sayre-McCord1
  • 81
    • 0003687747 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sayre-McCord, "Moral Theory and Explanatory Impotence," 274-75; for a similar point, see Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics, 193. Gibbard, it should be noted, agrees on this point, saying that "[e]ven if I am right that normative judgments have coordination as their biological function, that does not by itself show that there is no kind of fact . . . to which these judgments are adapted to correspond. One might imagine a program of 'normative realism' that proposes a kind of fact to do the job. . . . I, myself, though, have found no kind of fact that works . . ." Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings, 116.
    • Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics , pp. 193
    • Brink1
  • 82
    • 0003541293 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Sayre-McCord, "Moral Theory and Explanatory Impotence," 274-75; for a similar point, see Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics, 193. Gibbard, it should be noted, agrees on this point, saying that "[e]ven if I am right that normative judgments have coordination as their biological function, that does not by itself show that there is no kind of fact . . . to which these judgments are adapted to correspond. One might imagine a program of 'normative realism' that proposes a kind of fact to do the job. . . . I, myself, though, have found no kind of fact that works . . ." Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings, 116.
    • Wise Choices, Apt Feelings , pp. 116
    • Gibbard1
  • 83
    • 0001963741 scopus 로고
    • Colour as a secondary quality
    • Paul Boghossian and J. David Velleman, "Colour as a Secondary Quality," Mind 98, no. 389 (1989): 97. See also Paul Boghossian and J. David Velleman, "Physicalist Theories of Color," Philosophical Review 100, no. 1 (1991): 67-106. Note, of course, that Boghossian and
    • (1989) Mind , vol.98 , Issue.389 , pp. 97
    • Boghossian, P.1    Velleman, J.D.2
  • 84
    • 0011587938 scopus 로고
    • Physicalist theories of color
    • Paul Boghossian and J. David Velleman, "Colour as a Secondary Quality," Mind 98, no. 389 (1989): 97. See also Paul Boghossian and J. David Velleman, "Physicalist Theories of Color," Philosophical Review 100, no. 1 (1991): 67-106. Note, of course, that Boghossian and
    • (1991) Philosophical Review , vol.100 , Issue.1 , pp. 67-106
    • Boghossian, P.1    Velleman, J.D.2
  • 85
    • 0040866600 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Supervenience claims are the most common in the moral realism literature, so I will largely focus on them in what follows.
  • 86
    • 0040272366 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See, however, the discussion of Railton's program in note 81, below
    • See, however, the discussion of Railton's program in note 81, below.
  • 87
    • 0004202497 scopus 로고
    • New York: Norton
    • This is true, I think, of almost all of Sturgeon's examples. My own feeling is that if I were seeking an explanation for Hitler's conduct and was offered the explanation "He was morally depraved," I would take such an answer to be a bit of a joke: a repetition of the datum rather than an explanation. Contrast Sturgeon's moral "explanation" of Hitler with a sophisticated, and not at all vacuous, account such as that provided in Erik H. Erikson, Childhood and Society, 2d ed. (New York: Norton, 1963), 326-58. Erikson's account makes no use of putative moral facts to explain Hitler's behavior.
    • (1963) Childhood and Society, 2d Ed. , pp. 326-358
    • Erikson, E.H.1
  • 88
    • 0039680581 scopus 로고
    • Introduction
    • Fodor, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • See Jerry A. Fodor, "Introduction," in Fodor, The Language of Thought (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1975).
    • (1975) The Language of Thought
    • Fodor, J.A.1
  • 90
    • 0040866598 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Trust of course, also seems engendered by much else besides honesty: in the political realm, it is notorious that people trust their leaders notwithstanding a long and familiar history of deceit (consider Americans during the Persian Gulf War, trusting their leaders notwithstanding the experiences of Vietnam and Watergate). With respect to government, it seems more likely that it is what the anarchist Randolph Bourne called an attitude of "filial mysticism" toward the state rather than honesty that accounts for the willingness of the citizenry to "trust" the authorities. We might prefer an explanation of trust (if there were one) that would cover all these cases of trust-engendering.
