메뉴 건너뛰기




Volumn 18, Issue 2, 2001, Pages 236-256

Moral knowledge as practical knowledge

(1)  Annas, Julia a  

a NONE

Author keywords

[No Author keywords available]

Indexed keywords


EID: 0040030056     PISSN: 02650525     EISSN: None     Source Type: Journal    
DOI: 10.1017/s0265052500002971     Document Type: Article
Times cited : (34)

References (34)
  • 2
    • 0010915611 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Objectivity and truth: You'd better believe it
    • I am aware that discussion of moral realism has moved on since Mackie, but there has been surprisingly little change on the point I wish to examine. It is often assumed that the realist options are either a kind of minimalist realism, making only the internal commitments of moral discourse (for an example of this kind of realism, see Ronald Dworkin, "Objectivity and Truth: You'd Better Believe It," Philosophy and Public Affairs 25, no. 2 [1996]: 87-139), or a more substantial realism, making metaphysical commitments external to moral discourse, and this option is readily labelled "Platonism."
    • (1996) Philosophy and Public Affairs , vol.25 , Issue.2 , pp. 87-139
    • Dworkin, R.1
  • 3
    • 84875185524 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Mackie, Ethics, 38. Mackie frequently makes disparaging references to "intuition," which he gives no account of. He assumes that we know what intuition is from "the intuitionists," but this is not a great deal of help, since theories calling themselves intuitionist have diverged widely over what they take intuition to be and what kind of items (e.g., principles, kinds of value, individual features of situations) they take to be the objects of intuition.
    • Ethics , pp. 38
    • Mackie1
  • 4
    • 0039680230 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 23-24.
    • Ethics , pp. 23-24
  • 5
    • 0040272044 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 40.
    • Ethics , pp. 40
  • 6
    • 0040272028 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Ibid., 41.
    • Ethics , pp. 41
  • 7
    • 84875185524 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This harsh verdict is reasonable in that Mackie did, after all, read Plato in the original and was not dependent on possibly misleading translations. Mackie is also insensitive to Plato's uses of argument, reading the dialogues crudely as ways of putting forward positive ideas of Plato's own. Mackie regards the arguments of the Protagoras, for example, as Plato's own attempts to put forward a positive position, and deals with the obvious resulting problems by cheerfully ascribing to Plato "a lot of sophistry" (Mackie, Ethics, 187).
    • Ethics , pp. 187
    • Mackie1
  • 8
    • 0040272039 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • More expansively, we cannot access them by "sensory perception or introspection or the framing and confirming of explanatory hypotheses or inference or logical construction or conceptual analysis, or any combination of these" (ibid., 39).
    • Ethics , pp. 39
  • 9
    • 0039680239 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In his notes to chapter 1 of Ethics, Mackie says that his views were first written down in 1941, and cites Ayer's Language, Truth, and Logic and Stevenson's Ethics and Language as helping to determine the main outlines of his position (ibid., 241). He rejects characterization as a logical positivist on the grounds that he rejects both the verifiability principle as a criterion for descriptive meaning and the idea that moral judgments lack descriptive meaning (ibid., 39-40 ). Mackie's characterization of his position as empiricist can be faulted on the ground that many positions describing themselves as empiricist start from much less restrictive assumptions. Also, although in Ethics he holds that morality has to be "made" and that we "have to decide" what moral views to "adopt" (ibid., 106) , he writes a whole book on ethics, thus insulating his practice from his theoretical view. I have made some remarks on this issue in my "Doing without Objective Values: Ancient and Modern Strategies," in Stephen Everson, ed., Ethics, vol. 4 of Companions to Ancient Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 193-220, esp. 216.
    • Ethics , pp. 241
  • 10
    • 0039088045 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In his notes to chapter 1 of Ethics, Mackie says that his views were first written down in 1941, and cites Ayer's Language, Truth, and Logic and Stevenson's Ethics and Language as helping to determine the main outlines of his position (ibid., 241). He rejects characterization as a logical positivist on the grounds that he rejects both the verifiability principle as a criterion for descriptive meaning and the idea that moral judgments lack descriptive meaning (ibid., 39-40 ). Mackie's characterization of his position as empiricist can be faulted on the ground that many positions describing themselves as empiricist start from much less restrictive assumptions. Also, although in Ethics he holds that morality has to be "made" and that we "have to decide" what moral views to "adopt" (ibid., 106) , he writes a whole book on ethics, thus insulating his practice from his theoretical view. I have made some remarks on this issue in my "Doing without Objective Values: Ancient and Modern Strategies," in Stephen Everson, ed., Ethics, vol. 4 of Companions to Ancient Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 193-220, esp. 216.
    • Ethics , pp. 39-40
  • 11