  • 91
    • 0039680582 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The moral realist might protest that moral explanations have ceteris paribus clauses, and so there will naturally be exceptions to the regularities. The skeptic might ask, however, for a specification of the parameters of both these claimed regularities and their exceptions. Appeal to ceteris paribus clauses without any account of what these parameters are simply permits the defender of folk moral explanations to discount any counterexample to his claims with some hand-waving about "ceteris paribus."
  • 92
    • 0004269702 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • chap. 1
    • This question is just a variation of the question posed by Harman's account of the flaming cat case in Harman, The Nature of Morality, chap. 1.
    • The Nature of Morality
    • Harman1
  • 97
    • 0038568946 scopus 로고
    • Studies in the logic of explanation
    • reprinted in Joseph C. Pitt, ed., New York: Oxford University Press
    • In their classic 1948 paper discussing the covering-law model, Hempel and Paul Oppenheim set out one of its central tenets: "an explanation of a particular event is not fully adequate unless its explanans, if taken account of in time, could have served as a basis for predicting the event in question." Carl Hempel and Paul Oppenheim, "Studies in the Logic of Explanation," reprinted in Joseph C. Pitt, ed., Theories of Explanation (New York: Oxford University Press, 1988), 12.
    • (1988) Theories of Explanation , pp. 12
    • Hempel, C.1    Oppenheim, P.2
  • 99
    • 0002100524 scopus 로고
    • Berkeley: University of California Press
    • One possible exception is found in Thomas Haskell's account of the demise of slavery in his contributions to Thomas Bender, ed., The Antislavery Debate: Capitalism and Abolitionism as a Problem in Historical Interpretation (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992). It is unclear, however, whether Haskell's account depends on slavery being really wrong or simply on people believing it to be wrong (conjoined with the rise of national and international markets, which both altered people's sense of self and responsibility and made slavery more visible as an institution than ever before). In the case of the demise of segregation, the standard historical accounts emphasize three factors: (1) the migration of Southern blacks to the North (in the wake of the collapse of the Southern agricultural economy), which gave rise in the 1930s and 1940s to congressional districts in which blacks had real political power; (2) the frustration of black World War II GIs who faced segregationist impediments to seizing GI Bill opportunities, and who, in conjunction with newly empowered black labor-unionists, came to constitute much of the leadership of the civil rights movement at the local level; and, most importantly, (3) Cold War imperatives to do something about Jim Crow, which impeded efforts to win the hearts and minds of Africa and Asia.
    • (1992) The Antislavery Debate: Capitalism and Abolitionism as a Problem in Historical Interpretation
    • Bender, T.1
  • 100
    • 0003267118 scopus 로고
    • Multiple realization and the metaphysics of reduction
    • reprinted in Kim, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • I am assuming here, with Fodor and others, that multiple realizability blocks reduction. In fact, this seems to me true only on contentious assumptions about reduction, but these issues would take us too far afield. For critical discussion of the multiple realizability argument, see Jaegwon Kim, "Multiple Realization and the Metaphysics of Reduction," reprinted in Kim, Supervenience and Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993); and Brian Leiter and Alexander Miller, "Closet Dualism and Mental Causation," Canadian Journal of Philosophy 28, no. 2 (1998): 161-81, esp. 171-73.
    • (1993) Supervenience and Mind
    • Kim, J.1
  • 101
    • 0040272292 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Closet dualism and mental causation
    • I am assuming here, with Fodor and others, that multiple realizability blocks reduction. In fact, this seems to me true only on contentious assumptions about reduction, but these issues would take us too far afield. For critical discussion of the multiple realizability argument, see Jaegwon Kim, "Multiple Realization and the Metaphysics of Reduction," reprinted in Kim, Supervenience and Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993); and Brian Leiter and Alexander Miller, "Closet Dualism and Mental Causation," Canadian Journal of Philosophy 28, no. 2 (1998): 161-81, esp. 171-73.
    • (1998) Canadian Journal of Philosophy , vol.28 , Issue.2 , pp. 161-181
    • Leiter, B.1    Miller, A.2
  • 102
    • 0040866563 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The arc of the moral universe
    • Joshua Cohen, "The Arc of the Moral Universe," Philosophy and Public Affairs 26, no. 2 (1997): 94.
    • (1997) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.26 , Issue.2 , pp. 94
    • Cohen, J.1
  • 103
    • 84972258753 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 124. See also ibid., 95: "I am concerned with the consequences of slavery's injustice . . . and not simply the consequences of the fact that some people think of it as wrong."
    • Philosophy and Public Affairs , pp. 124
  • 104
    • 84972258753 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 124. See also ibid., 95: "I am concerned with the consequences of slavery's injustice . . . and not simply the consequences of the fact that some people think of it as wrong."
    • Philosophy and Public Affairs , pp. 95
  • 109
    • 84972258753 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 123. Cohen fudges here, and says only that the moral convictions are "explained in part by the injustice of slavery" (ibid.). However, this claim would only suffice if it were shorthand for "[T] he injustice of slavery is part of the best explanation for the moral convictions." It is not clear that this is what Cohen claims, or what he is entitled to claim.
    • Philosophy and Public Affairs , pp. 123
  • 111
    • 0039088363 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • It would have to be possible, of course, to define the relevant notion of "interest" without its being a fundamentally normative notion. However, we can surely equate "interest" with, for example, what agents would desire under appropriate conditions, and do this without endorsing such desires.
  • 112
    • 0040866556 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cohen, "The Arc of the Moral Universe," 120. For Rawls's and Scanlon's accounts, see John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971); and T. M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998).
    • The Arc of the Moral Universe , pp. 120
    • Cohen1
  • 113
    • 0004048289 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Cohen, "The Arc of the Moral Universe," 120. For Rawls's and Scanlon's accounts, see John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971); and T. M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998).
    • (1971) A Theory of Justice
    • Rawls, J.1
  • 114
    • 0003867020 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
    • Cohen, "The Arc of the Moral Universe," 120. For Rawls's and Scanlon's accounts, see John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971); and T. M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998).
    • (1998) What We Owe to Each Other
    • Scanlon, T.M.1
  • 118
    • 0040272365 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • That is, contractarian moral theorists such as Rawls and Scanlon; see note 76 above
    • That is, contractarian moral theorists such as Rawls and Scanlon; see note 76 above.
  • 119
    • 84977343185 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In particular, I have said nothing about Railton's theory, the most detailed in the literature. Railton presents us with a slightly different - and also more complex - case, since he is alone among contemporary moral realists in regarding his program as reductionist by way of reforming definitions of moral terms. See Railton, "Moral Realism"; and Railton, "Naturalism and Prescriptivity." This still does not, however, relieve Railton of the explanatory burden: if our explanatory account of the world is to include reforming definitions of moral terms in naturalistic terms, there must be some explanatory gain to justify doing so. In rough summary, Railton's approach is this: Railton claims that "what is morally best" is "what is instrumentally rational from a social point of view" (Railton, "Moral Realism," 200), but he also claims that we can explain certain historical developments in terms of "a mechanism whereby individuals whose interests are denied are led to form common values and make common cause along lines of shared interests, thereby placing pressure on social practices to approximate more closely to social rationality" (ibid., 199). Thus, in short, instrumental social rationality - or deviations therefrom - explains historical change, but instrumental social rationality also is just that to which "morally right" refers. Railton also seems to argue that we do get a gain in consilience from this moral explanation: on Railton's story seeing the connection between the explanatory mechanism, social rationality, and morality allows us to appreciate certain general historical tendencies in the evolution of moral norms (ibid., 195-96). Note three points about Railton's proposal: (1) for it to work at all Railton's quite specific reforming definition of "morally right" must be independently defended (Kantians and constructivists, among others, will dissent); (2) this reforming definition must really afford us some explanatory gain; and (3) the explanatory theory itself must be a good one if the explanatory considerations are to support moral realism. The refreshing amount of explanatory detail that Railton provides also makes his theory a clear target for critics of the explanatory paradigm: see, e.g., Alexander Rosenberg, "Moral Realism and Social Science," Midwest Studies in Philosophy 15 (1990): 150-66. Even supposing that Railton's theory could overcome the explanatory objections, it will still falter, I believe, because of its proposed reforming definition. Here, however, it will be considerations pertaining to the diversity of recognizably moral opinion, rather than explanatory impotence, that will prove fatal to the theory. I plan to address these issues elsewhere.