    • 0040866262 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In his notes to chapter 1 of Ethics, Mackie says that his views were first written down in 1941, and cites Ayer's Language, Truth, and Logic and Stevenson's Ethics and Language as helping to determine the main outlines of his position (ibid., 241). He rejects characterization as a logical positivist on the grounds that he rejects both the verifiability principle as a criterion for descriptive meaning and the idea that moral judgments lack descriptive meaning (ibid., 39-40 ). Mackie's characterization of his position as empiricist can be faulted on the ground that many positions describing themselves as empiricist start from much less restrictive assumptions. Also, although in Ethics he holds that morality has to be "made" and that we "have to decide" what moral views to "adopt" (ibid., 106) , he writes a whole book on ethics, thus insulating his practice from his theoretical view. I have made some remarks on this issue in my "Doing without Objective Values: Ancient and Modern Strategies," in Stephen Everson, ed., Ethics, vol. 4 of Companions to Ancient Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 193-220, esp. 216.
    • Ethics , pp. 106
  • 12
    • 80054133298 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • In his notes to chapter 1 of Ethics, Mackie says that his views were first written down in 1941, and cites Ayer's Language, Truth, and Logic and Stevenson's Ethics and Language as helping to determine the main outlines of his position (ibid., 241). He rejects characterization as a logical positivist on the grounds that he rejects both the verifiability principle as a criterion for descriptive meaning and the idea that moral judgments lack descriptive meaning (ibid., 39-40 ). Mackie's characterization of his position as empiricist can be faulted on the ground that many positions describing themselves as empiricist start from much less restrictive assumptions. Also, although in Ethics he holds that morality has to be "made" and that we "have to decide" what moral views to "adopt" (ibid., 106) , he writes a whole book on ethics, thus insulating his practice from his theoretical view. I have made some remarks on this issue in my "Doing without Objective Values: Ancient and Modern Strategies," in Stephen Everson, ed., Ethics, vol. 4 of Companions to Ancient Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 193-220, esp. 216.
    • (1998) Ethics, Vol. 4 of Companions to Ancient Thought , vol.4 , pp. 193-220
    • Everson, S.1
  • 13
    • 0040126218 scopus 로고
    • London: Routledge
    • For a valuable discussion of these claims, see Tom Sorell, Scientism (London: Routledge, 1991). Scientism takes many forms; here I am concerned only with assumptions made by philosophers who give science primacy in defining our epistemological concepts. These assumptions are not shared in the wider culture, even where that culture contains other kinds of deference toward science.
    • (1991) Scientism
    • Sorell, T.1
  • 14
    • 0039680229 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • Knowledge as understanding and knowledge as improved true belief are both prominent in ancient epistemology. As noted, Plato is mostly concerned with the former, though the latter is in question in the Meno and at the end of the Theaetetus. For a good introduction to these different strands in ancient epistemology, see Stephen Everson, ed., Epistemology, vol. 1 of Companions to Ancient Thought (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1990), particularly Everson's introduction.
    • (1990) Epistemology, Vol. 1 of Companions to Ancient Thought , vol.1
    • Everson, S.1
  • 15
    • 0040866263 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The Laches is particularly interesting in that Socrates's actual demand seems controversial: do we really show courage in resisting pleasures and temptations, as well as in resisting pains and discouraging factors? The claim that we do comes from thinking of courage as involving the idea of endurance more centrally than the idea of resisting unpleasant or dangerous circumstances. This is something on which people may reasonably disagree.
  • 16
    • 0039088042 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • We should remember, however, that in the first part of the Parmenides Plato has Socrates put forward an account of Forms much as they are found in the Phaedo and the Republic, and then has the account subjected to the same kind of relentless criticism that Socrates elsewhere directs at the positions of others. Furthermore, as in these other cases, the objections are nowhere met. Plato was obviously aware of intellectual difficulties in his account of Forms, and he continued to work toward more satisfactory characterizations. What we rather misleadingly call "the theory" of Forms is a cluster of ideas which Plato engaged with in different ways at different times.
  • 17
    • 0039680232 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • When Plato uses language that suggests insight or grasp, this is not as an alternative to hard and effortful thinking, but suggestive of what it is to come to understand something by thinking hard about it. Perception is a misleading metaphor for moral thinking if it is used (as it sometimes has been) to suggest that no effort is required, or that getting it right is easy and obvious. Such ideas could scarcely be further from Plato's insistence that moral thinking is hard and requires effort which many people are too lazy, or too focused on material success, to make.
  • 19
    • 0039680233 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • The appeal to mathematics in particular goes with a greatly raised standard for what is to count as having understanding of the kind which is sought
    • The appeal to mathematics in particular goes with a greatly raised standard for what is to count as having understanding of the kind which is sought.