    • Moral Realism
    • Railton1
  • 120
    • 84977343185 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In particular, I have said nothing about Railton's theory, the most detailed in the literature. Railton presents us with a slightly different - and also more complex - case, since he is alone among contemporary moral realists in regarding his program as reductionist by way of reforming definitions of moral terms. See Railton, "Moral Realism"; and Railton, "Naturalism and Prescriptivity." This still does not, however, relieve Railton of the explanatory burden: if our explanatory account of the world is to include reforming definitions of moral terms in naturalistic terms, there must be some explanatory gain to justify doing so. In rough summary, Railton's approach is this: Railton claims that "what is morally best" is "what is instrumentally rational from a social point of view" (Railton, "Moral Realism," 200), but he also claims that we can explain certain historical developments in terms of "a mechanism whereby individuals whose interests are denied are led to form common values and make common cause along lines of shared interests, thereby placing pressure on social practices to approximate more closely to social rationality" (ibid., 199). Thus, in short, instrumental social rationality - or deviations therefrom - explains historical change, but instrumental social rationality also is just that to which "morally right" refers. Railton also seems to argue that we do get a gain in consilience from this moral explanation: on Railton's story seeing the connection between the explanatory mechanism, social rationality, and morality allows us to appreciate certain general historical tendencies in the evolution of moral norms (ibid., 195-96). Note three points about Railton's proposal: (1) for it to work at all Railton's quite specific reforming definition of "morally right" must be independently defended (Kantians and constructivists, among others, will dissent); (2) this reforming definition must really afford us some explanatory gain; and (3) the explanatory theory itself must be a good one if the explanatory considerations are to support moral realism. The refreshing amount of explanatory detail that Railton provides also makes his theory a clear target for critics of the explanatory paradigm: see, e.g., Alexander Rosenberg, "Moral Realism and Social Science," Midwest Studies in Philosophy 15 (1990): 150-66. Even supposing that Railton's theory could overcome the explanatory objections, it will still falter, I believe, because of its proposed reforming definition. Here, however, it will be considerations pertaining to the diversity of recognizably moral opinion, rather than explanatory impotence, that will prove fatal to the theory. I plan to address these issues elsewhere.
    • Naturalism and Prescriptivity.
    • Railton1
  • 121
    • 84977343185 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In particular, I have said nothing about Railton's theory, the most detailed in the literature. Railton presents us with a slightly different - and also more complex - case, since he is alone among contemporary moral realists in regarding his program as reductionist by way of reforming definitions of moral terms. See Railton, "Moral Realism"; and Railton, "Naturalism and Prescriptivity." This still does not, however, relieve Railton of the explanatory burden: if our explanatory account of the world is to include reforming definitions of moral terms in naturalistic terms, there must be some explanatory gain to justify doing so. In rough summary, Railton's approach is this: Railton claims that "what is morally best" is "what is instrumentally rational from a social point of view" (Railton, "Moral Realism," 200), but he also claims that we can explain certain historical developments in terms of "a mechanism whereby individuals whose interests are denied are led to form common values and make common cause along lines of shared interests, thereby placing pressure on social practices to approximate more closely to social rationality" (ibid., 199). Thus, in short, instrumental social rationality - or deviations therefrom - explains historical change, but instrumental social rationality also is just that to which "morally right" refers. Railton also seems to argue that we do get a gain in consilience from this moral explanation: on Railton's story seeing the connection between the explanatory mechanism, social rationality, and morality allows us to appreciate certain general historical tendencies in the evolution of moral norms (ibid., 195-96). Note three points about Railton's proposal: (1) for it to work at all Railton's quite specific reforming definition of "morally right" must be independently defended (Kantians and constructivists, among others, will dissent); (2) this reforming definition must really afford us some explanatory gain; and (3) the explanatory theory itself must be a good one if the explanatory considerations are to support moral realism. The refreshing amount of explanatory detail that Railton provides also makes his theory a clear target for critics of the explanatory paradigm: see, e.g., Alexander Rosenberg, "Moral Realism and Social Science," Midwest Studies in Philosophy 15 (1990): 150-66. Even supposing that Railton's theory could overcome the explanatory objections, it will still falter, I believe, because of its proposed reforming definition. Here, however, it will be considerations pertaining to the diversity of recognizably moral opinion, rather than explanatory impotence, that will prove fatal to the theory. I plan to address these issues elsewhere.
    • Moral Realism , pp. 200
    • Railton1
  • 122
    • 84977343185 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In particular, I have said nothing about Railton's theory, the most detailed in the literature. Railton presents us with a slightly different - and also more complex - case, since he is alone among contemporary moral realists in regarding his program as reductionist by way of reforming definitions of moral terms. See Railton, "Moral Realism"; and Railton, "Naturalism and Prescriptivity." This still does not, however, relieve Railton of the explanatory burden: if our explanatory account of the world is to include reforming definitions of moral terms in naturalistic terms, there must be some explanatory gain to justify doing so. In rough summary, Railton's approach is this: Railton claims that "what is morally best" is "what is instrumentally rational from a social point of view" (Railton, "Moral Realism," 200), but he also claims that we can explain certain historical developments in terms of "a mechanism whereby individuals whose interests are denied are led to form common values and make common cause along lines of shared interests, thereby placing pressure on social practices to approximate more closely to social rationality" (ibid., 199). Thus, in short, instrumental social rationality - or deviations therefrom - explains historical change, but instrumental social rationality also is just that to which "morally right" refers. Railton also seems to argue that we do get a gain in consilience from this moral explanation: on Railton's story seeing the connection between the explanatory mechanism, social rationality, and morality allows us to appreciate certain general historical tendencies in the evolution of moral norms (ibid., 195-96). Note three points about Railton's proposal: (1) for it to work at all Railton's quite specific reforming definition of "morally right" must be independently defended (Kantians and constructivists, among others, will dissent); (2) this reforming definition must really afford us some explanatory gain; and (3) the explanatory theory itself must be a good one if the explanatory considerations are to support moral realism. The refreshing amount of explanatory detail that Railton provides also makes his theory a clear target for critics of the explanatory paradigm: see, e.g., Alexander Rosenberg, "Moral Realism and Social Science," Midwest Studies in Philosophy 15 (1990): 150-66. Even supposing that Railton's theory could overcome the explanatory objections, it will still falter, I believe, because of its proposed reforming definition. Here, however, it will be considerations pertaining to the diversity of recognizably moral opinion, rather than explanatory impotence, that will prove fatal to the theory. I plan to address these issues elsewhere.