  • 20
    • 0039088043 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • This point has been recognized in the secondary literature for some time now. See Paul Woodruff, "Plato's Early Theory of Knowledge," in Everson, ed., Epistemology, 60-84, for a very useful discussion of the many issues involved.
    • Epistemology , pp. 60-84
    • Everson1
  • 21
    • 84871945632 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Plato, Meno, 89e ff. and Plato, Protagoras, 319e ff. The obvious and agreed teachability of kinds of expertise comes in when these discussions center on the teachability or otherwise of virtue.
    • Meno
    • Plato1
  • 22
    • 84870816240 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • See Plato, Meno, 89e ff. and Plato, Protagoras, 319e ff. The obvious and agreed teachability of kinds of expertise comes in when these discussions center on the teachability or otherwise of virtue.
    • Protagoras
    • Plato1
  • 23
    • 1642598506 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • In the case of the productive skills, exercise of the skill produces a unified object whose organization reflects the expert's unified grasp of her skill and its requirements; see Plato, Gorgias, 503d-504b.
    • Gorgias
    • Plato1
  • 24
    • 25744443928 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • On this point, see ibid., 465a, 501a.
    • Gorgias
  • 25
    • 0039680240 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • A common objection is that we are in fact prepared (even if the ancients were not) to call someone an expert if she can reliably come out with a certain performance, whether or not she displays articulate understanding. Thus we are (allegedly) prepared to call someone an expert gardener even if they are stubbornly unwilling to say anything about the basis of their success, and to call someone an expert who knows lots of facts about, say, ranches in the Southwest between 1880 and 1885, despite never relating this to any wider context. There is more than one response to this alleged problem. First, we might be misusing the term "expert" in using it of these people, since they lack articulate understanding of what they are doing. It might also be the case that we are assuming that the people in question do have a unified understanding of what they do, but for some reason cannot, or are unwilling to, articulate it. If we thought the gardener really unable to relate frosts to early plantings, or the history buff completely ignorant of other contemporary facts, I doubt that we would call them experts.
  • 26
    • 28944442434 scopus 로고
    • My "virtue as a skill,"
    • My "Virtue as a Skill," International Journal of Philosophical Studies 3, no. 2 (1995): 227-43, traces some of the implications of this idea for virtue as a concept in a theory of morality.
    • (1995) International Journal of Philosophical Studies , vol.3 , Issue.2 , pp. 227-243
  • 27
    • 0040866261 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Hence, it is ineffective to object that moral knowledge cannot be thought of as a skill because the aims of local skills are obviously optional. Nor does the analogy import the claim that the object of moral thinking is already fixed, as with local skills. Clearly, living your life in a good way is not an aim which can be clearly defined in advance, unlike, say, the aims of plumbing or car repair.
  • 29
    • 0040866257 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • The inconclusive "argument from relativity" is directed at "moral codes," while the "argument from queerness" is directed at objective values.
  • 31
    • 0040866259 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • note
    • Cf. note 14 above, concerning the understanding of courage.
  • 32
    • 0003687747 scopus 로고
    • Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
    • "Internalism" has been used for a variety of different positions; here I take it to be the position that fully to understand a moral requirement is to be (to some degree) motivated by it. See David O. Brink, Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 45 ff.
    • (1989) Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics
    • Brink, D.O.1
  • 33
    • 0003593197 scopus 로고    scopus 로고
    • Oxford: Oxford University Press
    • For discussion of respect for the idea of moral learning, see the excellent comments in Rosalind Hursthouse, On Virtue Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 12-16.
    • (1999) On Virtue Ethics , pp. 12-16
    • Hursthouse, R.1
  • 34
    • 0009362547 scopus 로고
    • Unified science and psychology
    • Brian McGumness, ed., Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Reidel
    • "Must everyone in turn go through metaphysics as through a childhood disease? . . . No. . . . Every child can in principle learn to apply the language of physicalism correctly from the outset. . . . A new generation educated according to unified science will not understand the difference between the 'mental' and the 'physical' sciences, or between 'philosophy of nature' and of 'culture.'" Otto Neurath, "Unified Science and Psychology," in Brian McGumness, ed., Unified Science: The Vienna Circle Monograph Series (Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Reidel, 1987), 1-23. On page 8 Neurath says, without apparent irony, that he himself has long employed "an index verborum prohibitorum" such as "norm," "categorical imperative," and "intuition." Such is the world without Mackie's "errors."
    • (1987) Unified Science: The Vienna Circle Monograph Series , pp. 1-23
    • Neurath, O.1


* 이 정보는 Elsevier사의 SCOPUS DB에서 KISTI가 분석하여 추출한 것입니다.