    • Moral Realism , pp. 199
  • 123
    • 84977343185 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In particular, I have said nothing about Railton's theory, the most detailed in the literature. Railton presents us with a slightly different - and also more complex - case, since he is alone among contemporary moral realists in regarding his program as reductionist by way of reforming definitions of moral terms. See Railton, "Moral Realism"; and Railton, "Naturalism and Prescriptivity." This still does not, however, relieve Railton of the explanatory burden: if our explanatory account of the world is to include reforming definitions of moral terms in naturalistic terms, there must be some explanatory gain to justify doing so. In rough summary, Railton's approach is this: Railton claims that "what is morally best" is "what is instrumentally rational from a social point of view" (Railton, "Moral Realism," 200), but he also claims that we can explain certain historical developments in terms of "a mechanism whereby individuals whose interests are denied are led to form common values and make common cause along lines of shared interests, thereby placing pressure on social practices to approximate more closely to social rationality" (ibid., 199). Thus, in short, instrumental social rationality - or deviations therefrom - explains historical change, but instrumental social rationality also is just that to which "morally right" refers. Railton also seems to argue that we do get a gain in consilience from this moral explanation: on Railton's story seeing the connection between the explanatory mechanism, social rationality, and morality allows us to appreciate certain general historical tendencies in the evolution of moral norms (ibid., 195-96). Note three points about Railton's proposal: (1) for it to work at all Railton's quite specific reforming definition of "morally right" must be independently defended (Kantians and constructivists, among others, will dissent); (2) this reforming definition must really afford us some explanatory gain; and (3) the explanatory theory itself must be a good one if the explanatory considerations are to support moral realism. The refreshing amount of explanatory detail that Railton provides also makes his theory a clear target for critics of the explanatory paradigm: see, e.g., Alexander Rosenberg, "Moral Realism and Social Science," Midwest Studies in Philosophy 15 (1990): 150-66. Even supposing that Railton's theory could overcome the explanatory objections, it will still falter, I believe, because of its proposed reforming definition. Here, however, it will be considerations pertaining to the diversity of recognizably moral opinion, rather than explanatory impotence, that will prove fatal to the theory. I plan to address these issues elsewhere.
    • Moral Realism , pp. 195-196
  • 124
    • 84977343185 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Moral realism and social science
    • In particular, I have said nothing about Railton's theory, the most detailed in the literature. Railton presents us with a slightly different - and also more complex - case, since he is alone among contemporary moral realists in regarding his program as reductionist by way of reforming definitions of moral terms. See Railton, "Moral Realism"; and Railton, "Naturalism and Prescriptivity." This still does not, however, relieve Railton of the explanatory burden: if our explanatory account of the world is to include reforming definitions of moral terms in naturalistic terms, there must be some explanatory gain to justify doing so. In rough summary, Railton's approach is this: Railton claims that "what is morally best" is "what is instrumentally rational from a social point of view" (Railton, "Moral Realism," 200), but he also claims that we can explain certain historical developments in terms of "a mechanism whereby individuals whose interests are denied are led to form common values and make common cause along lines of shared interests, thereby placing pressure on social practices to approximate more closely to social rationality" (ibid., 199). Thus, in short, instrumental social rationality - or deviations therefrom - explains historical change, but instrumental social rationality also is just that to which "morally right" refers. Railton also seems to argue that we do get a gain in consilience from this moral explanation: on Railton's story seeing the connection between the explanatory mechanism, social rationality, and morality allows us to appreciate certain general historical tendencies in the evolution of moral norms (ibid., 195-96). Note three points about Railton's proposal: (1) for it to work at all Railton's quite specific reforming definition of "morally right" must be independently defended (Kantians and constructivists, among others, will dissent); (2) this reforming definition must really afford us some explanatory gain; and (3) the explanatory theory itself must be a good one if the explanatory considerations are to support moral realism. The refreshing amount of explanatory detail that Railton provides also makes his theory a clear target for critics of the explanatory paradigm: see, e.g., Alexander Rosenberg, "Moral Realism and Social Science," Midwest Studies in Philosophy 15 (1990): 150-66. Even supposing that Railton's theory could overcome the explanatory objections, it will still falter, I believe, because of its proposed reforming definition. Here, however, it will be considerations pertaining to the diversity of recognizably moral opinion, rather than explanatory impotence, that will prove fatal to the theory. I plan to address these issues elsewhere.
    • (1990) Midwest Studies in Philosophy , vol.15 , pp. 150-166
    • Rosenberg, A.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.